Incomplete Information and Robustness in Strategic Environments

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Incomplete Information and Robustness in Strategic Environments University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations Spring 2010 Incomplete Information and Robustness in Strategic Environments Antonio Penta University of Pennsylvania, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations Part of the Economic Theory Commons Recommended Citation Penta, Antonio, "Incomplete Information and Robustness in Strategic Environments" (2010). Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations. 134. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/134 This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/134 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Incomplete Information and Robustness in Strategic Environments Abstract Game theoretic modeling involves making assumptions on agents' infinite hierarchies of beliefs. These assumptions are understood to be only approximately satisfied in the actual situation. Thus, the significance of game theoretic predictions depend on robustness properties of the solution concepts adopted. Chapter 1 discusses recent results in this research area and their relations with the results obtained in the subsequent chapters. Chapter 2 explores the impact of misspecification of higher order beliefs in static environments, when arbitrary common knowledge assumptions on payoffs are relaxed. (Existing literature focuses on the extreme case in which all such assumptions are relaxed.) Chapter 3 provides a characterization of the strongest predictions, for dynamic games, that are "robust" to possible misspecifications of agents' higher order beliefs, and shows that such characterization depends on modeling assumptions that have hitherto received little attention in the literature (namely, the distinction between knowledge and certainty), raising novel questions of robustness. Chapter 4 develops a methodology to address classical questions of implementation, when agents' beliefs are unknown to the designer and their private information changes over time. The key idea is the identification of a solution concept that allows a tractable analysis of the full implementation problem: Full "robust" implementation requires that, for all models of agents' beliefs, all the perfect Bayesian equilibria of a mechanism induce outcomes consistent with the social choice function (SCF). It is shown that, for a weaker notion of equilibrium and for a general class of games, the set of all such equilibria can be computed by means of a "backwards procedure" that combines the logic of rationalizability and backward induction reasoning. It is further shown that a SCF is (partially) implementable for all models of beliefs if and only if it is ex-post incentive compatible. In environments with single crossing preferences, strict ex-post incentive compatibility and a "contraction property" are sufficiento t guarantee full robust implementation in direct mechanisms. This property limits the interdependence in agents' valuations. Degree Type Dissertation Degree Name Doctor of Philosophy (PhD) Graduate Group Economics First Advisor George J. Mailath Keywords Robustness; Mechanism Design; Robust Implementation; Dynamic Games; Incomplete Information; Rationalizability; Hierarchies of beliefs Subject Categories Economic Theory This dissertation is available at ScholarlyCommons: https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/134 INCOMPLETE INFORMATION AND ROBUSTNESS IN STRATEGIC ENVIRONMENTS Antonio Penta A DISSERTATION in Economics Presented to the Faculties of the University of Pennsylvania in Partial Ful…llment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy 2010 Supervisor of Dissertation George J. Mailath, Walter H. Annenberg Professor in the Social Sciences Graduate Group Chairperson Dirk Krueger, Professor of Economics Dissertation Committee: George J. Mailath, Walter H. Annenberg Professor in the Social Sciences Andrew Postlewaite, Harry P. Kamen Professor of Economics Qingmin Liu, Assistant Professor of Economics INCOMPLETE INFORMATION AND ROBUSTNESS IN STRATEGIC ENVIRONMENTS COPYRIGHT 2010 Antonio Penta Per Sara, il suo amore, e il suo sorriso. iii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I want to thank Prof. George Mailath for his dedication, his support, the valuable insights, and above all for having constantly challenged me. As a true mentor, he has set an example of intellectual honesty and professionalism which will accompany me throughout my own career. I also thank Prof. Qingmin Liu, for the careful and always constructive criticisms, and Prof. Andrew Postlewaite, for the sharpness of his thinking. Special thanks go to Prof. Pierpaolo Battigalli, who more than anyone has shaped my view and understanding of game theory. This very dissertation testi…es the extent of my intellectual debt to him. I owe a lot to the intellectual vivacity of Larbi Alaoui, to the inspiring passion of Dave Cass, and to a long list of colleagues and friends who have made these years at Penn a unique life experience. Everything I achieved though would not have been possible without the invaluable and unconditional support of my parents, the loyalty of my sister, and the friendship of Gil, Larbi, Deniz, Dionissi, Francesca, Leonardo and Michela. Of the many things I should thank them for, there is one that is above the others: their patience. Finally, I thank Sara, without whom everything would have had just a di¤erent ‡avor. iv ABSTRACT INCOMPLETE INFORMATION AND ROBUSTNESS IN STRATEGIC ENVIRONMENTS Antonio Penta George J. Mailath Game theoretic modeling involves making assumptions on agents’in…nite hierar- chies of beliefs. These assumptions are understood to be only approximately satis…ed in the actual situation. Thus, the signi…cance of game theoretic predictions depend on robustness properties of the solution concepts adopted. Chapter 1 discusses re- cent results in this research area and their relations with the results obtained in the subsequent chapters. Chapter 2 explores the impact of misspeci…cation of higher or- der beliefs in static environments, when arbitrary common knowledge assumptions on payo¤s are relaxed. (Existing literature focuses on the extreme case in which all such assumptions are relaxed.) Chapter 3 provides a characterization of the strongest predictions, for dynamic games, that are “robust” to possible misspeci…cations of agents’higher order beliefs, and shows that such characterization depends on model- ing assumptions that have hitherto received little attention in the literature (namely, the distinction between knowledge and certainty), raising novel questions of robust- ness. Chapter 4 develops a methodology to address classical questions of implementa- tion, when agents’beliefs are unknown to the designer and their private information changes over time. The key idea is the identi…cation of a solution concept that allows a tractable analysis of the full implementation problem: Full “robust” implementa- tion requires that, for all models of agents’beliefs, all the perfect Bayesian equilibria of a mechanism induce outcomes consistent with the social choice function (SCF). It v is shown that, for a weaker notion of equilibrium and for a general class of games, the set of all such equilibria can be computed by means of a “backwards procedure”that combines the logic of rationalizability and backward induction reasoning. It is further shown that a SCF is (partially) implementable for all models of beliefs if and only if it is ex-post incentive compatible. In environments with single crossing preferences, strict ex-post incentive compatibility and a “contraction property” are su¢ cient to guarantee full robust implementation in direct mechanisms. This property limits the interdependence in agents’valuations. vi Contents Acknowledgements iv 1 Incomplete Information and Robustness in Strategic Environments 1 1.1 Introduction................................ 2 1.2 Complete Information: Rationalizability and Equilibria . 4 1.2.1 (Static) Games with Complete Information. 5 1.2.2 Common Belief in Rationality and Equilibrium . 7 1.3 (Static) Games with Incomplete Information . 9 1.3.1 Harsanyi’sapproach: Bayesian Games and Equilibrium . 10 1.3.2 Non-Equilibrium Approach . 16 1.4 Interim Robustness in Static Games . 24 1.4.1 Relaxing all CK assumptions on payo¤s . 25 1.4.2 Belief-Free Models and Equilibrium . 32 1.4.3 Discussion............................. 33 1.5 DynamicGames.............................. 33 1.5.1 Relaxing all CK-assumptions on payo¤s (II) . 37 1.5.2 Equilibria in Belief-free environments . 47 2 On the Structure of Rationalizability on Arbitrary Spaces of Un- certainty 62 vii 2.1 Introduction................................ 62 2.2 Game Theoretic Framework . 65 2.2.1 Structure of Rationalizability without Richness . 67 2.3 Discussion................................. 74 3 Higher Order Beliefs in Dynamic Environments 76 3.1 Introduction................................ 77 3.2 Relaxing CK-assumptions and Robustness in Dynamic Games . 82 3.2.1 Preliminaries and Examples . 82 3.2.2 Non-technical Presentation of the Approach and Results . 88 3.3 Game Theoretic Framework . 93 3.4 Interim Sequential Rationalizability . 99 3.4.1 Example: Finitely Repeated Prisoner’sDilemma . 102 3.5 Robustness(-es) . 105 3.5.1 Upper Hemicontinuity . 105 3.5.2 Type Space Invariance . 106 3.5.3 Model Invariance . 106 3.6 The structure of in the Universal Model ............. 107 ISR 3.6.1 Sensitivity of Multiplicity to higher order beliefs . 109 3.6.2 Genericity of Uniqueness . 113 3.7 Related Literature and Concluding
Recommended publications
  • Repeated Games
    6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 15: Repeated Games Asu Ozdaglar MIT April 1, 2010 1 Game Theory: Lecture 15 Introduction Outline Repeated Games (perfect monitoring) The problem of cooperation Finitely-repeated prisoner's dilemma Infinitely-repeated games and cooperation Folk Theorems Reference: Fudenberg and Tirole, Section 5.1. 2 Game Theory: Lecture 15 Introduction Prisoners' Dilemma How to sustain cooperation in the society? Recall the prisoners' dilemma, which is the canonical game for understanding incentives for defecting instead of cooperating. Cooperate Defect Cooperate 1, 1 −1, 2 Defect 2, −1 0, 0 Recall that the strategy profile (D, D) is the unique NE. In fact, D strictly dominates C and thus (D, D) is the dominant equilibrium. In society, we have many situations of this form, but we often observe some amount of cooperation. Why? 3 Game Theory: Lecture 15 Introduction Repeated Games In many strategic situations, players interact repeatedly over time. Perhaps repetition of the same game might foster cooperation. By repeated games, we refer to a situation in which the same stage game (strategic form game) is played at each date for some duration of T periods. Such games are also sometimes called \supergames". We will assume that overall payoff is the sum of discounted payoffs at each stage. Future payoffs are discounted and are thus less valuable (e.g., money and the future is less valuable than money now because of positive interest rates; consumption in the future is less valuable than consumption now because of time preference). We will see in this lecture how repeated play of the same strategic game introduces new (desirable) equilibria by allowing players to condition their actions on the way their opponents played in the previous periods.
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture 4 Rationalizability & Nash Equilibrium Road
    Lecture 4 Rationalizability & Nash Equilibrium 14.12 Game Theory Muhamet Yildiz Road Map 1. Strategies – completed 2. Quiz 3. Dominance 4. Dominant-strategy equilibrium 5. Rationalizability 6. Nash Equilibrium 1 Strategy A strategy of a player is a complete contingent-plan, determining which action he will take at each information set he is to move (including the information sets that will not be reached according to this strategy). Matching pennies with perfect information 2’s Strategies: HH = Head if 1 plays Head, 1 Head if 1 plays Tail; HT = Head if 1 plays Head, Head Tail Tail if 1 plays Tail; 2 TH = Tail if 1 plays Head, 2 Head if 1 plays Tail; head tail head tail TT = Tail if 1 plays Head, Tail if 1 plays Tail. (-1,1) (1,-1) (1,-1) (-1,1) 2 Matching pennies with perfect information 2 1 HH HT TH TT Head Tail Matching pennies with Imperfect information 1 2 1 Head Tail Head Tail 2 Head (-1,1) (1,-1) head tail head tail Tail (1,-1) (-1,1) (-1,1) (1,-1) (1,-1) (-1,1) 3 A game with nature Left (5, 0) 1 Head 1/2 Right (2, 2) Nature (3, 3) 1/2 Left Tail 2 Right (0, -5) Mixed Strategy Definition: A mixed strategy of a player is a probability distribution over the set of his strategies. Pure strategies: Si = {si1,si2,…,sik} σ → A mixed strategy: i: S [0,1] s.t. σ σ σ i(si1) + i(si2) + … + i(sik) = 1. If the other players play s-i =(s1,…, si-1,si+1,…,sn), then σ the expected utility of playing i is σ σ σ i(si1)ui(si1,s-i) + i(si2)ui(si2,s-i) + … + i(sik)ui(sik,s-i).
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture Notes
    GRADUATE GAME THEORY LECTURE NOTES BY OMER TAMUZ California Institute of Technology 2018 Acknowledgments These lecture notes are partially adapted from Osborne and Rubinstein [29], Maschler, Solan and Zamir [23], lecture notes by Federico Echenique, and slides by Daron Acemoglu and Asu Ozdaglar. I am indebted to Seo Young (Silvia) Kim and Zhuofang Li for their help in finding and correcting many errors. Any comments or suggestions are welcome. 2 Contents 1 Extensive form games with perfect information 7 1.1 Tic-Tac-Toe ........................................ 7 1.2 The Sweet Fifteen Game ................................ 7 1.3 Chess ............................................ 7 1.4 Definition of extensive form games with perfect information ........... 10 1.5 The ultimatum game .................................. 10 1.6 Equilibria ......................................... 11 1.7 The centipede game ................................... 11 1.8 Subgames and subgame perfect equilibria ...................... 13 1.9 The dollar auction .................................... 14 1.10 Backward induction, Kuhn’s Theorem and a proof of Zermelo’s Theorem ... 15 2 Strategic form games 17 2.1 Definition ......................................... 17 2.2 Nash equilibria ...................................... 17 2.3 Classical examples .................................... 17 2.4 Dominated strategies .................................. 22 2.5 Repeated elimination of dominated strategies ................... 22 2.6 Dominant strategies ..................................
    [Show full text]
  • SEQUENTIAL GAMES with PERFECT INFORMATION Example
    SEQUENTIAL GAMES WITH PERFECT INFORMATION Example 4.9 (page 105) Consider the sequential game given in Figure 4.9. We want to apply backward induction to the tree. 0 Vertex B is owned by player two, P2. The payoffs for P2 are 1 and 3, with 3 > 1, so the player picks R . Thus, the payoffs at B become (0, 3). 00 Next, vertex C is also owned by P2 with payoffs 1 and 0. Since 1 > 0, P2 picks L , and the payoffs are (4, 1). Player one, P1, owns A; the choice of L gives a payoff of 0 and R gives a payoff of 4; 4 > 0, so P1 chooses R. The final payoffs are (4, 1). 0 00 We claim that this strategy profile, { R } for P1 and { R ,L } is a Nash equilibrium. Notice that the 0 00 strategy profile gives a choice at each vertex. For the strategy { R ,L } fixed for P2, P1 has a maximal payoff by choosing { R }, ( 0 00 0 00 π1(R, { R ,L }) = 4 π1(R, { R ,L }) = 4 ≥ 0 00 π1(L, { R ,L }) = 0. 0 00 In the same way, for the strategy { R } fixed for P1, P2 has a maximal payoff by choosing { R ,L }, ( 00 0 00 π2(R, {∗,L }) = 1 π2(R, { R ,L }) = 1 ≥ 00 π2(R, {∗,R }) = 0, where ∗ means choose either L0 or R0. Since no change of choice by a player can increase that players own payoff, the strategy profile is called a Nash equilibrium. Notice that the above strategy profile is also a Nash equilibrium on each branch of the game tree, mainly starting at either B or starting at C.
    [Show full text]
  • The Monty Hall Problem in the Game Theory Class
    The Monty Hall Problem in the Game Theory Class Sasha Gnedin∗ October 29, 2018 1 Introduction Suppose you’re on a game show, and you’re given the choice of three doors: Behind one door is a car; behind the others, goats. You pick a door, say No. 1, and the host, who knows what’s behind the doors, opens another door, say No. 3, which has a goat. He then says to you, “Do you want to pick door No. 2?” Is it to your advantage to switch your choice? With these famous words the Parade Magazine columnist vos Savant opened an exciting chapter in mathematical didactics. The puzzle, which has be- come known as the Monty Hall Problem (MHP), has broken the records of popularity among the probability paradoxes. The book by Rosenhouse [9] and the Wikipedia entry on the MHP present the history and variations of the problem. arXiv:1107.0326v1 [math.HO] 1 Jul 2011 In the basic version of the MHP the rules of the game specify that the host must always reveal one of the unchosen doors to show that there is no prize there. Two remaining unrevealed doors may hide the prize, creating the illusion of symmetry and suggesting that the action does not matter. How- ever, the symmetry is fallacious, and switching is a better action, doubling the probability of winning. There are two main explanations of the paradox. One of them, simplistic, amounts to just counting the mutually exclusive cases: either you win with ∗[email protected] 1 switching or with holding the first choice.
    [Show full text]
  • Incomplete Information I. Bayesian Games
    Bayesian Games Debraj Ray, November 2006 Unlike the previous notes, the material here is perfectly standard and can be found in the usual textbooks: see, e.g., Fudenberg-Tirole. For the examples in these notes (except for the very last section), I draw heavily on Martin Osborne’s excellent recent text, An Introduction to Game Theory, Oxford University Press. Obviously, incomplete information games — in which one or more players are privy to infor- mation that others don’t have — has enormous applicability: credit markets / auctions / regulation of firms / insurance / bargaining /lemons / public goods provision / signaling / . the list goes on and on. 1. A Definition A Bayesian game consists of 1. A set of players N. 2. A set of states Ω, and a common prior µ on Ω. 3. For each player i a set of actions Ai and a set of signals or types Ti. (Can make actions sets depend on type realizations.) 4. For each player i, a mapping τi :Ω 7→ Ti. 5. For each player i, a vN-M payoff function fi : A × Ω 7→ R, where A is the product of the Ai’s. Remarks A. Typically, the mapping τi tells us player i’s type. The easiest case is just when Ω is the product of the Ti’s and τi is just the appropriate projection mapping. B. The prior on states need not be common, but one view is that there is no loss of generality in assuming it (simply put all differences in the prior into differences in signals and redefine the state space and si-mappings accordingly).
    [Show full text]
  • Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2021) Strategic Games
    Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2021) Strategic Games Topics: terminology and notations (OR 1.7), games and solutions (OR 1.1-1.3), rationality and bounded rationality (OR 1.4-1.6), formalities (OR 2.1), best-response (OR 2.2), Nash equilibrium (OR 2.2), 2 2 examples × (OR 2.3), existence of Nash equilibrium (OR 2.4), mixed strategy Nash equilibrium (OR 3.1, 3.2), strictly competitive games (OR 2.5), evolution- ary stability (OR 3.4), rationalizability (OR 4.1), dominance (OR 4.2, 4.3), trembling hand perfection (OR 12.5). Terminology and notations (OR 1.7) Sets For R, ∈ ≥ ⇐⇒ ≥ for all . and ⇐⇒ ≥ for all and some . ⇐⇒ for all . Preferences is a binary relation on some set of alternatives R. % ⊆ From % we derive two other relations on : — strict performance relation and not  ⇐⇒ % % — indifference relation and ∼ ⇐⇒ % % Utility representation % is said to be — complete if , or . ∀ ∈ % % — transitive if , and then . ∀ ∈ % % % % can be presented by a utility function only if it is complete and transitive (rational). A function : R is a utility function representing if → % ∀ ∈ () () % ⇐⇒ ≥ % is said to be — continuous (preferences cannot jump...) if for any sequence of pairs () with ,and and , . { }∞=1 % → → % — (strictly) quasi-concave if for any the upper counter set ∈ { ∈ : is (strictly) convex. % } These guarantee the existence of continuous well-behaved utility function representation. Profiles Let be a the set of players. — () or simply () is a profile - a collection of values of some variable,∈ one for each player. — () or simply is the list of elements of the profile = ∈ { } − () for all players except . ∈ — ( ) is a list and an element ,whichistheprofile () .
    [Show full text]
  • Scenario Analysis Normal Form Game
    Overview Economics 3030 I. Introduction to Game Theory Chapter 10 II. Simultaneous-Move, One-Shot Games Game Theory: III. Infinitely Repeated Games Inside Oligopoly IV. Finitely Repeated Games V. Multistage Games 1 2 Normal Form Game A Normal Form Game • A Normal Form Game consists of: n Players Player 2 n Strategies or feasible actions n Payoffs Strategy A B C a 12,11 11,12 14,13 b 11,10 10,11 12,12 Player 1 c 10,15 10,13 13,14 3 4 Normal Form Game: Normal Form Game: Scenario Analysis Scenario Analysis • Suppose 1 thinks 2 will choose “A”. • Then 1 should choose “a”. n Player 1’s best response to “A” is “a”. Player 2 Player 2 Strategy A B C a 12,11 11,12 14,13 Strategy A B C b 11,10 10,11 12,12 a 12,11 11,12 14,13 Player 1 11,10 10,11 12,12 c 10,15 10,13 13,14 b Player 1 c 10,15 10,13 13,14 5 6 1 Normal Form Game: Normal Form Game: Scenario Analysis Scenario Analysis • Suppose 1 thinks 2 will choose “B”. • Then 1 should choose “a”. n Player 1’s best response to “B” is “a”. Player 2 Player 2 Strategy A B C Strategy A B C a 12,11 11,12 14,13 a 12,11 11,12 14,13 b 11,10 10,11 12,12 11,10 10,11 12,12 Player 1 b c 10,15 10,13 13,14 Player 1 c 10,15 10,13 13,14 7 8 Normal Form Game Dominant Strategy • Regardless of whether Player 2 chooses A, B, or C, Scenario Analysis Player 1 is better off choosing “a”! • “a” is Player 1’s Dominant Strategy (i.e., the • Similarly, if 1 thinks 2 will choose C… strategy that results in the highest payoff regardless n Player 1’s best response to “C” is “a”.
    [Show full text]
  • (501B) Problem Set 5. Bayesian Games Suggested Solutions by Tibor Heumann
    Dirk Bergemann Department of Economics Yale University Microeconomic Theory (501b) Problem Set 5. Bayesian Games Suggested Solutions by Tibor Heumann 1. (Market for Lemons) Here I ask that you work out some of the details in perhaps the most famous of all information economics models. By contrast to discussion in class, we give a complete formulation of the game. A seller is privately informed of the value v of the good that she sells to a buyer. The buyer's prior belief on v is uniformly distributed on [x; y] with 3 0 < x < y: The good is worth 2 v to the buyer. (a) Suppose the buyer proposes a price p and the seller either accepts or rejects p: If she accepts, the seller gets payoff p−v; and the buyer gets 3 2 v − p: If she rejects, the seller gets v; and the buyer gets nothing. Find the optimal offer that the buyer can make as a function of x and y: (b) Show that if the buyer and the seller are symmetrically informed (i.e. either both know v or neither party knows v), then trade takes place with probability 1. (c) Consider a simultaneous acceptance game in the model with private information as in part a, where a price p is announced and then the buyer and the seller simultaneously accept or reject trade at price p: The payoffs are as in part a. Find the p that maximizes the probability of trade. [SOLUTION] (a) We look for the subgame perfect equilibrium, thus we solve by back- ward induction.
    [Show full text]
  • Pure and Bayes-Nash Price of Anarchy for Generalized Second Price Auction
    Pure and Bayes-Nash Price of Anarchy for Generalized Second Price Auction Renato Paes Leme Eva´ Tardos Department of Computer Science Department of Computer Science Cornell University, Ithaca, NY Cornell University, Ithaca, NY [email protected] [email protected] Abstract—The Generalized Second Price Auction has for advertisements and slots higher on the page are been the main mechanism used by search companies more valuable (clicked on by more users). The bids to auction positions for advertisements on search pages. are used to determine both the assignment of bidders In this paper we study the social welfare of the Nash equilibria of this game in various models. In the full to slots, and the fees charged. In the simplest model, information setting, socially optimal Nash equilibria are the bidders are assigned to slots in order of bids, and known to exist (i.e., the Price of Stability is 1). This paper the fee for each click is the bid occupying the next is the first to prove bounds on the price of anarchy, and slot. This auction is called the Generalized Second Price to give any bounds in the Bayesian setting. Auction (GSP). More generally, positions and payments Our main result is to show that the price of anarchy is small assuming that all bidders play un-dominated in the Generalized Second Price Auction depend also on strategies. In the full information setting we prove a bound the click-through rates associated with the bidders, the of 1.618 for the price of anarchy for pure Nash equilibria, probability that the advertisement will get clicked on by and a bound of 4 for mixed Nash equilibria.
    [Show full text]
  • Extensive Form Games with Perfect Information
    Notes Strategy and Politics: Extensive Form Games with Perfect Information Matt Golder Pennsylvania State University Sequential Decision-Making Notes The model of a strategic (normal form) game suppresses the sequential structure of decision-making. When applying the model to situations in which players move sequentially, we assume that each player chooses her plan of action once and for all. She is committed to this plan, which she cannot modify as events unfold. The model of an extensive form game, by contrast, describes the sequential structure of decision-making explicitly, allowing us to study situations in which each player is free to change her mind as events unfold. Perfect Information Notes Perfect information describes a situation in which players are always fully informed about all of the previous actions taken by all players. This assumption is used in all of the following lecture notes that use \perfect information" in the title. Later we will also study more general cases where players may only be imperfectly informed about previous actions when choosing an action. Extensive Form Games Notes To describe an extensive form game with perfect information we need to specify the set of players and their preferences, just as for a strategic game. In addition, we also need to specify the order of the players' moves and the actions each player may take at each point (or decision node). We do so by specifying the set of all sequences of actions that can possibly occur, together with the player who moves at each point in each sequence. We refer to each possible sequence of actions (a1; a2; : : : ak) as a terminal history and to the function that denotes the player who moves at each point in each terminal history as the player function.
    [Show full text]
  • Repeated Games
    Repeated games Felix Munoz-Garcia Strategy and Game Theory - Washington State University Repeated games are very usual in real life: 1 Treasury bill auctions (some of them are organized monthly, but some are even weekly), 2 Cournot competition is repeated over time by the same group of firms (firms simultaneously and independently decide how much to produce in every period). 3 OPEC cartel is also repeated over time. In addition, players’ interaction in a repeated game can help us rationalize cooperation... in settings where such cooperation could not be sustained should players interact only once. We will therefore show that, when the game is repeated, we can sustain: 1 Players’ cooperation in the Prisoner’s Dilemma game, 2 Firms’ collusion: 1 Setting high prices in the Bertrand game, or 2 Reducing individual production in the Cournot game. 3 But let’s start with a more "unusual" example in which cooperation also emerged: Trench warfare in World War I. Harrington, Ch. 13 −! Trench warfare in World War I Trench warfare in World War I Despite all the killing during that war, peace would occasionally flare up as the soldiers in opposing tenches would achieve a truce. Examples: The hour of 8:00-9:00am was regarded as consecrated to "private business," No shooting during meals, No firing artillery at the enemy’s supply lines. One account in Harrington: After some shooting a German soldier shouted out "We are very sorry about that; we hope no one was hurt. It is not our fault, it is that dammed Prussian artillery" But... how was that cooperation achieved? Trench warfare in World War I We can assume that each soldier values killing the enemy, but places a greater value on not getting killed.
    [Show full text]