5 How Far and Fast Can We Push the Frontier of Human Rights Observance?

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

5 How Far and Fast Can We Push the Frontier of Human Rights Observance? 5 How Far and Fast Can We Push the Frontier of Human Rights Observance? “We cannot anticipate today what we shall know only tomorrow” wrote the philosopher Karl Popper. Equally prescient is Kierkegaard’s remark, “We have to live life forward, but we can only understand it backwards.” Any discussion of widening and deepening humanity’s observance of human rights must at the onset come to terms with those two observations. Only by having some perspective on how far and fast we have come can we gauge the optimum speed we can hope for in the future. The history of the evolution of human rights norms is a long – and slow – one. True there has been a spurt over the last sixty years and, as Henry Kiss- inger argues, even more so over the last decade. “An unprecedented move- ment has emerged to submit international politics to judicial procedures [and] has spread with extraordinary speed”, he recently wrote in a despairing and disparaging tone. It has been brought on in part by popular agitation personi- fied by the rapid growth and influence of Amnesty International and Human Rights Watch, but it truly is the cumulative work of centuries, if not millennia, of political, philosophical and religious thinking, hammered out on the anvil of revolutions, wars and political debate. There is, to mis-quote one of the two most important documents in the human rights canon, the American Declara- tion of Independence, nothing “self-evident” about it. Let me repeat myself, but somewhat more fully: “We hold these truths to be self-evident, that men are created equal, that they are endowed by their Cre- ator with certain unalienable Rights, that among those are Life, Liberty and the pursuit of Happiness.” All of us know, however, that Jefferson’s self evident truths about human rights have not seemed self-evident to most of humanity for most of its history. There is no revealed truth on this subject. Indeed Jef- ferson himself was a contented slave-owner, “happy”, to use a keyword in his declaration, to impregnate his female slaves, but not countenancing giving his offspring the rights to be the sons and daughters of an important man. A UNESCO document of 1949 spoke of “the antiquity and broad acceptance of the conception of human rights,” and suggested that the discussion of such rights goes right back to the beginnings of philosophy in both the East and the West. But as Brian Tierney argues in his book The Idea of Natural Rights, “few his- 90 Chapter five torians would agree with such a broad judgment.” Kenneth Minogue has written that the idea of human rights is “as modern as the internal combustion engine.” Some have dated it as beginning with Hobbes. Others with Grotius. And Tierney himself has a lot of time for those who say the father of subjective rights was the fourteenth century Franciscan philosopher, William of Ockham. Others argue that the ancient Greeks were the first to start to think about subjective rights. However, there appears to be no elaborated doctrine of natural rights among stoic thinkers. Roman law – the most detailed of all ancient systems – similarly fell short. Many scholars have argued that a doctrine of natural rights was al- ways implicit in Judeo-Christian teaching. But Moses’ law was commandment. So was Jesus’ and Mohammed’s and although St Paul wrote of law written in the hearts of men he certainly did not go so far to say that “all men are endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable rights”. Nor can one unearth these ideas in the early history of other cultures. Natural rights theories, for all their world- wide popularity today, are essentially a relatively recent Western invention, dat- ing from around the twelfth century, at the height of the medieval period. Nevertheless, as Tierney warned us, “it is unprofitable to ask whether the 12th century “discovered” the individual. In all cultures some people are more self-aware and reflective than others. But we can say that twelfth century Eu- ropean civilization was marked, like no other culture, with a new emphasis on personalism and humanism. Not least courtly love literature explored the joys and pain of human lovers. In marriage law, by the end of the twelfth century, the simple consent of the man and the woman, without the need to go to Church, was regarded as sufficient for a valid sacramental marriage. What a human right that was! When the French Franciscan philosopher, Ockham, arrived on the scene in the 14th century he took this a step further and maintained that the tra- ditional idea of an objective natural law – which existed in Roman law – be transformed into a new theory of subjective natural rights. Natural rights and natural law, he wrote, were derived from human rationality and free will and were independent of Christian revelation. (Today Pope Benedict is an enthusi- ast of this idea of natural law.) There were other schools of thought beside his. Gratian used Stoic thought on natural law when he wrote his great canonistic work, the Decretum in 1140 and Thomas Aquinas, in turn, used the Decretum in his seminal work, The Sum- ma Theologiae, written in the thirteenth century. Later in the sixteenth cen- tury, the Spanish Dominican monks, in particular Friar Bortolome Las Casas, in their quest to save the South American Indians from the pillage, exploita- tion and murder of the Spanish Conquistadores, built on Aquinas, elaborating the idea that all individuals were children of God and “made in his image”. But they also argued their case independent of Christian revelation, asserting as Ockham did that natural rights and natural law were derived from human ra- tionality and free will. Tragically, all the writings in Spain and all the victories won in the debating halls of Salamanca and Madrid on behalf of the Indians did little to save them from the depredations of the Spanish adventurers..
Recommended publications
  • RELG 399 Fall2019
    McGill University School of Religious Studies RELG 399 TEXTS OF CHRISTIAN SPIRITUALITY (Late Antiquity) In the Fall Term of 2019 this seminar course will focus on Christian spirituality in Late Antiquity with close study and interpretation of Aurelius Augustine’s spiritual odyssey the Confessiones, his account of creation in De genesi ad litteram, and his handbook of hermeneutics De doctrina Christiana. We will also read Ancius Manlius Severinus Boethius’s treatment of theodicy in De consolatione philosophiae, his De Trinitate, and selections from De Musica. Professor: Torrance Kirby Office Hours: Birks 206, Tuesdays/Thursdays, 10:00–11:00 am Email: [email protected] Birks Building, Room 004A Tuesdays/Thursdays 4:05–5:25 pm COURSE SYLLABUS—FALL TERM 2019 Date Reading 3 September INTRODUCTION 5 September Aurelius Augustine, Confessiones Book I, Early Years 10 September Book II, Theft of Pears 12 September Book III, Adolescence and Student Life 17 September Book IV, Manichee and Astrologer 19 September Book V, Carthage, Rome, and Milan *Confirm Mid-Term Essay Topics (1500-2000 words) (NB Consult the Style Sheet, essay-writing guidelines and evaluation rubric in the appendix to the syllabus.) 24 September Book VI, Secular Ambitions and Conflicts 26 September Book VII, Neoplatonic Quest for the Good 1 October Book VIII, Tolle, lege; tolle, lege 3 October Book IX, Vision at Ostia 8 October Book X, 1-26 Memory *Mid-term Essays due at beginning of class. Essay Conferences to be scheduled for week of 21 October 10 October Book X, 27-43 “Late have I loved you” 15 October Book XI, Time and Eternity 17 October Book XII, Creation Essay Conferences begin this week, Birks 206.
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphysics Today and Tomorrow*
    1 Metaphysics Today and Tomorrow* Raphaël Millière École normale supérieure, Paris – October 2011 Translated by Mark Ohm with the assistance of Leah Orth, Jon Cogburn, and Emily Beck Cogburn “By metaphysics, I do not mean those abstract considerations of certain imaginary properties, the principal use of which is to furnish the wherewithal for endless dispute to those who want to dispute. By this science I mean the general truths which can serve as principles for the particular sciences.” Malebranche Dialogues on Metaphysics and Religion 1. The interminable agony of metaphysics Throughout the twentieth century, numerous philosophers sounded the death knell of metaphysics. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Rudolf Carnap, Martin Heidegger, Gilbert Ryle, J. L. Austin, Jacques Derrida, Jürgen Habermas, Richard Rorty, and, henceforth, Hilary Putnam: a great many tutelary figures have extolled the rejection, the exceeding, the elimination, or the deconstruction of first philosophy. All these necrological chronicles do not have the same radiance, the same seriousness, nor the same motivations, but they all agree to dismiss the discipline, which in the past was considered “the queen of the sciences”, with a violence at times comparable to the prestige it commanded at the time of its impunity. Even today, certain philosophers hastily spread the tragic news with contempt for philosophical inquiry, as if its grave solemnity bestowed upon it some obviousness. Thus, Franco Volpi writes: ‘Grand metaphysics is dead!’ is the slogan which applies to the majority of contemporary philosophers, whether continentals or of analytic profession. They all treat metaphysics as a dead dog.1 In this way, the “path of modern thought” would declare itself vociferously “anti- metaphysical and finally post-metaphysical”.
    [Show full text]
  • The Foundations of Economic Personalism: Daniel Rush Finn Promise and Peril Saint John’S University
    Journal of Markets & Morality Volume 6, Number 2 (Fall 2003): 599–615 Copyright © 2003 The Foundations of Economic Personalism: Daniel Rush Finn Promise and Peril Saint John’s University The Acton Institute’s three-volume series on the Foundations of Economic Personalism contributes much to the dialogue between theology and economics. This article, however, identifies a number of shortcomings. These include an overly individualistic bias and a reliance on the Austrian school of economics that are not consonant with Christian and especially Catholic social thought on economic life. There is a certain naiveté about the philosophy of science and an artificial bifurcation between “economic” life (where values are assumed to be subjective) and the rest of life (where objective values are endorsed). The dia- logue between theology and economics is badly needed, but it requires a strong dose of self-criticism from all its participants. Introduction It is all too rare for theologians and economists to work seriously together. In an effort to overcome this unfortunate tendency, the Center for Economic Personalism at the Acton Institute commissioned and published a three- volume work titled Foundations of Economic Personalism. The first volume is entitled Beyond Self Interest: A Personalist Approach to Human Action, by Gregory R. Beabout, Ricardo F. Crespo, Stephen J. Grabill, Kim Paffenroth, and Kyle Swan. The second volume is Human Nature and the Discipline of Economics: Personalist Anthropology and Economic Methodology, by Patricia Donohue-White, Stephen J. Grabill, Christopher Westley, and Gloria Zúñiga. The third volume is entitled The Free Person and the Free Economy: 599 The Foundations of Economic Daniel Rush Finn Personalism: Promise and Peril A Personalist View of Market Economics, by Anthony J.
    [Show full text]
  • Setting Aside Naturalism in Favor of Personhood in Extreme Cases
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Dissertations Theses and Dissertations 2011 Restoring the Balance: Setting Aside Naturalism in Favor of Personhood in Extreme Cases Brian Joseph Buckley Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss Part of the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Buckley, Brian Joseph, "Restoring the Balance: Setting Aside Naturalism in Favor of Personhood in Extreme Cases" (2011). Dissertations. 216. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss/216 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 2011 Brian Joseph Buckley LOYOLA UNIVERSITY CHICAGO RESTORING THE BALANCE: SETTING ASIDE NATURALISM IN FAVOR OF PERSONHOOD IN EXTREME CASES A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE GRADUATE SCHOOL IN CANDIDACY FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY PROGRAM IN PHILOSOPHY BY BRIAN JOSEPH BUCKLEY CHICAGO, ILLINOIS MAY 2011 Copyright by Brian J. Buckley, 2011 All rights reserved. TABLE OF CONTENTS CHAPTER ONE: INTRODUCTION 1 CHAPTER TWO: TAYLOR AND HABERMAS ON NATURALISM AND THE IMPORTANCE OF THE HUMAN SCIENCES 11 Introduction 11 Charles Taylor and Naturalism 14 Scenarios 40 Habermas and the Concerns for The Future of
    [Show full text]
  • The Theological and Pastoral Influences of St. Bonaventure's Critical Retrieval of Joachim of Fiore on Joseph Ratzinger/Benedict XVI
    Providence College DigitalCommons@Providence Theology Graduate Theses Theology Spring 2013 Loving in the Present: The Theological and Pastoral Influences of St. Bonaventure's Critical Retrieval of Joachim of Fiore on Joseph Ratzinger/Benedict XVI William L. Patenaude Providence College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.providence.edu/theology_graduate_theses Part of the Religion Commons Patenaude, William L., "Loving in the Present: The Theological and Pastoral Influences of St. Bonaventure's Critical Retrieval of Joachim of Fiore on Joseph Ratzinger/Benedict XVI" (2013). Theology Graduate Theses. 1. https://digitalcommons.providence.edu/theology_graduate_theses/1 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theology at DigitalCommons@Providence. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theology Graduate Theses by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@Providence. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Graduate Thesis Submission Loving in the Present: The Theological and Pastoral Influences of St. Bonaventure’s Critical Retrieval of Joachim of Fiore on Joseph Ratzinger/Benedict XVI. Submitted by: William L. Patenaude Providence College April 24, 2011 Loving in the Present William Patenaude Introduction The influences of St. Bonaventure on Joseph Ratzinger/Benedict XVI1 have been noted in studies by Fr. Aidan Nichols O.P., Tracey Rowland, Fr. Maximilian Heinrich Heim, and others.2 A dedicated overview of Bonaventurian thought within the writings of the current Holy Father, however, is necessary to more fully appreciate the roots of Ratzinger/Benedict XVI’s theology and its imprint on (and implications for) Catholic theology, anthropology, and pastoral practices. The present work intends to demonstrate that Joseph Ratzinger’s 1957 thesis on St.
    [Show full text]
  • Belief in a Secular Age: Charles Taylor, John Henry Newman, and the New Evangelization David C
    Santa Clara University Scholar Commons Jesuit School of Theology Dissertations Student Scholarship 4-2018 Belief in a Secular Age: Charles Taylor, John Henry Newman, and the New Evangelization David C. Paternostro Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarcommons.scu.edu/jst_dissertations Part of the Religion Commons Recommended Citation Paternostro, David C., "Belief in a Secular Age: Charles Taylor, John Henry Newman, and the New Evangelization" (2018). Jesuit School of Theology Dissertations. 29. https://scholarcommons.scu.edu/jst_dissertations/29 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Scholarship at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Jesuit School of Theology Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Belief in a Secular Age: Charles Taylor, John Henry Newman, and the New Evangelization A thesis by David C. Paternostro, S.J. Presented to the Faculty of the Jesuit School of Theology of Santa Clara University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Licentiate in Sacred Theology Berkeley, California April 2018 Committee Signatures: __________________________ Thomas Cattoi, Ph.D. (Director) 24 April 2018 ________________________________ Jerome Baggett, Ph.D. (Second Reader) 24 April 2018 Acknowledgements---------------------------------------------------------------------------------ii Abstract----------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------iii
    [Show full text]
  • Nikolai Berdyaev's Personalism
    International Journal of Orthodox Theology 6:3 (2015) 63 urn:nbn:de:0276-2015-3054 Richard A. Hughes Nikolai Berdyaev’s Personalism Abstract The author portrays Russian philosopher Nikolai Berdyaev as a pioneer in Eastern Orthodox theology with his ideas of freedom and personality. After his deportation from the Soviet Union in 1922, Berdyaev expounded persona- lism in opposition to Western individualism and Marxist collecti- vism. Personality exists in the image and likeness of God, and it culminates in deification. He drew upon the Sobornost’ tradition of Russia and interpreted personality as a communion of love in contrast to reflective self-consciousness of the Augustinian tradition of Western theology. Keywords Richard A. Hughes M. B. Rich Professor of Meonic freedom, personality, Religion at Lycoming Sobornost´, Incarnation, deification College, PA, USA 64 Richard A. Hughes 1 Introduction The aim of this essay is to expound the personalism in the philosophy of Nikolai Berdyaev (1874−1948) and to assess its significance within the context of Orthodox theology. He was a Christian philosopher who considered himself to be a loyal son of the Russian Orthodox Church. In 1894 Berdyaev became a Marxist, and he was active in clandestine revolutionary groups. He believed that Marxism was the only means to overcome the evil of capitalism.1 On 11/12 March 1898 the police rounded up clandestine groups and arrested Berdyaev; he was sentenced to three years exile in Vologda. While in exile, he realized the limitations of Marxism and moved toward
    [Show full text]
  • Joseph Ratzinger's Philosophical Theology of the Person
    THEOLOGY OF POPE BENEDICT XVI Rocznik Teologii Katolickiej, tom XVII/3, rok 2018 DOI: 10.15290/rtk.2018.17.3.16 0000-0003-0382-3646 ks. Andrzej Proniewski Uniwersytet w Białymstoku Joseph Ratzinger’s Philosophical Theology of the Person Joseph Ratzinger’s scholarly refl ections and ideas convey a philosophi- cal theology of the person that points to relational complementarity. In this article, the author uses the image of a house in order to present Ratzinger’s philosophical theology of the human person. The fi rst part of this article ex- amines the foundations of Ratzinger’s theology and points out how diff erent philosophers have infl uenced his understanding of biblical anthropology. The second part presents the architectural supports of Ratzinger’s theology, which are the parallels that Ratzinger draws between the body and soul as well as God’s transcendence and man. The third section discusses the ceiling, meaning the beams (principles) of Ratzinger’s theology: the intellect, love, truth, beauty, and hope. Ratzinger’s approach to philosophical theology is both original and creative because he argues that, based on his dialogical understanding of the human person, the individual must transcend himself and because he demonstrates that relationship and dialogue are as primordial a form of being as substance. The essence of Ratzinger’s theology of the person is a biblical understanding of the human person that highlights man’s unique dialogical relationship to God. Key words: Joseph Ratzinger, Benedict XVI, theology of the person, personal- ism, man. Joseph Ratzinger refers to the personalism and existentialism of the beginning of the 20th century in order to arrive at an understand- ing of the human person.
    [Show full text]
  • Thomistic Personalism: an Investigation, Explication, and Defense
    Thomistic Personalism: An Investigation, Explication, and Defense Author: Michael Camacho Persistent link: http://hdl.handle.net/2345/666 This work is posted on eScholarship@BC, Boston College University Libraries. Boston College Electronic Thesis or Dissertation, 2009 Copyright is held by the author, with all rights reserved, unless otherwise noted. Thomistic Personalism An Investigation, Explication and Defense by Michael Camacho Senior Thesis Boston College Philosophy Department Scholar of the College Project Advisor: Dr. Marina McCoy Second Reviewer: Dr. Peter Kreeft 1 May 2009 Copyright © 2009 by Michael Camacho All rights reserved Contents Introduction ……………………………………………………………………………………….1 1. What is Thomistic Personalism? ……………………………………………………………...6 a. History of the Concept of “Person” …………………………………………………..6 b. The Method and Direction of Wojtyła’s Creative Synthesis ………………………..23 2. Why is Thomistic Personalism Necessary, and Is It Possible? ……………………………...36 a. The Need for a Synthesis ……………………………………………………………39 b. Is Thomistic Personalism Possible? …………………………………………………46 3. Essential Aspects of Wojtyła’s Philosophy of the Acting Person …………………………..52 a. Consciousness ……………………………………………………………………….53 b. Efficacy ……………………………………………………………………………...57 c. Fulfillment …………………………………………………………………………...62 d. Integration …………………………………………………………………………...64 e. Participation …………………………………………………………………………70 Conclusion: Application and Development ……………………………………………………..73 Works Cited ……………………………………………………………………………………..84 Introduction Man is only a reed, the weakest in nature; but he is a thinking reed. Through space the universe grasps me and swallows me up like a speck; through thought I grasp it. 1 Man is a paradox to himself, a living oxymoron, a being “in but not of the world.” 2 Each of us finds ourselves in this strange middling position. I am in the world insofar as I am a real, material object, an organism, an animal, a some thing .
    [Show full text]
  • Prudential Personalism" > Why Does It Matter?
    HONORING FR. O'ROURKE What Is "Prudential Personalism" > Why Does It Matter? Fr. O'Rourke Helped Retrieve a Vital Ethical Method in Catholic Theology I n one sense, there is nothing new about will suggest several practical implications of this I the theory called "prudential personal- theory for medicine and health care ethics. _^^ism" developed by Fr. Kevin D. WHERE DOES PRUDENTIAL PERSONALISM FIT IN THE O'Rourke, OP, JCD, STM, and his BROADER CONTEXT OF ETHICS?* Dominican confrere, Fr. Benedict M. Ethics is a kind of knowledge, but it differs from BY CHARLES E. Ashley, OP, PhD, through successive edi­ scientific or technical knowledge because it has to BOUCHARD, OP, do with "oughtness." Ethics, whether based in STD tions of their book Health Care Ethics religious faith or not, always tries to answer two Fr. Bouchard is (HCE)} It is the retrieval of an ethical questions: "What ought I to do?" and "What president and method developed, at least in part, by kind of person ought I to be?" These "doing" associate professor Aristotle, refined and adapted to Christian and "being" questions are at the heart of nearly of moral theology, every ethical system. Aquinas Institute life by St. Thomas Aquinas, and neglected There are two basic ways of answering these of Theology, and distorted by philosophers, reformers, questions, each of which has a variety of subsets St. Louis. and even the church itself. It was reappro- or subcategories. The first basic system is called deontological or "duty-based," because the priated in the 20th century by theologians answer to the "ought" question always refers to and philosophers alike.
    Why Does It Matter?" class="panel-rg color-a">[Show full text]
  • Carl Schmitt's Political Theology*
    Carl Schmitt’s Political Theology* HUGO BALL I. Carl Schmitt ranks among the few German savants who are equal to the pro - fessional dangers of a teaching chair in the present era. I do not hesitate to suggest that he has taken and established for himself the type of the new German savant. If the writings of this remarkable professor (not to say confessor) served only towards the recognition and study of its author’s catholic (universal) physiog - nomy, that alone would be enough to assure him a preeminent status. In a fine essay, “On Ideals,” Chesterton says that the remediation of our confused and des - perate age in no way requires the great “practical man” who is clamored for the world over, but rather the great ideologist. “A practical man means a man accus - tomed to mere daily practice, to the way things commonly work. When things do not work, you must have the thinker, the man who has some doctrine about why they work at all. It is wrong to fiddle while Rome is burning; but it is quite right to study the theory of hydraulics while Rome is burning.” 1 Carl Schmitt belongs to those who “study the theory of hydraulics.” He is an ideologist of rare conviction, and indeed it’s safe to say that he will restore to this word a new prestige, which among Germans has carried a pejorative meaning since Bismarck. 2 * This essay first appeared in Hochland 21, issue 2 (April–September 1924), pp. 263–86. Reprinted in Der Fürst dieser Welt: Carl Schmitt und die Folgen , ed.
    [Show full text]
  • The Common Sense Personalism of St. John Paul Ii (Karol Wojtyla)
    Studia Gilsoniana 3: supplement (2014): 619–634 | ISSN 2300–0066 Paweá Tarasiewicz John Paul II Catholic University of Lublin Poland THE COMMON SENSE PERSONALISM OF ST. JOHN PAUL II (KAROL WOJTYLA) Demonstrating a linkage between Karol Wojtyla’s philosophical personalism and common sense seems to necessitate showing Wojtyla’s appreciation for classical metaphysics as being nothing other than a phi- losophical development of the common sense interpretation of reality. 1 In my article, then, I am going to support two claims. First, that the personal- ism of St. John Paul II is specified by the metaphysical philosophy of the Lublin Philosophical School (further mentioned as LPS), which in turn means that Wojtyla’s philosophical legacy can not be properly understood unless examined against the background of the philosophical project of this School. Secondly, that Wojtyla’s usage of phenomenological method fully complies with the metaphysical approach to reality. A Framer of LPS Although in the 1950s the Faculty of Philosophy at the Catholic University of Lublin (further mentioned as KUL) formally consisted of many professors, there were merely a few who not only delivered lectures but also contributed in conceiving and running some common project of doing philosophy. In 1954, when he started to commute from Krakow to Lublin, Fr. Wojtyla joined a group of three other Lublin scholars (namely 1 In accord with metaphysics, I assume that common sense is a cognitive habit to apprehend reality in its most fundamental aspects. It is elicited in spontaneous, pre-scientific cognition, which conditions a normal human development in the area of knowing, acting, and produc- ing.
    [Show full text]