Plato on Soul and Body

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Plato on Soul and Body Plato on Soul and Body A Dissertationfor the Ph.D. Degree submitted to the Faculty ofArts, University of Glasgow by Maria Giannakopoulou Glasgow,April 2002 - Abstract This thesis examinesthe developmentof Plato's thought on the subject of the soul-body relation. I will not attemptto cover ever3ýing that Plato saysabout the soul - for exampleI will discuss'proofs' of immortalityonly in so far as they havea bearingon the interpretation of soul and body. In this life at least human beings have both a soul and a body; as a result, the soul by necessityinteracts with the body. This interaction, though, is not simply an interrelation between two completely different and separate entities; rather the relation betweensoul and body is far more complicated. The purpose of the introduction is to presenta preliminary view of the soul, in that way we could better understandthe background that Plato had to take under consideration. Within the introduction the Apology is used so as to show the importance of the idea of the soul in Socratic ethics, and to indicate that the Socratic idea that we should care for the soul rather than the body, becomescrucial within Plato's philosophy. The dialogues that follow, the Gorgias and the Meno, provide early indications of the complex relation required between soul and body, for Plato's moral, metaphysical and epistemological concerns. Thus, although Plato, in these dialogues, does not give us a clear definition of the soul's nature and its relation to the body, the perplexity and ambiguity concerning the soul's nature leadsto the more detailed analysisof it in later dialogues. The Phaedo appearsto offer a view of the soul as a simple immaterial entity wholly distinct from the body. Even within this dialogue, though, there are signs that this simple view of the soul is not adequatefor Plato's moral and metaphysical concerns, this becomesevident as well in the Symposium. i The first dialogue where the notion of the tripartite soul is introduced is the Republic. The chapter concernedwith the relevant books of the Republic - books IV, IX, and X- shows that the tripartite soul is in accordwith Plato's moral and metaphysicalconcerns. The soul is explicitly presentedas tripartite and because of this, it requires a close relation to the body. What is not yet achieved, though, in this dialogue'is the presentationof the particular relation required between soul and body. Although the tripartite theory implies a close relation between the lower parts of the soul and the body, Plato does nothing to explain exactly how the soul and the body are related. This is the task that the next chapteris set to accomplish. This is done through looking at the Timaeus. In the TimaeusI look at the detailed construction of the human being. The parts of the soul are located in the body. There is also some account of how bodily events affect the soul, and how the soul affects the body. The languageused by Plato shows that soul and body cannot be treated as simply two elementsthat are accidentally connected. The relation portrayed then betweenthe two is that of mutual dependence. In the final chapter, thus, I am concernedwith the crucial question whether Plato is a dualist or not. To arguethat Plato cannot fall under the categoryof Cartesiandualism, I discuss Descartes and Aristotle's views on the soul-body relation to show their differences. In particular by using Aristotle's view as an intermediate one, and by bringing forward a number of points discussed earlier in the thesis regarding Plato's view, I show that the key notion of Cartesiandualism cannot apply to Plato's theory. ii Acknowledgments I would like to thank my supervisor,Professor Richard F. StalleY, for his guidance and constructivecriticism. His patienceand tolerancetaught me not only how good a professorhe is, but alsowhat a valuableperson to know. My family who have been a constant source of encouragement. My parents for caring enoughto let me pursue my dream,my grandmotherfor her belief in me, and my sisters for establishingthat family bond not affected by distance. Numerous are the personswhose help was more than valuable during theseyears and I thank them wholeheartedly: Sakura Kamimura helped me to adjust through the first very important year of my research. My former flatmates and good friends Alexandros Alexiou, Eunice Stefanou and Nikolas Magriplis for being presentin good and bad times. My dear friends Kalli Mantala, Ekaterina Dimopoulou and Nikos Kosmas whose help proved as valuable as their friendship will always be. I would like to thank Dr. ConstantineHajivassiliou and Mrs. Eva, for their support and understanding. A big thanks goes to Danae and Maria for their love. Through their innocent eyesthey have shown me a better way to look at things. I would also like to thankmy Scottish'mother' Mrs. NancyDickinson who, like a true mother, was there for me whenever I neededher. A special thanks has to be given to Mr. Ian Dickinson for his patience,kindness and consideration. iii Finally, I would like to thank Rev. C. Papageorgiouand his family for all their help and support throughout theseyears. iv Contents 1. Introduction 1 2. Souland Body in the Gorgias 19 2.1 Socratesand Polus: Health Analogy 19 2.2 Punishment 23 2.3 The TreatmentAgainst Wickedness 29 2.4 Socratesand Callicles: Harmony/Order Within Oneself 38 2.5 Death 49 3. Meno 52 3.1 Virtue 53 3.2 The RecollectionArgument 55 3.3 Virtue andKnowledge 68 3.4 Conclusion 72 4. Phaedo 74 4.1 The CyclicalArgument 75 4.2 The RecollectionArgument 81 4.3 TheAffinity Argument 92 4.4 Simmiasand Cebes' Objections 100 4.5 Socrates'Reply to Cebes 108 4.6 The Final Argument 112 4.7 Plato'sMyth 115 4.8 Conclusion 117 5. The TripartiteNotion of the Soulin the Republic 123 5.1 RepublicIV 123 5.2 RepublicIX 136 5.3 RepublicX 152 5.3.1The Myth of Er 162 5.4 Conclusion 169 V 6. Timaeus 178 6.1 Introduction 178 6.2 Doctrine of Creation 178 6.3 World-Body and World-Soul 183 6.4 The CreatedWorld and The Human Being 191 6.5 Human soul-body Relation 196 6.6 Conclusion 215 221 7. Is Plato a Dualist? 7.1 Introduction 221 7.2 Descartes'Dualism 222 228 7.3 Aristotle on Soul-Body Relation 7.4 Plato, Aristotle and Descartes 230 7.5 Conclusion 239 Bibliography 242 vi Introduction Writing a thesis on Plato's view about the relation of soul and body, one has firstly to examine Plato's view of the soul. Plato, throughout the dialogues, presentsus with a numberof possiblereadings regarding the soul's nature,but a moredetailed reading of the dialogues can show that there is a development of thought from a simple soul, that is seen as reason, towards a tripartite soul. This change from a simple soul to a tripartite one may be seen as a random one, but I would like to argue that Plato's thought progressed towards the tripartite soul because of his metaphysical and epistemological concerns. Plato's notion of soul moreover, as it progresses,shapes his view of the relation between soul and body. To talk about the soul-body relation, then, requires also to establish the philosophical background in so far as it concerns the various views on the soul, qmXT).Such a background will show views that directly or indirectly influenced Plato. One of the essentialbeliefs of the ancient Greeks regarding the soul, OXTI, is that OXTI is what makes something 'living'; the possession or not of soul determines what is animate and what is inanimate. A characteristic example of the notion that soul is the source of life is Thales' philosophy. He held that whatever exhibited some kind of motion must have possessed soul: 'Thales, too, seems from what they relate, to have supposed that the soul was something kinetic, if he said that the [magnesian] stone possesses soul because it moves iron' (Aristotle de anima A2,405al9, K. Rý S. 89)'. But there is much more than this to the notion of qwXTI '. Within the philological tradition, the first reference to soul as an aetherial element is that given by Homer. One All the quotations regarding the Presocraticsare taken from G. S. Kirk, J. E. Raven and M. Schofield, The Presocratic Philosophers Cambridge University Press 1983, unless otherwise stated. I might ask what is the needfor presentingHomer's notion of the soul. Well, although Homer doesnot strictly belong to the philosophicalbackground of Plato, his works were consideredas authoritativeteachings among the ancient Greeks. Moreover, Plato's insistenceon using the Homeric epics to draw examples,and his usual argumentationagainst the validity of Homer'steachings in relationto moral concerns, indicatesthat Homeris a valid referenceas regardsthe shapingof people'sview of the soul. Homer,then, refersto soul as that which distinguishesthe living from the dead. In particular,he treatsthe soul as a ghost-likeshade. In fact, as Gulley puts it, any thoughtof survivalafter deathwas naturallyassociated with soul, sinceit wasthe soul, as the breath of life, which desertedthe body at deathý. A striking featureof the Homericview of soul is that the soulsare dream-likeshadows which in orderto show any mental capacity, need to drink blood. A view of this kind implies that the souls, although they are immaterial representationsof the people they were before they die, they are not fully conscious after death. As Bernard Williams says, 'psyche stands for Homer as something that is mentioned only when someoneis fainting, dying, or dead. When the person is dead, it is pictured as existing in a very flimsy, deprived, and unenviable condition A. His argument goes finther; he argues that the fact that the figures encounteredin the underworld bear the names of dead people does not show that they are, straightforwardly, those peoples.
Recommended publications
  • Radin Centre for the Study of Religion University of Toronto [email protected]
    Long Commentary on the De Anima of Aristotle. Written by Averroes (Ibn Rushd) of Cordoba. Translated and with introduction and notes by Richard C. Taylor, with Therese-Anne Druart, subeditor. New Haven CT: Yale University Press, 2009. 498 pages. ISBN: 978-0-0300-11668-7. $85.00 US, $97.95 CDN. Born in Andalusia in 1126, Averroes (or Ibn Rushd) is generally considered one of the most influential Arabic classical philosophers, and his impact on Western thought, through the interpretations of Thomas Aquinas, Duns Scotus, and others, can hardly be overestimated. Although Averroes wrote extensively in the fields of religious law (Bidayat al-Mujtahid wa Nihayat al-Muqtasad), philosophy (The Incoherence of the Incoherence) and their relationship (Decisive Treatise), his nickname, the Great Commentator, is a result of Averroes’ prolific commentaries on Greek philosophy, and particularly the works of Aristotle. The date of completion of Averroes’ Long Commentary is, although debatable, usually given at around 1186 C.E., and while its chronological relationship to the Short and Middle Commentaries (and therefore status as Averroes’ ‘final opinion’ on the De Anima) is debatable, the Long Commentary certainly presents Averroes’ most detailed examination of the De Anima. In form, it is basically a line-by-line exegesis, with Averroes reproducing Aristotle’s work and then proceeding to provide explanation, extension, and interpretation. Averroes’ Long Commentary is key to tracing how Averroes interpreted Aristotle’s work on the soul and how his own concept of the soul developed from his reading of Aristotle. The current translation of Averroes’ Long Commentary on the De Anima of Aristotle by Richard C.
    [Show full text]
  • How St. Thomas Goes Beyond Aristotle in His Treatment of the Soul
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Master's Theses Theses and Dissertations 1934 How St. Thomas Goes Beyond Aristotle in His Treatment of the Soul John F. Callahan Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Callahan, John F., "How St. Thomas Goes Beyond Aristotle in His Treatment of the Soul" (1934). Master's Theses. 87. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses/87 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1934 John F. Callahan HOW ST. THOMAS GOES BEYOND ARISTOTLE IN HIS TREATMENT OF THE SOUL by John F. Callahan A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in Loyola University. June. 1934 VITA Born in Chicago, Illinois, 1912; graduated from Corpus Christi School, 1925, and from St. Ignatius High School, 1929; received degree of Bachelor of Arts from Lo.yola University, Chicago, 1933. CONTENTS Page I. Introduction: St. Thomas and Aristotle 1 II. Aristotle on the. Soul • • • • • • • • • • • • • • . 5 III. Other Doctrines on the Soul • . 9 IV. St. Thomas on the Substantiality of the Soul ••• • •• 16 v. The Intellect as Form of the Body ••• . • • 17 VI. The Production of the Soul . • 21 VII. The Immortality of the Soul •••••••••• • • • • • 25 VIII.
    [Show full text]
  • The Agent Intellect As" Form for Us" and Averroes's. Critique of Al-Farabi
    Tópicos, Revista de Filosofía ISSN: 0188-6649 [email protected] Universidad Panamericana México Taylor, Richard C. The Agent Intellect as "form for us" and Averroes's. Critique of al-Farabi Tópicos, Revista de Filosofía, núm. 29, 2005, pp. 29-51 Universidad Panamericana Distrito Federal, México Available in: http://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=323027318003 How to cite Complete issue Scientific Information System More information about this article Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America, the Caribbean, Spain and Portugal Journal's homepage in redalyc.org Non-profit academic project, developed under the open access initiative The Agent Intellect as "form for us" and Averroes's Critique of al-FarabT Richard C. Taylor Marquette University This article explicates Averroes's understanding of human knowing and abstraction in this three commentaries on Aristotle's De Anima. While Averroes's views on the nature of the human material intellect changes through the three commentaries until he reaches is famous view of the unity of the material intellect as one for all human beings, his view of the agent intellect as 'form for us' is sustained throughout these works. In his Long Commentary on the De Anima he reveals his dependence on al-Farabi for this notion and provides a detailed critique of the Farabian notion that the agent intellect is 'form for us' only as agent cause, not as our true formal cause. Although Averroes argues that the agent intellect must somehow be intrinsic to us as our form since humans 2tieper se rational and undertake acts of knowing by will, his view is shown to rest on an equivocal use of the notion of formal cause.
    [Show full text]
  • Separate Material Intellect in Averroes' Mature Philosophy Richard C
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by epublications@Marquette Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Philosophy Faculty Research and Publications Philosophy, Department of 1-1-2004 Separate Material Intellect in Averroes' Mature Philosophy Richard C. Taylor Marquette University, [email protected] Published version. "Separate Material Intellect in Averroes' Mature Philosophy," in Words, Texts and Concepts Cruising the Mediterranean Sea. Eds. Gerhard Endress, Rud̈ iger Arnzen and J Thielmann. Leuven; Dudley, MA: Peeters, 2004: 289-309. Permalink. © 2004 Peeters Publishers. Used with permission. ORIENTALIA LOVANIENSIA ANALECTA ---139--- 'WORDS, TEXTS AND CONCEPTS CRUISING THE MEDITERRANEAN SEA Studies on the sources, contents and influences of Islamic civilization and Arabic philosophy and science Dedicated to Gerhard Endress on his sixty-fifth birthday edited by R. ARNZEN and J. THIELMANN UITGEVERIJ PEETERS en DEPARTEMENT OOSTERSE STUDIES LEUVEN - PARIS - DUDLEY, MA 2004 SEPARATE MATERIAL INTELLECT IN A VERROES' MATURE PHILOSOPHY Richard C. T AYLOR Marquette University, Milwaukee The doctrine of the material intellect promulgated by Averroes (i126- 1198) in his latest works is surely the teaching for which he has been most maligned both in the medieval era and in modern times. In medi­ eval times Duns Scotus spoke of "That accursed Averroes" whose "fan­ tastic conception, intelligible neither to himself nor to others, assumes the intellective part of man to be a sort
    [Show full text]
  • A Brief Account of the Relation Between Prudence and Decision in Aristotle’S Nicomachean Ethics ______
    Beytulhikme An International Journal of Philosophy ISSN: 1303-8303 Volume 5 Issue 1 June 2015 Research ArticleDoi: 10.18491/bijop.35105 ___________________________________________________________ A Brief Account of the Relation between Prudence and Decision in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics ___________________________________________________________ Aristoteles’in ‘Nikomakhos’a Etik’ Eserinde Karar ve Basiret Arasındaki İlişkinin Kısa Bir İzahı YAKUP HAMDİOĞLU s o p h y Cumhuriyet University o Received: 19.02.15Accepted: 13.04.15 Abstract: Aristotle’s ethical theory tells us how happiness gives shape to the human life. Happiness containing within itself the ef- fort toward the end especially manifests itself in using the tools, which will enable us to acquire our ultimate end, skillfully. This study aims to give a brief account of how the relationship between prudence and decision, which correspond to two of these tools, is established in his Nicomachean Ethics for understanding the concep- tual framework of his moral philosophy. Keywords: Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, ecision, prudence, happi- ness, virtue, soul. Beytulhikme An International Journal of Phil ___________________________________________________________ Yakup Hamdioğlu, Yrd. Doç. Dr. Cumhuriyet Üniversitesi Edebiyat Fakültesi Felsefe Bölümü 58140, Sivas, [email protected] 96 Yakup Hamdioğlu −Why? “For one swallow does not make spring, nor does one day; nor, similarly, does one day or a short time make us blessed and happy.” (Aristotle, NE: 1098a21-2) It could serve a convenient starting point to note that literature abounds with numerous analyses, which take Aristotle to be among first-rate phi- s o p h y losophers as far as the history of philosophy is concerned. His monumen- o tal impact on the direction of medieval philosophy, modern philosophy and contemporary philosophy is unquestionable.
    [Show full text]
  • Matter and Form, Body and Soul, in De Anima • Follow-Up on Final Argument in Plato’S Phaedo
    24.01: Classics of Western Philosophy Matter and Form, Body and Soul, in De Anima • Follow-up on Final argument in Plato’s Phaedo. • Introduction to Aristotle (see additional biographical handout). 1. Hylomorphism Unlike Plato, Aristotle was fascinated by the natural world. Instead of Plato’s division between two vastly different realms, Aristotle distinguishes two aspects of ordinary things – form and matter. Form only exists when it enforms matter; moreover, matter is just potential to be enformed. Aristotle identifies matter with potentiality, form with actuality. Think of a carved statue: the wood is the matter, the potential statue; the shape is the form, which makes it an actual statue; the matter/form complex is the individual thing, the statue. In the case of artifacts like statues, we impose form on the matter. But the form/matter in statues is just an analogy to help us understand the basic idea. Aristotle was mainly interested in explaining the characteristic changes in and growth and development of natural things. Why does water boil when heated and freeze when cold? Why do some trees produce apples and others oranges? Why do human embryos develop into adult humans and dog embryos develop into adult dogs? This can’t be explained simply by their matter (which is basically the same stuff), but by the form that makes something water, or an apple tree, or a human, i.e., in virtue of which the things are what they are. In ‘On the Soul’ we find Aristotle applying his wider metaphysical views to the topic of living things.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle on the Soul (De Anima I.1, I.4, II.1, III.4)
    Aristotle on the Soul (De Anima I.1, I.4, II.1, III.4) History of Ancient Philosophy New York University Guest Lecture by Vera Flocke, November 12, 2018 Why Study Philosophy? Plato Aristotle 2 / 31 Why Study Philosophy? Plato Aristotle 3 / 31 Why Study Philosophy? Plato Aristotle 4 / 31 Why Study Philosophy? Plato Aristotle 5 / 31 Why Study Philosophy? Plato Aristotle \[T]he one aim of those who \All human beings by nature practice philosophy in the desire to know". proper manner is to practice for (Metaphysics I.1, 980a, 20) dying and death". (Phaedo 64a) 6 / 31 Roadmap 1. What is the Soul? 2. What makes us Human? 7 / 31 1. What is the Soul? 8 / 31 Recap: Aristotle's Four Causes 9 / 31 Recap: Natural Things nature: natural things: 10 / 31 Recap: Natural Things nature: \a type of principle and cause of motion and stability within those things to which it primarily belongs in their own right and not coincidentally" (Physics II.1, 192b, 23-24) natural things: matter-form compounds (Physics II.2, 194a, 15) 11 / 31 living beings 12 / 31 This is a striking idea! the matter of anger is \a boiling of the blood and of the hot [element] around the heart". (De Anima I.3, 403b) 13 / 31 Souls as the Forms of Living Beings I I I 14 / 31 Souls as the Forms of Living Beings I what the living being is for I its nature, an inner principle of change and rest I the essence of a living being 15 / 31 potentiality and actuality \We say, then, that one kind of being is substance.
    [Show full text]
  • 0160-0220 – Tertullianus – De Anima a Treatise on the Soul This File Has
    0160-0220 – Tertullianus – De Anima A Treatise on the Soul this file has been downloaded from http://www.ccel.org/ccel/schaff/anf03.html ANF03. Latin Christianity: Its Founder, Tertullian Philip Schaff IX. 181 A Treatise on the Soul.1489 [Translated by Peter Holmes, D.D.] ———————————— Chapter I.—It is Not to the Philosophers that We Resort for Information About the Soul But to God.1490 HAVING discussed with Hermogenes the single point of the origin of the soul, so far as his assumption led me, that the soul consisted rather in an adaptation1491 of matter than of the inspiration1492 of God, I now turn to the other questions incidental to the subject; and (in my treatment of these) I shall evidently have mostly to contend with the philosophers. In the very prison of Socrates they skirmished about the state of the soul. I have my doubts at once whether the time was an opportune one for their (great) master—(to say nothing of the place), although that perhaps does not much matter. For what could the soul of Socrates then contemplate with clearness and serenity? The sacred ship had returned (from Delos), the hemlock draft to which he had been condemned had been drunk, death was now present before him: (his mind) was,1493 as one may 1489 [It is not safe to date this treatise before A.D. 203, and perhaps it would be unsafe to assign a later date. The note of the translator, which follows, relieves me from any necessity to add more, just here.] 1490 In this treatise we have Tertullian’s speculations on the origin, the nature, and the destiny of the human soul.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato and Aristotle on What Is Common to Soul and Body. Some Remarks on a Complicated Issue
    Chapter 8 Plato and Aristotle On What Is Common to Soul and Body. Some Remarks on a Complicated Issue Marcelo D. Boeri Abstract Aristotelian scholars tend to reject the Cartesian dualism as applied to Aristotelian model of the soul, and favor the view that denies that the soul is radically opposed to body. This is so due the fact that Aristotle takes the living being to be a unified whole (composed by form and matter). I start by reminding that both Plato and Aristotle argue that by their very nature soul and body are different, but at the same time they maintain that there are things that are ‘common’ to soul and body. The issue is how it is possible that two entities so different in nature have something in common. I argue that the key to the problem lies in the fact that both Plato and Aristotle regard the soul and the body as capacities, and that – in so far as they are able to act and to be acted upon – such is the ‘commonality’ shared both by soul and body. Given that capacities are relational entities, both of them turn out to be very plastic notions that should not necessarily be understood as entirely foreign to each other. 8.1 Introduction Both Plato and Aristotle famously argue that soul and body are two different kinds of entities: the soul is immaterial and the body material; the former is able to set in motion the body, and the latter is motionless.1 If this is so, one might assume that by their very nature soul and body are two profoundly disparate entities.
    [Show full text]
  • A. in De Anima 1.1-20 We Present the Opening of the Commentary Not
    A. In De Anima 1.1-20 We present the opening of the commentary not because it contains an important lamblichean interpretation of Aristotle or the soul but because it shows the high esteem in which the commentator holds Iamblichus. Although it is safe to conclude that the commentator usually follows lamblichus in his interpretations, there is at least one point of disagreement between them, on the interpretation of Aristotle's active and passive Intellect. Iamblichus believes that these are the unparticipated and participated Intellects and are, therefore, above the soul in rank. The commentator, on the other hand, believes that they are in the soul, although he attempts to argue that he and Iamblichus are not at odds but only looking at the same issue from different perspectives. See 313-314 and Steel 142-145 and 153- 154. i] 1tEpt a\rrffiv tffiv npayJ.tcitcov tffiv t£ aA.A.cov . The Greek term for "metaphysical realities" is auta ta npayJ.tata, literally "the facts themselves" or "the actual circumstances" or "the matters of import­ ance." The commentator repeats the term below (1.13-14), where it is contrasted with the text (A.EI;tc;) of Aristotle. There it seems to be the soul itself, i.e., the metaphysical principle at issue in the De Anima. The noun is used again in line 18, where it refers to external realities including the soul. Urmson (15) translates the first instance as "things themselves," the second as "the subject-matter itself," and the third as "things." Another difference between Urmson's translation and ours concerns the number of conjuncts in the first clause.
    [Show full text]
  • God's Life-Generating Power and Its Transmission in Aristotle's Biology
    1 God’s Life-Generating Power and Its Transmission in Aristotle’s Biology and Cosmology Is it possible that Aristotle presented three very different phases in his philoso- phy and that only one of these was scientifically important? Such was Werner Jaeger’s claim in 1923, and still there is no alternative theory. Is it likely that, during his lectures in the Peripatos, Aristotle talked about a vital pneuma connected with the soul as the principle of life, but that pneuma plays no role in his seminal work On the Soul? Is it conceivable that he called God the “Great Leader” of the cosmos, but saw no divine governance in Nature? These critical questions about the standard theory on Aristotle have spurred the author of this book to develop a perspective on Aristotle’s philosophy that breaks with the accepted view. A crucial part is assigned to pneuma as the vital principle in all that lives. Pneuma is the fine-material carrier of all psychic functions and is governed by the soul as entelechy. The soul is the principle that controls the activity of pneuma in a goal-oriented way (oriented, that is, to the form of the living being). The entelechy is a cognitive principle that acts on the vital pneuma and is active from the very beginning of life, as a kind of automatic pilot. In human beings, however, the entelechy can also be “awakened” to intellectual- ity. All entelechies of living beings, including those of the stars and planets, are actuated by the Power that proceeds inexhaustibly from the divine, tran- scendent Intellect.
    [Show full text]
  • Theophrastus and the Intellect As Mixture Myrna Gabbe University of Dayton, [email protected]
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by University of Dayton University of Dayton eCommons Philosophy Faculty Publications Department of Philosophy 2008 Theophrastus and the Intellect as Mixture Myrna Gabbe University of Dayton, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.udayton.edu/phl_fac_pub Part of the Philosophy Commons eCommons Citation Gabbe, Myrna, "Theophrastus and the Intellect as Mixture" (2008). Philosophy Faculty Publications. 106. https://ecommons.udayton.edu/phl_fac_pub/106 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Philosophy at eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. THEOPHRASTUS AND THE INTELLECT AS MIXTURE By Myrna Gabbe, University of Dayton De Anima III 5 introduces one of Aristotle’s most perplexing doctrines. In this short and obscure chapter, Aristotle distinguishes between an intellect that becomes all things, the so-called potential intellect, and an intellect that makes all things, the so-called productive intellect (430a14-15). It is generally held that the intellect that becomes all things is described in De Anima III 4, since Aristotle there tells us that the intellect knows by becoming its objects (429a15-18). This intellect has acquired the title “potential intellect” since it must be potentially the objects of thought in order to become and think the objects of thought (429a18-24). But scholars do not agree on what these intellects are, what they do or how they relate to each other.
    [Show full text]