<<

y.$ /J/^' W^/7

UNIVERSITY OF FLORIDA LIBRARIES

COLLEGE LIBRARY

Digitized by the Internet Archive

in 2011 with funding from LYRASIS IVIembers and Sloan Foundation

http://www.archive.org/details/essaysinpublicphOOinlipp

BOOKS BY

A PREFACE TO POLITICS DRIFT AND MASTERY THE STAKES OF DIPLOMACY THE POLITICAL SCENE AND THE NEWS THE PHANTOM PUBLIC MEN OF AMERICAN INQUISITORS A PREFACE TO MORALS INTERPRETATIONS 1931-1932 INTERPRETATIONS I933-I935 THE METHOD OF FREEDOM THE NEW IMPERATIVE THE GOOD

U. S, FOREIGN POLICY: SHIELD OF THE REPUBLIC

U, S. WAR AIMS

THE COLD WAR, A STUDY IN U. S. FOREIGN POLICY ISOLATION AND ALLIANCES: AN AMERICAN SPEAKS TO THE BRITISH ESSAYS IN THE PUBLIC

Wifh William O. Scroggs THE UNITED STATES IN WORLD AFFAIRS 1931

THE UNITED STATES IN WORLD AFFAIRS 1 932 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY

ESSAYS IN THE PUBLIC

by WALTER LIPPMANN

An Atlantic Monthly Press Book

Little, Brown and Company • Boston • Toronto COPYRIGHT 1955, BY WALTER LIPPMANN

ALL RIGHTS RESERVED. NO PART OF THIS BOOK IN EXCESS OF FIVE HUNDRED WORDS MAY BE REPRODUCED IN ANY FORM WITHOUT PERMISSION IN WRITING FROM THE PUBLISHER

LIBRARY OF CONGRESS CATALOG CARD NO. 55-6533

Published Fehntary ig^^ Reprinted February 1955 (twice) Reprinted March 1955 {tvuice) Reprinted October 1955

ATLANTIC-LITTLE, BROWN BOOKS ARE PUBLISHED BY LITTLE, BROWN AND COMPANY IN ASSOCIATION WITH THE ATLANTIC MONTHLY PRESS

Published simultaneously in Canada by Little, Brown & Company (Canada) Limited

PRINTED IN THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA To Helen They are ill discoverers that think there is no land, when they see nothing but sea.

BACON. Advancement of

Learning, II: VII, 5 Acknowledgments

Once again I am deeply indebted to Edward Weeks, the editor of the Atlantic Monthly, for his editorial criticism and for his help in the editing and the revision of the ttyit.

I can only acknowledge gratefully this debt which I could not repay.

I wish to thank Dean McGeorge Bundy of Harvard

University for his very helpful criticism of the text; Mr.

Stanley Salmen of Little, Brown for his reassurance and advice; Mr. Curtis W. Cate of the Atlantic Monthly Press for his constructive suggestions, and Dr. Mortimer J. Adler, Director of the Institute for Philosophical Research, who was consulted when the manuscript was finished, and who offered very prompt assistance with the footnotes and with certain of the logical problems.

W.L.

Washington, D.C. 1954

Contents

BOOK ONE: The Decline of the West

CHAPTER i: The Obscure 3

1. My for Writing This Book

2. i^ij: The Revolutionary Year

3. Internal Revolution in the

4. The Paralysis of

CHAPTER 11: The Malady of Democratic States 16

1. Public Opinion in War and Peace

2. The Compulsion to Make Mistakes

3. The Pattern of the Mistakes

4. Democratic Politicians

CHAPTER III: The Derangement of Powers 28

1. The Governors and the Governed

2. The People and the Voters

3. The Recently Enfranchised Voters

CHAPTER IV : The Public Interest 41

1. What Is the Public Interest?

2. The Equations of 1

Xll CONTENTS

CHAPTER v: The Two Functions 47

1. The Elected Executive

2. The Protection of the Executive

3. The Voters and the Executive

4. The Enfeebled Executive

CHAPTER VI : The Totalitarian Counterrevolution 58

1. Certain of Its Lessons

2. A Prognosis

CHAPTER VII : The Adversaries of Liberal 63

1. Liberalism and Jacobinism

2. The Paradigm of Revolution

3. Democratic

4. Prom Jacobinism to Leninism

5. The Overpassing of the Bound

BOOK two: The Public Philosophy

CHAPTER VIII : The Eclipse of the Public Philosophy 9

1. On the Efficacy of

2. The Great Vacuum

3. The Neglect of the Public Philosophy

4. The Laius of the Rational Order

5. The Rupture in Modern CONTENTS xiii

CHAPTER IX : The Renewal of the Public Philosophy 113

1. The Capacity to Believe

2. Vor Example: The Theory of

3. For Example:

4. The Limits of Dissent

5. The Mirror of

6. Man's Second

CHAPTER x: The Two Realms 141

1. The Confusion of the Realms

2. The Good in This World

3. The and the Prophets

4. The Realm of the Spirit

5. The Balance of Poivers

6. The Mechanics of the Balance

CHAPTER XI : The Defense of Civility 160

1. The Thesis Restated

2. The Communication of the Public Philosophy

3. Constitutionalism Made Concrete

4. The of Accommodation

5. The Limits of Accommodation

6. The of

7. The Mandate of Heaven

Index 183

BOOK ONE

The Decline of the West

CHAPTER I The Obscure Revolution

I. My Reason for Writing This Book

During the fateful summer of 1938 I began writing a book in an effort to come to terms in my own and heart with the mounting disorder in our Western society.

I was Hving in Paris at the , and I had learned that the decision had been taken which was soon to lead Mr.

Chamberlain and Monsieur Daladier to Munich. Little hope remained that another world war could be averted except by abject surrender, and yet there was no sure pros- pect that France and Great Britain would be able to with- stand the onslaught that was coming. They were unpre- pared, their people were divided and demoralized. The Americans were far away, were determined to be neutral, and were unarmed. I was filled with foreboding that the nations of the Atlantic Community would not prove equal to the challenge, and that, if they failed, we should lose our great traditions of civility,^ the Western man had won for himself after centuries of struggle and which were now threatened by the rising tide of barbarity.

I began writing, impelled by the need to make more intelligible to myself the alarming failure of the Western

^ Sir Ernest Barker, Traditions of Civility (1948). The phrase is from Coventry Patmore. 4 THE DECLINE OF THE WEST

liberal democracies to cope with the of this cen-

tury. I had done a draft of the book when the fall of

France made it evident that we, too, must soon be en- gaged and, moreover, engaged alone if the Battle of Brit- ain was lost.

But at this time the American people were as unpre- pared in their as in their military establishment.

Could the democracies be rallied, could they be collected and nerved for the ordeal so that they would be equal

to this mortal challenge? They had the superior assets. They had the numbers, the resources, the influence. But did they have the insight, the discipline to persevere, and the resolution to go through with it? Though they had the means, did they also have the , and did they still know how? A second world war was making up out of the ruins and the failures of the first, and there was nothing to show that the Western democratic governments were in control of their affairs and capable of making the nec- essary decisions. They were reacting to events and they were not governing them. Could they avoid defeat and conquest without an exhaustion which would rend the fabric of Western society, without enormities of suffering which would alienate the masses of the people, and with-

out resorting to measures of violence which might be-

come inexpiable? They were so very late, and they were

becoming engaged in they knew not what. They had re- fused to take in what they saw, they had refused to be- lieve what they heard, they had wished and they had waited, hoping against hope.

It did not come easily to one who, like myself, had

known the soft air of the world before the wars to rec- THE OBSCURE REVOLUTION 5

ognize and acknowledge the sickness of the Western Hberal democracies. Yet as we were drawn unready and unarmed into the second of the great wars, there was

no denying, it. seemed tojne, that there is ,a dgep^dis-- order in our society which comeg not from the machina- tions of our enemies and from the adversities of the hu-

,,.man_condition but from within ourselves,^ I was one of a

large company who^^ felt that way. "Never doubting that the utmost resistance was imperative and that defeat would be irreparable and intolerable, they were a com- pany who knew in their hearts that by total war our world could not be made safe for democracy nor for the

four freedoms.i W^,.were, I had come to see, not_w;ounded

i5tiTsIc1t, and because_we_were failing to bring order- and peace tojiie_wDxId, we were beset by those who believed

they have been chosen to succeed us. '

2. 1 9 If: The Revolutionary Year

In December 1941 I put the manuscript away, know- ing that so much was going to happen to the world and

to me that if ever I went back to the book, it would be to

start all over again. When I did come back to it after the

war, the foreboding which had inspired it was in a terrible measure realized. Something had gone very wrong in the liberal demqaracies. They had, to be sure, defeated their enemies. They had avoided defeat and subjection. But they were unaW^_jta-inake_peace and to restore order. For the sernprl finn£_in a generRtinn they had failed to prevent a ruinous war, they had been unwilling to pre- 6 THE DECLINE OF THE WEST pare themselves to wage the war, and when at long last and at exorbitant cost they had managed to defeat their enemies, they had been unable to make peace out of their victories. They were entangled in a vicious circle of wars that led to ever bigger and wider wars. Could it be denied that they were sick with some kind of in- capacity to cope with reality, to govern their affairs, to defend their vital interests and, it might be, to insure their survival as free and democratic states? There was no mistaking the decline of the West. _ Thirty years after Wilson had proclaimed a world at' peace under democratic governments, the North Atlantic democracies were preoccupied with the defense of western

Europe and the fringes of the Eurasian continent. In less than half a century it had come to that. In 1900 men everywhere on earth had acknowledged, even when they resented, the primacy of the Western nations. They were the recognized leaders in the of mankind, and it was taken as axiomatic that the question was when, and not whether, the less advanced people would have learned how to use the Western technology, to hold free elections, to respect the Bill of Rights and to live by its . Until 19 17 the mod£Lior__a_new govefnm£nt_anyj^fire in the world, even in Russia, -was liberaX-demiTcratT- in the British, the French, or the Amer- ican style. But by the end of 1920 things had taken a sharp turn. Lord Bryce was then finishing his Modern Democ- racies, and though he still wrote in the prewar manner that democracy was spreading and that the number of democracies in the world had doubled within fifteen years, THE OBSCURE REVOLUTION 7 he had seen the warning signs and he was troubled. It might not be "really helpful to the younger generation," he wrote in the preface, but he could not "repress the pes- simism of ." He had to say that "although de- mocracy has spread, and although no country that has tried it shows any signs of forsaking it, we are not yet en- titled to hold with the men of 1789 that it is the natural and, therefore, in the long run, the inevitable form of . Much has happened since the rising sun of liberty dazzled the eyes of the States-General at Versailles. Popular government has not yet been proved to guarantee, always and everywhere, good government. If it be im- probable, yet it is not unthinkable that, as in many coun- tries impatience with tangible substituted democracy for or , a like impatience might some- ^ day reverse the process."

Three years later Mussolini marched on Rome, and

Italy became the first of the bigger democracies "to re-j, verse the process." In retrospect we can now see that what Lord Bryce, writing at the end of the First World War, thought was the pessimism of experience was in fact the intuition of a sensitive and knowing observer. He

had felt in his bones, being too close to the to

perceive it, that a fundamental change in the prospects of democracy was in the making.

There had occurred, I now believe, an unrecognized

revolution within the democratic states. By the third year of the First World War the cumulative losses had be-

come so exorbitant that the institutional order of all the

belligerents gave way under the stress and strain. The

^ James Bryce, Alodern Democracies (1921), Vol. I, p. 42. 8 THE DECLINE OF THE WEST war had become, in Ferrero's telling phrase, hyperbolic, and the prewar governments were incapable of imposing-^ such unlimited drafts upon the endurance and the loyal-> ties of the people. In the defeated countries the price ^of this was revolution against the established order. The Romanoff, the Hohenzollern, the Hapsburg and the Otto- man Empires collapsed. In the victorious countries insti- tutions were not overthrown, rulers were not exiled, im- prisoned or executed. But the constitutional order was altered subtly and yet radically, within itself.

3. Internal Revolution in the Democracies

A VIGOROUS critic of democracy. Sir Henry Maine, writ- ing in 1884 just as England was about to adopt general manhood suffrage, observed that "there could be no grosser mistake" than the impression that "Democracy differs from Monarchy in essence." For "the tests of suc- cess in the performance of the necessary and natural duties of a government are precisely the same in both cases." ^ These natural and necessary duties have to do with the defense and advancement abroad of the vital interests of the state and with its order, security, and solvency at home. Invariably these duties call for hard decisions. They are hard because the governors of the state must tax, conscript, command, prohibit; they must assert a public interest against private inclination and against what is easy and popular. If they are to do their

'Sir Henry Maine, Popular Government (1886), pp. 60-61. THE OBSCURE REVOLUTION 9 duty, they must often swim against the tides of private feeHng.

The hardness of governing was little realized in the early 1900's. For more than half a century, while democ- racy was making its historic advance, there had been a remarkable interlude during which the governments rarely had to make hard decisions. Since Waterloo there had been no world war, and after the American Civil

War only a few short and localized wars. It was a time of expansion, development, liberation; there were new con- tinents to be colonized and there was a new industrial system to be developed. It seemed as though mankind had outlived the tempests of history. The governments — which were increasingly democratic, liberal and hu- mane — were spared the necessity of dealing with the hard issues of war and peace, of security and solvency, of constitutional order and revolution. They could be con- cerned with improvements, with the more and more and the better and better. was secure, liberty was assured, and the way was open to the pursuit of private . In this long peace, the liberals became habituated to the notion that in a free and progressive society it is a good thing that the government should be weak. For several gen- erations the West had flourished under governments that did not have to prove their strength by making the hard decisions. It had been possible to dream, without being rudely awakened, that in the rivalry of the diverse in- terests all would somehow come out for the best. The government could normally be neutral and for the most part it could avoid making positive judgments of good and bad and of right and wrong. The public interest lO THE DECLINE OF THE WEST could be equated with that which was revealed in election returns, in sales reports, balance sheets, circulation figures, and statistics of expansion. As long as peace could be taken for granted, the public good could be thought of as being immanent in the aggregate of private trans- actions. There was no need for a governing power which transcended the particular interests and kept them in order by ruling over them.

All this was only, as we now know, a daydream during a brief spell of exceptionally fine weather. The dream ended with the outbreak of the First World War. Then we knew that the Age of Progress had not reformed the

human condition of diversity and conflict; it had not miti- gated the violence of the struggle for survival and domination.

In fact, the violence was intensified and extended as never before. The expansion and development during the

peaceful decades had wrought, as Graham Wallas pointed out on the eve of the war, "a general change of social scale," ^ and that change of scale had revolutionary con- sequences. The forty years which separated the Franco- Prussian War from the First World War were, says John

U. Nef, "in terms of material welfare . . . the most

successful years in history ... In little more than one generation the world's population grew by almost as

much as it had grown during the untold generations

which separate Adam, the first man, from Newton, the

first man of of the seventeenth century. According to the enterprising calculations of Golin Clark, the real income per person gainfully employed improved 75 per

* Graham Wallas, The Great Society, Ch. I. THE OBSCURE REVOLUTION II cent or more from 1870 to 19 14, while the hours of work were substantially reduced in the wealthier coun- ^ tries of Western Europe . . . and in North America." Because of the increase in the population, in the vol- ume of production, and in the destructiveness of v/eapons, the war which brought to an end the Age of Progress had, says Nef, "none of the limiting features of the warfare which had been characteristic of Newton's age. Europe could now afford enormous armies, could replenish and supply them again while the fighting proceeded. More money was needed to kill than ever before, but the money required turned out to be small in comparison with the money that could be raised (with the help of refined ad- vances in the use and manipulation of credit), and in relation to the quantity of munitions which money and credit could buy." All this meant that when war broke out again, the advanced nations had become, as Nickerson says, "capable of sacrifices so irrationally great that the bleeding victor would faint upon the corpse of his vic- tim." "^

The strain of the war worked up a menacing popular pressure upon the weak governments. We can, I think, point to 1 9 17 as the year when the pressure became so strong that the institutional framework of the established governments broke undds: it.

^ John U. Nef, War and Human Progress, Ch. i8. * "In the military massacres of 1914-1915-1916 the French had lost permanently over 900,000 men, the British about half that number, and the Germans well over 800,000 . . . the Russians had mobilized 12,000,- 000 men and of them at least four million are presumed to have died, another 2,500,000 had become prisoners or were missing and an addi- tional million were seriously wounded." Hoffman Nickerson, The Armed Horde (1940), pp. 292-294. 12 THE DECLINE OF THE WEST

The strain became unbearable. 1 9 1 7 was the year of the two Russian . It was the year of the American

involvement which brought with it the declaration of the

Wilsonian . For Italy it was the year of Caporetto.

For Austria-Hungary it was the beginning of the end under the successor of Francis Joseph. For Germany it was the year of the July crisis and of the need of the Prussian mon- archy to listen to the Reichstag and its demand for a negotiated peace. For France it was the year of the mu- tinies, and for Britain the year of mortal peril from the submarine. In eastern and central Europe tortured and in- furiated masses brought down the historic states and the institutions of the old regime. In western Europe and in North America the breakthrough took the form — if

I may use the term — of a deep and pervasive infiltration.

Behind the fagade, which was little changed, the old structure of executive government with the consent of a representative assembly was dismantled — not every- where and not in all fields, but where it mattered the most — in the making of high policy for war and peace.

The existing governments had exhausted their impe- rium — their authority to bind and their power to com- mand. With their traditional means they were no longer able to carry on the hyperbolic war; yet they were unable to negotiate peace. They had, therefore, to turn to the people. They had to ask still greater exertions and sacri- fices. They obtained them by "democratizing" the conduct and the aims of the war: by pursuing total victory and by promising total peace. In substance they ceded the executive power of decision THE OBSCURE REVOLUTION I3 over the strategical and the poHtical conditions for con- cluding the war. In effect they lost control of the war.

This revolution appeared to be a cession of power to the .

representative assemblies, and when it happened it was j acclaimed as promising the end of the evils of secret diplomacy and the undemocratic conduct of unpopular wars. In fact, the powers which were ceded by the execu- tive passed through the assemblies, which could not ex- ercise them, to the mass of voters who, though unable! also to exercise them, passed them on to the party bosses,' the agents of pressure groups, and the magnates of the' new media of mass communications. The consequences were disastrous and revolutionary. -

The democracies became incapacitated to wage war for,

rational ends and to make a peace which would be ob- ^ served or could be enforced.

4. The Paralysis of Governments

Perhaps, before going any further, I should say that I am a liberal democrat and have no wish to disenfranchise my fellow citizens. My hope is that both liberty and de- mocracy can be preserved before the one destroys the . Whether this can be done is the question of our time, what with more than half the world denying and despairing of k. Of one thing we may be sure. If it is to be done at all, we must be uninhibited in our examination of our condition. And since our condition is manifestly connected with grave errors in war and peace that have ,

14 THE DECLINE OF THE WEST

been committed by democratic governments, we must adopt the habit of thinking as plainly about the sovereign

people as we do about the politicians they elect. It will

not do to think poorly of the politicians and to talk with bated breath about the voters. No more than the kings before them should the people be hedged with divinity.

Like all princes and rulers, like all sovereigns, they are

ill-served by flattery and adulation. And they are betrayed

by the servile hypocrisy which tells them that what is

true and what is false, what is right and what is wrong, can be determined by their votes.

If I am right in what I have been saying, there has

developed in this century, a^ functional derangement of

the relationship between the mass of the people and the government. The people have acquired power which they

are incapable of _exercising, and the governments they

elect have lost powers wJTJchjheyLmnst recover if they are to^^govern. What then are the true boundaries of the peo-

ple's power? The answer cannot be simple, tint for a

I rough beginning let us say that the people are able to

givejind to_withhold their consent to being^overried —

\ their consent to what the government asks of^hem, pro-

to in of their poses them , and has done the conduct

I ^affairs. They can elect the government. They can remove

1 k. They can approve or disapprove its_performance. Biit they cannot administer the governinent. They cannot

( themselves perform. They~carmot normally initiate and

' propose the necessary legislation. A niass cannot govern. The people, as Jefferson said, areTToT^'qualifiedrlio exer-

cise themselves the Executive Department; but they are

qualified joname the person who shaLLexercise it ^-^..- 5^^ THE OBSCURE REVOLUTION 15

They are not qualified to legislate; with us therefore they only choose the legislators." ' ^ Where mass opinion dpminate^s _tLe .government, there is a morbid derangement of the true functions of ^ower. The derangement brings abouLthe enfeeblement,. verging on paralysis, of the capacity to govern. This breakdown in the constitutional order is the cause of the precipitate ajid^catastrophic dec l ine of Western society. I t may, i f it carmQLbfi..-ai:i"£Sted.-aniL tevexsecL^ing about the fall of the West. The propensity to this derangement and the vulner- ability of our society to it have a long and complex his- tory. Yet the more I have brooded upon the events which

I have lived through myself, the more astounding and significant does it seem that the decline of the power andv influence and self-confidence of the Western democracies has been so steep and so sudden. We have fallen far in a. short span of time. However long the underlying erosion had been going on, we were still a great and powerful and flourishing community when the First World War

began. What we have seen is not only decay — though much of the old structure was dissolving — but some- thing which can be called an historic catastrophe.

'' Works (Ford ed. V, pp. 103-104, 1892-1898) cited in Yves IL Simon, Philosophy of Democratic Government (1951), p. 169. CHAPTER II The Malady of Democratic States

I. Public Opinion in War and Peace

Writing in 191 3, just before the outbreak of the war, and having in mind Queen Victoria and King Edward the VII, Sir Harry Johnston thus described how foreign affairs were conducted in the Nineteenth Century:

In those days, a country's relations with its neighbors or with distant lands were dealt with almost exclusively by the head of the State — Emperor, King, or President — acting with the more- or-less dependent Minister-of-State, who was no representative of the masses, but the employe of the Monarch. Events were prepared and sprung on a submissive, a confident, or a stupid people. The public Press criticized, more often applauded, but had at most to deal with a fait accompli and make the best of it. Occasionally, in our own land, a statesman, out of office and dis- contented, went round the great provincial towns agitating against the trend of British foreign policy — perhaps wisely, perhaps unfairly, we do not yet know — and scored a slight success. But once in office, his Cabinet fell in by degrees with the views of the

Sovereign and the permanent officials (after the fifties of the last century these public servants were a factor of ever-grov/ing im- portance); and, as before, the foreign policy of the Empire was shaped by a small camarilla consisting of the Sovereign, two Cabinet Ministers, the permanent Under-Secretary of State for THE DEMOCRATIC MALADY 17

Foreign Affairs, and perhaps one representative of la plus haute finance}

Without taking it too literally, this is a fair description of how foreign affairs were conducted before the First World War. There were exceptions. The Aberdeen gov- ernment, for example, was overthrown in 1855 because of its inefficient conduct of the Crimean War. But gen- erally speaking, the elected parliaments were little con- sulted in the deliberations which led up to war, or on the high strategy of the war, on the terms of the armistice, on the conditions of peace. Even their right to be in- formed was severely limited, and the of the system was, one might say, that war and peace were the business of the executive department. The power of deci-/ sion was not in, was not even shared with, the House of Commons, the Chamber of Deputies, the Reichstag.

The United States was, of course, a special case. The 1 Congress has always had constitutional rights to advise and to be consulted in the declaration of war and in the ratification of treaties. But at the time I am talking about, that is to say before the First World War broke out, it was American policy to abstain from the role of a great power, and to limit its sphere of vital interests to the

Western Hemisphere and the North Pacific Ocean. Only iiLISiiiiidjhe American constitutional system for deal- ing with_foreign_affairs become involved with the conduct _ of world affairs.

For the which I outlined in the first chapter

^ Sir Harry Johnston, "Common Sense in Foreign Policy," pp. 1-2, cited in Howard Lee McBain & Lindsay Rogers, The New of

'?e (1922), p. 139. l8 THE DECLINE OF THE WEST this system of executive responsibility broke down during the war, and from 19 17 on the conduct of the war and then the conditions of the armistice and the peace were subjected to the dominating impact of mass opinions.

Saying this does not mean that the great mass of the people have had strong opinions about the whole range of complex issues which were before the military staffs and the foreign offices. The action of mass opinion has not been, and in the nature of things could not be, con- tinuous through the successive phases in which affairs de- velop. Action has been discontinuous. Usually it has been a massive negative imposed at critical junctures when a new general course of policy needed to be set. There have, of course, been periods of apathy and of indiffer- ence. But democratic politicians have preferred to shun foresight about troublesome changes to come, knowing that the massive veto was latent, and that it would be expensive to them and to their party if they provoked it.

In the winter of 191 8— 191 9, for example, Lloyd

George, Clemenceau, Wilson and Orlando were at a criti- cal juncture of modern history. The Germans were de- feated, their government was overthrown, their troops disarmed and disbanded. The Allies were called upon to decide whether they would dictate a punitive peace or would negotiate a peace of reconciliation. In the Thirties the British and the French governments had to decide whether to rearm and to take concerted measures to contain Hitler and Mussolini or whether to remain unarmed and to appease them. The United States had to decide whether to arm in order to contain the THE DEMOCRATIC MALADY 19

Japanese or to negotiate with them at the expense of China. During the Second World War the British and the American governments had again to make the choice be- tween total victory with unconditional surrender and ne- gotiated settlements whose end was reconciliation.

These were momentous issues, like choosing at the fork of the road a way from which there is no turning back: whether to arm or not to arm — whether, as a conflict blows up, to intervene or to withdraw — whether in war to fight for the unconditional surrender of the adversary or for his reconciliation. The issues are so momentous that public feeling quickly becomes incandes- cent to them. But they can be answered with the only words that a great mass qua mass can speak — with a Yes or a No. Experience since 1917 indicates that in of war and peace the popular answer in the democracies is likely to be No. For everything connected with war has become dangerous, painful, disagreeable and exhausting to very nearly everyone. The rule to which there are few excep- tions — the acceptance of the Marshall Plan is one of them

— is that at the critical junctures, when the stakes are high, the prevailing mass opinion will impose what amounts to a veto upon changing the course on which the government is at the time proceeding. Prepare for war in time of peace? No. It is bad to raise taxes, to un- balance the budget, to take men away from their schools or their jobs, to provoke the enemy. Intervene in a developing conflict? No. Avoid the risk of war. Withdraw from the area of the conflict? No. The adversary must not 20 THE DECLINE OF THE WEST be appeased. Reduce your claims on the area? No. Right- eousness cannot be compromised. Negotiate a com- promise peace as soon as the opportunity presents itself? No. The aggressor must be punished. Remain armed to enforce the dictated settlement? No. The war is over.

The unhappy is that the prevailing public opinion has been destructively wrong at the critical junctures. The people have imposed a veto upon the judgments of in- formed and responsible officials. They have compelled the governments, which usually knew what would have been wiser, or was necessary, or was more expedient, to be too late with too little, or too long with too much, too pacifist in peace and too bellicose in war, too neutralist or appeasing in negotiation or too intransigent. Mass opin- ion has acquired mounting power in this century. It has shown itself to be a dangerous master of decisions when the stakes are life and death.

2. The Compulsion to Make Mistakes

The errors of public opinion in these matters have a common characteristic. The movement of opinion is slower than the movement of events. Because of that, the cycle of subjective sentiments on war and peace is usually out of gear with the cycle of objective develop- ments. Just because they are mass opinions there is an inertia in them. It takes much longer to change many minds than to change a few. It takes time to inform and

to persuade and to arouse large scattered varied multi- tudes of persons. So before the multitude have caught up THE DEMOCRATIC MALADY 21 with the old events there are hkely to be new ones com- ing up over the horizon with which the government should be preparing to deal. But the majority will be more aware of what they have just caught up with near at hand than with what is still distant and in the future. For these reasons the propensity to say No to a change of course sets up a compulsion to make mistakes. The opinion deals with a situation which no longer exists. When the world wars came, the people of the liberal democracies could not be aroused to the exertions and the sacrifices of the struggle until they had been frightened by the opening disasters, had been incited to passionate hatred, and had become intoxicated with un- limited hope. To overcome this inertia the enemy had to be portrayed as incarnate, as absolute and congeni- tal wickedness. The people wanted to be told that when

this particular enemy had been forced to unconditional surrender, they would re-enter the golden age. This

unique war would end all wars. This last war would make the world safe for democracy. This crusade would make the whole world a democracy.

As a result of this impassioned nonsense public opin-. ion became so envenomed that the people would not countenance a workable peace; they were against any public man who showed "any tenderness for the Hun," ^ or was inclined to listen to the "Hun food snivel."

^ Cf. Harold Nicolson, Peace>naking. Chap. III. 22 THE DECLINE OF THE WEST

3. The Pattern of the Mistakes

In order to see in its true perspective what happened, we must remember that at the end of the First World War the only victorious powers were the liberal democ- racies of the West. Lenin, who had been a refugee in

Switzerland until 19 17, was still at the very beginning of his struggle to become the master of the empire of the Romanoffs. Mussolini was an obscure journalist, and nobody had dreamed of Hitler. The men who took part in the Peace Conference were men of the same standards and tradition. They were the heads of duly elected gov- ernments in countries where respect for civil liberty was the rule. Europe from the Atlantic to the Pripet Mafshes

lay within the military orbit of their forces. All the un- democratic empires, enemy and ally, had been destroyed by defeat and revolution. In 1918 — unlike 1945 — there had been no Yalta, there was no alien foreign min-

ister at the peace conference who held a veto on the settle- ment.

Yet as soon as the terms of the settlement were known,

it was evident that peace had not been made with Ger-

many. It was not for want of power but for want of

statesmanship that the liberal democracies failed. They

failed to restore order in that great part of the world

which — outside of revolutionary Russia — was still

within the orbit of their influence, still amenable to their

leadership, still subject to their decisions, still working

within the same economy, still living in the same inter-

national com,munity, still thinking in the same universe

of discourse. In this failure to make peace there was gen- THE DEMOCRATIC MALADY 23 erated the cycle of wars in which the West has suffered so sudden and so spectacular a decline. Public opinion, having vetoed reconciliation, had made the settlement unworkable. And so when a new genera- tion of Germans grew up, they rebelled. But by that time the Western democracies, so recently too warlike to make peace with the unarmed German Republic, had become too pacifist to take the risks which could have prevented the war Hitler was announcing he would wage against Europe. Having refused the risk of trying to pre- vent war, they would not now prepare for the war. The European democracies chose to rely on the double nega- tive of unarmed appeasement, and the American democ- racy chose to rely on unarmed isolation. When the unprevented war came, the fatal cycle was repeated. Western Europe was defeated and occupied be- fore the British people began seriously to wage the war. And after the catastrophe in Western Europe eighteen agonizing months of indecision elapsed before the sur- prise and shock of Pearl Harbor did for the American people what no amount of argument and evidence and reason had been able to do.

Once again it seemed impossible to wage the war energetically except by inciting the people to paroxysms of hatred and to Utopian dreams. So they were told that the Four Freedoms would be established everywhere, once the incurably bad Germans and the incurably bad

Japanese had been forced to surrender unconditionally.

The war could be popular only if the enemy was altogether evil and the Allies very nearly perfect. This mixture of envenomed hatred and furious righteousness 24 THE DECLINE OF THE WEST

made a public opinion which would not tolerate the cal- culated compromises that durable settlements demand. Once again the people were drugged by the

which had aroused them to fight the war and to endure

its miseries. Once again they would not think, once again

they would not allow their leaders to think, about

an eventual peace with their enemies, or about the dif-

ferences that must arise among the Allies in this coalition,

as in all earlier ones. How well this popular diplomacy

worked is attested by the fact that less than five years after the democracies had disarmed their enemies, they were imploring their former enemies, Germany and Japan, to rearm. '' The record shows that the people of the democracies,

having become sovereign in this century, have made it

increasingly difficult for their governments to prepare

properly for war or to make peace. Their responsible I officials have been like the ministers of an opinionated

and willful despot. Between the critical junctures, when public opinion has been inattentive or not vehemently

aroused, responsible officials have often been able to cir-

cumvent extremist popular opinions and to wheedle their

way towards moderation and good sense. In the crises,

however, democratic ofi&cials — over and above their own human propensity to err — have been compelled to make the big mistakes that public opinion has insisted upon. Even the greatest men have not been able to turn back

the massive tides of opinion and of sentiment.

There is no mystery about why there is such a tendency

for popular opinion to be wrong in judging war and

peace. Strategic and diplomatic decisions call for a kind THE DEMOCRATIC MALADY 25

of — not to speak of an experience and a seasoned judgment — which cannot be had by glancing

at newspapers, listening to snatches of radio comment,

watching politicians perform on television, hearing oc-

casional lectures, and reading a few books. It would not be enough to make a man competent to decide whether

to amputate a leg, and it is not enough to qualify him to

choose war or peace, to arm or not to arm, to intervene

or to withdraw, to fight on or to negotiate.

Usually, moreover, when the decision is critical and urgent, the public will not be told the whole truth. What

can be told to the great public it will not hear in the

complicated and qualified concreteness that is needed for a practical decision. When distant and unfamiliar and complex things are communicated to great masses of people, the truth suffers a considerable and often a radical distortion. The complex is made over into the simple, the hypothetical into the dogmatic, and the relative into an absolute. Even when there is no deliberate distortion by censorship and propaganda, which is unlikely in time of war, the public opinion of masses cannot be counted upon to apprehend regularly and promptly the reality of things. There is an inherent tendency in opinion to feed upon rumors excited by our own wishes and fears.

4. Democratic Politicians

At THE critical moments in this sad history, there have been men, worth listening to, who warned the peonle against their mistakes. Always, too, there have been men 26 THE DECLINE OF THE WEST inside the governments who judged correctly, because they were permitted to know in time, the uncensored and unvarnished truth. But the chmate of modern de- mocracy does not usually inspire them to speak out. For what Churchill did in the Thirties before Munich was exceptional: the general rule is that a democratic politi- cian had better not be rigEFloo^joon. Very_often th e penalty is political d^ath. It is much safer to keep in stepwith_the parade of opinion than to try_to,^ggpZHP with the sw i fter movement of events.

In government offices which are sensitive to the vehe- mence and passion of mass sentiment public men have no sure tenure. They are in effect perpetual office seekers, always on trial for their political , always required to court their restless constituents. They are deprived of their independence. Democratic politicians rarely feel they can afford the luxury of telling the whole truth to the people.^ And si nce not telling it, though prudent, ^ ii-n.n'""'^fo '' fable. they find iL_£asier if they themselves do not have to hear too often joo mjicti_o£j:he_SQur_truth. The men under them who X£part.^iKL collect the news

CQme-,10 xgalize in their turn that it is safer to be wrong before it has become fashionable to be^jnght.

" "As we look over the list of the early leaders of the republic, Washing- ton, John Adams, Hamilton, and others, we discern that they were all men who insisted upon being themselves and who refused to truckle to the people. With each succeeding generation, the growing demand of the peo- ple that its elective officials shall not lead but merely register the popular will has steadily undermined the independence of those who derive their power from popular election. The persistent refusal of the Adamses to sacrifice the integrity of their own and moral standards and values for the sake of winning public office or popular favor is another of the measuring rods by which we may measure the divergence of American life from its starting point." James Truslow Adams, The Adams (1930), p. 95. THE DEMOCRATIC MALADY 27

With exceptions so rare that they are regarded as miracles and freaks of nature, successful democratic poli- ticians are insecure and intimidated men. They advance politically only as they placate, appease, bribe, seduce, bamboozle, or otherwise manage to manipulate the de- manding and threatening elements in their constituen- cies. The decisive consideration is not whether the propo- sjtion^ is good Jrut whetjier k is popular — not whether it will work well and prove itself but whether the active

talking constituents like it immediately. Politicians ration- > ,^ alize this servitude by saying that in a democracy public I men are the servants of the people.

This devitalization of the governing power is the t rnalady of democratic states. A s the malady grows the executives become highly susceptible to encroachment and usurpation by elected assemb lies; they are prgssed. and harassed by the higgling of parties, by the agents of organized interests, and by the spokesmenof sectarians anHfldeorogues. The malady "l^n be fatal7~Tr~carr~be deadly to the very survival of the state as a free society if, when the great and hard issues of war and peace, of. security and solvency, of revolution and order are up for decision, the executive and judicial departments, with their civil servants and technicians, have lost their power to decide. CHAPTER III The Derangement of Powers

I. The Governors and the Governed

When I describe the malady of democratic states as a (derangement in the relation between the mass of the people and the government, 1 am, of course, implying that there is a sound relationship arid that we should be able to know what it is. We must now examine this as- sumption. We are looking into the relation between, on the one hand, the governing or executive power, and, on the_ other hand, the elected assembly and the voters in the constituencies. The best place to begin is in the simple beginnings of our constitutional development — in the medieval English Parliament — before the essential func- tions and their relation had become complicated by their later development. No relationship, sound or unsound, could exist until the functions of execution and representation had become,' differentiated. In primitive they are not differ-i entiated. Under the Norman and Angevin rulers the dif- ferentiation had not yet occurred. These rulers "judged and legislated as well as administered." ^ But by the thir- teenth century the differentiation is already visible, and

^ A. F. Pollard, The of Parliament (1926), p. 240. ^ "

DERANGEMENT OF POWERS 29

the essential relation in which we are interested can be

recognized. There is a writ issued under Henry III in 1254, summoning Parliament. The sheriff of each

county is ordered to "cause to come before the King's Council two good and discreet Knights of the Shire,

whom the men of the county shall have chosen for this

purpose in the stead of all and of each of them, to con-

sider along with knights of other shires what aid they " will grant the King."

Let us note the dualism. There is the government,

which means the King and his Council of prelates and peers. Then there are the Knights of the Shires, repre-

senting the men of the counties. They are to meet, and

the King will ask the Knights what aid they will grant to

him. This is the basic relationship. The government can

act. Because it can act, it decides what action should be

taken, and it proposes the measures; it then asks the rep- resentatives of those who must supply the money and the

men for the means to carry out its decisions. The gov- erned, through their representatives, the two Knights of

the Shire from each county, give or withhold their con-

sent.

From the tension and the balance of the two powers j,. — that of the ruler and that of the ruled — there evolved the written and the unwritten contracts of the constitu-

tion. The grant of aid by the ruled must be preceded by

the ruler's redress of their grievances. The government

will be refused the means of governing if it does not

listen to the petitions, if it does not inform, if it does not

^Encyclopedia Britannica (1952), Vol. 19, p. 164, article "Representa- tion." 30 THE DECLINE OF THE WEST

consult, if it cannot win the consent of, those who have been elected as the representatives of the governed.

The executive active state, , ^ isthe power in the the

asking and the proposing power. The representative as-

sembly is the consenting power, the petitioning, the ap- proving and the criticizing, the accepting and the refusing

powe r. The two powers are necessary if there is to be

order and freedom. But each must be true to its own nature, each limiting and complementing the other. The government must be able to govern and the citizens must be represented in order that they shall not be oppressed. The health of the system depends upon the relation-

ship of the two powers. If either absorbs or destroys

the functions of the other power, the is de- ranged.

There is here a relationship between governors and

governed which is, I would contend, rooted in the nature

of things. At the risk of reasoning by analogy, I would

suggest that this duality of function within a political

society has a certain resemblance to that of the two sexes. In the act of reproduction each sex has an unalterable

physiological function. If this function is devitalized or is

confused with the function of the other sex, the result is

sterility and disorder.

In the final acts of the state the issues are war and peace, security and solvency, order and insurrection. In

these final acts the executive power cannot be exercised

by the representative assembly. Nor can it be exercised

after the suppression of the assembly. For in the derange-

ment of the two primary functions lie the seeds of dis-

aster. DERANGEMENT OF POWERS 3I

2. The People and the Voters

A RECENT historian of the Tudor Revolution, Mr. G. R.

Elton, says that "our history is still much written by whigs, the champions of political freedom," and that "while the safeguards against have long been understood and often described, — strong rule, prevent- ing anarchy and preserving order, requires still much exploration." There have been periods, he goes on to say, of which the Tudor Age was one — and our own, we may add, is another — when men were so ready to be governed, being so oppressed by disorder, that they have preferred strong government to free gov- ernment.

The Western liberal democracies are a declining power in human affairs. I argue that this is due to a, derangement of the functions of their governments which disables them in coping with the mounting disorder. I do not say, indeed it is impossible to know surely, whether the malady can be cured or whether it must run its course.

But I do say that if it cannot be cured, it will continue to erode the safeguards against despotism, and the failure of the West may be such that freedom will be lost and will not be restored again except by another revolution. But for either contingency, for cure now or for recovery after a catastrophe, our first necessity is to work towards an adequate knowledge of the two functions, their na- ture, and their derangement.

In order to do so it is necessary at the outset to reduce the ambiguity of the term "the people." For it has two different meanings, which it mav be convenient to dis- ;

32 THE DECLINE OF THE WEST tinguish typographically. When we speak of popular sovereignty, we must know whether we are talking about The People, as voters, or about The People, as a com- munity of the entire living population, with their prede- cessors and successors.

It is often assumed, but without warrant, that the opin- ions of The People as voters can be treated as the ex- pression of the interests of The People as an historic ' community. The crucial problem of modern democracy arises from the fact that this assumption is false. The voters cannot be relied upon to represent The People.

The opinions of voters in elections are not to be accepted^ unquestioningly as true judgments of the vital interests of the community. To whom, for example, did the Preamble of the Con- stitution refer when it said that "We, the People of the

United States . . . ordain and establish this Constitu- tion"? On September 17, 1787, about forty members signed the draft on which they had been working since May 25, for one hundred and sixteen days. In Article

VII of their text they stipulated that if and when con- ventions in nine states had ratified it, then for those nine states The People of the United States would have or- dained and established the Constitution. In this context

a majority of the delegates elected to nine state con- ventions were deemed to be entitled to act as The People of the United States. The inhabitants of the United States who were quali-

fied to vote for these delegates were not a large number.

They included no slaves, no women and, except in New York, only such adult males as could pass property and DERANGEMENT OF POWERS 33

Other highly restrictive tests. We do not have accurate figures. But according to the census of 1790 the popula- tion was 3,929,782. Of these, 3,200,000 were free persons and the adult males among them who were entitled to vote

are estimated to have been less than 500,000. Using the

Massachusetts figures as a statistical sample, it may be assumed that less than 160,000 actually voted for delegates to all the ratifying conventions; and of those voting, per- haps 100,000 favored the adoption of the Constitution.^

The exact figures do not . The point is that the voters were not — and we may add that they have never been and can never be — more than a fraction of the

total population. They were less than 5 per cent when the Constitution was ordained. They were not yet 40 per cent in 1952 when, except under the special conditions in the South, we had universal adult suffrage. Manifestly, the voters can never be equal to the whole population, even to the whole living adult population.

Because of the discrepancy between The People as' voters and The People as the corporate nation, the voters have no title to consider themselves the proprietors o f the commonwealth and to claim that their interests are identi- cal with the public interest. A prevailing plurality of the voters are not The People. The claim that they are is a

^ These figures are from a memorandum prepared for me by my friend, Prof. Allan Nevins. In his covering letter, January 24, 1952, he says: "Anyone who writes about election figures in our early national history treads upon very unsafe ground. Trustworthy data—the statistics and the general information—are too scanty for any explicit statement of detailed conclusions for the country as a whole. As you will see, I have found fig- ures for various states and localities, but we have no warrant for generaliz- ing them to apply to the country in its entirety. What we can say ivith absolute certainty, I think, is that in these early elections the vote was under 3 per cent of the whole population." 34 THE DECLINE OF THE WEST bogus title invoked to justify the usurpation of the execu- tive power by representative assembhes and the intimida- tion of public men by demagogic politicians. In fact demagoguery can be described as the sleight of hand by. which a faction of The People as voters are invested with the authority of The People. That is why so many crimes_j are committed in the people's name.

There are eminent political philosophers who reject this analytical distinction. Those who are strongly nominalist in their cast of mind, which modern men tend to be, look upon the abstract concept of a corporate people as mere words and rather like conjuring up spooks. Thus, according to that resolute nominalist, Jeremy Bentham,

"the community is a fictitious body, composed of the in- dividual persons who are considered as constituting as it were its members. The interest of the community then is, what? — The sum of the interests of the several mem- ^ bers who compose it."

There is an apparent toughness and empirical matter- of-factness in this statement. But the hard ice is thin. For Bentham has forgotten that "the several members who compose" the community are never identically the same members from one hour to another. If a community were what he says it is, then in theory it should be possible to make a directory of its members, each with his address.

But no such list could ever be compiled. While it was being compiled, new members would be being born and old members would be dying. That is why it makes no sense to describe "The People of the United States" who

'' Jeremy Bentham, The Principles of Morals and Legislation, Ch. I, Sec. IV. DERANGEMENT OF POWERS 35

ordained and established the Constitution as the inhabit- ants of the United States on that particular June 21, 1788, when the Constitution was established and or-

dained. Between sunrise and sunset of that historic day ^

the persons composing The People had changed. In thirty

years they had changed greatly; and in a hundred years,

entirely.

The people, then, is not only, as Bentham assumed, the

aggregate of living persons . The people is also the stream of individuals, the connected generations of changing per- sons, that Burke was talking about when he invoked the partnership "not only between those who are living" but also with "those who are dead, and those who are to be

born." The People are a corporation, an entity, that is to ? <

say, which lives on while individuals come into it and go

out of it .

For this reason Bentham cannot have been right when~^ he said that the interests of the community are no more... than the sum of the interests of the several members who happen to compose it at any particular instant of time. He cannot have been right when he said that "the happiness of the individuals, of whom a community is composed, that is their and their security, is the end and the sole end which the legislator ought to have in view." ""

For besides the happiness and the security of the in- dividuals of whom a community is at any moment com- posed, there are also the happiness and the security of the individuals of whom generation after generation it will be composed. If we think of it in terms of individual persons,

the corporate body of The People is for the most part in-

* Ibid., Ch. Ill, Sec. I. .

36 THE DECLINE OF THE WEST visible and inaudible. Indeed as a whole it is nonexistent, in that so many are dead and so many are not yet born. Yet this corporate being, though so insubstantial to our senses, binds, in Burke's words, a man to his country with

"ties which though light as air, are as strong as links of iron." That is why young men die in battle for their country's sake and why old men plant trees they will never sit under.

This invisible, inaudible, and so largely nonexistent community gives rational meaning to the necessary ob- jectives of government. If we deny it, identifying the peo- ple with the prevailing pluralities who vote in order to serve, as Bentham has it, "their pleasures and their secu- rity," where and what is the nation, and whose duty and business is it to defend the public interest? Bentham leaves us with the state as an arena in which factions con- tend for their immediate advantage in the struggle for survival and domination. Without the invisible and tran- scendent community to bind them, why should they care for posterity? And why should posterity care about them, and about their treaties and their contracts, their commit- ments and their promises? Yet without these engagements to the future, they could not live and work; without these engagements the fabric of society is unraveled and shredded.

'Edmund Burke's speech on Conciliation with America (1775). DERANGEMENT OF POWERS 37

3. The Recently Enfranchised Voters

The doctrine of popular sovereignty is ancient and^' venerable. But until about the second half of the Nine-'

teenth Century, it did not imply the enfranchisement^-^

of the people. When, for example, Charlemagne vv^as

crovv^ned in 800 A.D., the Pope professed to be declaring the will of the people. This has been called the principle

of "virtual representation." ' Those who do not vote be- cause they lack the franchise, or cannot vote because they

are infants or even unborn, are presumed to be repre-

sented by someone like the Pope, the king, the parlia-

ment, speaking in their name. By the coronation of 800 A.D, the empire was being transferred from the Greeks to the Germans. A reason was needed to explain why a German prince, rather than

the Emperor of Byzantium, was to be henceforth the law-

ful successor of the Roman Caesars. The office of emperor was not hereditary, and in any event Charlemagne could have made no claim of kinship; the emperor was not ap- pointed by the Pope; he was chosen by the German princes who belonged to the College of Electors. A doc- trine was necessary which would justify and could compel everyone to believe that Charlemagne was the legitimate successor of Caesar. The publicists of the new empire took for a foundation the accepted theory that "the Imperial power, as successoi to the Imperium of the Roman Caesars, was founded orig-

' The great exponent of "virtual representation" was Burke. Cf. his speech (1784) On the Reform of the Representation of the Commons in Parliament. .

38 THE DECLINE OF THE WEST inally on an act of transference performed by the people in the Lex Regia." ^ They argued that what had happened once at the beginning of the imperial power would have to happen again whenever the throne was vacant. As the imperium "escheats or reverts to the people"; and the people had then to choose a new emperor, they might even "translate" the empire from one nation to another, in this instance from the Greeks to the Germans. Need- less to say, "the people," who were presumed to have this power, had neither votes nor any other means of making their will known. It was presumed that they wished to have their power exercised for them. In the coronation of

Charlemagne, the Pope did this: he 'merely declared and exercised the people's will."

All this seems long ago and far away. But if we reject virtual representation, the question remains: if the Pope or the king, or the parliament of magnates, cannot repre- sent The People, how do a plurality of voters truly de- clare and exercise The People's will? It sounds incongru- ous to modern ears that the Pope should represent the people. But is it so congruous that the people should ben represented by a count of the votes of some persons? The-^ conundrum springs from the fact that while The People as a corporate body are the true owners of the sovereign' power. The People, as an aggregate of voters, have di- verse, conflicting self-centered interests and opinions. K-^ plurality of them cannot be counted upon to represent the-^^ corporate nation.

The distinction upon which I am dwelling does not, as

^ Otto von Gierke, The Development of Political Theory, translated by Bernard Freyd (1939; original first published 1880), p. 92. DERANGEMENT OF POWERS 39 one might suppose, cease to matter when the voters be- come enormously many. Cannot a multitude of voters be regarded as the practical equivalent of all the people?

They cannot be. To multiply the voters makes it no more probable that a plurality of them will truly represent the public interest. Our experience with mass elections in the twentieth century compels us, I think, to the contrary con- clusion: that public opinion becomes less realistic as the mass to whom information must be conveyed, and argu- ment must be addressed, grows larger and more heteroge- neous.

All this will seem less odd if we remind ourselves that political democracy, as we know it in this century, is a very recent political phenomenon. The moral presump- tion in favor of universal suffrage may perhaps be said to have been laid down by the American and the French

Revolutions at the end of the eighteenth century. But (until the end of the nineteenth century) the actual ad- vance towards universal suffrage was in fact spasmodic and slow. In 1900, voters in the United Kingdom were only 1 1 per cent of the population: they were 43 per cent in 1922. The Representation of The People Act in 1918 had very nearly tripled the electorate by simplifying the extremely complex regulations for voting and by extend- ing the suffrage to women thirty years of age and quali- fied as occupants. In France the voters were 27 per cent of the population in the election of 1881; in 195 1 they were 45 per cent. Until the last quarter of the nineteenth century, in most of Western and Northern Europe, the proportion of voters to population was not more than States 5 per cent. In 1890 voters in the United were .

40 THE DECLINE OF THE WEST

about 15 per cent of the population. It has been only since the First World War, owing to the enfranchisement of women and, in some measure, of southern Negroes, that the proportion has risen to over 30 per cent. Large mass electorates are something quite new, much

newer than the ideals, the ideas, the institutions and the

usages of the liberal state. Political orators often assume

that the mass of the people voted their own liberties. But

the fact is that they acquired the vote after they had/-^

acquired their liberties and, in fact, largely because not

being able to vote was felt by free men to be incompatible

with their equal dignity.^ The Bill of Rights (1689) is more than two centuries older than universal suffrage in Great Britain. The enfranchised people did not establish

the rule that all powers are under the law, that must be made, amended and administered by due process, that a legitimate government must have the consent of the governed.

I dwell upon this point because it throws light upon the fact, so disconcerting an experience in this century, that> the enfranchised masses have not, surprisingly enough,-; , been those who have most stanchly defended the institu-..'' tions of freedom. —

" James Bryce, Modern Democracies, Vol. I, Ch. IV. Cf. also John Stuart Mill, Considerations on Representative Government. In On Liberty, Rep- resentative Government, The Subjection of Women (London, Oxford University Press, 1946), Ch. VIII, pp. 272-294. , ,

CHAPTER IV The Public Interest

I. What Is the Public Interest?

We are examining the question of how, and by whom, the interest of an invisible community over a long span of time is represented in the practical work of governing a modern state.

In ordinaxy_cirajinstaiicesjvo^ to j transcend their particular, localized and _self-regarding opinions. As well expect men laboring in the valley to see the land as from a mountain top. In their circumstances, which as private persons they cannot readily surmount, the voters are most likely to suppose that whatever seems ob- viously good to them must be good for the country, and good in the sight of God.

I am far from implying that the voters are not entitled to the representation of their particular opinions and in- terests. But their opinions and interests should be taken-^ for what they are and for no more. They are not — as such — propositions in the public interest. Beyond theic being, if they are genuine, a true report of what various groups of voters are thinking, they have no intrinsic au- thority. The Gallup polls are reports of what people are thinking. But that a plurality of the people sampled in the 42 THE DECLINE OF THE WEST poll think one way has no bearing upon whether it is sound . For their opportunities of judging great issues are in the very nature of things limited, and

the statistical sum of their opinions is not the final verdict/' on an issue. It is, rather, the beginning of the argument. In that argument their opinions need to be confronted by the views of the executive, defending and promoting the public interest. In the accommodation reached between/ the two views lies practical public policy.

Let us ask ourselves. How is the public interest dis- cerned and judged? From what we have been saying we know that we cannot answer the question by attempting to forecast what the invisible community, with all its un- born constituents, will, would, or might say if and when it ever had a chance to vote. There is no point in toying with any notion of an imaginary plebiscite to discover the public interest. We cannot know what we ourselves will be thinking five years hence, much less what infants now in the cradle will be thinking when they go into the poll- ing booth.

Yet their interests, as we observe them today, are within the public interest. Living adults share, we must believe, the same public interest. For them, however, the public interest is mixed with, and is often at odds with, their private and special interests. Put this way, we can say, I suggest, that the public interest may be presumed to , be__whaL,jl£il.,,^ouid_choose if they saw clearly, thought ' rationally, acted disinterestedly andjbenevglently. * ' THE PUBLIC INTEREST 43

2. The Equations of Reality

A RATiONALman^ acting in _the real world may be defined as one who decides where he will strike a balance be- tween what he desires and what can be done. It is only in imaginary worlds that we can do whatever we wish. In the real world there are always equations which have to be adjusted between the possible and the desired. Within limits, a man can make a free choice as to where he will strike the balance. If he makes his living by doing piece- work, he can choose to work harder and to spend more.

He can also choose to work less and to spend less. But he cannot spend more and work less.

Reality confronts us in practical affairs as a long and intricate series of equations. What we are likely to call

"facts of life" are the accounts, the budgets, the orders of battle, the election returns. Sometimes, but not always, the two sides of the equations can be expressed quantitatively in terms of money, as supply and demand, as income and outgo, assets and liabilities, as exports and imports. Valid choices are limited to the question of where, not whether, the opposing terms of the equation are to be brought into equilibrium. For there is always a reckoning.

In public life, for example, the budget may be balanced by reducing expenditures to the revenue from taxes; by raising taxes to meet the expenditures, or by a combina- tion of the two, by borrowing, or by grants in aid from other governments, or by fiat credit, or by a combination of them. In one way or another the budget is in fact al-Ui 'ways balanced. The true nature of the reckoning would-^ be clearer if, instead of talking about "an unbalanced 44 THE DECLINE OF THE WEST budget," we spoke of a budget balanced not by taxes but by borrowing, of a budget balanced by inflation, or of a budget balanced by subsidy. A government which cannot raise enough money by taxes, loans, foreign grants, or by getting its fiat money accepted, will be unable to meet its bills and to pay the salaries of its employees. In bank- ruptcy an involuntary balance is struck for the bankrupt.

He is forced to balance his accounts by reducing his ex- penditures to the level of his income.

Within limits, which public men have to bear in mind, the choices as to where to balance the budget are open. In making these choices, new equations confront them.

Granted that it is possible to bring the budget into bal- ance by raising taxes, how far can taxes be raised? Some- what but not ad infinitum. There are no fixed criteria.

But though we are unable to express all the equations quantitatively, this does not relieve us of the necessity of balancing the equations. There will be a reckoning. Prac- tical judgment requires an informed guess: what will the taxpayers accept readily, what will they accept with grum- bling but with no worse, what will arouse them to resist- ance and to evasion? How will the taxpayers react to the different levels of taxes if it is a time of peace, a time of war, a time of cold war, a time of social and economic disturbance, and so on? Although the various propositions cannot be reduced to precise figures, prudent men make estimates as to where the equations balance.

Their decisions as to where to balance the accounts must reflect other judgments — as to what, for example, are the military requirements in relation to foreign af-

fairs; what is the phase of the business cycle in relation to THE PUBLIC INTEREST 45 the needs for increased or decreased demand; what is the condition of the international monetary accounts; which are tlie necessary public works and welfare measures, and which are those that are desirable but not indispensable.

Each of these judgments is itself the peak of a pyramid of equations: whether, for example, to enlarge or to reduce the national commitments at this or that point in the world — given the effect of the decision at other points in the world.

We may say, then, that public policy is made in a field of equations. The issues are the choices as to where the balance is to be struck. In the reality of things X will ex- act an equivalence of Y. Within the limits which the spe- cific nature of the case permits — limits which have to be estimated — a balance has to be reached by adding to or subtracting from the terms of the equation.

Oftener than not, the two sides of the equation differ in that the one is, as compared with the other, the pleas- anter, the more agreeable, the more popular. In general

the softer and easier side reflects what we desire and the

harder reflects what is needed in order to satisfy the de-

sire. Now the momentous equations of war and peace, of solvency, of security and of order, always have a harder or

a softer, a pleasanter or a more painful, a popular or an

unpopular option. It is easier to obtain votes for appro-

priations than it is for taxes, to facilitate consumption than

to stimulate production, to protect a market than to open

it, to inflate than to deflate, to borrow than to save, to de-

mand than to compromise, to be intransigent than to ne-

gotiate, to threaten war than to prepare for it.

Faced with these choices between the hard and the soft, ' i. 46 THE DECLINE OF THE WEST the normal propensity of democratic governments is to. please the largest number of voters. The pressure of the j"^ electorate is normally for the soft side of the equations.'

That is why governments are unable to cope with reality when elected assemblies and mass opinions become deci- sive in the state, when there are no statesmen to resist the inclination of the voters and there are only politicians to

excite and to exploit them .

There is then a general tendency to be drawn down- ward, as by the force of gravity, towards insolvency, to- wards the insecurity of factionalism, towards the erosion of liberty, and towards hyperbolic wars. CHAPTER V The Tv^o Functions

I. The Elected Executive

Our inquiry has shown, I beheve, that we cannot take j

popular government for granted, as if its principles were, settled and beyond discussion. We are compelled to agree with Sir Henry Maine who wrote, some seventy years ago, that "the actual history of popular government since

it was introduced, in its modern shape, into the civilized

world," does "little to support the assumption that popu-

lar government has an indefinitely long future before it.

Experience rather tends to show that it is characterized i ^

by great fragility, and that since its appearance, all forms'" of government have become more insecure than they

^ were before." We have been dwelling upon the devitalization of thex executive power as the cause of the fragility that Maine

speaks of. It is, I have been saying, the disorder which re-

s ults froma functional_dera£gement_m the relationship

between the executive power on the one hand, the repre-_ sentative assemblies and the mass electorates on the other jiand. Democratic states_arejusceptible to this derangement be-

' Sir Henry Maine, Popular Government (1886), p. 20. •

48 THE DECLINE OF THE WEST

*

-\ ' cause congenitally the executive, when dependent on elec-

'-' ^ tion, is weaker th an the elected' representatives. The normal " — - -^ — . ^ -J drainage of power in a jdenrnrratir ^s tate is away^from the

governing center and_down into the constituencies." And

the normal tendency of elections is to reduce elected of-

ficers to the role of agents of organized pluralities. Mod-

ern democratic governments are, to be sure, big govern-

ments, in their personnel, in the range and variety of

their projects, the ubiquitousness of their interventions.

But to be big is not necessarily to be strong. They are, in

fact, swollen rather than strong, being too weak to resist

the pressure of special interests and of the departmental bureaucracies.

As a rule competition in the electoral market works like Gresham's law: the soft money drives the hard money out of circulation. The competitive odds are heav-

ily against the candidate who, like Burke with the electors

of Bristol, promises to be true to his own best reason and

judgment. The odds are all in favor of the candidate who-

offers himself as the agent, the delegate, the spokesman, the errand boy, of blocs of voters. ^V* -^^^

"Yves R. Simon, Philosophy of Democratic Government, p. 136, quotes Jefferson, Notes on Virginia (Memorial ed.; Washington, 1903), Vol. II, ^ pp. 162-163 (the writer is surveying what he terms the "capital defects of

the constitution") : "All the powers of government, legislative, executive, and judiciary, result to the legislative body. The concentrating these in the

same hands is precisely the of despotic government. It will be no alleviation that these powers will be exercised by a plurality of hands, and not by a single one. One hundred and seventy-three despots would surely be as oppressive as one. Let those who doubt it turn their eyes on the republic of Venice. As little will it avail us that they are chosen by ourselves. An elective despotism was not the government we fought for, but one which should not only be founded on free principles, but in which the powers of government should be so divided and balanced among sev- eral bodies of magistracy, as that no one could transcend their legal limits, without being effectually checked and restrained by the others." THE TWO FUNCTIONS 49

In a modern democratic state, the chief executive office

must be elective. But as heredity, prescrip tijonj^ . cojasecra-

tion, rank and hierarchy are dissplyejd hy.. _the_acids of modernity, the executives become totally^de^endent on election. They have no status and no tenure which rein- force their consciences, which invest them with power to withstand the tides of popular opinion and to defend the public interest.

They hold their offices for a short time, and to do this they must maneuver and manipulate combinations among the factions and the pressure groups. Their policies must be selected and shaped so as to attract and hold together these combinations. There are_ moments, the "finest hours," when communities are lifted above their habitual selves in unity and fellowship. But these moments are rare. They are not the stuff of daily life in a democracy, and they are remembered like a miracle in a dream. In the daily routine of dernocratic politics, elected executives can never for long take their eyes from the mirror of the constituencies. They must not look too much_out_of the window at the realities beyond.

2. The Protection of the Executive

During the nineteenth century good democrats were pri- marily concerned with insuring representation in the as- semblies and with extending the control of the assembliesjr over the executive power. It is true that the problem of the inadequate executive, overridden and dominated by the assembly, was very much in the minds of the Found- 50 THE DECLINE OF THE WEST

ing Fathers at the Philadelphia , and it has

been a continuing concern of the critics and opponents of democracy. But until the twentieth century the problem was not sharply and urgently posed. That there was such

a problem was well known. But it was not the immediate problem.^

For some generations before 19 14, the West enjoyed fine political weather. Moreover, the full force of the coming enfranchisement, emancipation, and secularization

of the whole population had not yet worked its conse-

quences. Governments still had authority and power,

which were independent of the assemblies and the elec-

torates. They still drew upon the traditional sources of au- thority — upon prescription, hereditary prerogative, and consecration.

Yet the need to protect the executive and judicial pow- ers from the representative assemblies and from mass

opinion has long been understood.^ Many expedients havei -^

been devised to soften, to neutralize, to check and to bal-|

ance the pressure of parties, factions, lobbies, sects. The) expedients have taken, says Bryce. two generaH^orms, the

one being^o pu^ constitutional restrictions upon the as -j,

sembly and the other, "by a_diYisionjofj:he whole pow er..

of- the people," to weaken it. This has been done by elect-"^ in ^the legislature and the executive separately, or by hav-

ing the legislative bodies elected by the differing constitu-

encjes andat different times. The constitutional mechanisms have never themselves

'But cf. Woodrow Wilson, Congressional Governmeyit, Ch. 5. * Hamilton, Jay, Madison, The federalist, (Modern Library), No. 48, pp. 322-326; No. 49, pp. 330-332; No. 71, pp. 464-466. ^ James Bryce, Modern Democracies (1921), Vol. II, Ch. LXIII. THE TWO FUNCTIONS 51

been sufficient to protect the executive. And much inven- tion and reforming energy have been appHed to finding ; other ways to insulate the judicial, the executive and the administrative functions from the heavy pressures of "pol-

itics" "politicians." has to separate 4. and The object been 1

them from the electoral process. The judiciary must be in- dependent of fear and favor. There must be no connection

between the judgment of the courts and the election re-

turns. The civil service, the military services, the foreign

service, the scientific and technical services, the quasi- judicial administrative tribunals, the investigating com- missions, the public schools and institutions of learning, should be substantially independent of the elections.

These reforms were inspired by the dire effects of the

spoils system, and they were pushed as practical remedies

for obvious evils.

Yet implicit in them there is a principle which, if it

canbe^pplied deep l y enough, gets at the root ofjhe^ dis-

order of niodern d emocracy. It is that though public of-/^

ficials are elected by the voters, or are appoirued" bylneh ; wEo are elected, they owe their primary allegiance not to

the opinions of the voters but to th^law, to the criteriaof

their professions, to the integrity of the and

In which they work, to their ownconscientious and re-

sponsible convictions oTlheir duty withiri,the rules and the frame of reference_thgy_have sworn to respect.

3. The Voters and the Executive

The implied principle may be defined in other terms by saying that--while jhe electors choose the ruler, they do 52 THE DECLINE OF THE WEST not own any shares in him and they have no right to com-] mand him. His duty^is to the oflEice and not to his electors.

Their duty is to fill the office and not to direct the office-j.; holder. I realize that, as I have stated it, the principle runs counter to the popular view that in a democracy public men are the servants (that is, the agents) of the people

(that is, of the voters). As the game of politics is played, what I am saying must seem at first like a counsel of per- fection.

There are, however, reasons for thinking that it is not an abstract and empty bit of theorizing. One is that until comparatively recent times, it has been the principle on which the election of rulers — lay and spiritual — has usually been carried out. In the early church, says Acts VI, the twelve apostles called the multitude of the disciples to them and said,

"Look ye out among you seven men of honest report, full of the Holy Ghost and , whom we may appoint over this business." When these men had been chosen,

and had prayed, "the apostles . . . laid their hands upon them." Having been ordained, they were not the servants of the multitude who had elected them, but of God. This principle applied to the election of Popes. As

Suarez says, "The Pope is elected by cardinals, yet he re- ceives his powers from God immediately." ^ The same principle applied to elected kings. After the electors had chosen the king, he was crowned and anointed. Then his duty was to his own vows and not to the electors. The act of election did not bind the ruler to the electors. Both par-

° Yves R. Simon, op. cit., p. 174. t

THE TWO FUNCTIONS 53 ties to the transaction were bound only to the office; the electors to designate a king worthy of the office, the king to fill the office worthily.

If we look closely at the matter, we find, I believe, this must be the principle of election when the electors are choosing, not someone to represent them to the govern-

ment, but the governors themselves. Though it is not too well r ecognized, there is a radical difference between the election of an executive and the election of a representa- tive. For while the executive is in honor bound not to^ considerTTTmseTF as the agent -ofJiis-_£lector5^xhe_j:epre-

sentative is expected to be, withinjdie_limits_of reason and , the^general public interest,^ heir agent.^ --'

This distinction has deep roots in the political experi- ence of Western society, and, though unrecognized in principle, it is implicit in our moral judgments. Everyone who has a case in court is entitled, we believe, to be rep- resented by a lawyer who, within the law and the code of professional practice, is expected to be the partisan and advocate of his client. But this presupposes not only that his opponent will be effectively represented too, but that

the case will go to a court where the judge is not an advo-

cate and has no clients. The judge is bound by his judicial vows. The same ethical standards are recognized, though

they are applied less rigorously, in the executive branch of the government. No President or head of a department

could afford to admit that he was using his office to fur-

ther the interests of a client or of a pressure group, or

even of his party. His acts must be presented as taken in obedience to his oath of office, which means taken disin-

''Hamilton, Jay, Madison, op. cit., No. 10, pp. 55-62. 54 THE DECLINE OF THE WEST

terestedly and rationally. He must never in so many words admit that in order to gain votes he sacrificed the public

good, that he played "politics." Often enough he does just

that. fealty to the public interest is his . he But And 1

' ..0 must, at the very least, pay it the homage of hypocrisy. When we move over to the representative assembly,

the image is different, and the ethical rule is applied, if at

all, loosely and lightly. The representative is in some very considerable degree an agent, and the image of his virtue

is rather like that of the lawyer than of the judge. There

are, of course, occasions when he is in fact the holder of

one of the great offices of state — as when he must speak and vote on a declaration of war and the ratification of a

treaty. But in the general run of the mundane business

which comes before the assembly, he is entitled, indeed

he is in duty bound, to keep close to the interests and sen-

timents of his constitutents, and, within reasonable limits,

to do what he can to support them. For it is indispensable-]

to the freedom and the order of a civilized state that the voters should be effectively represented. But representation^'

must not be confused with governing. '

4. The Enfeebled Executive

In the effort to understand the malady of democratic

government I have dwelt upon the underlying duality of [functions: goyeri]mg^^Ci2it is^^^^^ of the

l legislating, 1 aws and the initiative in and representm^jhe

living persons who are governed, who must pay , who THE TWO FUNCTIONS 55 f^ must work, who must fi,a:ht and, it may be, die for the acts of the ,governm_ent. I attribute the democratic disas-

ter of the twentieth century to a derangement of these primary functions. ^^^ / The power of the executive has become enfeebled, V often to the verge of impotence, by the pressures of the representative assembly and of mass opinions. This de- rangement of the governing power has forced the demo-

cratic states to commit disastrous and, it could be, fatal

mistakes. It has also transformed the assemblies in most,

perhaps not in all, democratic states from the defenders of local and personal rights into boss-ridden ,

threatening the security, the solvency, and the liberties of

the state.

In the traditions of Western society, civilized govern-

ment is founded on the assumption that the two powers H exercising the two functions will be in balance — that

they will check, restrain, compensate, complement, in-

form and vitalize each one the other.

In this century, the balance of the two powers has beenL seriously upset. Two great streams of evolution have con-

verged upon the modern _demQ'''''arip.'s m dpyifgliTP^jr^pn-

feeble, and to eviscerate the executive^ower^ ' One is the -^ enormous expansion of public_expenditure, chiefly for war

and reconstruction; this has augmented^ the power of_the assemblies which vote the appropriations on which the ex- ecutive depends. The_other_develQpment which has acted to enfeeble the executive powec^^g^he growing incapacity ,,

'^ of the large maj ority of the democratic peoples to believe t

in intangible realities. This has stripped the government

' of that imponderable authority which is derived from tra- 56 THE DECLINE OF THE WEST dition, immemorial usage, consecration, veneration, pre- scription, prestige, heredity, hierarchy. At the beginning of our constitutional development the King, when he had mastered the great barons, was the proprietor of the greatest wealth in the realm. The crown was also the point from which radiated the imponderable powers to bind and to command. As the King needed money and men for his wars, he summoned representa- tives of the counties and the boroughs, who had the money and the men he needed. But the imponderable powers, together with very considerable power in land and in men, were still in the King's own hands. Gradu- ally, over the centuries, the power of the Parliament over the supplies of the government grew larger. They had to appropriate a larger proportion of a much greater total. At- the same time, in the white light of the enlightenment and the secularization of men's minds, the imponderable,

powers of the crown diminished. "I

Under the stress and the strain of the great wars of the, twentieth century, the executive power has become elabo-L rarely dependent upon the assemblies for its enormous ex-' penditures of men and of money. The executive has, at the same time, been deprived of very nearly all of his im- ponderable power: fearing the action of the representa- tive assembly, he is under great temptation to outwit it or\ bypass it, as did Franklin D. Roosevelt in the period of^'^ the Second World War. It is significant, I think, certainly W^ uV'^ it is at least suggestive, that while nearly all the Western "^ governments have been in deep trouble since the First World War, the constitutional of Scandina- via, the Low Countries, and the United Kingdom have THE TWO FUNCTIONS 57 shown greater capacity to endure, to preserve order with freedom, than the repubhcs of France, Germany, Spain and Italy. In some measure that may be because in a re- pubhc the governing power, being wholly secularized, loses its prestige; is stripped, if prefers, of much of k one _, ^ , '.'^j.' ^^'"^ all the illusiQns,..Q£inixiiisic majesty. -/^-T^^uj^m '^ 'i'^ '^,^ The evaporatIon_ o£jbe. imponderabJe_powers, a total -,\ Uw^^^^ dependence upon the assemblies and the mass electorates,"^^ ' ^^>- has upset the balance of powers between the two func- ^^^,,^''~ tions of the state. The executive has lost both its material ^^""'C^^ mU and its ethereal powers. The assemblies and the mass elep* u torates have acquired the monopoly of effective powers.] J\

This is the internal revolution which has deranged the, ' constitutional system of the liberal democratic states. ^ L CHAPTER VI The Totalitarian Counterrevolution

I . Certain of Its Lessons

We can learn something about the kind of incapacity which has brought on disaster for the modern democracies by the nature of the counterrevolutions that have under- mined and overthrown so many of them. There are various types of counterrevolutions. The most notable are the

Soviet Communist, Italian Fascist, German National So- cialist, Spanish Falangist, Portuguese Corporatist, the Tito-

ist, and Peronist. . . . Besides these organized counterrev- olutionary movements, professing doctrines of an anti-

liberal and undemocratic character, there is, in large areas

of the world, a very strong tendency to nullify the demo- cratic system behind the facade of democratic institutions. The countries where elections are free and genuine, where

civil liberty is secure, are still powerful. But they embrace a shrinking minority of mankind.

Now in all these counterrevolutionary movements

there are two conimQfl characteristid&t' One is the separa-i tion of thegoverning power from the large electorate .'

In the totalitarian states this is done by not holding free elections; in the great number of nontotalitarian but also THE COUNTERREVOLUTION 59 nondemocratic states, it is done by controlling and rigging the elections.

The other^x:ommon characteristic of the counterrevolu- tions is thai^political power, which is taken away from the electorate, the parties and the party bosses, is then passed to_an^e lite corps niarked off from the mass of the( people by speciajjraining and by special vows. The totali- tarian revolutions generally liquidate the elite of the old regime, and then recruit their own elite of specially trained and specially dedicated and highly disciplined men. Elsewhere, when the liberal democratic system fails, the new rulers are drawn from the older established elites — from the army officers, from the clergy, the higher bureaucracy and the diplomatic corps, from uni- versity professors.

It is significant that in the reaction against the practical failure of the democratic states, we find always that the electoral process is shut down to a minimum or shut off entirely, and that the executive function is taken over — more often than not with popular assent — by men with a special training and a special personal commitment to the business of ruling the state. In the enfeebled democ- racies the politicans have with rare exceptions been men without sure tenure of office. Many of the most important are novices, improvisers, and amateurs. After a counter- revolution has brought them down, their successors are almost certain to be either the elite of the new revolu- tionary party, or an elite drawn from predemocratic in- stitutions like the army, the church, and the bureauc- racy. In their different ways — which ideologically may be 6o THE DECLINE OF THE WEST

at opposite ends of the world — the post-democratic

rulers are men set apart from the masses of the people.'

They are not set apart only because they have the power

to arrest others and to shoot them. They would not long

hold on to that kind of power. They have also an aura of i

majesty, which causes them to be obeyed. That aura ema- nates from the popular belief that they have subjected

themselves to a code and are under a discipline by which

they are dedicated to ends that transcend their personal

desires and their own private lives.

2. A Prognosis

The nature of the counterrevolution reflects a radical

deficiency in the modern liberal democratic state. This deficiency is, as I have been saying, the enfeeblement and virtual paralysis of the executive governing func- tions. The strong of the counterrevolution is needed, on the one hand, to stop the electoral process from encroaching upon and invading the government, and, on the other hand, to invest the government not only with all material power but also with the imponderable force of majesty.

It is possible to govern a state without giving the masses of the people full representation. But it is not possible to go on for jong without a government which can and does in fact govern. If, therefgrg^the p£ople_find ^^latjhey must choose whether they will bejgpresented in

an assembly Y/hirh ;<; I'n^-p rape tent to govern, or whether THE COUNTERREVOLUTION 6l

they will be governed -withaut-being_r£pt£sented, there

IS no doubt at all as to how_the issue will be decided. They will choose authority, which promises to be pateti ^' '^' ^v-

ev nal, in preference to freedom which threatens to b hi c,.^,. I lie. fratricidal. For large communities cannot do without be- ing governed. No ideal of freedom and of democracy will long be allowed to stand in the way of their being governed.

The plight of the modern democracies is serious. They have suffered great disasters in this century and the con- sequences of these disasters are compounding themselves.

The end is not yet clear. The world that is safe for de-. -, mocracy and is safely democratic is shrunken. It is still' shrinking. For the disorder which has been incapacitating the democracies- in this century is, if anything, becoming more virulent as time goes on. A continuing practical failure to govern will lead — no one can say in what form and under what banners — to counterrevolutionary measures for the establishment of strong government. The alternative is to withstand and to reverse the descent towards counterrevolution. It is a much harder way. It demands popular assent to radical measures which will restore government strong enough to govern, strong enough to resist the encroachment of the assemblies and of mass opinions, and strong enough to guarantee private liberty against the pressure of the masses.

It would be foolish to attempt to predict whether the crisis of the democratic state will be resolved by such an internal restoration and revival or by counterrevolution.

No doubt the danger of counterrevolution is greater in 62 THE DECLINE OF THE WEST countries where the margins of Hfe are thinner. No doubt the prospects of a restoration and revival are best in countries where the traditions of civiHty, as the public philosophy of Western society, have deep roots and a long history. 1

CHAPTER VII The Adversaries of

Liberal Democracy

I. Liheralism and ]acobinism

We are living in a time of massive popular counter- revolution against . It is a reaction to the failure of the West to cope with the miseries and anx-

ieties of the Twentieth Century. The liberal democracies have been tried and found wanting — found wanting not only in their capacity to govern successfully in this period

of wars and upheavals, but also in their ability to defend

and maintain the political philosophy that underlies the

liberal way of life. If we go back to the beginnings of the modern demo-

cratic movements in the eighteenth century, we can dis- .

tinguish two diverging lines of development. The one is a i

way_of progress in liberal constitutional democracy. The

other is a morbid course of development into totalitarian conditions.^

One of the first to realize what was happening was Alexis de Tocqueville. He foresaw that the "democratic

nations are menaced" by a "species of oppression . . . unlike anything that ever before existed in the world."

^ Cf. J. C. Talmon, The Rise of Totalitarian Democracy. —

64 THE DECLINE OF THE WEST

But what is more, he discerned the original difference be-

tween the healthy and th e morbid development of democ-

racy.

In 1833, after his voyage in America, where he had foreseen the threat of mass democracy, de Tocqueville visited England.' There he was impressed with the con-

trast between the attitude of the English ,

which was just in the way of accommodating itself to a newly enfranchised mass of voters, and the French no- blesse of the Ancien Regime,

He went on to reflect that

. . . from an early time a fundamental difference existed between the behavior of the governing classes in England and in France. The nobility, the cornerstone of medieval society, revealed in England a peculiar ability to merge and mix with other social

groups, while in France it tended, on the contrary, to close its

ranks and preserve its original purity of birth.

In the earlier Middle Ages all Western Europe had a similar social system. But some time in the Middle Ages, one cannot say exactly when, a change pregnant with tremendous consequences

occurred in the British Isles and in the British Isles only _the English nobility developed into an open aristocracy while the continental noblesse stubbornly remained within the rigid limits

of a caste .

^ De Tocqueville did not write a book on England, as he had already written one on America and was later to write one on France. His views on England were not accessible until recently, when Miss Ada Zemach published her study, Alexis de Tocqueville on England, in the Revieiv of

Politics for July 195 1, Vol. 13, No. 3. This valuable paper is collated from de TocqueviUe's correspondence and notes. Miss Zemach says that "unlike his views on America and France, which are carefully stated in special books written at great length and in elaborate form, his ideas about Eng- land are more impressionistic in nature, scattered as they are in no par- ticular order among volumes of correspondence, sometimes appearing in a bunch in the Journal de Voyage, sometimes as sudden asides in the big systematic works, emphasizing and defining a certain trend of thought by way of comparison and opposition." THE ADVERSARIES 65

This, observes de Tocqueville, is the most revolutionary'

fact in Enghsh history, and he claims to have been the"

first to observe its importance and to grasp its full signifi-

cance. It is, truly, a deep and illuminating observation on

the conditions which are favorable to a healthy and pro- gressive evolution of democracy and on the conditions

which make k morbid and degenerative. The crucial dif-

ference is between what we might call enfranchisement

by assimilation into the governing class, as exemplified in England, and, per contra, enfranchisement by the over-

throw and displacing of the governing class as exempli- fied i n Franj:e. In the one the government remains but becomes more responsible and more responsive; in the

other, the government is overthrown with the liquidation

of the governing class.

Although the two ways of evolution appear to have the

same object — a society with free institutions under popu- lar government — they are radically different and they arrive at radically different ends.

The first way, that of assimilation, presumes the exist-

ejice of a state which is already constitutional in principle/

which is under laws that are no longer arbitrary, though

they may be unjust and unequal. Into this constitutional

state more and more people are admitted to the govern-

ing class and to the voting electoratei(The unequal and

the unjust laws are revised until eventually all the people

have equal opportunities to enter the government and to

be represented! Broadly speaking, this has been the work- ing theory of the British movement towards a democratic

society at home and also in the Commonwealth and Em-

pire. This, too, was the working theory of the principal GG THE DECLINE OF THE WEST

authors of the American Constitution, and this was how

— though few of them welcomed it — they envisaged the enfranchisement of the whole adult population.

The other way is that of the Jacobin revolution. The people rise to power by overthrowing the ruling class and

by liquidating its privileges and prerogatives. This is the doctrine of democratic revolution which was developed by French thinkers in the eighteenth century and was put into practice by the Jacobin party in the French Revolu-

tion. In its English incarnation the doctrine became

known as Radicalism. In America, tFough it had its early disciples, notably Tom Paine, not until the era of the

Founding Fathers was over, not until the era of Andrew .

Tackson, did the Jacobin doctrine become the popular po-' litical creed of the American democracy, y The Jacobin philosophy rests on a view of human so-

ciety which the encyclopedist, Holbach, stated in this way:

/ We see on the face of the globe only incapable, unjust sover- eigns, enervated by luxury, corrupted by flattery, depraved through unpunished Hcense, and without talent, morals, or good \ qualities.^

What Holbach had, in fact, seen on the face of the globe was the French court — then the most powerful in

Europe and the paragon of all the lesser courts. When he

was writing, it would have been difficult for anyone on the

continent of Europe to imagine a king and a ruling class

who were not, like those he saw living at the Court of Versailles, exclusive and incompetent, corrupt, unteach- able and unconcerned.

*Cited in Taine. The Ancient Regime ( p. 220. Hippolyte A. 1888) , THE ADVERSARIES 67

"Would you know the story in brief, of almost all our wretched-

ness?" asked Diderot. "Here it is. There existed the natural man , and into this man was introduced an artificial man, whereupon

a civil war arose within him lasting through life ... If you propose to become a over him, ... do your best to poison him with a theory of morals against nature; impose every kind of fetter on him; embarrass his movements with a thousand obstacles; place phantoms around him to frighten him. Would you see him

happy and free? Do not meddle with his affairs. ... I appeal to every civil, religious and political institution; examine these

closely, and, if I am not mistaken, you will find the human species, century after century, subject to a yoke which a mere handful of knaves chose to impose on it. . . . Be wary of him who seeks to establish order; to order is to obtain the mastery of others by giv- ing them trouble.^ X]

If we compare the mood of this passage with that of the Declaration of Independence, the work of the other brand of revolutionists, we must be struck by the of Diderot. Diderot had been exasperated to a blind destruc- tive despair by the rigidity of the French governing caste.

He could not feel that there was anything to be done with any government, judging by the one he suffered un- der, except to abolish it.

Jeflferson and his colleagues, on the other hand, were interested in government. They were in rebellion because they were being denied the rights of representation and of participation which they, like other subjects of the same King, would have enjoyed had they lived in England.

The Americans were in rebellion against the "usurpa- tions" of George III, no t against authority as such but, against the abuse^of authority. The American revolution-

* Ibid., pp. 220-221. 68 THE DECLINE OF THE WEST ists had in fact participated in the colonial governments.

They intended to play leading parts, as indeed they did, in the new government. Far from wishing to overthrow the authority of government, or to deny and subve rt, as

Diderot did, the moral foundations of authority, they went into rebellion first in order to .t;ain admittance into , and then to take possession of, the organs of government. When they declared that "a prince (George III) whose character is thus marked by every act which may define a tyrant, is unfit to be the ruler of a free people," they were not saying that there was no one who was fit to be the ruler of a free people. They were imbued with the , English that the governing class must learn to share its special prerogatives by admitting new members. The American Revolutionists were themselves the new mem- bers who had been unjustly, in fact illegally, excluded from the government of the colonies. They themselves meant to govern the colonies after they had overthrown the government of the King. They were not nihilists to whom the revolutionary act of overthrowing the sove r- eign is the climax and consummation of everything.

2. The Paradigm of Revolution

Of THE two rival , the Jacobin is almost everywhere in the ascendant. It is a ready philosophy for men who, previously excluded from the ruling class, and recently enfranchised, have no part in the business of gov- erning the state, and no personal expectation of being called upon to assume the responsibilities of office. The THE ADVERSARIES 69

Jacobin doctrine is an obvious reaction, as de Tocque- ville's observation explains, to government by a caste.

When there is no opening for the gradualness of reform and for enfranchisement by assimilation, a revolutionary collision is most likely.

The Jacobin doctrine is addressed to the revolutionary collision betv^^een the inviolable governing caste and the excluded^ men claiming the redress of their grievances and their place in the sun. Though it professes to be a po- litical philosophy, the doctrine is not, in fact, a philoso- phy of government. It is a gospel and also a strategy for revolution. At announces the promise that the crusade which is to overthrow the ruling caste will by the act of

revolution create a good society. ^>

The peculiar essence of the dogma is that the revolu- tion itself is the creative act. Towards the revolution as such, because it is the culmination and the climax, all the -i^Uc

'^'*'' .,1.^ labor and the sacrifice of the struggle are to be directed. '

The revolutionary act will remove the causes of evil in human society. Again and again k has been proved how effective is this formula for arousing, sustaining and or- ganizing men's energies for revolution: to declare that evil in society has been imposed upon the many by the few — by priests, nobles, capitalists, imperialists, liberals, aliens — and that evil will disappear when the many who

.' are pure have removed these few who are evil, j !

^The summons to revolution in the Communist Mani- festo of 1848 uses the same formula as the Jacobins had used a half century earlier./Marx and Engels were men steeped in the Western revolutionary tradition, and habit- uated, therefore, to the notion that the act of revolution 70 THE DECLINE OF THE WEST

removes the source of evil and creates the perfect society.

The French Revolution had not made this perfect society. For by 1848 there were the capitalist oppressors. Marx

and Engels called for the next revolutionary act, announc-

ing that now the Third Estate, the bourgeois capitalists, needed to go the way of the liquidated nobles and clergy,

/ This is the formula: that when the revolution of the \

masses is victorious over the few, there will exist the \ classless society without coercion and violence and withy^

\ freedom for all. This formula reappears whenever condi-

tions are revolutionary — that is to say, when necessary

reforms are being refused. The formula is the strategy of

rebellion of those who are unable to obtain the redress of

grievances. The rulers are to be attacked. So they are iso-

lated. They are few. So they are not invincible. They bear

the total guilt of all the sufferings and grievances of men.

To remove them is then to cure all evil. Therefore, their

overthrow, which is feasible, will be worth every sacrifice.

Since the world will be good when the evil few have been

overthrown, there is no need for the doubts and the dis-

putes which would arise among the revolutionists if they had to make serious practical decisions on the problems of the post-revolutionary world. "You are summoned," said Barrere to the National

Assembly, "to give history a fresh start." ''' This was to be_

done by stripping off, as Taine puts it , the garments of the

artificial man, all those fictitious qualities which make

him "ecclesiastic or layman, noble or plebeian, sovereign

or subject, proprietor or proletarian, ignorant or culti-

^ Ibid., p. 232. THE ADVERSARIES 7I vated." The established authorities who have made man wear these garments for their selfish and sinister ends must go. The authorities must go, the garments must be removed^nd then there will be left "man in himself, the same under all conditions, in all situations, in all coun- tries, in all ages." ^ These natural men would be very different from the fallen and deformed wretches who now inhabit the world.

They would be Adam before he fel l — Adam who fell by the machinations of the and the priests, and not by his own disobedience. Let this "infamous thing," with its upholders, be crushed, said Voltaire of the anclen regime.

Then, added Condorcet exultingly, "tyrants and slaves, and priests with their senseless and hypocritical instru- ments," will disappear, and there will be only "free men ^ recognizing no other master than reason."

To appreciate the compelling influence of these ideas, we must realize that Rousseau and his Jacobin disciples were not saying that "except for the clergy and the nobil- ity" all the Frenchmen of the eighteenth century were rational and good men. That may have been what the most simple-minded got from the Jacobin orations. But the doctrine could never have become, as in fact it has, the political of the democracies had it stood for anything so obviously contrary to common sense and ordi- nary experience. Rousseau's dogma of the natural goodness of man did not move him to much or admiration of his fellow- men. In his Inequalities Among Mankind, he described the inside of a civilized man in terms which John Adams, for

^ Ibid., p. 231. 72 THE DECLINE OF THE WEST

all his tough-mindedness, found "too black and horrible to ^ be transcribed." To Rousseau, as to John Calvin who lived in Geneva before him, men were fallen and depraved, deformed

with their lusts and their aggressions. The force of the

new doctrine lay in its being a gospel of redemption and regeneration. Men who were evil were to be made good. >/Jacobinism is, in fact, a Christian heresy — perhaps the y Y niost influential since the Arian. / In that it preached the need of redemption, its recep- tion was prepared by the Christian education of the peo- ple of Western Europe and of North America. Like Saint Paul, the Jacobins promised a new creature who would

"be led of the spirit" and would not be "under the law."

But in the Jacobin gospel, this transformation was to be achieved by the revolutionary act of emancipation from

authority. The religious end was to be reached, but with- out undergoing the religious experience. There was to be no dark night of the for each person in the labor of

his own regeneration. Instead there were to be riots and strikes and votes and seizure of political power. Instead of

the inner struggle of the individual soul, there was to be one great public massive, collective redemption.

'' John Adams, A Defense of the Constitutions of Government of the United States of America (1787), from the Life and Works of ]ohn Adams (edited with The life by Charles Francis Adams, 1851), Vol. IV., p. 409. THE ADVERSARIES 73

3. Democratic Education

We live long enough after the new gospel was pro-

claimed to have seen what came of it. The post- revolutionary man, enfranchised and emancipated, has

not turned out to be the New Man. He is the old Adam. Yet the future of democratic society has been staked on the promises and the predictions of the Jacobin gospel. For the Jacobin doctrine has pervaded the theory of mass education in the newly enfranchised mass democra-

cies. In America and in most of the newer liberal democ-

racies of the Western world, the Jacobin heresy is, though not unchallenged and not universal, the popular and dom- inant theory in the schools.

Its popularity is easily accounted for. It promises to

solye the problem which is otherwise so nearly insoluble

— how to educate rapidly and sufficiently the ever-, expanding masses who are losing contact with the tradi-

- tions of Western society. The explosive increase of the

population in the past hundred and fifty years, its recent

enfranchisement during the past fifty years, the dissolu-

tion, or at least the radical weakening, of the bonds of the family, the churches, and of the local community have

combined to make the demand upon the schools almost

impossibly big.

Not only do the schools have to teach the arts and sciences to a multiplying mass of pupils. They have also

to act in the place of the family, the household economy, the church, and the settled community, and to be the bearers of the traditions and the disciplines of a civilized

jife. What the school system could do has never been 74 THE DECLINE OF THE WEST anywhere nearly equal to the demands upon it. The mod- ern democracies have never been willing to pay the price of recruiting and training enough teachers, of supporting enough schools and colleges, of offering enough scholar- ships to give all children equal opportunities.

. The Jacobin doctrine does not solve this problem of mass education — as it does not solve or even throw light upon the problem of how to construct and govern the

Utopian society which is to exist when the revolution has taken place. What it does is to provide an escape from > f these unsolved problems. It affirms that in politics the state will wither away and then there will be no prob-i k-^'" lems of how to govern it. For the democratic schools it affirms that there is no problem of supplying the demand: fo r almost nothing has to be taught in school and almost

no effort is needed to learn it .

"The fundamental principle of all ," said

Rousseau in his reply to Archbishop de Beaum ont's con- demnation of his book, £/?2/7g, "is th at man is a being naturally good, loving and order: that there is not any original perversity in the human he , and that the " ^ fi rst movements of nature are always right.

And so, when Rousseau's disciple, P estalozzi, the cele- brat_ed_educator, said that "in the newborn child are hid- " den those faculties which are to unfold during life^ ^ he meant that the hidden faculties which would unfold were

*J. J. Rousseau, "Lettre a C. de Beaumont," in Oeuvres Completes de J. J. Rousseau, edited by P. R. Auguis (Paris, Dalibon, 1824-1825), Vol. 7, p. 44. Translation from Geoffrey O'Connell, in Atnerican Education (1938), p. 23. ® J. H. Pestalo2zi, address on his birthday in 18 18, cited in the Encyclo- pedia of Religion and , Vol. V, p. 166. THE ADVERSARIES 75 all of them good ones. Only good faculties, it transpired, were inherited. The evil faculties, on the contrary, were acquired. So Froebel, who was Pestalozzi's disciple, felt

able to say that "the still young being, even though as yet unconsciously like a product of nature, precisely and ^° surely wills that which is best for himself." Froebel, of course, had no way of proving that infants are precise and sure about anything. Nor did Rousseau

know how to prove that there is no perversity in the hu-

man heart, and that the first movements of nature are al-

ways right. But if only all this could be taken as true,

how miraculously it simplified the problems of the new

democracies! If men do not have to acquire painfully by

learning, if they are born with the necessary good facul-

ties, if their first intentions are always right, if they un-

consciously but precisely and surely will what is best for

themselves from infancy on, then there is in the very na- •

ture of things a guarantee that popular government must succeed. The best government will be the one which governs

the least and requires, therefore, the least training and ex-

perience in the art of governing. The best education for

deniocracy will be the one which trains, disciplines, and

teaches the least. For the necessary faculties are inborn

and they are more likely to be perverted by too much cul-

ture than to wither for the lack of it. There is, moreover, no body of public knowledge and no public philosophy

that the schools are called upon to transmit. There are, therefore, no inconvenient questions of faith and morals,

questions on which there is no prospect of agreement by

'°F. W. A. Froebel, Education of Man, Sec. 8. -jG THE DECLINE OF THE WEST

popular decision. The curriculum can be emptied of all the studies and the disciplines which relate to faith and to

morals. And so while education can do something to en- able the individual to make a success of his own career, the instinctive rightness and righteousness of the people

can be relied upon for everything else.

This is a convenient and agreeably plausible escape

from reality. Pestalozzi described it by saying that . . .

Sound Education stands before me symbolized by a tree planted

near fertilizing water. A little seed, which contains the design of

the tree, its form and proportion, is placed in the soil. See how it germinates and expands into trunk, branches, leaves, flowers and

fruit! The whole tree is an uninterrupted chain of organic parts,

the plan of which existed in its seed and root. Man is similar to

the tree. In the newborn child are hidden those faculties which

are to unfold during life.^-^

The metaphor reveals very neatly how the Jacobin

\ theory inhibits education.^ In no way that is relevant to

the problems of politics and eH^ucation is a man similar, as

Pestalozzi says he is, to a tree which is planted near ferti-

lizing water. For the tree will never, no matter how fer-

tilizing the water near which it is planted, grow up and

take to writing treatises, as Pestalozzi did, on the educa-

tion of trees and how to raise the best trees from all the

little saplings. The tree will never worry about whether

its little saplings are going to be planted near the most

fertilizing of the waters. The educator of a tree is, in short,

not another tree. The educator of a tree, the man who

plants it near the fertilizing water, is a being so radically

different from a tree that the tree is incapable of being

^^Encyclopedia of Religion a)id Ethics, Vol. V, p. i66. THE ADVERSARIES 77 aware of his existence. If, however, the tree were enough

hke a man to notice such things, the teacher of the trees who cultivates them would be worshiped as the god of trees.

Pestalozzi's trees are, in fact, a caricature, but a telling one, of the educational vacuum created by the Jacobin theory. The tradidon of the trees is transmitted in their seed, and the older trees are unable to teach and the sap- lings are unable to learn. Each tree exists for itself, draw- ing what it can from the fertilizing waters if they happen to be there. Now if human education is founded upon this notion, it must fail to transmit the moral system, indeed the psychic structure, of a civilized society. Relying upon die inherent t ightness of the natural impulses of man's first nature, the theory does away with the second Jacobin ^ civilized nature,_with the ruler of the impulses, who is identified with the grand necessities of the common- wealth . It overthrows the ruler within each man, — he who exercises "the royal and politic rule" over his "irasci- ble and concupiscible powers." C^hen reason no longer represents society within the human psyche, then it becomes the instrument of appetite, > desire and passion?\A.s William Godwin said in 1798:

"Reason is wholly confined to adjusting the comparison between the different objects of desire and investigating ^^ the most successful mode of attaining those objects." More than a hundred years later (1911) Prof. William

MacDougal put it this way: "The instinctive impulses de-

^^ From a memorandum setting forth his intended work. Reproduced in C. K. Paul, William Godwin: His Friends and Contemporaries. (Boston,

1876), Vol. I, p. 294. yS THE DECLINE OF THE WEST termine the end of all activities, and ... all the com- plex intellectual apparatus of the most highly developed

mind is but . . . the instrument by which those impulses

." ^^' seek their satisfactions. . . Or, as Bernard Shaw has it,

"Ability to reason accurately is as desirable as ever, since it is only by accurate reasoning that we can calculate our ac- tions so as to do what we intend to do — that is, to fulfill ^* our will."

If it is the role of reason merely to be an instrument of each man's career, then the mission of the schools is to turn out efficient careerists. They must teach the know- how of success, and this — seasoned with the social amenities and some civic and patriotic exhortation — is the subject matter of education. The student elects those subjects which will presumably equip him for success in his career. The rest are superfluous. There is no such thing as a general order of knowledge and a public philosophy, which he needs to possess.

4. From Jacobinism to Leninism

Towards the middle of the nineteenth century, Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels produced an explanation of why the first revolution had not fulfilled the promises of the Jacobins. It was that "Modern bourgeois society, rising out of the ruins of feudal society,_did not make an end of class antagonisms. It merely set up new classes in place " of the old.

^''William MacDougal, Social Psychology (London, Methuen & Co., 1950), p. 38. "G. B. Shaw, Quintessence of Ibsenism (i 891), p. 15. THE ADVERSARIES 79

As Marx and Engels were scholars and men of the world, they should not have been surprised to find that

"the history of all human society past and present has been the history of class struggles," and, had they not be- come possessed by the Jacobin dogma, they would have thought it most probable that there would be class strug- gles in the future. But in the Jacobin philosophy the world as it is must be transformed; the day is soon to come when history, reaching its culmination, will end, and there will be no more struggles. So Marx and

Engels decided that one more, though this time the con- clusive and the final, revolution was called for, in order to achieve the classless society: "The proletariat ... is compelled to organize itself as a class," and "by means of a revolution, it makes itself the ruling class and, as such, sweeps away by force the old conditions of production.

. . . Then it will, along with these conditions, have swept away the conditions for the existence of class an- tagonisms and of classes generally, and will thereby have abolished its own supremacy as a class."

The revolution which is behind us has failed. But the revolution which is still to come will put "in place of the old bourgeois society, with its classes and class antagonisms ... an association, in which the free development of each is the condition for the free development of all."

By the beginning of the twentieth century it was be- coming more and more apparent that Marxism was go- ing to undergo the same disappointment as had the Jacobin movement. Since Marx and Engels wrote the

^"^ These quotations are from the Manifesto of the Communist Party (1848). 8o THE DECLINE OF THE WEST

Communist Manifesto a very considerable progress had been made in carrying out its specific planks. What that document had asked in 1848, "the most advanced na- i tions" had gone a long way toward doing. They were ' taxing, inheritances, they had virtually nationalized cen- tral banking, transportation and communications, they were extending the industries owned by the state, they were abolishing child labor and providing free education in public schools.^^

Yet these reforms were not leading to the classless* society. Instead of one class or no class it was more prob- able that modern societies were heading towards a diver- sity of classes. Nor, as Engels had promised in his "Anti- " Diihring," did it look as if the state . . . withers away."

As a matter of fact the progressive reforms were tequir- 1/3''' ing a ra pid enlargement of the powers of the state and an ^^jf'P"^'^

'^^^"^'^^ expansion of the bureaucracy . The Marxian predictions wei:e not being fulfilled. The rich were not becoming •"'^"'^ richer while the poor became poorer. The middle class "'''V^'*'^" was not disappearing. It was growing larger. Society was not splitting into the two great hostile camps of the

bourgeoisie and the proletariat. If it was splitting, it was ., into factions and into pressure groups. ^ Owing to the wide disparity between the dogma and

the existential reality of things, a crisis developed within the revolutionary socialist movement. This crisis was re- solved by Lenin. He could not do again what Marx had done a half century earlier. He could not once more

identify the next class, and this time the positively last

class, that had to be overthrown. He could not point to

" Cf. the concrete proposals contained in the Communist Manifesto. '

THE ADVERSARIES 8l the last barricade that had to be stormed. It was then that

Lenin resolved the crisis within the revolutionary move- | ^ ment by committing it to the totalitarian solution . Aban- doning the naive but attractive promise that Utopia would follow simply and automatically from the revolutionary act, he replaced it with the terrible doctrine that Utopia must be brought about by an indefinitely prolonged pro- cess of unlimited revolution which would exterminate all opposition, actual and potential. The totalitarian tendency has always been present and logically implied in the modern revolutionary move- ment.^' Yet Mr. Isaiah Berlin is no doubt right in saying that while Lenin's solution of the crisis within the revolu- tionary movement "marked the culmination of a process,"

this was "an event . . . which altered the history of our world." '^ In 1903, at the conference of the Russian Social Democratic Party, which began in Brussels and ended in London, Lenin was asked by a delegate named Posadov- sky "whether the emphasis laid by the 'hard' Socialists

. . . upon the need for the exercise of absolute authority by the revolutionary nucleus of the Party might not prove incompatible with those fundamental liberties to whose realization , no less than liberalism, was officially dedicated." Posadovsky asked whether the basic, minimum civil liberties — "the sacrosanctity of the per- son" — could be infringed and even violated if the parry leader so decided.

" Cf. Eric Voegelin, The New Science of Politics, particularly Ch. IV, et seq.; also J. L. Talmon, The Rise of Totalitarian Democracy. ^® Isaiah Berlin, "Political Ideas in the Twentieth Century" {Foreign

Affairs, April 1950, Vol. XXVIII, No. 3, pp. 364-366). 82 THE DECLINE OF THE WEST

The answer was given by Plekhanov, one of the founders of Russian Marxism, and, says Mr. Berhn, "its most venerated figure, a cultivated, fastidious and mor- ally sensitive scholar of wide outlook," who had for twenty years lived in Western Europe and was much respected by the leaders of Western Socialism. Plekhanov was the very of civilized "scientific" thinking among Russian revolutionaries. "Plekhanov, speaking solemnly, and with a splendid disregard for grammar, pronounced the words, salus revoluttae stiprema lex. Cer - t ainly, if the revolution demanded it, everything — de- mocracy, liberty, the rights of the individual — must be sacrificed to it. If the democratic assembly elected by the Russian people after the revolution proved amenable to

Marxist tactics, it would be kept in being as a Long

Parliament; if not, k would be disbanded as quickly as possible. A Marxist revolution could not be carried through by men obsessed by scrupulous regard for the principles of bourgeois liberals. Doubtless whatever was valuable in these principles, like everything else good and desirable, would ultimately be realized by the victori- ous working class; but during the revolutionary period preoccupation with such ideals was evidence of a lack of seriousness."

Mr. Berlin goes on to say that "Plekhanov, who was brought up in a humane and liberal tradition, did, of course, later retreat from this position himself. The mix- ture of Utopian faith and brutal disregard for civilized morality proved too repulsive to a man who had spent the greater part of his civilized and productive life among

Western workers and their leaders. Like the vast majority THE ADVERSARIES 83 of Social Democrats, like Marx and Engels themselves, he was too European to try to realize a policy which, in the words of Shigalev in Dostoevski's The Possessed,

'starting from unlimited liberty ends in unlimited despot- ism.' But Lenin accepted the premises, and being logically driven to conclusions repulsive to most of his colleagues, accepted them easily and without apparent qualms. His assumptions were, perhaps, in some sense, still those of the optimistic rationalists of the eighteenth and nine- teenth centuries: the coercion, violence, execution, the total suppression of individual differences, the rule of a small, virtually self-appointed minority, were necessary only in the interim period, only so long as there was a powerful enemy to be destroyed."

But how was it that Lenin, and so many after him, have accepted easily and without apparent qualms the repulsive process of violence, executions, suppressions, de- ception, under the unlimited rule of self-appointed oligarchs? Why do the full-fledged totalitarians, Lenin, Hitler, Stalin, not shrink from the means they adopt to achieve their end? The answer ij that the inhuman means ..^uv^^-: ^--J are justijfied by the superhuman end J they are the agents o.-^. of history or of nature. They are the men appointed to fulfill the destiny of creation. They have been known as atheists. But in fact God was their enemy, not because they did not believe in the Deity, but because they them- selves were assuming His functions and claiming His prerogatives. \ 84 THE DECLINE OF THE WEST

5. The Overpassing of the Bound

This is the root of the matter, and it is here that the ulti- '^^^"Xk mate issue lies. Can men, acting like , be appointed to] j establish heaven on earth? If we believe that they can be,f ,i.s ,,,^ then the rest follows. To fulfill their mission they must ^iln.-^-^'^

''''"" assume a godlike omnipotence. They must be jealous gods, '^.jj, monopolizing power, destroying all rivals, compelling ex- " ^ • elusive loyalty. The family, the churches, the schools, the j

corporations, the labor unions and co-operative societies, I

the voluntary associations and all the arts and sciences, ; must be their servants. Dissent and deviation are treason j and is sacrilege. .'

But the monopoly of all power will not be enough. - There remains the old Adam. Unless they can remake the fallen nature of a man, the se lf-elected gods cannot make a heaven of the earth. In the Jacobin gospel of the eigh t- eenth century, and even in the Marxist gospel of the nine- teenth ce ntury, the new man would be there when the artificial garments were removed — when once he was emancipated by the revolutionary act from the deformation imposed upon him by the clergy, the nobility and the bour- geoisie. A hundred years later the new man was nowhere i^n sight. So the early and softer gospel gave way to a later and infinitely harder one. The new man and the new heaven on earth demanded the remaking of pre-Lenin ist and pre-Hitlerian man. The decrees of history as revealed to Marx, and the decrees of nature as revealed to Hitler, had to be carried out. THE ADVERSARIES 85

But in order to do that, the human species had first to be transformed — or failing that, exterminated . Destiny called upon the mortal god to make surviving mankind

"an active unfailing carrier," as Hannah Arendt says, "of a law to which human would otherwise only pas- ^^ sively and reluctantly be subject."

In the eyes of its devotees, this is not an inhuman and

Satanic doctrine. It is above and beyond humanity. It is for the superman that its gospel announces. The ruthlessness, the arbitrariness, the cruelty are not monstrous wicked- ness. They are natural and necessary, predestined like the fall of a sparrow, in the sublime construction of the earthly paradise.

The issue is carried outside the realm of rational dis- course. As Richard Hooker said of the Puritan revo- lutionaries three centuries ago, when men believe they are acting "under the absolute command of Almighty

God," their discipline "must be received . . . although the world by receiving it should be clean turned ^^ upside down." There is no arguing with the pre-j tenders to a divine knowledge and to a divine mission.

They are possessed with the of pride, they have yielded to the perennial temptation. This is the sover- eign evil against which the traditions of civility are arrayed.

Here is "the mortal sin original," the forbidden fruit, which Satan tempts Eve to eat:

" Hannah Arendt, Ideology and Terror; A Novel Form of Government. From the Review of Politics (published at the University of Notre Dame,

July, 1953), Vol. XV, No. 3. ^ Of the Laws of Ecclesiastical Polity. In Vol. I, The Works of Richard

Hooker, edited by J. Keble (second edition, Oxford University, 1841),

Preface, Ch. VIII, Sec. 5, p. 182. 86 THE DECLINE OF THE WEST

Taste this, and be henceforth among the Gods Thyself a God- dess.^^

This tasting of the tree, as Adam says to Dante, was ^^ "the overpassing of the bound." Zeus, says Aeschylus

... is a chastener of froward wills And he correcteth with a heavy hand. Wherefore be ye instructors of your Lord, And with well-reasoned admonitions teach Him To have a humbler heart and cast away

The sin of pride, for it offendeth God.^^

The delusion of men that they are gods — the preten- sion that they have a commission to act as if they were gods — is, says Aeschylus, "the blind arrogance of child- ish thought. " It can become "the very madness of a mind diseased." Yet it is not a new and recent infection, but rather the disposition of our first , of our natural and uncivilized selves. Men have been barbarians much

longer than they have been civilized. They are only pre- cariously civilized, and within us there is the propensity, persistent as the force of gravity, to revert under stress

and strain, under neglect or temptation, to our first na- tures. Rousseau and the Jacobins, Marx and the nineteenth-

century socialists, did not introduce new impulses and pas- sions into men. They exploited and aggravated impulses

^ Paradise Lost. In the Poetical Works of John Milton, Bk. V, lines

77778. _ "'^Divine Comedy, translated by C. E. Norton (1941), Paradise, Canto XXVI, verse 117. '^The Persians, lines S28-836. THE ADVERSARIES 87 and passions that are always there. In the traditions of civiHty, man's second and more rational nature must master his first and more elemental.

The Jacobins and their successors made a political reli- gion founded upon the reversal of civility. Instead of rul- ing the elemental impulses, they stimulated and armed them. Instead of treating the pretension to being a god as the mortal sin original, they proclaimed it to be the glory and destiny of man. Upon this gospel they founded a popular religion of the rise of the masses to power. Lenin,

Hitler and Stalin, the hard totalitarian Jacobins of the twentieth century, carried this movement and the logical implications of its gospel further and further towards the very bitter end.

And what is that bitter end? It is an everlasting war with the human condition: war with the finitude of man and with the moral ends of finite men, and, therefore, war against freedom, against justice, against the laws and against the order of the good society — as they are con- served in the traditions of civility, as they are articulated in the public philosophy.

BOOK TWO The Public Philosophy

CHAPTER VIII The Eclipse of the PubUc Philosophy

I. On the Efficacy of Ideas

There are those who would say, using the words of philosophers to prove it, that it is the characteristic illu- sion of the tender-minded that they believe in philosophy. Those who can, do; those who cannot, teach and theorize.] And being theorists by profession, they exaggerate the efficacy of ideas, which are mere airy nothings without mass or energy, the mere shadows of the existential world of substance and of force, of habits and desires, of machines and armies.

Yet the illusion, if it were one, is inordinately

tenacious. It is impossible to remove it from the common sense in which we live and have our being. In the famil-

iar daylight world we cannot act as if ideas had no conse-

quences. The whole vast labor and passion of public life

would be nonsense if we did not believe that it makes a

difference what is done by parties, newspapers, books,

broadcasts, schools and churches. All their effort would be irrelevant, indeed nonsense, like an argument about 92 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY what Nebuchadnezzar should be served for tomorrow morning's breakfast.

The most thoroughgoing skeptic is unable, in practice, to make a clean sweep — to say that since ideas have no consequences there is no such thing as a good idea or a bad one, a true idea or a false one. For there is no escap- ing the indubitable fact of experience that we are often mistaken, and that it makes a difference to have been wrong.

The chemistry of our bodies is never mistaken. The reaction of one chemical element to another chemical element is always correct, is never misled by misinforma- tion, by untruth, and by illusion. The doctor can be mis- taken about the chemistry of his patient, having failed to detect a substance which falsifies his diagnosis. But it is only the doctor who can be wrong; the chemical process cannot be. Why do men make mistakes? Because an important part of human behavior is reaction to the pictures in their heads. Human behavior takes place in relation to a pseudo-environment — a representation, which is not quite the same for any t\v'0 individuals, of what they suppose to be — not what is — the reality of things.^

This man-made, this cultural environment, which has its being in the minds of men, is interposed between man as a biological organism and the external reality. It is in this realm that ideas are efficacious. They are efficacious be- cause men react to their ideas and images, to their pic- tures and notions of the world, treating these pictures as if they were the reality.

^ Cf. my Public Opinion, Chapters I to X. THE ECLIPSE 93

The airy nothings in the realm of essence are effica-

cious in the existential world when a man, believing it

to be true or good, treats the idea as if it were the reality.

In this way faith in an idea can quite literally remove a mountain. To be sure no man's idea can remove a

mountain on the moon. But if the American people took

it into their heads that life would not be worth living until Pike's Peak was in the suburbs of Chicago, they

could move Pike's Peak. They could do it if they and

their descendants were sufficiently devoted to the idea for a long enough time.

Nothing would happen to Pike's Peak if the idea of

removing it were merely proclaimed and celebrated. The

idea would have to become, like the idea of winning a war, the object and the focus of the nation's energies. Then the idea would operate in the minds of men who voted, who planned, who would engineer the undertak-

ing, who would raise the money, would recruit the labor, would procure the equipment, and — shall we say — would suppress the mounting resistance of the objectors

to the project.

Because ideas have the power to organize human be-

havior, their efficacy can be radical. They are indeed radi-

cal when, as the image of what a man should be, they

govern the formation of his character and so imprint a lasting organization on his behavior.^ Because the images of man are the designs of the molds in which characters

are formed, they are of critical concern. What is the

^ I am using the term "character" as Erich Fromm does, in his Man for Himself (1947), p. 49, meaning "the relatively permanent form in which human energy is canalized in the process of assimilation and socialization." 94 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY image of the good king, the good courtier, the good sub- ject — of the good master and of the good slave — of the good citizen, the good soldier, the good politician, the good boss, the good workingman? The images matter |V very much. The ones which prevail will govern educa- tion. The ideas of what men should be like become efiEica- cious in the existential world because, as they are imposed by the family, the school and the community, they cause men to "acquire the kind of_character which makes them want to actjn 'the way they have to^^acOiS members of

the societ^r of a special class witITiirTf.""They learn "to

^Ijzf^what, objectively, it is necessary for them to do,"

md "outer force is . . . replaced by" thoT'^'mwer com-i .-— pulsion^^^ theff^ow^SKSacters.''^ — ,{

That there are limits to education in this sense, we

cannot doubt. But we do not know where they are. There

is, that is to say, no clear and certain boundary between

character which is acquired and those more or less un-

educable traits of human nature, evolved during the long ages and transmitted by inheritance. We are quite unable to predict with any certainty or precision how far the

individual pupil is educable — or rather how far he is

still educable by the time a particular educator gets hold of him, and after he has already acquired a character of

sorts in his infancy. Yet, however crude and clumsy our knowledge of the

process, there is no doubt that a character is acquired by experience and education. Within limits that we have not

' Erich Fromm, "Individual and Social Origin of Neurosis," American Sociological Revietv, Vol. 9 (1944), pp. 380-384. Reprinted in Clyde Kluckhohn and Henry Alexander Murray, Personality in Nature, Society, and Culture, (1948), pp. 407, et seq. THE ECLIPSE 95 measured, human nature is malleable. Can we doubt it when we remember that when Shakespeare was alive there were no Americans, that when Virgil was alive there were no Englishmen, and that when Homer was alive there were no Romans? Quite certainly, men have acquired the ways of thinking, feeling and acting which we recognize as their ethnic, national, class and occupa- tional characteristics. Comparatively speaking these characteristics are, moreover, recently acquired. Even within the brief span of historical time characters have been acquired and have been lost and have been re- placed by other characters. This is what gives to man's history, despite his common humanity, its infinite va- riety.

Because human nature is, as Hocking puts it, "the most plastic part of the living world, the most adaptable, the most educable," ^ it is also the most mal-adaptable and mis-educable. The cultural^ heritage which con- tains the whole structure and fabric of the good life is acquired. It may be rejected. It may be acquired/ badly. It may not be acquired at all. For we are not born with it. If it is not transmitted from one generation

to the next, it may be lost, indeed forgotten through

a dark age, until somewhere and somehow men re- discover it, and, exploring the world again, recreate it anew.

The acquired culture is not transmitted in our genes,

and so the issue is always in doubt. The good life in the

good society, though attainable, is never attained and pos-

* William Ernest Hocking, Human Nature and Its Remaking (1923), P 15- 96 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY

sessed once and for all. So what has been attained will

again be lost if the wisdom of the good life in a good

society is not transmitted.

That _ is the central and critical condition of the I Western society: that the democracies are ceasing to re- I

ceive the tra.ditions of civility in which the good society,

the liberal, \^emocra.tic way of life at its best, originated and developed. They are cut off from the public philoso-

phy and the poJiticalarts which are. needed to goyem the

liberal democratic society. They have not been initiated

into its secrets, and they do not greatly care for as much

of it as they are prepared to understand. In Toynbee's terrible phrase, they are proletarians who are "in" but are not "of" the society they dominate.

2. The Great Vacuum

To SPEAK of a public philosophy is, I am well aware, to

raise dangerous questions, rather like opening Pandora's box.

Within the Western nations, as Father Murray has put

it, there is "a plurality of incompatible faiths";^ there is also a multitude of secularized and agnostic people. Since

there is so little prospect of agreement, and such certainty

of dissension, on the content of the public philosophy, it

seems expedient not to raise the issues by talking about

them. It is easier to follow the rule that each person's

^ John Courtney Murray, S.J., "The Problem of Pluralism in America," in Thought (Fordham University, Summer, 1954). %

THE ECLIPSE 97 beliefs are private and that only overt conduct is a public matter.

One might say that this prudent rule reflects and registers the terms of settlement of the religious wars and of the long struggle against exclusive authority in the realm of the spirit by "thrones or dominations, or principalities or powers." Freedom of religion and of thought and of speech were achieved by denying both to the state and to the established church a sovereign monopoly in the field of religion, philosophy, morals, science, learning, opinion and conscience. The liberal constitutions, with their bills of rights, fixed the boundaries past which the sovereign — the King, the Parliament, the Congress, the voters — were forbidden to go. Yet the men of the seventeenth and eighteenth cen- turies who established these great salutary rules would certainly have denied that a community could do without a general public philosophy. They were themselves the adherents of a public philosophy — of the doctrine of natural Jaw, which held that there was law "above the

ruler and the sovereign people . , . above the whole ^ community of mortals."

The traditions of civility spring from this principle, which was first worked out by the Stoics. As Ernest

Barker says:

The rational faculty of man was conceived as producing a com- mon conception of law and order which possessed a universal

* Cf. Otto von Gierke, Political Theories of the Middle Age. translated with an introduction by Frederick William Maitland (London, Cambridge University Press, 1927), pp. 73-87; and more especially note #256. Also cf. Leo Strauss, Natural Right and History (1953). 98 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY

validity. . . . This common conception included, as its three great notes, the three values of Liberty, Equality and the brother-

hood or Fraternity of all mankind. This common conception, and

its three great notes, have formed a European set of ideas for over

two thousand years. It was a set of ideas which lived and moved

in the Middle Ages; and St. Thomas Aquinas cherished the idea of a sovereign law of nature imprinted in the heart and nature of

man, to which kings and legislators must everywhere bow. It was a set of ideas which lived and acted with an even greater anima- tion from the days of the Reformation to those of the French

Revolution . . . Spoken through the mouth of Locke, [they had justified} the English Revolution of 1688, and had recently served

to inspire the American Revolution of 1776 . . . They were ideas of the proper conduct of states and governments in the

area of internal affairs. They were ideas of the natural rights of man — of liberty, political and civic, with sovereignty residing essentially in the nation, and with free communication of thoughts and opinions; of equality before the law, and the equal repartition

of public expenses among all the members of the public; of a general fraternity which tended in practice to be sadly restricted within the nation, but which could, on occasion, be extended by

decree to protect all nations struggling for freedom.''^

These traditions were expounded in the treatises of

philosophers, were developed in the tracts of the publicists, were absorbed by the lawyers and applied in

the courts. At times of great stress some of the endan-

gered traditions were committed to writing, as in the Magna Carta and the Declaration of Independence. For the guidance of judges and lawyers, large portions were

described — as in Lord Coke's examination of the common law. The public philosophy was in part expounded in the

Bill in the first j of Rights of 1689. It was re-enacted ten

''Sir Ernest Barker, Traditions of Civility (1948), pp. 10-12. THE ECLIPSE 99 amendments of the Constitution of the United States. The largest part of the pubHc philosophy was never explicitly stated. Being the wisdom of a great society over the gen- erations, it can never be stated in any single document.

But the traditions of civility permeated the peoples of the West and provided a standard of public and private action which promoted, facilitated and protected the institutions of freedom and the growth of democracy.

The founders of our free institutions were themselves adherents of this public philosophy. When they insisted upon excluding the temporal power from the realm of the mind and the spirit, it was not that they had no public philosophy. It was because experience had taught them that as power corrupts, it corrupts the public phi- losophy. It was, therefore, a practical rule of politics that the government should not be given sovereignty and proprietorship over the public philosophy.

But as time went on, there fell out of fashion the public philosophy of the founders of Western institutions.

The rule that th.e jemporal power should be excluded from the realm of the mind and of the spirit was then subtly transformed. It became the rule that ideas and principles are private — with only subjective relevance and significance. Only when there is "a clear and present danger" to public order are the acts of speaking and publishing in the public domain. All the jfirst and last things were removed from the public domain. All_that has to do with what man is and should be, or how he should hold himself in the scheme of things, what are his/ p: rightful ends and the legitimate means, became private' / (J J and subjective and publicly unaccountable. And so, the lOO THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY liberal democracies of the West became the first great society to treat as a private concern the formative beliefs that shape the character of its citizens.

This has brought about a radical change in the mean-|, ing of freedom. Originally it was founded on the postu- late that there vi^as a universal order on w^hich all rea- sonable men were agreed: within that public agreement on the fundamentals and on the ultimates, it was safe to permit and it would be desirable to encourage, dissent and dispute. But with the disappearance of the public phi- losophy — and of a consensus on the first and last things — there was opened up a great vacuum in the public mind, yawning to be filled.

As long as it worked, there was an obvious practical advantage in treating the struggle for the ultimate alle- giance of men as not within the sphere of the public interest. It was a way of not having to open the Pandora's box of theological, moral and ideological issues which divide the Western society. But in this century, when the hard decisions have had to be made, this rule of has ceased to work. The expedient worked only as long as the general mass of the people were not seriously dissatisfied with things as they are. It was an expedient that looked towards reforms and improvement. But it as- sumed a society which was secure, progressive, expand- ing, and unchallenged. That is why it was only in the fine Victorian weather, before the storm clouds of the great wars began to gather, that the liberal democratic policy of public agnosticism and practical neutrality in ultimate issues was possible. THE ECLIPSE lOI

3. The Neglect of the Public Philosophy .

We come, then, to a crucial question. If the discussion of public philosophy has been, so to speak, tabled in the liberal democracies, can we assume that, though it is not being discussed, there is a public philosophy? Is there a body of positive principles and precepts which a good citizen cannot deny or ignore? I am writing this book in the conviction that there is. It is a conviction which I have acquired gradually, not so much from a theoretical education, but rather from the practical experience of seeing how hard it is for our generation to make democ-" racy work. I believe there is a public philosophy. Indeed

there is such a thing as the public philosophy of civility .

It does not have to be discovered or invented. It is known. But it does have to be revived and renewed.

The public philosophy is known as , a name which, alas, causes great semantic confusion.^ This phi- losophy is the premise of the institutions of the Western society, and they are, I believe, unworkable in communi- ties that do not adhere to it. Except on the premises of this philosophy, it is impossible to reach intelligible and workable conceptions of popular election, majority rule, representative assemblies, free speech, loyalty, property, corporations and voluntary associations. The founders of these institutions, which the recently enfranchised democ-

racies have inherited, were all of them adherents of some one of the various schools of natural law.

® Cf. Mortimer Adler, "The Doctrine of Natural Law in Philosophy," University of Notre Dame Natural Law Institute Proceedings, Vol. I, pp. 65-84. 102 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY

In our time the institutions built upon the foundations

'of the public philosophy still stand. But they are used by

.^ /a public- who are not being taught, and no longer adhere •^ !to, the philosophy. Increasingly, the people are alienated

from the inner principles of their institutions. The ques-

tion is whether and how this alienation can be overcome,

and the rupture of the traditions of civility repaired.

Needless to say I am not about to argue that the rup- ture can be repaired by a neo-classical or neo-medieval

restoration, or by some kind of romantic return to feudal- ism, folk-dancing and handicrafts. We cannot rub out the modern age, we cannot roll back the history that has

made us what we are. We cannot start again as if there had been no advance of science, no spread of and secularism, no industrial revolution, no dissolution of the old habitual order of things, no sudden increase in the

population. The poignant question is whether, and, if so,

how modern men could make vital contact with the lost,

traditions of civility.

The appearance of things is quite obviously unpromis-

ing. There is radical novelty in our modern ways of life.

The climate of feeling and the style of thought have

changed radically. Modern men will first need to be con-

vinced that the traditions of civility were not abandoned

because they became antiquated. This is one of the roots

of their unbelief and there is no denying its depth. Since the public philosophy preceded the advance of modern

science and the industrial revolution, how can it be ex-

pected to provide a positive doctrine which is directly

and practically relevant to the age we live in?

It does, one must admit, look like that, and quite evi- THE ECLIPSE IO3 dently the original principles and precepts do not now provide the specific rules and patterns of a way of life in the circumstances of this age. A rereading of the political classics from Aristotle to Burke will not give the answers to the immediate and concrete questions: to the burning issues of diplomacy, military defense, trade, taxes, prices, and wages. Nor have the classical books anything to say about repairing automobiles, treating poliomyelitis, or proceeding with nuclear fission. As handbooks for the busy man, wanting to know how to do this or that, they are now lamentably out of date. The language is archaic, the idiom is strange, the images are unfamiliar, the practi- cal precepts are addressed to forgotten issues.

But this irrelevance and remoteness might be the dust which has settled during the long time when philosophers and scholars and popular educators have relegated the public philosophy to the attic, when they have treated it as no longer usable by modern and progressive men. It is a neglected philosophy. For several generations it has been exceptional and indeed eccentric to use this philoso- phy in the practical discussion of public policies.

Neglect might well explain its dilapidated condition.

If this were the explanation, it would encourage us to explore the question of a renascence. Could, modern men again make vital contact with the traditions of civility?

At least once before something of the sort did happen. The traditions were articulated in the Graeco-Roman world, and submerged in the West by the decline and

the fall of the Western empire. Later on they were re- vived and renovated and remade in a great flowering

of discovery and enterprise and creativity. The revival of I04 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY learning did not provide maps for Columbus to use in discovering America. But it did produce much human wisdom which helped Columbus and his contemporaries to discover themselves and their possibilities. The ancient world, we may remind ourselves, was not destroyed because the traditions were false. They were submerged, neglected, lost. For the men adhering to them had become a dwindling minority who were overthrown and displaced by men who were alien to the traditions, having never been initiated and adopted into them. May it not be that while the historical circumstances are obvi- ously so different, something like that is happening again?

4. The Universal Laws of the National Order

FdR OVER two thousand years, says Barker, European thought has been acted upon by the idea that the ra- tional faculties of men can produce a common concep- tion of law and order which possesses a universal validity.

This conception was first formulated as a theory by Zeno and the Stoics. It was absorbed by the Roman lawyers, was adopted by the Christian fathers, was re-established and reworked by Saint Thomas Aquinas, and in a new formulation, after the Renaissance and Reformation, it provided the philosophy of the English Revolution of 1688 and of the American Revolution of 1776. The long life of this idea and, above all, the recurring revival of the idea in all ages, would seem to indicate that it re- flects a wide and recurring human need — that it is in- THE ECLIPSE IO5

volved with practical questions of policy in the face of recurring poHtical problems.

That the idea is not mere moonshine and cobwebs is attested by history. Barker tells us that in 330 B.C. Alexander was planning the empire in which he would be equally lord of the Greeks and the Persians, in which both Greeks and Persians would be equally bound to

perform military service, and would be encouraged to

intermarry. This was a revolutionary idea. Aristotle, who

was then teaching at the Lyceum, advised Alexander against a policy which would bring the two worlds — the Greek and the barbarian — into the same political sys- tem. Aristotle advised Alexander to deal with the Greeks

as a leader and with the Persians as a master. But Alexander rejected the advice, certainly for practi- cal reasons, and perhaps also for idealistic reasons. He

"acted in the spirit of the policy afterwards enunciated by Eratosthenes {an Alexandrian scholar of the next cen- tury} who, 'refusing to agree with men who divided

mankind into Greeks and barbarians . . . declared that it was better to divide men simply into the good and '" bad.'

In adopting this policy, Alexander anticipated in ac- tion what Zeno and the Stoics were soon to be teaching — that, as Plutarch wrote long afterwards, "men should not live their lives in so many civic republics, separated from one another by different systems of justice; they should reckon all as their fellow citizens, and there should be one life and one order (cosmos), as it were of

* Ernest Barker, Introduction to his translation of Aristotle's Politics (1946), p. lix. I06 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY one flock on a common pasture, feeding in common ^^ under one joint law." We must here dwell specially on the fact that Alexander anticipated in action what Zeno and the Stoics were soon to be teaching. This shows that the idea of a rational order is not only an attractive and a sublime conception but that it is a necessary assumption in the government of large and heterogeneous states. Alexander came to it in spite of Aristotle's teaching to the con- trary. His practical experience compelled him to see that in an empire which included the Persians as well as the Greeks there had to be a common law which was valid for both. To be valid for both the Greeks and the Per- sians, the law had in some significant degree to have their consent. The Persians could not be commanded^and coerced.

As in fact the laws were promulgated to the Persians by Alexander, who was a Greek, it was necessary to convince the Persians that Alexander's laws reflected something that was higher than the will and the inten- tions of the Greeks, something that was binding on both the Greeks and the Persians. That something was the faculty of distinguishing by reason the good and the bad. For this faculty was not peculiar to the Greeks but was common to both Persians and Greeks. Alexander had discovered empirically what Zeno was to formulate theoretically — that a lar^e plural society

cannot b^-gQxernedjwithoiiti^cQgnizing t^^^ trans^cend-

ing its plural interests, there is a rational order with a

^°lbid., lix-lx. Cf. Saint Paul on the One Church, which was "neither

Greek nor Jew . . . Barbarian, Scythian, bond nor free." THE ECLIPSE IO7 superior common law. This common law is "natural" in the sense that it can be discovered by any rational mind, that it is not the willful and arbitrary positive command of the sovereign^power/^ This is the necessary assump- tion, without which it is impossible for different peoples with their competing interests to live together in peace and freedom within one community. The Roman lawyers worked out what Alexander had anticipated and what the Stoics taught. By the time of Cicero there were, says Barker, three different bodies and conceptions of law.^" The first, called ms civile, was applicable only to Roman citizens. The second was a body of commercial laws, known as the ius gentium, that were enforced by the Roman courts in all commercial cases: "a common law of contract throughout the em-

''' pire."

The ins gentium was meant to contain what was com- mon and universal, separated from what was peculiar and local, in the laws of all states. And beyond this practical common law for commercial intercourse, the Roman jurists recognized that in theory there was also natural law, the ius nattirale, which is "the law imposed on mankind by common human nature, that is, by reason in response to human needs and instincts." " This is not, says Barker, "a body of actual law, which can be en-

forced in actual courts" . . . but "a way of looking at

things — a spirit of 'humane interpretation' in the mind

" Cf. Otto von Gierke, Natural Law and the Theory of Society, trans-

lated with an Introduction by Ernest Barker ( 1934) , Vol. I, pp. 224-225. ^^ Ibid., p. xxxvi. '^ F. de Zulueta, "The Science of Law," in The Legacy of Rome, edited by Cyril Bailey (Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1928), p. 202. " Ibid., p. 204. I08 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY of the judge and the jurist — which may, and does, af- fect the law which is actually enforced, but does so with- out being actual law itself." The idea of a universal rational order became sub-- stantial and effective in the Roman law. This was the law of a great society which did in fact bring peace and order to the Western world. The remembrance of the

Roman peace is stamped indelibly on the consciousness of Western men. After the fall of the Roman Empire, the Roman law, which was practiced in some degree almost everywhere, and was taught everywhere, was recognized as "the law of an international civilization and relatively ^^ universal." With the beginning of the new age, after 1500, Roman law, as codified and digested in the Corpus Juris of Justinian, was regarded as the concrete expression of universal human reason. When the question came to be asked, says Barker, "What does this conception of Natural Law actually contain or include?" the answer tends to be, during the Middle Ages generally and down to the rise of a new school of Natural Law after 1500,

"It contains or includes the whole of Roman law, which \ is, as a u'hole, both supremely reasonable and universally ^^ diffused, and is therefore natural."

5. The Rupture in Modern Times

The new school of natural law, which flourished from about 1500 to 1800, was a response to the pluralism of

" Gierke, op. cit., p. xxxix. THE ECLIPSE IO9 the modern age; to the rise of national states, to the schism of the Church, to the explorations and to the expansion of world commerce, to the advance of science and of secularism, to the progressive division and speciali- zation of labor. As the diversity of belief, opinion and interest became greater, the need for a common criterion and for common laws became more acute. The new school of natural law was able to meet this need until the end of the eighteenth century. That was long enough to preside over the founding of the British and the American constitutional orders, and of those which derive from them. But the school of natural law has not been able to cope with the pluralism of the later modern age — with the pluralism which has resulted from the industrial revolution and from the enfranchise- ment and the emancipation of the masses of the people. In the simple and relatively homogeneous society of the eighteenth century natural law provided the prin-

ciples of a free state. But then the mode of such thinking went out of fashion. In the nineteenth century little was done to remint the old ideas. They were regarded as obsolete and false, as hostile to the rise of democracy, and they were abandoned to the reactionaries. The great frame of reference to the rational order was missing. No body of specific principles and precepts was worked out in

order to regulate international relations, nor to cope with the problems raised by the industrial revolution and the advance of science and technology.

Yet, in^this_ pluralized and fragmenting society a public philosophy with common and binding principles was

more necessary than it had ever been. The proof of the IIO THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY

need is in the impulse to escape from freedom, which

Erich Fromm has described so well. ^^ It has been growing

'vVV-ti strongerjas the emancipation of the masses of the people from authorityjias brought the dissolution of public, gen-| '-'f^'-^'-^

"^^^^'^ '"'' eral, objective criteria of the true and the false, th^ right t '" and die wrong. "I can assure you," wrote Andre Gide '.r"! in 1928, "that the feeling of freedom can plunge the ' V''"

soul mto a sort or anguish. 1

"We know it from within, by a sort of immediate and personal experience," says Gilson, who was writing between the wars, that "Western culture was steadily

^^ following its process of dissolution." Similarly, Spengler's famous book on The Decline of the West was first pub- lished in 19 1 8 but it was written before the outbreak of the war. But until the historic disasters of our own time, the \

loneliness and anxiety of modern men had been private, i without public and overt political effect. As long as the public order still provided external security, their inner

insecurity was still a personal and private and inward af- fair. Since the breakdown of public order during thcs First World War, there has been no security for multi-f, tudes and no ease of mind for anyone. Observing the public disorder in which he himself had

always lived, and knowing how the inner disorder pro- voked ^he impulse to escape frorn it. Hitler conceived his doctrine. He had the insight of genius into human weak-

" Erich Fromm, Escape from Freedom. "T^e Journals of Andre Gide. translated by Justin O'Brien (1947-51), Vol. Ill, 1928-1939, entry for Nov. 15, 1928, p. 26. ^"Etienne Gilson, The Unity of Philosophical Experience, (1937), p. 271. THE ECLIPSE III

ness, and he wrote in Mein Kampf that the masses are

"like a woman . . . who will submit to the strong man

rather than dominate the weakling . . . the masses love the ruler rather than the suppliant, and inwardly they are ,,.C^'^ far more satisfied by a doctrine which tolerates no rival than by the grant of liberal freedom; they often feel at a

loss what to do with it, and even easily feel themselves ~^ deserted."

The masses that Hitler was planning to dominate are the modern men who find in freedom from the con-

straints of the ancestral order an intolerable loss of guid- ance and of support. With Gide they are finding that the

burden of freedom is too great an anxiety. The older structures of society are dissolving and they must make their way through a time of troubles. They have been taught to expect a steady progress towards a higher stand-

ard of life, and they have not been prepared to withstand

the frustrations of a prolonged crisis in the outer world

and the loneliness of their self-centered isolation.

They are the men who rise up against freedom, unable

to cope with its insoluble difficulties and unable to en- dure the denial of communion in public and common . They have found no answer to their need and no remedy for their anguish in the principles and practice of freedom as they have known them in the liberal democra-

cies of this century. There is a profound disorientation in their experience, a radical disconnection between the no-

tions of their minds and the needs of their . They have become the "lonely crowd" "^ that Riesman has de-

y\*-'-^-~y Uiu'Jk f, y.^-'A'^ jfv^^i-i ^ ™ Adolf Hitler, Mein Kampf (1939), p. 56. ^ David Riesman, . X^xiA^ 0-i,-Vj-v-<^ j^xi-^'W, 112 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY scribed. They are Durkheim's anomic mass. ^^ They_ are

Toynbee's f>roletarians who are "of" but not "in" the com- munity they, |ive in; for they have "no 'stake' in that com- munity^beyond the fact of its physical existence." Their

"true hallmark ... is neither poverty nor humble birth but is the consciousness — and the resentment that this consciousness inspires — of being disinherited." "^ They are, as Karl Jaspers says, men dissolved into "an anony- mous.mass" because they are "without an authentic world, yJ- "^ without provenance or roots," without, that is to say, belief and faith that they can live by.

"^ Emile Durkheim, Suicide.

'^Arnold Toynbee, A Study of History, (1951), Vol. I, p. 41; Vol. V, p.63. "^ Karl Jaspers, The Origin and Goal of History, translated from the German edition of 1949 by Michael Bullock (London, Routledge and Kegan Paul, Ltd., 1953), pp. 127-128. CHAPTER IX The Renewal of the PuMic Philosophy

I. The Capacity to Believe

The freedom which modern men are turned away from, not seldom with rehef and often with enthusiasm, is the hollow shell of freedom. The current theory of free- dom holds that what men believe may be important to them but that it has almost no public significance. The outer defenses of the free way of life stand upon the legal guarantees against the coercion of belief. But the citadel is vacant because the public philosophy is gone, and all that

the defenders of freedom have to defend in common is a public neutrality and a public agnosticism. Yet when we have demonstrated the need for the pub-

lic philosophy, how do we prove that the need can be sat- isfied? ^ Not, we may be sure, by exhortation, however

eloquent, to rise to the enormity of the present danger, still

less by lamentations about the glory and the grandeur

that are past. Modern men, to whom the argument is ad-|

dressed, have a low capacity to believe in the invisible, the I intangible, and the imponderable.

Exhortation can capture the will to believe. But of the

* 6. Cf. Leo Strauss, Natural Right and History ( 1953) , p. 114 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY will to believe there is no lack. The modern trouble is in a low capacity to believe in precepts which restrict and restrain private interests and desire. Conviction of the need of these restraints is difficult to restore once it has been radically impaired. Public principles can, of course, be imposed by a despotic government. But the public phi- losophy of a free society cannot be restored by fiat and by force. To come to grips with the unbelief which underlies the condition of anomy, we must find a way to re-establish confidence in the validity of public standards. We must renew the convictions from which our political morality springs.

In the prevailing popular culture all philosophies are the instruments of some man's purpose, all truths are self- centered and self-regarding, and all principles are the ra- tionalizations of some special interest. There is no public criterion of the true and the false, of the right and the wrong, beyond that which the preponderant mass of vot- ers, consumers, readers, and listeners happen at the mo- ment to be supposed to want.

There is no reason to think that this condition of mind can be changed until it can be proved to the modern skeptic that there are certain principles which, when they have been demonstrated, only the willfully irrational can deny, that there are certain obligations binding on all men who are committed to a free society, and that only the willfully subversive can reject them.

When I say that the condition of anomy cannot be cor- rected unless these things are proved to the modern skep- tic, I mean that the skeptic must find the proof compel- ling. His skepticism cannot be cured by forcing him to THE RENEWAL II5 conform. If he has no strong behefs, he will usually con- form if he is made to conform. But the very fact that he has been forced by the government or by the crowd will prove that the official doctrine lacked something in the way of evidence or of reason to carry full conviction. In the blood of the martyrs to intolerance are the seeds of unbelief.

In order to repair the capacity to believe in the public philosophy, it will be necessary to demonstrate the practi- cal relevance and the productivity of the public philoso- phy. It is almost impossible to deny its high and broad generalities. The difficulty is to see how they are to be ap- plied in the practical affairs of a modern state. We are back, in a manner of speaking, before the Ro- man lawyers worked out the ius gentium and related it to the ius naturale, back with Alexander the Great, who un- derstood the pressing need for common laws in a plural society, and with Zeno who formulated the higher gen- eralities. Given the practical need which is acute, and the higher generalities, which are self-evident, can we de- velop a positive working doctrine of the good society un- der modern conditions? The answer which I am making to this question is that it can be done if the ideas of the public philosophy are recovered and are re-established in i

the minds of men of light and leading./ - > - ^^^,/ '),,xj vv^'-'U-v'^)

2. VoY Example: The Theory of Property

Let us, then, put the matter to the test by applying the public philosophy to some of the great topics of our public life. Il6 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY

I shall begin with the theory of private property — before and after the loss of the public philosophy and the rupture of the traditions. We can do this conveniently by examining what Blackstone, working in the middle of the eighteenth century, does with the theory of private prop- erty. Blackstone's mind was formed in the classical tradi- tion. But Blackstone's world was in movement, and he was not equal to the creative effort of using the tradition to cope with the new circumstances. He had declared that security of the person was the first, that liberty of the individual was the second, and that property was "the third absolute right inherent in every Englishman." " But, as a civilized man, he had to do more than to assert the absolute right. He had "to examine more deeply the rudiments and grounds" ^ on which it could be justified rationally.

Between the lines of his elegant and stately prose one can see, I think, that Blackstone was puzzled. According to his tradition, the rational justification of property is as a system of corresponding and reciprocal rights and duties. In the public philosophy an absolute right to property, or to anything else that affects other men, cannot be en- tertained. To claim it is to be outside the law and the bounds of civility. This conception of property is most easily intelligible in a society where the principal forms of private property are in agricultural land. The land is visi- ble and its products are known to all. This lends itself to a definition of the corresponding rights and duties: of the

" Sir William Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of England, Book

I, Ch. I.

' Ibid., II, 1. THE RENEWAL II7 landlord with his tenants and hired workers below him in the hierarchy and above him with the sovereign power, claiming taxes and services. When the main forms of property are intangible the difl&culty of defining rights and duties is much greater. When Blackstone was writing, England was a rising com- mercial power and the comparatively simple problems of a society based on landed property were already over- taken by the problems of an economy in which property was owned as money, as commercial paper, as stocks and bonds. It was easy enough to assert rights to intangible property, but difficult to define the duties of intangible property. Yet unless that was done, property would not be under general laws.

Blackstone is in a way a tragic figure in that, thanks to his education, he had the intimation that the right direc- tion was to work toward bringing intangible property un- der public standards. Yet for one reason or another he did not take it. He was, however, troubled. He knew that

"nothing ... so generally . . . engages the affections of mankind" as that "sole and despotic dominion which one man claims and exercises over the external things of the world, in total exclusion of the right of any other in- dividual in the universe." But as a man steeped in the civilized traditions of the West, he knew, too that there must be rational limits put upon the acquisitive and pos- sessive instincts. As a man of the world, that is to say of his world and of the world that was to come, he Joiew also how little the rising men oLproperty wishedjojiear about obligations that would limit their absolute rights. So, with a certain regret, and perhaps with an intuitive Il8 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY foreboding, he wrote that "Pleased as we are with the pos- session, we seem afraid to look back to the means by which it was acquired, as if fearful of some defect in our

title . . . not caring to reflect that ( accurately and strictly speaking) there is no foundation in nature or in natural law, why a set of words upon parchment should convey the dominion of land: why the son should have a right to exclude his fellow-creatures from a determinate spot of ground, because his father had done so before him: or why the occupier of a particular field or of a jewel, when lying on his death-bed, and no longer able to maintain possession, should be entitled to tell the rest of the world ^ which of them should enjoy it after him." Blackstone thought that these questions which chal- lenge "the sole and despotic dominion" of the property holder, "would be useless and even troublesome in com- mon life." As a man of his world he felt bound to say that

"it is well if the mass of mankind will obey the laws when made, without scrutinizing too nicely into the reason for making them." But as one formed in the traditions of

civility, hejzould not ignore the question of whether there

was "some defect in our title" to absolute property. And

as an exponent of "rational science" he felt bound to ex- pound the classical conception of private property. He puts it this way: a man's property

. . . consists in the free use, enjoyment and disposal of all his acquisitions, without any control or diminution, save only by the

laws of the land. The original of private property is probably

founded in nature . . . but certainly the modifications under

which we at present find it, the method of conserving it in the

*lbid., II, I. THE RENEWAL II9

present owner, and of translating it from man to man, are entirely derived from society; and are some of those civil advantages in exchange for which every individual has resigned a part of his

natural liberty.'^

.- 'The rights of property, that is to say, are a creation of

^|he laws of the state. And since the laws can be altered, there are no absolute rights of property. There are legal

rights to use and to enjoy and to dispose of property. The laws define what are the rights to use and to enjoy and to dispose of property, which the courts will enforce.

For, says Blackstone . . .

The earth and all things therein are the general property of all

mankind, exclusive of other beings, from the immediate gift of the creator.

It is in order that, and only in order that, the earth may be enjoyed most fully that

. . . the legislature of England has universally promoted the grand ends of civil society, the peace and security of individuals, by steadily pursuing that wise and orderly maxim of assigning [Italics mine} to everything capable of ownership a legal and determinate owner.^

Conceived in this fashion, private property can never .^^,^^_..,.j ,^-i 4^'

be regarded as giving to any man an absolute title to ex- ^.^rj. iWUiiW 7 ercise "the sole and despotic dominion" over the land and

the resources of nature. The ultimate ti|le_jlQes_noLiie in

the owner. The title is in "mankind," in The People as a corporate community. The rights of the individual in that patrimony are creations of the law, and have no other validity except as they are ordained by law. The purpose

^ Ibid., I, I, 3. (Italics mine). ' Ibid., II, I. 120 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY of laws which estabhsh private property is not to satisfy the acquisitive and possessive instincts of the primitive man, but to promote "the grand ends of civil society" — which comprehend "the peace and security of individuals." Because the legal owner enjoys the use of a limited necessity belonging to all men, he cannot be the sovereign lord of his possessions. He is not entitled to exercise his absolute and therefore arbitrary will. He owes duties that correspond with his rights. His ownership is a grant made by the laws to achieve not his private purposes but the common social purpose. And, therefore, the laws of property may and should be judged, reviewed and, when necessary, amended, so as to define the specific system of rights_and duties that will promote the ends of society.

This is a doctrine of private property which denies the pretension to a "sole and despotic dominion." When Biackstone, though his conscience was troubled, accepted the sole and despotic dominion, he broke with the public philosophy and the traditions of civility. After his break the recognized theorists developed regressively the con- ception of private property as an absolute right. For a time they excluded from -political philosophy, from juris- prudence and from legislation, almost any notion that property had duties as well as rights.

, Absolute private property inevitably produced intoler- able evils. Absolute owners did grave damage to their neighbors and to their descendants: they ruined the fertil- ity, of the land, they exploited destructively the minerals under the surface, they burned and cut forests, they de- stroyed the wild life, they polluted streams, they cornered THE RENEWAL 121 supplies and formed monopolies, they held land and re- sources out of use, they exploited the feeble bargaining power of wage earners.

For such abuses of absolute property the political scien- tists_and the law makers had no remedy. They had lost •-» the tradition that property is the creation of the law for ;' social purposes. They had no principles by which the law couldTdieal wfth the abuses of property. The individualists of the nineteenth century could not, therefore, defend and preserve the system of private property by reforming it, and by adapting it to the circumstances of the modern age. They knew much about the rights of property and little about any corresponding duties. And so, because there was no legal remedy for the abuses of private property, because the duties which are the rational jus- tification of property were no longer defined and en- forced, the idea of private property lost its rational justification.

Between the property holders and the propertyless, who became the majority in many countries, there was, in consequence, no connecting bond, no consensus within the same realm of rational discourse. The proletariat had

the duty to respect the rights of owners. But the own-' ;; ers owed no reciprocal duty to the proletariat. There were*' V.^./, no obligations in which the proletarians found their ' righ^. Thus there arose the ominous phenomenon of "the i,J fii.iv-6^

-'^ ">'' two nations," the confrontation of those who owned the '"-''^'i ^^ earth by those who had nothing to lose. The latter were cs'-h'^ -^y more numerous than the former. As they acquired votes, r^t^.^'- the main issue in the domestic politics of the democracies ''''^V'k'/

- ^ became the struggle between the minority who had so ;• . 122 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY much absolute property and the great mass of the elector- ate who had so little property. To this conflict there have been and are_rwo possible outcomes: a gradual, cumulative, and perhaps at last a violent expropriation of the men of property — i>r re- forms of the laws of property which restore adequate- du- ties. But for several generations after Blackstone, the very idea of property as a system of duties was obscured. The public philosophy was discarded, and the most humane and enlightened men of the nineteenth century had little notion how rational reforms could be made. The alterna- tives, it appeared, were to defend absolute property against the growing discontent of the propertyless, or to abolish private property. It was a dangerous and a false dilemma. But in the nineteenth century this became the dilemma. The choice, it was said, was between individual- ism and collectivism, between Manchester and Marx, be- tween absolute property maintained by the force of the few and absolute property abolished by the dictatorship of the mass. The case of Blackstone has shown that a different and better theory of property was possible. It was possible if he and his successors had adhered to the public philoso- phy — if they had used, instead of abandoning, the prin- ciples which he stated so well. The earth is the general property of all mankind. Private titles of ownership are assigned by law-making authorities to promote the grand ends of civil society. Private property is, thereforg, a sys- tem of legal rights and duties. Under changing conditions the systernmust be kept in accord with the_grand ends of civil society. THE RENEWAL 123

Blackstone and his successors did not work out legal propositions from these principles.^ As I am contending that it would have been better if they had done so, I now ask myself what is the validity of these principles? Are they devices, like the rules of the road, for regulating the traffic? If they are only that, then another set of assump- tions could be just as valid, like the rule of the road in

Britain that one must drive to the left. One could, and in fact men have, constructed systems of property on quite different assumptions — on the assumption, for example, that the earth is the general property of white men only, or of a master race of white men, or of those castes which have not sinned in a previous incarnation. But if the prin- ciples are more than that, if they have a validity which overrides such special claims, what is the virtue which gives them their validity?

They are the laws of a rational order of human society

— in the sense that all men, when they are sincerely and lucidly rational, will regard them as self-evident. The ra- tional order consists of the terms which must be met in order to fulfill men's capacity for the good life in this world. They are-the terms of the widest consensus of ra^ tional men in a pluraLsQciety. They are the propositions to which all men concerned, if they are sincerely and lucidly rational, can be expected to converge. There could never be a consensus that Africa belongs to the descendants of the Dutch settlers; a property system founded on that pre- tension cannot be generally acceptable, and will generate disorder. The classical doctrine has a superior validity in that a system of property based upon it may obtain a con-

''Cf. my The Good Society, Ch. 12. 124 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY sensus of support in the community, and would have the prospect of being workable. When we speak of these principles asjiatural laws, we must be careful. They are not scientific "iaws" like the laws of the motions of the heavenly bodies. They do not describe human behavior as it is. They prescribe jwhat it should be. They do not enable us to predjct what men will actually do. They are the principles of right behavior in the good society, governed by the Western traditions of civility.

It is possible to organize a state and to conduct a gov- ernment on quite different principles. But the outcome will not be freedom and the good life.' ,^\^ ,JC ivu-ii |^\ 'l-o'

3. For Example: Freedom of Speech

Only within a community which adheres to tK^' public _^^^,^ philosophy is there sure and sufficient ground for the free- Ir'

dom to think and to ask questions, to speak and to publish. ,.h.-.^

Nobody can justify in principle, much less in practice, a ••••'-'^ claim that there exists an unrestricted right of anyone to '\ci^ utter anything he likes at any time he chooses. There can, for example, be no right, as Mr. Justice Holmes said, to cry "Fire" in a crowded theater. Nor is there a right to tell a customer that the glass beads are diamonds, or a voter that the opposition candidate for President is a So- viet agent. Freedom of speech has become a central concern of the Western society because of the discovery among the

Greeks that , as demonstrated in the Socratic dia- logues, is a principal method of attaining truth, and par- THE RENEWAL 125 ticularly a method of attaining moral and political truth.

"The ability to raise searching difficulties on both sides of a subject will," said Aristotle, "make us detect more easily ^ the truth and error about the several points that arise."

The right to speak freely is one of the necessary means to the attainment of the truth. That, and not the subjective of utterance, is why freedom is a necessity in the good society. This was the ground on which Milton in the Areopa- gitica opposed the order of Parliament (1643) that no book should be printed or put on sale unless it had first been licensed by the authorities:

As therefore the state of man now is; what wisdom can there be to choose, what continence to forbear without the knowledge

of evil? . . . Since therefore the knowledge and survey of vice is in this world so necessary to the constituting of human virtue, and the scanning of error to the confirmation of truth, how can we more safely, and with less danger, scout into the regions of sin and falsity than by reading aU manner of tractates and hearing ^ all manner of reason?

The method of is to confront ideas with op- posing ideas in order that the pro and the con of the dis-

pute will lead to true ideas. But the dispute must not be I

treated as^jtrial of strength. It must be a means of eluci- dation. In a Socratic dialogue the disputants are arguing co-operatively in order to acquire more wisdom than either of them had when he began. In a sophistical argu-

ment the is out to win a case, using and

not dialectic. "Both alike," says Aristotle, "are concerned

^Topics, Bk. I. Ch. i, 101335. "Milton's Areopagitka (Oxford University Press, 1949), pp. 18-19. !

126 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY with such things as come, more or less, within the general ken of all men and belong to no definite science." '" But while "dialectic is a process of criticism wherein lies the

^^ path to the principles of all inquiries," "rhetoric is con- ^" cerned with the modes of persuasion."

Divorced from its ori_ginal purpose and justification, as j> a process of__criticism, freedom to think and speak are not self-eviderit_jiecessides. It is only from the hope and the intention of discovering truth that freedom acquires such high public significance. The right of self-expression is, as such, a private amenity rather than a public necessity. The right to utter words, whether or not they have meaning, and regardless of their truth, could not be a vital interest of a great state but for the presumption that they are the chaff which goes with the utterance of true and significant words.

But when the chaff of silliness, baseness, and deception is so voluminous that it submerges the kernels of truth, freedom of speech may produce such frivolity, or such mischief, that it cannot be preserved against the demand for a restoration of order or of decency. If there, is. a divid-'| ing line between liberty and license, it j_s.^whei£j[reedom| of speech is no longer respected as a proc;g4ure- of thei truth and becomes the unrestricted right to exploit the ignorance, and to incite the passions, of the people. Then freedom is such a hullabaloo of sophistry, propaganda, special pleading, lobbying, and salesmanship that it is dif- ficult to remember why freedom of speech is worth the and trouble of defending it.

^"Rhetoric, Bk. I, Ch. i, 135431-3. ^^ Topics, Bk. I, Ch. 2, ioib3-4.

^^ Rhetoric, Bk. I, Ch. i, 135534. THE RENEWAL 127

WhatJias been lost in the tumult is the meaning of the obligation which is involved in .the_righL.to speak freely.

It is tlie 'obligation to subject_th£ utterance to criticism |-^ and debate. Because jhe dialectical debate is a procedure* for attaining motal and political truth, the righLIQ=-speak is protected by a willingness to debate.

In the public philosophy, freedom of speech is con- ceived as the means to a confrontation of opinion — as in a Socratic dialogue, in a schoolmen's disputation, in the critiques of scientists and savants, in a court of law, in a representative assembly, in an open forum.

Even at the canonisation of a saint, [says John Stuart Mill} the church admits and listens patiently to a "devil's advocate."

The holiest of men, it appears, cannot be admitted to posthumous honors, until all that the devil could say against him is known and weighed. If even the Newtonian philosophy were not permitted to be questioned, mankind could not feel as complete assurance of its truth as they now [1859} do. The beliefs which we have most warrant for, have no safeguard to rest on, but a standing invitation to the whole world to prove them unfounded. If the challenge is not accepted, or is accepted and the attempt fails, we are far enough from certainty still; but we have done the best that the existing state of human reason admits of; we have neglected nothing that could give the truth the chance of reach- ing us: if the lists are kept open, we may hope that if there be a better truth, it will be found when the human mind is capable of receiving it; and in the meantime we may rely on having at- tained such approach to truth, as is possible in our day. This is the amount of certainty attainable by a fallible being, and this is the sole way of attaining it.^^

^^ J. S. Mill, On Liberty. In On Liberty, Representative Government, The Subjection of Women (London, Oxford University Press, 1946), Ch. II, pp. 28-29. 128 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY

And because the purpose of the confrontation is to dis- cern truth, there are rules of evidence and of parHamen- tary procedure, there are codes of fair deaHng and fair comment, by which a loyal man will consider himself bound when he exercises the right to publish opinions.

For the right to freedom of speech is no license to deceive, and willful misrepresentation is a violation of its princi- ples. It is sophistry to pretend that in a free country a man has some sort of inalienable or constitutional right to de- ceive his fellow men. There is no more right to deceive than there is a right to swindle, to cheat, or to pick pock- ets. It may be inexpedient to arraign every public liar, as we try to arraign other swindlers. It may be a poor policy to have too many laws which encourage litigation about matters of opinion. But, in principle, there can be no im- munity for lying in any of its protean forms.

. In our time the application of these fundamental prin-

ciples poses_.^many unsolved practical problems . For the modern media of ma.ss communication do not lend them- selves easily to a confrontation of opinions. The dialectical process for finding truth works best when the same audi- ence hears all the sides of the disputation. This is mani- festly impossible in the moving pictures: if a film advo- cates a thesis, the same audience cannot be shown another film designed to answer it. Radio and television broadcasts do permit some debate. But despite the effort of the com- panies to let opposing views be heard equally, and to or- ganize programs on which there are opposing speakers, the technical cgnditioas of broadcasting do not favor gen-l uine and productive debate. For the audience, tuning on- and tuning off here and there, cannot be counted upon to THE RENEWAL 129 hear, even in summary form, the essential evidence and

the main arguments on all the significant sides of a ques-

tion. Rarely, and^on very few public issues, does the mass ^ ^-

audience have the benefit of the process by which truth isr'''^t ,, Vi,. sifted from error the dialectic of debate in which there — ] ^ ^'"^J^ j,^,,

.," is immediate ^ challenge, reply, cross-examination, and te-[ .^. i .^•u.tJbyk ^"^^'"^ . buttal. The men who resularly broadcast the news and '

comment the cannot like a speaker in the , . _ »- upon news — ;,

Senate or in the House of Commons — be challenged by ''f . r ^^ '"* one of their listeners and compelled then and there to '" verify their statements of fact and to re-argue their infer- ences from the facts.

Yet when genuine debate is lacking, freedom of speech does not work as it is meant to work. It has lost the prin- ciple which regulates it and justifies it — that is to say, dialectic conducted according to and the rules of evidence. If there is no effective debate, the unrestricted right to speak will unloose so many propagandists, procur- ers, and panderers upon the public that sooner or later in self-defense the people will turn to the censors to protect them. An unrestricted and unregulated right to speak can- not be maintained. It will be curtailed for all manner of reasons and pretexts, and to serve all kinds of good, fool- ish, or sinister ends. For in the absence_of debate unrestricted utterance ^^-.-u^^ M ' leads to the degradation of opinion. By a kind of Gresh- am's law the more ratipnal_js^ overcome by the less ra- tional, and the opinions that will prevail will be those which are held most ardently by those with the most pas- sionate wi ll. For that reason the freedom to speak can never be maintained merely by objecting to interference 130 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY with the hberty of the press, of printing, of broadcasting, of the screen. It can be maintained only by promoting -i~- debate.

In the end what men will most ardently desire is to sup- press those who disagree with them and, therefore, stand in the way of the realization of their desires. Thus, once confrontation in debate is no longer necessary, the tolera- tion of all opinions leads to intolerance. Freedom of speech, separated from its essential principle, leads through a short transitional chaos to the destruction of freedom of speech.

It follows, I believe, that in the practice of freedom of speech, the degree of toleration that will be maintained is directly related to the effectiveness of the confrontation in debate which prevails or can be organized. In the Senate of the United States, for example, a Senator can promptly be challenged by another Senator and brought to an ac- counting. Here among the Senators themselves the condi- tions are most nearly ideal for the toleration of all opin-

^* ions. At the other extreme there is the secret circulation of anonymous allegations. Here there is no means of chal- lenging the author, and without any violation of the prin- ciples of freedom, he may properly be dealt with by detec- tives, by policemen, and the criminal courts. Between such extremes there are many problems of toleration which de- pend essentially upon how effective is the confrontation in debate. Where it is efficient, as in the standard news- paper press taken as a whole, freedom is largely unre- stricted by law. Where confrontation is difficult, as in broadcasting, there is also an acceptance of the principle

^* For non-Senators attacked by Senators the case is different. }

THE RENEWAL I3I that some legal regulation is necessary — for example, in order to insure fair play for political parties. When con- frontation is impossible, as in the moving picture, or in the so-called comic books, there will be censorship.

4. The Limits of Dissent

The counterrevolutionary movements have subjected the

liberal democracies to severe stresses and strains : how to t insure their security and survival without abandoning their liberties. They are faced with popular movements, aided and abetted by unfriendly foreign powers, and employing the machinery of democratic government to capture it and in order to abolish it. When they are working to attain power and before they do attain it, the fascist and commu- nist parties invoke all the guarantees of the bill of rights, all the prerogatives of popular parties, of elections, of rep- resentation of the assemblies, of tenure in the civil service.

But when they attain power, they destroy the liberal demo- cratic institutions on which, as on a broad staircase, they climbed to power.

This ploitation of free institutions is, it seems to me, ex {^{i!^, yuu^ Ul^<

compelling proof^hat these institutions are inseparable vs. '«^A*<- from the public philosophy. If the connection is forgotten,

'' " "^ as is so generally the case in the contemporary democra- '

cies, free institutions are poorly defended by the liberal democracies. They are the easy prey of their enemies.

Either the fascists seize power in order to forestall the

communists, or the communists seize power to forestall

the fascists. 132 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY

There is no equivocation in the pubhc philosophy about the principle of the defense of free institutions. The rule is that the right to enjoy them and the duty to maintain them are inseparable. The right to these institutions is, that is to say, for those who adhere to them.

The criterion of loyalty is an indubitable commitment to defend and preserve the order of political and civil rights. The question of whether the liberal democratic states should outlaw, or in other ways contain, counter- revolutionary movements is not one of principle but of expediency and practical prudence. There is no doubt about the principle: that the counterrevolutionary move- ments are enemies of the state, and must be defeated.

In applying the principle the specific question of whether this party or that individual is or is not loyal is a matter to be determined by due process. For while there can be no right to destroy the liberal democratic state, there is an inalienable right to have the question ad- judicated justly in all particular cases as to whether this person or that is an enemy of the state. This right cannot be denied to those who have not been proved guilty without denying it to all who would be proved not guilty.

The limits of dissent are not too difficult to fix when we are dealing with avowedly revolutionary parties like the communists and the fascists. The borderline between sedition and radical reform is between the denial and the acceptance of the sovereign principle of the public phi- losophy: that we live in a rational order in which by sin- cere inquiry and rational debate we can distinguish the true and the false, the right and the wrong. The counter- THE RENEWAL I33 revolutionists, who suppress freedom in order to propa- gate the official doctrine, reject the procedure by which in the free society official policy is determined.

Rational procedure is the ark of the covenant of the \ j.

public philosophy. There js no set of elejction laws .^^ ^-^\ or constitutional guarantees which are unchangeable. jX^v^^*^^

What is unchangeable is the commitment to rational ^^(.t't r^,>-^- determination, the commitment to act in public life on the assumption which C. S. Peirce stated as fol- lows:

Human opinion universally tends in the long run to a definite form, which is the truth. Let any human being have enough in- formation and exert enough thought upon any question, and the result will be that he will arrive at a certain definite conclusion, which is the same that any other mind will reach under sufficiently

favorable circumstances. . . . There is, then, to every question a true answer, a final conclusion, to which the opinion of every man is constantly gravitating. He may for a time recede from it, but give him more experience and time for consideration, and he will finally approach it. The individual may not live to reach the truth; there is a residuum of error in every individual's opinions.

No matter; it remains that there is a definite opinion to which the mind of man is, on the whole and in the long run, tending.

On many questions the final agreement is already reached, on all it will be reached if time enough is given. The arbitrary will or other individual peculiarities of a sufficiently large number of minds may postpone the general agreement in that opinion in- definitely; but it cannot affect what the character of that opinion shall be when it is reached. This final opinion then is independent, not indeed of thought in general, but of all that is arbitrary and individual in thought; is quite independent of how you, or I, or any number of men, think. ^^

^^ Cited in Herbert W. Schneider, A History of (1946), p. 517. From a review of Eraser's Works of George Berkeley in North American Review, Vol. CXIII (1871), pp. 455-456. 134 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY

It is not possible to reject tliis faith in the efficacy of reason and at the same time to believe that communities of men enjoying freedom could govern themselves suc- cessfully.

5. The Mirror of History

We find, then, that the principle of freedom of sj^eech, like that of private property, falls within the bounds of the publicph i 1 osophy. It can ^e justified, applied, regu- lated in a plural society only by adhering to the postulate that there is a_rational order of things in which i tis pos- sible, by sincere inmiiry and rational debate, to distin- guish the true and thejFalse, the right and the wrong, the good which leads to the realization of human ends and the evil which leads to destruction and to the death of civility.

The free political institutions of the Western world were conceived and established by men who believed that honest reflection on the common experience of mankind would always cause men to come to the same ultimate conclusions. Within the Golden Rule of the same philoso- phy for elucidating their ultimate ends, they could engage with confident hope in the progressive discovery of truth.

All issues could be settled by scientific investigation and by free debate if — but only if — all the investigators and the debaters adhered to the public philosophy; if, that is to say, they used the same criteria and rules of reason for arriving at the truth and for distinguishing . THE RENEWAL I35

Quite evidently, there is no clear sharp line which can be drawn in any community or among communities be- tween those who adhere and those who do not adhere to the public philosophy. But while there are many shades and degrees in the spectrum, the two ends are well- defined. When the adherence of the whole body of peo-; pie to the public philosophy is firm, a true community ex4 ists; where there is division and dissent over the main principles the result is a condition of latent war.

In the maintenance and formation of a true community the articulate philosophy is, one might say, like the thread which holds the pieces of the fabric together. Not every- one can have mastered the philosophy; most people, pre- sumably, may have heard almost nothing about it. But if among the people of light and. leading the public philoso- phy has, as the Chinese say, the Mandate of Heaven, the beliefs and the habits which cause men to collaborate will remain^ whole. But if the public philosophy is discarded among them, being treated as reactionary or as nonsensi- cal, then the stitches will have been pulled out and the fabric will come apart.

The fabrics_in the metaphor are the traditioiis of how the good life is lived and the good, society is governed. When the^cQme_apMt^as they have in the Western de- mocracies, the result is tantamount to a kind of collective amnesia. The liberal democracies have been making mis- takes in peace and in war which they would never have made were they not suffering from what is a failure of memory. They have forgotten too much of what their predecessors had learned before them. The newly en- franchised democracies are like men who have kept their 136 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY appetites but have forgotten how to grow food. They have the perennial human needs for law and order, for freedom and justice, for what only good government can give them. But the art of governing welLhas to be learned. If it is to be learned, it has to be transmitted from the old to the young, and the habits and the ideas must be main- tained as a seamless web of memory among the bearers of the tradition, generation after generation.

When the continuity ofjhej^aditions^of civility is rup-"\

tured, the community is threatened: unless the rupture is i repaired, the community will break down into factional, } class, racial and regional wars. For when the continuity is interrupted, the cultural heritage is not being trans- \ mitted. The new generation is faced with the task of re- discovering and re-inventing and relearning, by trial and error, most of what the guardians of a society need to know.

No one generation can do this. For no one generation of men are capable of creating for themselves the arts and sciences of a high civilization. Men can know more than their ancestors did if they start with a knowledge of what their ancestors had already learned. They can do ad- vanced experiments if they do not have to learn all over again how to do the elementary ones. That is why a so- ciety can be progressive only if it conserves its traditions.

The generations are, as Bernard of Chartres said, "like dwarfs seated on the shoulders of giants," enabled, there- fore, to "see more things than the Ancients and things ^^ more distant."

"Cited in fitienne Gilson, The Spirit of (1940). p. 426. THE RENEWAL 137

But traditions are more than the culture of the arts and sciences. They are the pubHc world to which our private worlds are joined. This continuum of public and pri- vate memories transcends all persons in their immediate and natural lives and it ties them all together. In it there is performed the mystery by which individuals are adopted and initiated into membership in the commu- nity.

The body which carries this mystery is the history of the community, and its central theme is the great deeds and the high purposes of the great predecessors. From them the new men descend and prove themselves by be- coming participants in the unfinished story.

"Where I belong," says Jaspers, "and what I am living ^^ for, I first learned in the mirror of history." When the individual becomes civilized he acquires a second nature.

This second nature is made in the image of what he is and is living for and should become. He has seen the im- age in the mirror of history. This second nature, which rules over the natural man, is at home in the good society.

This second nature is no proletarian but feels itself to be a

rightful proprietor and ruler of the community. Full al-i , -. legiance to a the community can be given only by man's ^ di^''l second nature, ruling over his first and primitive nature,! (^^_^ ^ ^J and treating it as not finally himself. Then the disciplines and the necessities and the constraints of a civilized life have ceased to be alien to him, and imposed from without. ^* They have become his own inner imperatives.

"Karl Jaspers, Origin and Goal of History (1953), p. 271. ^* Cf. my Preface to Morals. 138 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY

6. Man's Second Nature

In the dialogues recounting the death of Socrates, Plato has painted the classic portrait of the civilized citizen. On the afternoon of his execution, Socrates is arguing with his friends. The jailers have left the door of the prison open, and Socrates is explaining why he refuses to escape.

. . . The Athenians have thought fit to condemn me, and accord- ingly I have thought it better and more right to remain here and undergo my sentence; for I am inclined to think that these muscles and bones of mine would have gone off long ago to Megara or

Boeotia — by the dog of Egypt they would, if they had been moved only by their own idea of what was best, and if I had not chosen as the better and nobler part, instead of playing truant and running away, to undergo any which the state inflicts. There is surely a strange confusion of causes and condi- tions in all this. It may be said, indeed, that without bones and muscles and the other parts of the body I cannot execute my purposes. But to say that I do as I do because of them, and that this is the way in which mind acts, and not from the choice of the best, is a very careless and idle mode of speaking.-^^

Socrates is saying that he, himself, is not the organism of his muscles and his bones, his reflexes, affections and instincts. He, Socrates, is the person who governs that or- ganism. He exercises what Saint Thomas Aquinas called "a royal and politic rule" over his "irascible and concupis- cible powers." These powers of the organism, its first nature, are, as Cardinal Newman said, "ever insurgent against reason." But Socrates is the ruler of that organism.

He is the "I" who can say "if Z had not chosen" to rule them, then they would have rebelled and run away. This

'^'^Phaedo, 98-99. In The Dialogues of Plato, translated by B. Jowett (1937)- ,

THE RENEWAL 139

Socrates who rules them is the adopted and initiated citizen of Athens. They are the appetites and instincts of

the natural man. For one who is ruled by his appetites is a barbarian, and quite incapable of being an Athenian citizen.

The friends of Socrates, who were there on that last day, would perhaps have said that it was only "human" that he should want to run away when he had the chance.

But Socrates chose to afHrm the opposite, to insist that he

was most fully human because he was willing and able to govern his desires.

Needless to say the lesson of this great story is not

servility and conformism, and it does not carry any im- plication that the people of Athens who condemned Soc-

rates were right in their judgment. As Crito says, when he has closed his eyes, "of all the men of his time whom

I have known he was the wisest and justest and best."

The point of the story is that Socrates would not save him-

self because an Athenian citizen could not cheat the law, least of all for his own personal advantage. ^° If Athens

was to be governed, it must be by citizens whc by their

second natures preferred the laws to the satisfaction of

their own impulses, even to their own will to live. Unless the citizens would govern themselves with such authority,

the Athenian city would be ungovernable. If they fol-

lowed their first natures, Athens would be trampled down in the stampede.

This is theJimge_ofaman who has become fit tgjrule.

He is ruled wijhin by his second and civilized nature. His

true self exercises the power of life and death over his

natural self. For it is the true person who has qualified as

"^ibid., 118. 140 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY proprietor of the laws and institutions of Athens and of the ideal of life which they serve. The necessities and the purposes of Athenian life are not something outside of

Socrates, something alien, extraneous, imposed and only reluctantly conformed with. They are the ends of his own true character, established in that part of his being which he calls himself.

This is the inwardness of the ruling man — whatever

his titles and his rank — that for the .sake of his realm, of :

his order, of his regiment, of his ship, of his cause, he_is : yj)-^'

his the noble master of owruweaker and meaner passionsj, i.>^' 'f

Although this is the aristocratic code, it is not inherent in prerogative and birth. It is functional to the capacity to rule. It is because aristocrats have been rulers, and not be- cause they were born into the aristocracy, that they have held themselves to the aristocratic . When, like the French nobles on the eve of the Revolution, they have lost the self-mastery which is the principle of the ruling man, they are unable to rule. Then, if they cling too long to their privileges, many of them will lose their noble heads. CHAPTER X The Two Realms

I. The Confusion of the Realms

Against man living in the civilized tradition, who like' Socrates rules his private impulses by the laws of the pub- lic worMr there are arrayed the great adversaries. They tempt him with a total prornise — that in a short and glorious struggle they will take him into the earthly heaven where he will realize all his hopes. The root of the matter is in these two conceptions of the human condi- tion, and the ultimate issue is in the conflict between

them. . ^.^ As the bitter^nd has become visible in the countries of the total revolution, we can see how desperate is the pre- dicament of modern men. The terrible events show that the harder they try to make earth into heaven, the more they make it a hell.

Yet, the yearning for salvation and for perfection is most surely not evil, and it is, moreover, perennial in the human soul. Are men then doomed by the very nature of things to be denied the highest good if it cannot be ma- terialized in this world and if, as so large a number of modern men assume, it will not be materialized in an- other world? 142 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY

The answer to this question is known. It can be had by recognizing the difference between the realm of existence where objects are materiahzed to our senses, and the realm of essence, where they are present to the mind. I am using the ambiguous but irreplaceable word "essence" as meaning the true and undistorted nature of things. The understanding of our relation to these two realms of be- ing is exceedingly difficult to communicate, so difHcult that, as a matter of fact, it has remained an esoteric wis- dom.

Yet if there is a way out of the modern predicament, it begins, I believe, where we learn to recognize the differ- ence between the two realms. For the radical^ error oi-the modern democratic gospel is that it promises, not the good life of this world, but thejeriecLJife of heaven. The root of the error is the confusion of the two realms — that of this world where the human condition is to be born, to live, to work, to struggle and to die, and that of the tran- scendent world in which men's souls can be regenerate and at peace. The confusion of these two realms is an ulti- mate disorder. It inhibits the good life in this world. It falsifies the life of the spirit.

2. The Good in This World

The ideals of the good life and of the good society fail far short of perfection, and in speaking of them we must not use superlatives. They are worldly ideals, which raise no expectations about the highest good. Quite the con- trary. They are concerned with the best that is possible among mortal and finite, diverse and conflicting men. THE TWO REALMS 143

Thus the id£als_ of freedom, justice, representation, con- sent,_law, arejof_th£^_^arth, earthy. They are for men who are still (as Saint Paul says in Timothy I, 9-10) under th? law. For

. . . the law js_nQL_aiade for a righteous man, but for the lawless and disobedient, for the ungodly and for sinners, for unholy and profane, for murderers of fathers and murderers of mothers, for manslayers,

For whoremongers, for them that defile themselves with man-

kind, for menstealers, for liars, for perjured persons . . .

The word "freedom" has several meanings. But none would have occurred to anyone who had not been in the human condition of diversity and conflict, who had not known the issues of life among worldly men and the fini- tude of his own powers. We can, for example, distinguish three principal mean- ings to the term. Each has been the formative principle of a school of thought.

There is Hobbes, who said that "liberty or freedom, signifieth (properly) the absence o£^pposition." ^ In his use of the word, we are free in respect to all the actions which no one else prevents us from doing.

There is a meaning given to the word "liberty" by Locke: "the power a man has to do or forebear doing any particular action." Here we are not free merely because we may do something; we must also be^hlejJO^djDJr, — we must have the faculty for doing it and the means to do it.

The word "freedom" has still another meaning in the

^Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan (Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1943), Part II, Ch. XXI. John Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, edited by A. C. Fraser. (Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1894), Vol. I, Bk. II, Ch. XXI, Sec. 15. 144 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY classical and Christian tradition. As Montesquieu put it, freedom "can consist only in the power of doing what we (5ught to will, and in not being constrained to do what we ought not to will."^ We are free if we have the faculty of knowing what we ought to do and the will to do it. These are not merely verbal differences, arising from ambiguity or equivocation. They are rather facets of a complex idea. For when any one of the meanings is put to a practical test, almost invariably we have to turn to the other meanings to correct its deficiencies. It is, therefore, impossible to choose one meaning, rejecting all the others, or, in fact, to come to rest in a conclusion which fixes a total meaning.

There is no final resting point, because "in the flux of things," as William James says, "things are off their bal- ance. Whatever equilibrium our finite attain

to are but provisional . . . everything is in ... a sur- rounding world of other things." And "if you leave it to work there, it will inevitably meet with friction and op- position from its neighbors. Its rivals and enemies will destroy it unless it can buy them off by compromising some part of its original pretensions."^

Words like liberty, equality, fraternity, justice, have various meanings which reflect the variability of the flux of things. The different meanings are rather like different clothes, each good for a season, for certain weather and for a time of day, none good for all times. In the infinite change and diversity of the actual world, our conceptual

^ Charles de Montesquieu, The Spirit of Laivs, Bk. XI, 3. * William James, A Pluralistic Universe. In Essays in Radical Empiri- cism and A Pluralistic Universe (1947), pp. 88, 90. THE TWO REALMS I45 are never exactly and finally the whole truth.

For, as James said, while "the essence of life is its con-

tinually changing character . . . our concepts are all dis- continuous and fixed." Like a winter overcoat, none can be worn with equal comfort in January and in July. Yet the summer will end, it too being subject to change. There will come a season and a time for wearing the warmer coat. So it is a mistake to think that we could. -1^\A(.^'"^ wear the same coat all the time, and a mistake to throw it ,..,rv'tH ,;i'*'-''^ away, supposing in the summer that it will never be win- ..^..trv'-- ter again.

This is the human condition. To it, in the traditions of civili0^s addressed the worldly;jwisdom of the good life. In this actual world of diversity and change, how do we find the right rule? We shall not find it, says Aristotle, if we look for more "clearness" than "the subject matter ad- mits of." ^' Matters concerned with conduct and what is good for us have no fixity," and, he added, "the agents themselves must in each case consider what is appropriate ^ to the occasion." But the agents, we may note, do not improvise a rule which they consider appropriate to the occasion. They "con- sider" something. And that something, says Aristotle, is that "it is the nature of things" — including the nature of the worldly virtues — "to be destroyed by defect and ex- cess." The problem, then, is to discern "the mean" — the point between excess and defect where the good, which the virtue aims at, is preserved.

That would be less difficult to do than in fact it is if the

^ Nicomachean Ethics, Book I, Ch. 2, 1094b. 12. ^ Ibid., Book II, Ch. 2, 1104a. 9. 146 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY mean between excess and defect were a fixed point. But

it is not. Ttie defect of , says Aristotle, is coward-

ice, as when a man "flies from and fears everything and does not stand his ground against anything." The excess of courage is the rashness of a man "who fears nothing

at all but goes to meet every danger." But to say this does

not fix the mean in such a way that each man knows, as he knows when the traffic light is red or green, just when he should stand his ground and when he should not. To expect to be given — to expect not to have to judge and find — the fixed points which are the mean in each particular case is, says Aristotle, to ask for more precision than can be given to this subject. We must not think of the mean as being a fixed point between the extremes. When we do that, we are allowing ourselves to suppose that the mean is the point at which a kind of bargain is struck between 50 per cent of excess and 50 per cent of deficiency. But that is not the true mean. Courage is not half cowardice and half rashness. is not half self-indulgence and half complete abstinence. Th^^rue ,u^ -•>

mean is at the tension of push and pull, qfjttraction and,>:f^'-\^'

resistance among the extremes. ;l^^^""^

The outcome, as Aristotle said it would be, is imprecise

and inconclusive, and there is little reason to think that

the wisdom of the world can ever rise above these imper- fections.

3. The Law and the Prophets

Nor does the wisdom of the spirit solve precisely the

perplexing problems of worldly conduct. For it is the vi- THE TWO REALMS 147 sion of a realm of being in which the problems of earthly existence are not solved but transcended. In the immediate, urgent, and particular issues of daily life the major prophets, the seers and the sages, have re- markably little to offer by way of practical advice and specific guidance. The deposit of wisdom in the Bible and in the classic books does not contain a systematic and com- prehensive statement of moral principles from which it is possible to deduce with clarity and certainty specific an- swers to concrete questions. He who goes to this wisdom looking for guidance of this sort will be disappointed. If he finds it there, he must come to it by analogy and by inference. The specific rules of conduct are not explicitly there. Were they there, the history of mankind would have been different. For terrible wars and poisonous ha- treds arise among men who draw irreconcilably different practical conclusions from the same general principles.

There is a hiatus between the highest wisdom and the actual perplexities with which men must deal. An ency- clopedia of all that the prophets and the philosophers have taught will not tell a man clearly and definitely how to make laws, how to govern a state, how to educate his children — how, in fact, to decide the problems that the priest encounters in the confessional, the doctor with his patients, the lawyer with his clients, the judge with the litigants, the man of affairs in his business. Faced with practical decisions, they need to know what choice they should make among the alternatives. But con-

crete guidance of this sort can be found only incidentally in the words of the prophets and the philosophers. They have not compiled systematic codes of specific rules for 148 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY concrete cases. These codes are in the books of the scribes, the casuists, the lawgivers and the judges, and their author- ity is imputed. It rests on the assumption that the specific rules of conduct are implicit in the inspired utterance, and have merely been deduced from it. The recorded sayings of Jesus and the Apostles do not contain a comprehensive body of laws and of precepts for the ordering of men's lives. In fact the Apostles seem not to have realized the need of a clear record of the sacred deposit. According to Eusebius (VI, L-4), when Peter in Rome learned that Mark remembered his sayings and was writing them down, "he neither directly forbade nor en- couraged it." The voluminous and very detailed corpus of

Christian laws is the work of popes, bishops, councils, can- onists, casuists, doctors and writers of textbooks. The work began immediately after the apostolic age.

The Reverend Thomas J. Slater, S.J., the author of a leading Catholic manual of moral for English- speaking countries, says that "the Gospels contain a short summary of the teaching of Jesus Christ; this is developed somewhat in certain directions in the other writings of thf New Testament, but the preachers of the Word soon found it convenient to have by them brief summaries of the moral teaching of our Lord by itself." ' In response to this need there was written, as early as the end of the first century, such works as the Didacke, or the Teaching of the Twelve Apostles and the Pastor of Hennas. The

Didache, says Father Slater, is the first handbook of mor- als which comes down to us. It lays down the two moral

'' Thomas J. Slater, A Manual of Moral Theology for English-Speaking Countries (5th ed.), Vol. II, p. 308. THE TWO REALMS 1 49 principles of love of God and of neighbor, and then — because it is a book addressed to the practical difl&culties of men — it sets out -to- specify the principal positive and negative duties that men owe to their parents, children, servants, neighbors and the poor. The working out of comprehensive systems of specific rules for life in this world became necessary in connection with the peniten- -^ tial system which was organized in the sixth, seventh and eighth centuries.^ When the Fourth Lateran Council in

12 1 5 made confession of sin obligatory upon the faithful at least once a year, it was necessary to have comprehen- sive reference books to guide the priest in the confessional concerning the great variety of human issues.^ The great jnultitudgs_^oL nien everywhere and always | have_demanded detailed_coji£S_oi_ conduct. They are neces- sary to their comfort, their convenience ancithe|r peace of mind, and no religion with a mass following is with- out its manuals of casuistry, its Koran, its Talmud, its

Calvin's Institutes. For those who can live by the spirit alone have always been a mere handful, little groups here and there, shiit away from and exalted above the nor- mal life of their times. Without the casuists, who legislate the specific rules, translating and transmuting the inspired words into an intelligible system of ceremonial and legal precepts, the vision of the seer could not make much con- tact with the existential world.

^ J. C. Ayer, A Source Book for Ancient Church History ( 1913) , p. 624. ^Encyclopedia of Religion and Ethics, Vol. Ill, p. 241. Catholic En- eyclopedia, Vol. Ill, pp. 416-417. The Summa de Poenitentia et Matri- monio was produced in 1235. From then on, until the publication of the last edition of the Theologia Moralis by St. Alphonsus Maria de Liguori in 1785, there was an enormous output of specific rules. 150 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY

4. The Realm of the Spirit

For the vision is not of this world but of another and radically different one. The Apostles, as a matter of fact, believed themselves to be living in the last days of the world, and they made no provision for a systematic and definitive record of the sacred deposit. But even if they had not believed that the end of the existing world was near, it would still be true that what they taught is not ad- dressed to this world but to a very different one.

There is, for example, the precept that we should love our enemies. It has troubled the doctors of the Church as it has the common man. Aquinas remarks that the good do not bear with the wicked to the extent of enduring the injuries done to God and their neighbors; St. Chrysostom says that "it is praiseworthy to be patient under one's own wrongs, but the height of impiety to dissemble injuries ^° done to God."

The saying disintegrates when we attempt to treat it as a specific rule of political conduct. "What, then, is its wis- dom? It is not the wisdom of the public world and of how to govern it. It is the wisdom of the economy of our pas- sions, and of their education and their ordering. It does not give the rules of behavior in the actual world. It sets before men a vision of themselves transformed.

Quite evidently the ideal of non-resistance would, if

literally and consistently followed, abandon the world to the predatory. Poverty, universally practiced, would sink the world in squalor and darkness. Universal celibacy

" Edward A. Westermarck, "The Origin and Development of the Moral

Ideas (1912-1917), Vol. I, pp. 77-78. THE TWO REALMS I51

would extinguish human hfe. All this is so obvious that,

manifestly, these ideas, which we find in all high religion,

cannot,be_treated as public rules of human conduct. They

are, however, related 10 JiumanLConduct. For they affect

the nature of man, in that the vision of ourselves trans- formed can modify our appetites and our passions. They are not the practical ideals of the existential

world. They are the ideals of a realm of being where men HvA'i'A'^p«<.^<-''*' are redeemed and regenerated and the evils of the world ^A^^'U^'tW'-*^ have been outgrown. While they are on earth and belong

to a human society, men cannot enter that realm. But they can be drawn toward that realm. They cannot be drawn out of the carnal world. But they can be drawn away from its excesses, and, by imitation, they can be- come in some measure nearer to that which they would be ii they had become perfect. A man who has humility will have acquired in the last reaches of his beliefs the saving doubt of his own certainty.

Though he produces wealth and uses it, and though he re- sists evil, he will have little acquisitiveness and posses- siveness, he will have no final attachment to things, he will have no strong lust for power or for vengeance. He cannot and he will not be perfect. But in some measure he will be pulled toward perfection.

Knowledge of the other realm is not communicable in the prosaic language of the familiar material world. For it comes from a vision of a world which is not to be per- ceived by our senses. The language of the seers cannot be direct statements of propositions. They must speak in po- etic parable and metaphor which intimates and may voke that which is inexpressible in prose. These parables 152 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY and metaphors are addressed not to the government of men, but, in the language of Saint Paul, to the creation of the new man. Who is this new man? In the famous chap- ter of Galatians,^^ Paul explains that the Scripture, mean- ing the law and the prophets of the Old Testament,

"hath concluded all under sin." They are addressed to un- regenerate men, to men as they are in the world, to the sons of Adam and Eve who have suffered what Aquinas called a "wounding of nature." In them, "reason" has lost

"its perfect hold over the lower parts of the soul."

"The law," says Saint Paul, "was our schoolmaster." It corrected our ignorance, malice, weakness and lust. But after the faith in Christ is come, "we are no longer under a schoolmaster." When our passions are transformed by allegiance to the other realm of being, we do not need to be disciplined. The regenerate man, says Saint Paul, is not conformed to this world, but is transformed in the renew- ing of his mind.^" In the City of God, says St. Augustine, "sin shall have no power to delight," and men will "not be able to sin." ^^ They are led of the spirit and have been

"redeemed." They can, as Confucius said, follow what their hearts desire without transgressing what is right.

5. The Balance of Powers

As A^MAN^awakens from his primordial condition where, as Bacon said, custom is the principal magistrate of his life, he finds himself living in two worlds and subject to

" Galatians, III: 22-24. ^Romans, XII: 2. " The City of God, XXII, 30. THE TWO REALMS 153 two allegiances. There is the familiar world which he knows through his senses and there is a world of which he has only intimations and knows only through the eyes of his mind. He is drawn between the two disparate realms of being, and the tension j?ythiaj:hem is the in- exhaustible theme of human discourse. To _ neither canjbel ''"^ir^''^ \!t^ give his whole allegiance. Their prevailing contrasts are rl/V<^ his wretchedness. Their occasional harmonies in the lives of saints and the deeds of heroes and the excellence of genius are his glory.

In the traditions of civility, the prevailing view has been that the two realms are inseparable but disparate, and that maa^mujt_woik-QuLhis__destiny in the balance, which is never fixed finally between the two.

This is a view which has, however, always been chal- lenged. There are the hedonists who would withdraw wholly^m^o the realm of existence, to eat, drink, and be merry without the and the qualms that go with im- mortal yearnings. The view of civility has been challenged by the ascetics. who. would withdraw from the realm of existence, waiting for the end of the world and their own release from mortality. It has been challenged by the primitive Chiliasts, who live in the expectation that the millenium, according to the revelation of Saint John, is near at hand. And it has been challenged by the modern perfectionists who believe that by their own revolutionary acts men can make themselves the creators of heaven on this earth. In all these views the error stems from the same fundamental disorder. All refuse to recognize that, on the one hand, the two realms cannot be fused, and that, on the other hand, they cannot be separated and isolated 154 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY

— that they^musLt be related by striking, maintaining, re- dressing a balance between them.

This is a complex and subtle truth, rather like a surd in which cannot be expressed in the finite terms of ordinary quantities. Because we are drawn between the two realms, there can be no definitive line of demarcation of the orbits of the state and of the church. Though the political govern- ment is concerned primarily with the affairs of the exis- tential world, though the churches are primarily com- mitted to the realm of the spirit, they meet whenever and wherever there are issues of right and wrong, issues of what is the nature of man, of what is his true image, his place in the scheme of things, and his destiny. Both the state and the churches are involved in these decisions, and their relationship cannot be defined by any clear, pre- cise demarcation of their respective spheres of influence.

In the tension between them, which is the theme of so much of the history of the Western society, neither must be allowed to conquer and absorb the other. The experi- ence of the West has taught that lesson. But it has taught, also, that the two .realms cannot be separated, that they cannot be isolated and insulated in iiifferent_ compart- ments. There is little room for freedom under the ab- solute power of a totalitarian church which dominates the

secular force of the government, and none under a totali-

tarian state which has absorbed the spiritual powers into

the secular. The best that is possible in the human condi-

tion, and in the world as it is, is that the state and the churches should each be too strong to be conquered, not

strong enough to have unlimited dominion. It is in the THE TWO REALMS 155 righting of the balance between them that reason escapes from the oppressions of excessive power, and can reahze its opportunities. But while the separation of the powers of the churches and of the state is essential to a right relationship be- tween them, the negative rule is not the principle of their right relationship. Church and state need to be sepa- rate, autonomous, and secure. But they must also meet on all the issues of good and evil.

These issues arise concretely in the fixing of public policy about the family, marriage, divorce, the authority of the father and of the mother, the guardianship of children, education, inheritance, the distribution of wealth, crime and punishment, standards of taste, loyalty and allegiance, righteous and unrighteous war. These is- sues, as Pope Leo XIII said in the Encyclical Immortale Dei (1885), belong "to the jurisdiction and judgment of both" the ecclesiastical and the civil power. In all these matters the final word is in neither of the two realms of being. There is in truth no final word. Instead there are the provisional points of equilibrium of an un- ending tension among variable elements. Where exactly ' the point of equilibrium will be in a particular place ancf ^ at a particular time cannot be defined a priori. It must be judged empirically within the postulates of the publicj philosophy. For the elements which have to come into equilibrium are variables. That is „why governing is not engineering but an art. That is why the same constitution and codes of laws cannot, like the plans for a jet engine, be used by all countries at any time or by any country all the time. 156 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY

6. The Mechanics of the Balance

The idea of the balancing of powers among states and within them has been used so long by so many, in such different circumstances and with such different intentions, that it is not, as a recent critic puts it, "free from - " logical, semantic and theoretical confusion."

Yet this is not a reason for agreeing with Cobden that the idea is "an undescribed, indescribable, incomprehensi-

^'' ble nothing."

If a term has many diverging definitions, it is better to begin by assuming that it is full of meanings. For none of the main ideas of our civilization has a single meaning. ^^

But in the great ideas there is some kind of central validity around which disagreements and a variety of meanings continue to revolve. Every one of the great ideas is confusing, because it is too full of meaning to be de- fined simply. But if it were empty of meaning, it would have disappeared into the void along with last week's argument between two drunken men.

Anyone using a complex term like "the balance of power" must, of course, say what he means by it. I start with Hobbes, who said that "in the natural state of men

" Ernst B. Haas, ""The Balance of Power: Prescription, Concept or Propaganda?" World Politics, Vol. V, No. 4 (July 1953). This article is a useful inventory of definitions and applied meanings of the term "balance of power" in the field of international relations.

^^ Cited by Haas from Richard Cobden, Political Writings (London,

1 1878) , pp. 1 i-i 14. ^* Cf. The Great Ideas, a Syntopicon, Mortimer J. Adler, Editor. THE TWO REALMS I57

when there is no government and no law, there is a war ^' of every man against every man."

Hobbes did not say that everyone is in fact trying to

kill everyone else but that there is "a perpetual and rest-

less desire of power after power, that ceaseth only in

death . . . and that this competition of riches, honor, command, or other powers incline us to contention, en- mity and war because the way of one competitor to the

attaining of his desires is to kill, subdue, supplement, or

^'^ repel the other." But how out of the anarchy of warring powers can a

government arise which is strong enough to impose law and order, and how can men be induced to respect the laws? Granted that out of the struggle of the rival lords,

a victor will emerge as sovereign lord who rules all the

others: the question is how one lord among other lords

can become strong enough to overcome all the others.

The answer is that almost never can he do this by pitting

his strength against that of all the others jointly; rarely,

too, can he do that by pitting his strength against each of

them separately, one after the other. The general rule is

that he must be able to take advantage of and, in meas-

ure, to contrive a situation where his rivals oppose each other. When their forces are balanced against one an- other, they are neutralized, and his power may then be sufficient to govern them.

This, we may say, is the mechanical principle by which

the perpetual and restless desire for power after power is brought into an order. The desire for power has to be

"Hobbes, op. cit., Part I, Ch. 13.

"^Ibid., Part I, Ch. II.

/ 158 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY

reduced. This can rarely be done, and never for long, by an omnipotent ruler. Tyranny, as Aristotle observed long

ago, is short-lived.'^ Nor can the desire for power be reduced sufficiently by education and exhortation. As

Montesquieu said, "... constant experience shows us

that every man invested with power is apt to abuse it,

and to carry his authority as far as it will go. Is it not

strange, though true, to say that virtue itself has needs

of limits? To prevent this abuse it is necessary from the very nature of things that power should be checked by power." ^"^

In the measure that power is checked by power, that opposing powers are in balance, neither can prevail. Both are constrained within a common situation. In this condi- tion, when the ponderable forces are in balance, neither being able or willing to exert decisive force, the im- ponderable means of reason become efficacious.

Inter arma silent leges. In the clash of arms the laws are silent. We may add that in the truce of arms the laws are heard. Like any technical procedure, the balancing of power to neutralize power can be used for good, bad and in- different ends. There are many who would say that the good end which politicians always profess is merely the rationalization of the perpetual and restless desire for power after power. "The truth of the matter," said

Nicholas Spykman,^^ "is that states are interested only

in a balance v/hich is in their favor . . . the balance

'^'^ Politics, Book V, Ch. 12, I3i5bi3.

^Montesquieu, op. cit., Book XI, Sec. 4. ^ N. Spykman, American Strategy in World Politics (1942), pp. 21- 25- THE TWO REALMS 159 desired is the one wliich neutralizes other states, leaving

the home state free to be the deciding force and the deciding voice."

But of what "matter" is this the "truth"? That particu- lar states and, we may add, particular parties, factions, and individual politicians, are interested "in a balance which is in their favor." No doubt they are. No doubt they have Hobbes's desire for^power after power. This is the truth about the first, or fallen nature of jii£n. But this iv^i^iz/ll^cuc^'-L- is not a truth about the balance of power. It is the truth ijv^-* /vu-UvJ about the condition which the balance of power can be ci /wwii u-A-f.-'i**^ used to correct. Each contender for power, we must assume, will seek to win the contest — to become the ruler, and to exercise the deciding voice. But there remains still what the ruler

— when he has the deciding voice — is interested in deciding. Will he use the position he has achieved in the system of forces in order to aggrandize his own power, and to increase his own privileges? Or is his chief interest in the order itself — that is to say, in the nation, the commonwealth, the great community — in its survival and in its harmony and in its development?

There is a radical difference between being a contender^

for power, a rival among rivals, and being the guardian 1 of the order which intends to regulate all the rivalries.

|

In the one, the technique of the balance of power is used as an instrument of aggression and defense. In the other, it is used as the structural principle of public order in the good society. . ;

CHAPTER XI The Defense of Civility

I. The Thesis Restated

We have now rnade a reconnaissance in the__gublic

philosophy in order to tes M:he chances of its revival. Our

warrant for making this attempt rests on certain general findings about the condition of the Western world. y^ The f^rstls th^t free- igstitutions and-deiiiocracv_were ^ conceived and estabii|bed__by men who adhered to^ a ' / puW^c^philosophy;^ Though there have been many schools

in this philosophy, there are fundamental principles com-

mon to all of them:""ttrat;"th Cicero's wordsi "law_is_xtLe

bond of civil society," and that all men, governors and the governed, are always under, are never above, laws; that these laws_^can be developed^and__refineii^j:ational discu^on, and that the highestj^ws are those upon which

all rational men of good will, when fully informed, will tend to agree. ^^-"^ The second finding from which we have proceeded, in v. our inqurry, is that themoHerh democracies have aban-. ^doned the main concepts, principles, precepts, and the

/ general manner of thinking which I have been calling the \^ puHic^philosppIiy-. I hold that liberal democracy is not an intelligible form of government and cannot be made to work except by men who possess the philosophy in which .

THE DEFENSE OF CIVILITY l6l

liberal democracy was conceived and founded. The

prospects of liberal democracy in this time of mighty

counterrevolutions are, therefore, bound up with the ques-

tion whether the public philosophy is obsolete or whether

it can be revived, reunited and renewed.

I believe that the public philosophy can be revived,!

and the reconnaissance which we have made has been a.-*

demonstration that when it is applied to such central

concepts as popular sovereignty, property, freedom of

speech, and education, the public philosophy clarifies the .Mi ^;''A*J problems towards rational ac-j and opens_the_way and ,, ,.^,\x:f^'^ solutions. philosophy ceptable The revival of the public ,^ ^ ni^^

depends on whether its principles and precepts — which iJ.^^^ were articulated before the industrial revolution, before

the era of rapid technological change, and before the rise of the mass democracies — depends on whether this old

^w^ilosopiilosophy can be reworked for the modefri " age>If this r *^— , ~~T cainrorbe done, then the free and democratic nations face

\ tRFTotafirarian challenge without- a public philosophy

which: free men believe in and cherish^^ with no public 'i faith beyond-a. mere official agnosticism, neutrality and I - •JndijEerence^, There is not much doubt how the struggle

is likely to end if it lies between those who, believing,

care very much — and those who, lacking belief, can- not care very much.

2. The Communication of the Public Philosophy

We come now to the problem of communicating the ublic philosophy jjrjiie^jaaodern democracies. ^p The prob- lem has been, to be sure, only too obvious from the be- 1 62 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY ginning. For, as we have seen, the public philosophy is in* a deep contradiction with the Jacobin ideology, which is, in fact, the popular doctrine of the mass democracies.

The public ^ilosophy is addressed to the government of our appetites and passions by the reasons__of_a^ second, civilized, and, therefore, acquired nature. Therefore, the public philpsophy^cannot be popular. For it aims-tojiesist and to regulatejhQse_Yerj ^d^ires and opinions which are most^ j)Ojpular. The warrant of the public philosophy is that while the regime it imposes is hard, the results of^ rational and disciplined government will be good.'jJAnd", '^^

'^'''"' '^ so, while the right but hard decisions are not likely to be popular when they are taken, the wrong and soft deci- ^ sions will, if they are frequent and big enough, bring on a disorder in which freedom and democracy are destroyed.

If we ask whether the public philosophy can be com- municated to the democracies, the answer must begin with the acknowledgment that there must be a doctrine to communicate. The philosophy must first be made clear and pertinent to our modern anxieties. Our reconnais- sance has been addressed to that first need.

But beyond it lies the problem of the capacity and the willingness of modern men to receive this kind of phi- losophy. The concepts and the principles of the public philosophy have their being in the realm of immaterial entities. They cannot be experienced by our sense organs or even, strictly speaking, imagined in visual or tangible terms. Yet these essences, these abstractions, which are

out of sight and out of touch, are to have and to hold

men's highest loyalties.

The problem of communication is posed because in •

THE DEFENSE OF CIVILITY 163 the modern world, as it is today, most_men — not all men, to be sure, but most active and influential men — are in practice positivists who hold that the only world which has re.ality is the physical world. Only seeing is believing. Nothing is real enough to be taken seriously, nothing can be a matter of deep concern, which cannot, or at least might not, somewhere and sometime, be seen, heard, tasted, smelled, or touched.

Julius Caesar was a real person because we feel sure we could have seen him in Rome had we been there in his lifetime. By the same kind of popular common sense, communities have believed that werewolves were real. Had not a woman named Thiebenne Paget admitted that she was one of the wolves that was seen on July 18, 1603, in the District of Couvres? ^ To common sense the real is what, but only what, we believe has weight, mass, energy.

. . . What's Hecuba to him, or he to Hecuba, that he should weep for her?

What are the ideas and ideals, the laws and the obliga- tions, of the rational order if, like Hecuba, they are not flesh and blood? Conijnoa.^eLnse.is.430sixivist_aiid_ credulous, and the usual liuman way: of satisfying it has beento -materialize ideas when those ideas had to be_treated_as_real. Men have incarnated the gods, they have re-embodied their ancestors, they have personified the laws, they have hypostasized their ideas. They have made the abstractions and universals intelligible in concrete terms, and so mat-

^ The World's Great Folktales, arranged and edited by James R. Foster (1953), p. 135. 164 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY ters of genuine concern, by connecting them with the realities of everyday experience.

The difficulty of communicating imponderable truths^ -t^'

to common sense is not a new one. Through the ages , >^ truths that could not be materialized have been regarded - -^ as esoteric, and communicable only to an initiated few.

The Gospels state that there were mysteries which Jesus could unveil only to a few. He said, "He who has ears to hear, let him hear." ^ But —

"When he was alone, those who were about him with the twelve asked him concerning the parables. And he said to them, "To you has been given the secret of the kingdom of God, but for those

." ^ outside everything is in parables . .

Only privately to his own disciples, says Mark, did he explain "everything"; to "the whole crowd" he spoke the word "as they were able to hear it; he did not speak to them without a parable." Why? Because, says Dante, the divine mysteries are beyond the reach of human understanding —

It is needful to speak thus to your wit, since only through objects of sense does it apprehend that which it afterwards would make worthy of the intellect. For this the scripture condescends to your capacity, and attributes feet and hands to God, and means other- wise.'*

There is a need to condescend to our capacity because, as Paul Tillich puts it, "It is impossible to be concerned about something which cannot be encountered concretely,

^The Gospel According to St. Mark, IV: 9. ""Ibid., IV: 10-12. * Divine Comedy, translated by C. E. Norton (1941), Paradise, Canto IV, versus 40-45. THE DEFENSE OF CIVILITY 165 be it in the realm of reality or in the realm of

. . . the more concrete a thing is, the more the possible concern about k. The completely concrete being, the in- dividual person, is the object of the most radical concern

— the concern of love." There is in consequence, he says, an "inescapable inner tension in the idea of God"

— between God conceived as transcending all that is particular and finite, on the one hand, and the concrete- ness of an image of God on the other. In order to have a human concern there is needed a "being to being rela- tionship ... a concrete God, a God with whom man can deal" in his religious experience.^

While Tillich is a theologian examining the meaning of God, which he defines as the "name for that which concerns men ultimately," his findings illuminate the problem which we are studying. How can men be con cerned effectively with ideas and ideals that transcend their personal experierice and cannot be verified empiri- cally in the realm of existence? The principles of the good society calLfor. a concern with _an order of jpeing — which cannot be proved^existentially to the sense organs — where it matters supremely that the human person is inviolable, that reason shall regulate the will, that truth shall prevail over error.

Because it is difficult to care about that which is not concrete, there is, in Tillich's language, "a tension in human experience." In order to become concerned about, to feel committed to, transcendent objects, we have to believe in them: to believe in them they must be con- crete, they must in fact or in imagination be drawn into

^Paul Tillich, Systematic Theology (1951), Vol. I, Part II, p. 211. l66 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY the orbit of our sense organs. But as we condescend in this fashion to our capacity, attributing foot and hand to God, the behef becomes involved with, often dependent upon, the materiahzation. Because of this dependence, the behef is vulnerable. For a little knowledge, as for example that the foot and hand are a metaphor, may destroy the belief.

3. Constitutionalism Made Concrete

Early in the history of Western society, political think- ers in Rome hit upon the idea that the concepts of the public philosophy — particularj.y_dieidea of recipro- cal rights and duties under law — could be given con- creteness_by treating them as contracts. In this way, free^ dom emanating from a. constitutional order has been advocated, explained, made real to the imagination and the conscience of Western men; by establishing the pre- sumption that civilized society is founded on a public .

A contract is an agreement reached voluntarily, quid- pro quo, and likely, therefore, to be observed — in any event, rightfully enforceable. Being voluntary. It has the consent of the parties. The presumption is not only that one party has acceded to what the other party proposed, but also that, in the original meaning of the word, both parties have consented — that they have thought, felt and judged the matter together.*^ Being a contract, the agreement will, presumably, be specific enough to mini-

*Cf. Encyclopedia of Religio)! and Ethics, Vol. IV, article "Consent," THE DEFENSE OF CIVILITY 167 mize the quarrels of misunderstanding. It will say what the parties may expect of one another. It will say what are their respective rights and duties. In the field of the contract, their relations will be regulated and criteria will exist for adjudicating issues between them. These are the essential characteristics of a constitu- tional system. It can be said to prevail when every man in and out of office is bound by lawful contracts. Without this, that is^ without constituiionaLg-over-njnent,-there is no freedom. For the antithesis to being free is to be at the mercy of men who can^agt^arbitrariiy. It is not to know what may be done to you. It is to have no right to an accounting, and to have no means of objecting. Despotism and anarchy prevail when a constitutional order does not exist. Both are lawless and arbitrary. Indeed, despotism may be defined as the anarchy of lawless rulers, and anarchy as the despotism of lawless crowds.

The first priricipk_o_f a civilized state is that poj^eius j legitimate only when it is under contract. Then it is, as we say, duly constituted. This principle is of such con- trolling significance that in the Western world the mak- ing of the contracts of government and of society has usually been regarded as marking — historically or sym- bolically — the crossing of the line which divides barbar- ity from civility.

Yet, as a matter of fact, there were not many actual documents. The public men who developed the constitu- tional systems of the West had a few texts, actually signed and sealed and delivered, to work with. There were, says Gierke, some "actual contracts between Ger- man princes and the estates of their realms." There are 1 68 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY the celebrated contracts like Magna Carta, the Bill of Rights, the American Constitution. But genuine historic

contracts are scarce, and they do not begin to cover all

the political powers that need to be regulated. There are not and never have been, and indeed could

never be, specific contracts covering the unwritten laws

of the good society, covering the domain of manners, as

Lord Moulton called it, which includes "all things that a man should impose upon himself, from duty to good

taste." ' It is necessary somehow to give authority to these

unwritten laws, to invest them in some way with the

reality of concreteness. The public philosophers drew by analogy upon the Roman Law, which presumed that in certain cases an agreement had been reached and an obligation incurred by acts unaccompanied by any ex- .^ press pact {quasi ex contractu)

( The general idea that the unwritten laws _Qf public

behavior are contractual and rest on consent was mate- rialized in myjhs of an original covenant, entered into by

the first ancestor^.-and binding upon their descendants.

These myths, which appear in many versions at various

times and places, make credible — by materializing it

— the ethereal notion that civility is a fabric of under-'' standings. The Ark of the Covenant, says Deuteronomy, contained the two tables of stone on which were written

with the finger of God the Ten Commandments. Now, as

a matter of fact, the Ark and the two tables of stone did

not exist when Deuteronomy was compiled. But if they

'Lord Moulton, "Law and Manners," in Atlantic Monthly (July 1924). ® Charles Howard Mcllwain, The Growth of Political Thought in the West (1932), p. 118. THE DEFENSE OF CIVILITY 1 69 had never existed, how would the authors of Deuteron- omy have convinced the Israehtes that they must obey the Ten Commandments? They would not have gotten much obedience to the Commandments if they had told the Israelites that it was not certain, but merely probable, that they had been drawn up by Moses himself, and that it could be assumed that the Commandments re- flected the considered judgment of Moses of how best to promote the greatest happiness of the greatest number of Israelites. The Ten Commandments had a better chance of being obeyed by the Israelites if they were written by God, rather than by another Israelite. And it was easier to believe that God did write them if, once upon a time, the two tables of stone had been deposited in the Ark of the Covenant. Many in the modern age have rejected the idea of the contractual basis of power because, as a matter of fact, there never was an historic contract. Bentham, for ex- ample, knew that the two tables of stone could not be found and he wrote that "the origination of governments from a contract is a pure fiction, or in other words a

falsehood . . . where is it but from government that ^ contracts derive their binding force?"

Tg^^his^we must reply that a fiction is not necessarily a falsehood. It may be the jvehicle_of_a_. truth. Where^do- governments derlve^ihe^^ower, which Bentham speaks of, to bind_contracts? Only where the governments are con- ducted by merL^jn_,a..£omrimnity_who feel_ihemselves

^ Jeremy Bentham, Anarchical Fallacies; Being an Examination of the Declaratio7i of Rights Issued During the French Revolution, Art. II, Sentence i. lyO THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY bouniii^jthe^belief that contracts are binding. The laws prevail when the lawmakers and the judges and the law enforcers are attached to the laws. When they are not attached to the laws, the laws of contract and the laws of the rights of man — the laws of the constitution, of charters, of treaties — are a dead letter, like, for ex- ample, the encyclopedic bill of rights in the Soviet Con- stitution of 1936. "The personal liberty of the individual," says Black- stone, in the celebrated chapter on "The Legal Rights of

^° Englishmen," is protected in part by the Habeas Corpus Act, which provides that "no subject of England can be long detained in prison" unless it can be proved in court that he is lawfully imprisoned. "Lest this act should be evaded by demanding unreasonable bail or

sureties for the prisoner's appearance, it is declared . . . that excessive bail ought not to be required."

But the HabeasXjQXpus^Act, which is a legal device to protect the personaHiberty of the individual, does that — obviously enough — only where and when it is observed and enforceable. That will be only in a^^country where the executive_j,nd-J:he, .assembly,-«the_judges, the jailers and the lawyers feel bound, as if by personal contract, to the principles of the Habeas Corpus Act. Otherwise, no matter what the words of the law, k can happen to any- one, as to the man in Kafka's story, that he might never find out why he was in prison. Blackstone could not have written with such assurance that the Habeas Corpus

Act prevents arbitrary detention in prison if in the Eng- land of his time the rights and duties that the Act de-

^^ Commentaries, Book I, Chapter I, 2. THE DEFENSE OF CIVILITY 171 clares had not become concrete and real, had not be- come matters of genuine concern.

4. The Language of Accommodation

Men have been laboring with the problem of how to make concrete apd real whatJs-JLb^ttact^^d, immaterial ever since the Greek philosophers began to feel the need to accommodate the popular Homeric religion to the ad- vance of science. The theologians, says Aristotle, are like the philosophers in that they promulgate certain doc- trines; but they are unlike them in that they do so in mythical form.^^ The method of accommodation employed by the phi- losophers has been to treat the materialization in the myth/as allegaryj: as translation of the same knowledge into Miother language. ^^ To converse with the devil, for example, could then mean what literally it says — to talk face to face with the devil, a concrete materialized personage. But it could mean, also, the imitation of a wicked nature without — as the Cambridge Platonist ^^ John Smith wrote, "a mutual local presence," that is to say without meeting a devil in person. This was an ac- commodation to those who, believing in the wickedness of evil, could not believe in the personified devil. The devil could mean either "some apostate spirit as one par-

" Werner Jaeger, The Theology of the Early Greek Philosophers (The Gifford Lectures 1936), p. 10. Cf. Aristotle, , Bk. Ill, Ch. 4, loooa 4-18. '"Cf. Basil Willey, The Seventeenth Century Background (1952), Ch. IV.

"^jbid., p. 138 et s-^y. o

172 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY ticular being," and also "the spirit of apostasie which is lodged in all men's natures." This is the method of plural interpretation; it uses "the language of accommodation."

It is justified and legitimate, said John Smith in his dis- course entitled "A Christian's Conflicts and Conquests," because "truth is content, when it comes into the world, to wear our mantles, to learn our language, to conform itself as k were to our dress and fashions ... it speaks with the most idiotical sort of men in the most idiotical way, and becomes all things to all men, as every sonne of ^^ truth should do for their good."

5. The Limits of Accom?nodation

But there are limits beyond_ which_ we cannot carry ^'

the time-honored jnethod ^ f accommO-dating-the^^iversity I of beliefs. As we know from the variety and sharpness of schisms and sects in our time, we have gone beyond the limits of accommodation. We know, too, that as the divisions grow wider and more irreconcilable, there arise issues of loyalty with which the general principle of toler- ation is unable to cope.

For the toleration of differences is possiblg^only oa the assumption tha^jhere i s no vitaj_threatxo the commun ity.

Toleration is not, therefore, a sufficient principle fort dealing with the diversity of opinions and beliefs. It is' itself dependent upon the positive ^rincipleof accommo- dation.. The principle calls for the effort to find agree^ ment beneath the d ifferences.

^^ Ibid., p. 146. THE DEFENSE OF CIVILITY I73

In studying how accommodation is achieved, we may begin by observing that it is the philosophers, using Aristotle's broad terminology, who work out and promote the plural interpretation. They propose the terms for ac- commodating their immaterial belief to the concrete and materialized imagery of the fundamentalists. Thus it was the Cambridge Platonist, John Smith, who took the initia- tive about the devil. John Smith was not addressing the fundamentalists who believed in the personified devil; in fact what he said about the whole matter was not meant to trouble the fundamentalists at all. He was ad- dressing men who were unable to believe in the person- ified devil and yet were still in essential communion with the fundamentalists. For they did believe in the spirit of the devil which, as everyone knows, is in all of us. In this accommodation the Christian Platonists gave up try- ing to believe what they could not believe. They went on believing that which in its essence their fundamentalist

neighbors believed. Thus they could continue to live in the same community with them.

There is an impressive historical example of how by, ». . Lc*:)^ i^^ '-^-'«'-*^' >«^^ -i^ accommodation k is possible to cammunicate_these_diffi- 1 "^"^ cult truths to a large Jieterogeneous society. In mediaeval ' Christendom a great subject of accommodation was the

origin and sanction of the public philosophy itself, of the natural laws of the rational order. Otto von Gierke says that despite the innumerable learned controversies of

the lawyers, the theologians and the philosophers, "all were agreed that there was natural law, which, on the one hand, radiated from a principle transcending earthly power, and on the other hand was true and perfectly 174 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY

binding law . . . the highest power on earth was sub- ject to the rules of natural law. They stood above the Pope and above the Kaiser, above the ruler and above the sovereign people, nay, above the whole com-

munity of mortals. Neither statute nor act of govern- ment, neither resolution of the people nor custom, could

break the bounds that thus were set. Whatever con- tradicted the eternal and immutable principles of natural

^"'^ law was utterly void and would bind no one."

But though there was agreement on this, th£££_jK_as deep controversy over whether the natural laws were the commands of God or whether they were the dictates of an etemal^reason grounded on the being of God, and , unalterable even by God himself. How were men to imagine, to materialize and make concrete the natural

law which is above the Pope and the Kaiser and all mortals? As decrees of an omniscient and omnipotent

heavenly king? Or as the principles of the nature of things? There were some who could not conceive of

binding laws which had to be obeyed unless there was a lawgiver made in the image of the human lawgivers they had seen or heard about. There were others to whose

capacity it was not necessary to condescend with quite that much materialization.

The crucial point, however, is not where the naturalists

and supernaturalists disagreed. It is that they did agree

that there was a valid law which, whether it was the commandment of God or the reason of things, was trans-

^^ Otto von Gierke, Political Theories of the Middle Age, translated with an Introduction by Frederick William Maitland (Cambridge Uni- versity Press, 1927). Cf. pp. 73-87 and more especially Note 256. THE DEFENSE OF CIVILITY 175 cendent. They did agree that It was not something de- cided upon by certain men and then proclaimed by them.

It was not someone's fancy, someone's prejudice, some- one's wish or rationahzation, a psychological experience and no more. It is there objectively, not subjectively. It can be discovered. It has to be obeyed.

6. The Death of God

As LONG, then, as both and the theolo- gian believe in the objective order, there can be accom- modation about the degree ..aniLkind--of--materiali2ation.,y:a-^' is very great. So, too, must be the range and variety of the images which condescend to their varying capacities. We can, therefore, avoid much misunderstanding if we do not confound the materialization — which is the mode of communicating belief — with the subject of the belief. For not until we go down under the comparatively super- ficial question of belief or unbelief, in any particular materialization, do we find the radical problems of belief and unbelief. When Martin Buber speaks of "the great images of God fashioned by mankind," ^^ he recognizes that there can be many images, or indeed that there can be no image which has concreteness to our sense perceptions.

The critical question does not turn on whether men / do or do not believe in an imagery. It turns on whether they believe that a man is able "to experience a reality \

"Martin Buber, Eclipse of God (1952), p. 22. J ?

176 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY absolutely independent of himself." When Sartre, fol- lowing Nietzsche, says that "God is dead," the critical point is not that he refuses to believe in the existence, however attenuated, of an anthropomorphic God. There can be, indeed there is, great faith and deep religion without any concrete image of God. The radical un- belief lies underneath the metaphor of God's death. It is in Sartre's saying that "ifIJiave_done^away with God the Father, som£on£_isjiegcled to invent values~7T~rlife h"as~ nojneaning a /^riof \;_;_^os„up_,to_you jto give it_aL meaning, and value is nothing but the meaning that you ^^ choose."

With this, Sartre Jias done away not orily withjjod the Father but with the recognition that beyond our private worlds there^ is a public world to which we belong. If ^

is is right, is true, is only the what good, what what what ^ J |

( " individual "chooses" to "invent," then we are outside the " t

-^'''\ traditions of civility. We are back in the war of all men .h;, against all men. There is left no ground for accommoda- tion among the varieties of men; nor is there in this proclamation of anarchy a will to find an accommodation.

And why, we may ask, is there among such modern philosophers as these no concern like that of their great predecessors, to find an accommodation? It is not only because they themselves have ceased to believe in the metaphors — in the sacred images. They have ceased to believe that behind the metaphors and the sacred images there is any kind of independent reality that can be known and must be recognized.

"Jean Paul Sartre, , translated by Bernard Frechttnan (1947), p. 58. See also Martin Buber, op. cit., p. 93. THE DEFENSE OF CIVILITY 177

Thus they reject "the concept of 'truth' as something dependent upon facts largely outside human control," which, as Bertrand Russell says, "has been one of the ways in which philosophy hitherto has inculcated the nec- essary element of humility. When this check upon pride is removed, a further step is taken on the road towards a certain kind of madness — the intoxication of power

which invaded philosophy with Fichte . . . and to which modern men, whether philosophers or not, are prone. I am persuaded that this intoxication is the greatest danger of our time, and that any philosophy which, however unintentionally, contributes to it is in- ^^ creasing the danger of vast social disaster."

7. The Mandate of Heaven

At the end, then, the questions, are^how we conceive of ourselves^ and_iJie___public world beyond our private selves. Much depends upon the philosophers. For though they are not kings, they are, we may say, the teachers of the teachers. "In the history of Western governments," says Francis G. Wilson,^^ "the transitions of society can be marked by the changing character of the ," who have served the government as lawyers, advisers, administrators, who have been teachers in the schools, who have been members of professions like medicine and theology. It is through them that doctrines are made to operate in practical affairs. And their doctrine, which

"Bertrand Russell, History of (1945), p. 828. ^^ Francis G. Wilson, ""Public Opinion and the Intellectuals," in Ameri- can Political Science Revietv (June 1954). lyS THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY

they, themselves, have learned in the schools and uni-

versities, will have the shape and the reference and the

direction which the prevailing philosophy gives it.

That is hD-W-and-why-^ii-lesophy- and theology are the ultimate .and decisive studies in which we engage. In them are defined the main characteristics of the images of man which will be acted upon in the arts and sciences

of the epoch. The role of philosophers is rarely, no doubt,

creative. But it is critical, in that they have a deciding

influence in determining what may be believed, how it can be believed, and what cannot be believed. The

philosophers, one might say, stand at the crossroads.

While they may not cause the traffic to move, they

can stop it and start it, they can direct it one way or the other.

. / I do not contend, though I hope, that the decline of .^ // Western society will _be_,ai:rested.4£-4Ji£_jeachers in_our

^T^::^ schools and univ£rsiti£_s come, kack:.ja^£ great tradition

/\^ of the public philosoph y. But I do contend that the_^-

cline, which is already far advanced, cannot be arrested

if the prevailing philosophers oppose this restoration and

revival, if they impugn rather than support the validity

of an order which is superior to the values that Sartre

tells each man "to invent." What the prevailing philosophers say about religion

is not itself, in Tillich's terms, religion as an ultimate

concern of worship and of love. But if the philosophers

teach that religious experience is a purely psychological

phenomenon, related to nothing beyond each man's psy- chic condition, then they will give educated men a bad

intellectual conscience if they have religious experiences. THE DEFENSE OF CIVILITY I79

The philosophers cannot give them reHgion. But they can keep them away from it. Philosophers play the same role in relation to the prin- ciples of the good society. These require, as we have seen, the mastery of human nature in the raw by an acquired rational second nature. In the literal sense, the princip les of the good society must be unpopular until they have | prevailed__sufficieniiy_jto_^lter the 4?opular impulses. For the popular i mpulses ar£_ppp'^gp'-l tr> pnhh'r princip les.

These principles cannot be made to prevail if they are discredited, — if they are dismissed as superstition, as ob- scurantism, as meaningless metaphysics, as reactionary, as self-seeking rationalizations.

The public philosophy is in a large measure intellectu- ally discredited among contemporary men. Because of that, what we may call the terms of discourse in public controversy are highly unfavorable to anyone who ad- heres to the public philosophy. The signs and seals of legitimacy, of tightness and of aiith^_Jiaye_.,i)een taken over by men wbo^jrgject, even when they^are not the avowed adversaries of, the doctrine^pf constitutional de- mocracy. ,U.,^,<^v-fe

If the decline__of_the_West under the misrule of the I people is ta^bejialted, it will be necessary to_ alter these

terms_ of discourse. They are now set overwhelmingly

against..,tlie_. cxedibility and against the tightness of jhe

principles of the constitutjonal^state; they are set_^in_favQr of the Jacobin conception of the emancipated and sovereiga_42eople.^*'

I have been arguing, hopefully and wishfully, that it ^ Cf . Chapter Seven. Y

l80 THE PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY

may be possible to alter the terms of discourse if a con- vincing demonstration can be made that the principles of the good society are not, in Sartre's phrase, invented and chosen — that the conditions which must be met

if there is to be a good society are there, outside our

wishes, where they can be discovered by rational in- quiry, and developed and adapted and refined by rational

discussion.

If eventually this were demonstrated successfully, it

would, I believe, rearm all those who are concerned with

the anomy of our society, with its progressive barbariza-

tion, and with its descent into violence and tyranny. Amidst the quagmire of moral impressionism they would stand again on hard intellectual ground where there are significant objects that are given and are not merely pro-

jected, that are compelling and are not merely wished.

C Their lY2Pf,J^2lvl'^ b*" fP-P'^tablishfrl that there ts a pnMir

y'wqrld, sove reign_ abo .e the infinite numbex^f contradic-

/ toryand_ competing private jworld s. Without this cer- ^'^ tainty, their struggle must be unavailing.

As the defenders of civility, they cannot do without

the signs and seals of legitimacy, of tightness and of

truth. For it is a practical rule, well known to experi-

enced men, that the relation is very close between our

capacity to act at all and our conviction that the action we

are taking is right. This does not mean, of course, that

the action is necessarily right. What is necessary to con-

tinuous action is that it shall be believed to be right. Without that belief, most men will not have the energy and will to persevere in the action. Thus satanism, which

prefers evil as such, is present in some men and perhaps THE DEFENSE OF CIVILITY l8l potential in many. Yet, except in a condition of the pro- foundest hysteria, as in a lynching, satanism cannot be preached to multitudes. Even Hitler, who was enormously

Satanic and delighted in monstrous evil, did nevertheless need, it would seem, to be reassured that he was not only a great man but, in a mysterious way, a righteous one. William Jennings Bryan once said that to be clad in the armor of righteousness will make the humblest citizen of all the land stronger than all the hosts of error."^ That is not quite true. But the reason the humblest citizen is not stronger than the hosts of error is that the latter also are clad in an armor which they at least believe is the armor of righteousness. Had they not been issued the armor of righteousness, they would not, as a matter of fact, be a host at all. For political ideas acquire operative force in human affairs when, as we have seen, they ac- quire legitimacy, when they have the title of being right which binds men's consciences. Then they possess, as the

Confucian doctrine has it, "the mandate of heaven."

In the crisis within the Western society, there is at issue now the mandate of heaven.

^Speech at Democratic National Convention (Chicago, 1896).

Index

Adams, James Truslow, i6n. Bentham, Jeremy, 169; on the Adams, John, 26;;.,' on Rousseau's interests of the community, civilized man, 72 34-35 Adler, Mortimer, cited, loi Berlin, Isaiah, on Leninism, 81; on Aeschylus, on delusion that men Plekhanov and Lenin, 82-83 are gods, 86 Bernard of Chartres, 136 Alexander the Great, 115; insist- Bible, beginning of Christian law ence on common law for Greeks in, 148 and Persians, 105-106 Bill of Rights, 40, 98, 168 American Civil War, 9 Blackstone, Sir William, on Habeas American Constitution, 168 Corpus Act, 170; on theory of American Revolution of 1776, 98, private property, 1 16-120 104; aims of, 67-68 Britain. See Great Britain Apostles, beginning of Christian Bryan, William Jennings, 181 law in sayings of, 148 Bryce, Lord James M:, cited, 4o».; Aquinas, St. Thomas, 98, 104, 138, on danger to democracy, 6-7; on 150, 152 pressure of mass opinion, 50 Arendt, Hannah, 85 Buber, Martin, on images of God, A reopagitica, 125 175 Aristotle, 103, 158, 171, 173; ad- Budget, as illustration of public vice to Alexander, 105; on find- policy, 43-45 ing the right rule, 145, 146; on Burke, Edmund, 103; on the peo- free speech, 125-126 ple, 35-36 Austria-Hungary, collapse of, 12

Ayer, J. C, cited, 149;;. Caesar, Julius, 163 Calvin, John, 72 Bacon, Francis, 152-153 Calvin's Institutes, 149 Balance of power, definitions, 156- Censorship, 131 159 Chamberlain, Neville, 3 Barker, Ernest, 104; on common Charlemagne, 37 conception of law, 97-98; on ius Christian law, development of, 148- naturde, 107-108; on origin of 149; inapplicable to political universal laws, 104-107 conduct, 150-152 Barrere, 70 Church, and state, 152-155; ideal- Behavior, power of ideas to organ- istic precepts of, 150-152 ize, 93-94 Churchill, Sir Winston, 26 1

1 84 INDEX

Cicero, 107, 160 counterrevolution, 60; derange- Clark, Colin, 10 ment of functions of government Clemenceau, Georges, 18 in, 14, 31; duties of governing Cobden, Richard, 156 in, 8-9; effect of public opinion Coke, Sir Edward (Lord Coke), 98 on foreign policy in, 16-20; en- Communist Aiariifesto, fulfillment franchisement of the people in, of predictions and reforms, 80 39-40; evolution of Parliament, Community, as defined by Bentham 29; executive power enfeebled and Burke, 34-36 by pressures of assembly and Condorcet, Jean Antoine de, 7 opinion in, 25-27, 48-49, 55-57; Confucius, 152 failure to avert Second World Constitution of the United States, War, 3-5; governing versus rep- 168; first ten amendments, 98- resentation in, 51-54; inability 99; meaning of people, 32-33 to make peace, 5-6, 12-13; insti- Constitutional Convention, con- tutions still based on public phi- cerned with problem of inade- losophy, 101-102; Jacobinism in quate executive, 49-50; under- education of, 73-78; liberalism standing of term people in, 32- and Jacobinism in, 63-71; loss 33 of public philosophy and politi- Constitutional government, based cal arts in, 96, 134-137; propen- on contracts, 166-167 sity to please the voters in, 46; Contract, as basis of constitutional public philosophy eclipsed by government, 166-167 public agnosticism in, 99- Corpus Juris, 108 100; the public interest defined, Counterrevolution, characteristics 41-46 of, 58-59; reaction to failure of De TocqueviUe. See Tocqueville liberal democracies, 63 Diderot, Denis, 67 Courts, protection from pressure of Dostoevski, Feodor Mikhailovich, mass opinion, 51 83 _ , Crimean War, 17 Durkheim, Emile, 112 Crito, on Socrates, 139 Culture, acquired through educa- Education, character acquired by tion and experience, 94-95; see experience and, 94-95; influence also Public philosophy of Jacobinism in, 73-78; subject- matter of democratic, 78 Daladier, Sdouard, 3 Edward VII, 16 Dante, on divine mysteries, 164 Elections, eliminated or controlled Debate, essential to freedom of in counterrevolutionary move- speech, i 28-1 31 ments, 58-69; executive power Declaration of Independence, 98; weakened by dependence on, 48- aims of, 67-68 49 Democracies, appeasement and iso- Elton, G. R., on strong government, lation in, 23; compulsion to 31 make mistakes in, 20-21; con- Enfranchisement, by assimilation, fusion of this world and tran- 39-40, 65-66; consequences to scendent world in, 142; critical governmental power, 50 mistakes of public opinion in, Engels, Friedrich, debt to Jacobins, 22-25; deficiency reflected by 69-70; on class struggle, 78 1 1

INDEX 185

England, de TocqueviUe on govern- tions, 143-144; deranged demo- ing class in, 64-65. See also cratic governments a threat to, Great Britain 31 English Revolution of 1688, 98, Freedom of speech, limits of dis- 104 sent, 1 31-134; modern abuses Eratosthenes, 105 caused by lack of debate, 128- Europe, enfranchisement of the 131; purpose and justification of, people in, 39; reliance on un- 124-128 armed appeasement, 23 French Revolution, 98; Jacobin Eusebius, 148 doctrine in, 66 Executive, and representatives, 53- Froebel, F. W. A., on will of child, 54; devitalized by pressure of 75 electorate, 46, 48, 55-57; duty Fromm, Erich, no; on education, to office, 51-53; eiJorts to pro- 94 tect from pressure of mass opin- ion, 50-51; function of, 30; in Gallup polls, and public policy, counterrevolutionary movements, 41-42 59-60; loss of material and George III, 67, 68 ethereal powers, 56-57 Germany, 57; July crisis, 12; Na- tional Socialist counterrevolu- Ferrero, Guglielmo, 8 tion, 58; rebellion against peace Fichte, Johann Gottlieb, 177 settlement in, 23 First World War, conduct of for- Gide, Andre, in; on feeling free- eign affairs before, 16-17; failure dom, no of peace settlement, 12-13, 22- Gierke, Otto von, io7«., 167; on 23; government changes during, belief in natural law, 97, i7 3«.- 7-8; material progress preceding, 174 9-1 Gilson, fitienne, cited, i36».; on Foreign policy, effect of public dissolution of Western culture, opinion on, 19-20; in nineteenth no century, 16-17 Godwin, William, on reason, 77 Foster, James R., cited, 163^. Government, basis of constitu- Four Freedoms, 23 tional, 166-167; relationship of France, 57; decisions of the thirties, executive and representatives in, 18; enfranchisement of the 29-30; role of people in, 14-15; people in, 39; failure to avert tendency to please the voters in, war, 3-5; governing class in, 64; 46 manpower losses, im.; mutinies Great Britain, 56; decisions of the in, 12 thirties, 18; enfranchisement of Francis Joseph, Emperor, 12 the people in, 39, 65; failure to Franco-Prussian War, 10 avert war, 3-5; in First World Free institutions, destroyed in War, im., 12; in Second World counterrevolutionary movements, War, 23; nineteenth century 131; inseparable from public foreign policy, 16-17 philosophy, 131- 134 Greece, traditions lost in, 104 Freedom, achievement of religious, 97; changed meaning of, 100; Haas, Ernst B., 156 current theory of, 113; defini- Habeas Corpus Act, 170-17 i86 INDEX

Hamilton, Alexander, iGn., 50?;., Johnston, Sir Harry, on conduct of foreign affairs, 16-17 Hapsburg Empire, collapse of, 8 Justinian, 108 Henry III, Parliament summoned by, 29 Koran, 149 Hitler, Adolph, 18, 22, 83, 87, 181; on the masses, iio-iii Law, Christian, 146-149; nat- Hobbes, Thomas, freedom defined, ural, 107-109, 173-174; Roman, 143; on balance of power, 156- 107-108 157 Lenin, Nikolay, 22, 87; as self- Hocking, William Ernest, on appointed agent of history, 83; adaptability of humans, 95 revolutionary movement changed HohenzoUern Empire, collapse of, to totalitarianism by, 80-83 8 Leninism, from Jacobinism to, 78- Holbach, Paul Heinrich von, on 83 unjust rulers, dd Leo XIII, Pope, on orbit of church Holmes, Justice Oliver Wendell, and state, 155 124 Liberalism, and Jacobinism, 63-71 Hooker, Richard, on Puritan revo- Liberty. See Freedom lutionaries, 85 Lloyd George, David, 18 Locke, John, 98; on freedom, 143 Ideas, efficacy of, 91-96 Italy, 57; Fascist counterrevolution, MacDougal, William, on power 58 of instinctive impulses, 77-78 lus civile, 107 Madison, James, 5o«., 53«. Itis gentium., 107, 115 Magna Carta, 98, 168 lus iiaturale, 107-108, 115 Maine, Sir Henry, on duties of democratic government, 8; on

Jackson, Andrew, (i(c, fragility of popular government, Jacobin revolution, doctrine of, G

ment, 14-15 Murray, John Courtney, S. J., on Jesus, beginning of Christian law plurality of faiths, 96 in precepts of, 148 Mussolini. Benito, 7, 18, 22 1

INDEX 187

Natural law, belief in, 173-174; analyzed, i6-~i-!\ on innate t^ood- meaning of, 107-108; new ness of child, 74 school of, 108-109 Philosophy, efficacy of, 91-96. See Natural rights of man, progress of also Public philosophy idea, 98 Plato, 138 Nef, John U., on material progress Plekhanov, on demands of revolu-

of West, 10- 1 tion, 82 Nevins, Allan, on early American Plutarch, on common law, 105-106 elections, 33^?. Politicians, intimidated by public Newman, Cardinal Henry, 138 opinion, 25-27. See also Execu- Nicholson, Harold, 21 tive Nickerson, Hofifman, 11 Pollard, A. F., 28 Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm, 176 Popular sovereignty, enfranchise- ment not implied in, 37-38 Opinion. See Public opinion Portugal, Corporatist movement, Orlando, Vittorio Emanuele, 18 58 Ottoman Empire, collapse of, 8 Posadovsky, 81 Power, balance of, 156-159 Paget, Thiebenne, 163 Private property, 11 5- 124; abuses Paine, Tom, 66 of absolute, 120-122; different Paris Peace Conference, failure of, and better theory possible, 122- 22-23 124 Parliament, evolution of relation- Property. See Private property ship between government and Public expenditure, increasing people in, 28-30 power of representative assembly Peace, role of public opinion in, over, 55-56 22-25 Public interest, and the equations Pearl Harbor, 23 of reality, 43-46; defined, 41-42 Peirce, C. S., on human opinion, Public opinion, effect of universal 133 suffrage on, 39; in war and People, alienated from public phi- peace, 16-20; inertia of, 20-21; losophy, 100, 102; as corporate pattern of mistakes, 22-25; pro- being, 35-36; as understood in tecting executive from pressure the Constitution, 32-33; com- of, 50-51; role in Paris peace municating public philosophy to, settlement, 22-23; versus public 162-166; defined as voters or as interest, 41-42; vulnerability of community, 31-36; enfranchise- democracies to, 15 ment not implied in popular Public philosophy, as cultural heri- sovereignty, 37-38; inability to tage, 94-95, 134-137; communi- cope with freedom, 111-112; cation of, 161-166; democracies political power denied in coun- cut off from, 96; evolution of terrevolution, 58-59; represented universal laws, 104-108; free- in Parliament, role in 29; democ- dom of speech, 1 24-1 31; intel- racy, 14-15; tendency to choose lectually discredited, 179; lan- 60-61. authority, See also Public guage of accommodation, 171- opinion 172; liberal democracy based on, Peronist counterrevolution, 58 1 60-161; limits of accommoda- Pestalozzi, H., faulty J. metaphor tion, I72W.-I75; limits of dis- INDEX

Public philosophy {Conti77ued) St. John, 153 sent, 131-134; minority's adher- St. Mark, on miracle of Jesus, ence to, 104; need for revival of, 164 101-102, 113-115, 161; origins St. Paul, on laws for the lawless, and adherents of, 97-99; out of 143; on regeneration, 152 fashion, 99-100; theory of pri- St. Thomas Aquinas. See Aquinas vate property, 115-124 Sartre, Jean Paul, 180; denial of Public policy, making, 45-46 God, 176 Schneider, Herbert W., i33«. Reformation, common concep- Schools, demands upon, 73-74. See tion of law during, 98 also Education Reisman, David, 111-112 Second World War, fatal cycle re- Religion, achievement of freedom peated in, 23; propaganda of, of, 96-97 23-24 Representation of The People Act, Shaw, Bernard, on value of reason- 39 ing, 78 Representative, duties distinct from Simon, Yves R., on concentration those of executive, 53-54 of power in legislative body, Representative assembly, function 48«. of, 30; increased power of, 55-57 Slater, Rev. Thomas J., S. J., on Revolution, called by Marx and development of Christian law, Engels, liberalism versus 79; 148-149 Jacobinism as doctrine for, 63- Smith, John, 173; on truth, 171- 71; see also American Revolu- 172 tion of 1776 and English Revo- Socrates, civilized nature of, 138- lution of 1688 139 Right, Aristotle on, 145-146 Soviet Constitution of 1936, 170 Rights. See Natural law and Nat- Spain, 57; Falangist counterrevolu- ural rights tion, 58 Roman Empire, common law de- Speech, freedom of, 1 24-1 31 veloped by, 107 Spengler, Oswald, no Roman law, development of, 107- Spykman, Nicholas, on balance of 108 power, 158-159 Romanoff Empire, collapse of, 8 Stalin, Josef, 83, 87 Rome, traditions lost, 104 Stoics. See Zeno Roosevelt, Franklin D., 56 Strauss, Leo, 97«., ii3«. Rousseau, Jean Jacques, 86; on Suffrage. See Universal suffrage natural goodness of man, 74; philosophy of, 71-72 Taine, Hippolyte a., GG, 67, 70- Russell, Bertrand, on intoxication 71 of power, 177 Talmon, J. C, 63;;., 8iw. Russia, democratic model for new Talmud, 149 government in, 6; manpower Ten Commandments, 168-169 losses, ii«.; revolution of 1917, Tillich, Paul, 178; on belief in 12; Soviet Communist counter- God, 164-165 revolution, 58 Titoist counterrevolution, 58 St. Augustine, 152 Tocqueville, Alexis de, impressions St. Chrysostom, 150 of democracy, 64-65 INDEX 189

Totalitarianism, as understood by interest, 41-42; versus the com- Lenin, 80-83. ^^^ ^^^0 Counter- munity, 31-35 revolution Toynbee, Arnold, 96, 112 Wallas, Graham, 10 War, role of public opinion in, 23- United Kingdom. See Great Brit- 25. See also First World War, ain Second World War United States, enfranchisement in, Washington, George, 26«. 39-40, 66; foreign policy before Westermarck, Edward A., i^on. First World War, 17; indecision Western democracies. See Democ- during Second World War, 3-5, racies 18-19, 23; Jacobinism in, 66. Western Europe, defeats in Second See also American Revolution of World War, 23

1776 Western society, decline of, 6 flf. United States Senate, toleration of Willey, Basil, cited, 17 1«. opinion in, 130 Wilson, Frank G., on influence of Universal suffrage, advance toward, intellectuals in society, 177-178 39-40; eiTect on public opinion, Wilson, Woodrow, 6, 18, 50». 39; not implied in popular World War. See First World War, sovereignty, 37-38; preceded by Second World War Bill of Rights, 40 U.S.S.R. See Russia Yalta agreement, 22

Victoria, Queen, 16 Zeno, 104, 105, 115; common law Voegelin, Eric, 8i«. formulated by, 106-107 Voltaire, Frangois Marie de, 71 Zernach, Ada, on de Tocqueville, Voters, opinions and the public 64«.

PPI-IEGE UBRARY ^ Date Due

P^^D^I^SIT^eCtoEGE Due Refurnt UL 9 'b/ OCT 2 1 ^ CT2 iiii s^stsrmiry 5'6(Pj|j^

AUG t? • ^a c I '61 AUG ^ 7 1 M6 3 Q ^7 JAN 1 7 ^/Vj_ SJii.

ililAR 2 2 l^ m. Q'6i a! Vj \ 3 -? B mhy *Ay * A\J6 6 IPC 1958 W0V7 '61|iiOf yiP>g7

DECS 'oii^ifi 7P5l fiCT (^M 1 78 1358 '62 2 1 '62 MPW 2 9 c' /

(3.Z

Essays in the public philosoph main 321.82L766eC.2

3 lEbE D3E47 0536