Roderick M. Chisholm Profiles

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Roderick M. Chisholm Profiles RODERICK M. CHISHOLM PROFILES AN INTERNATIONAL SERIES ON CONTEMPORARY PHILOSOPHERS AND LOGICIANS EDITORS RADU J. BOGDAN, Tulane University ILKKA NIINILUOTO, University 0/ Helsinki EDITORIAL BOARD D. F0LLESDAL, University o/Oslo S. KÖRNER, University 0/ Bristol J. J. C. SMART, Australian National University W. STEGMÜllER, Universität München P. SUPPES, Stanjord University K. SZANIAWAKI, University oj Warsaw J. VUILLEMIN, College de France VOLUME 7 RODERICK M. CHISHOLM Edited by RA DU J. BOG DAN Tulane University SPRINGER-SCIENCE+BUSINESS... MEDIA, B.V . library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Roderick M. Chisholm. (Profiles: an international se ries on contemporary philosophers and logicians ; v. 7) Bibliography: p. Includes index. 1. Chisholm. Roderick M. I. Bogdan, Radu 1. 11. Series: Profiles (Dordrecht, Netherlands) ; v. 7. B945.C464R63 1986 191 86-3851 ISBN 978-90-481-8422-4 ISBN 978-94-017-2919-2 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-017-2919-2 All Rights Reserved © 1986 by Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht Originaily published by D. Reidel Publishing Company in 1986 Softcover reprint ofthe hardcover 1st edition 1986 No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording or by any information storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner. T ABLE OF CONTENTS EDITORIAL INTRODUCTION Vll PREFACE IX Part One RODERICK M. CHISHOLM - Self-Profile 3 A. My Philosophical Education 3 B. Thought and Reference 13 C. Ontology Intentionally Considered 24 D. Knowing 37 E. Ethics and the Normative Element 49 F. Action 56 G. Bodies 65 H. Persons 71 Part Two STEVEN E. BOER - Chisholm on Intentionality, Thought, and Reference 81 PANAYOT BUTCHVAROV - States of Affairs 113 RADU J. BOG DAN - The Objects of Perception 135 KEITH LEHRER and KEITH QUILLEN - Chisholm on Certainty 157 DOUGLAS N. WAL TON - Chisholm's Theory of Action 169 RODERICK M. CHISHOLM - Replies 195 TABLE OF CONTENTS Part Three BIBLIOGRAPHY OF RODERICK CHISHOLM 219 INDEX OF NAMES 235 INDEX OF SUBJECTS 237 vi EDITORIAL INTRODUCTION The aim of this series is to inform both professional philosophers and a larger readership (of social and natural scientists, methodologists, mathematicians, students, teachers, publishers, etc.) about what is going on, who's who, and who does what in contemporary philosophy and logic. PROFILES is designed to present the research activity and the results of already outstanding personalities and schools and of newly emerging ones in the various fields of philosophy and logic. There are many Festschrift volumes dedicated to various philosophers. There is the celebrated Library oj Living Phi/osophers edited by P. A. Schilpp whose format influenced the present enterprise. Still they can only cover very little of the contemporary philosophical scene. Faced with a tremendous expansion of philosophical information and with an almost frightening division of labor and increasing specialization we need systematic and regular ways of keeping track of wh at happens in the profession. PRO­ FILES is intended to perform such a function. Each volume is devoted to one or several philosophers whose views and results are presented and discussed. The profiled philosopher(s) will summarize and review his (their) own work in the main fields of signifi­ cant contribution. This work will be discussed and evaluated by invited contributors. Relevant historical and/or biographical data, an up-to­ date bibliography with short abstracts of the most important works and, whenever possible, references to significant reviews and discussions will also be included. Since rigorous argumentation and a rational approach to philosophical problems are among the most worthwhile trends in con­ temporary philosophical thought, PROFILES will give priority to surveys vii EDITORIAL INTRODUCTION of the work of authors and schools of thought that meet these standards. However, this preference allows for a broad spectrum of philosophical and methodological viewpoints. As a vehicle of information about, and systematization of, contemporary philosophical and logical knowledge, PROFILES will strive to report on any major contribution to that body of knowledge, be it personal or collective. PROFILES will also re port on research and new projects that, although still esoteric and even tentative, may be expected to become seminal and influential in some field of philosophicalor logical studies. The sooner the information about such new ventures is disseminated and systematized, the greater will be its im­ pact on undergraduate and graduate students, researchers, teachers on all levels, editors, publishers, university and foundation managers, etc. The editors will welcome information on personal and collective research in progress, Ph.D. theses, surveys and monographs dealing with individual philosophers and schools of thought working in contem­ porary philosophy and logic. RA DU J. BOG DAN ILKKA NIINILUOTO Tulane University University oj Helsinki viii PREFACE With legendary rigor, ca re and detail, Roderick Chisholm's systematic program of philosophical analysis has been directed at many philosophical areas and problems. There is no way a single volume can do justice to the scope and depth of Chisholm's work. This volume is no exception. But it attempts to give the reader a fair sampie of Chisholm's remarkable output and of the critical reactions to it. The volume opens with Chisholm's Self-Profile, followed by five essays on distinct areas ofChisholm's work: intentionality, thought and reference (Steven Boer), ontology and states of affairs (Panayot Butch­ varov), the objects of perception (Radu J. Bogdan), knowledge and cer­ tainty (Keith Lehrer and Keith Quillen), and action (Douglas N. Walton). Chisholm's replies to these essays and a bibliography of his works, with the author's abstracts, conclude the volume. My warmest thanks to Roderick Chisholm and each of the con­ tributors for bringing this project to life. July 1985 RADU J. BOG DAN ix .
Recommended publications
  • Substance and the Concept of Personal Identity
    AN OPEN ACCESS Ergo JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY Substance and the Concept of Personal Identity JenS KIPPer University of Cologne In this paper, I identify and discuss the following feature of our judgments about hypothetical scenarios concerning the identity of persons: with respect to the vast majority of scenarios, both members of a pair of logically complementary proposi- tions about personal identity are conceivable. I consider a number of explanations of this feature that draw on the metaphysics and the epistemology of personal identity, none of which prove to be satisfactory. I then argue that in order to give an adequate explanation, one needs to recognize an important characteristic of our concept of personal identity: it is such that if there are mental substances (or the like), they constitute personal identity. At the same time, there can still be persons if there are no such substances. Since this finding casts doubts on the way that thought experi- ments about personal identity are usually set up, I end by outlining its potential consequences for the debate over the identity of persons. 1. Introduction The debate over the nature of personal identity is as replete with thought experi- ments as many other philosophical debates. But there is a nagging suspicion that thought experiments work differently when the identity of persons is concerned. For example, it is natural to think that our judgment that the person in Harry Frankfurt’s (1969) famous case is responsible for what he did is based on our conceptual competence. When John Locke argues, however, that the person in the body of a cobbler who has the memories of a prince is that prince (1694/1975: 340), he does not seem to be stating a conceptual truth.
    [Show full text]
  • A Critique of Roderick Chisholm
    DOI: https://doi.org/10.26512/rfmc.v8i2.35865 Intentionality and the Logico-Linguistic Commitment: A Critique of Roderick Chisholm [Intencionalidade e Compromisso Lógico-Linguístico: Uma crítica a Roderick Chisholm] Luis Niel* Abstract: The aim of this article is to analyze and criticize Roderick Chisholm’s con- ception of intentionality, which has, historically, served as the point of departure for most accounts of intentionality in analytic philosophy. My goal is to highlight the problematic ’logico-linguistic commitment’ presupposed by Chisholm, according to which mental concepts should be interpreted by means of semantic concepts. After addressing Chisholm’s differentiation between the ontological thesis (the idea that the intentional object might not exist) and the psychological thesis (the conception that only mental phenomena are intentional), as well as his defining criteria for intentionality (non-existential implication, independency of truth-value, and indirect reference), I fo- cus on the manifold problems presented by his theory. First, the two initial criteria entail a conceptual confusion between the semantic concept of ’intensionality’ and the mental concept of ’intentionality’. Second, according to these criteria-and against Chisholm’s explicit intention-perception and other cognitive activities should not be considered intentional. Third, there are no grounds for the artificial conflation of intentionality and the concept of ’propositional attitudes’-an equation which is an explicit tenet of the logico-linguistic commitment. In general, I argue that an interpretation of intentionality based on this commitment obscures the true meaning of the concept of intentionality, as it is presented, for instance, by phenomenology. Keywords: Chisholm. Intentionality. Intensionality. Propositional Attitudes. Logico- linguistic Commitment.
    [Show full text]
  • Essence, Plenitude, and Paradox
    PHILOSOPHICAL PERSPECTIVES Philosophical Perspectives, 25, Metaphysics, 2011 ESSENCE, PLENITUDE, AND PARADOX Sarah-Jane Leslie Princeton University Essentialism in philosophy is the view that there are in principle two ways of having properties and including parts: the essential way and the accidental way (e.g, Fine, 1994, 1995; Johnston 1984, 2006; Kripke, 1980; Salmon 1986, 2005; Yablo 1987). As I understand the view, even an extreme essentialist — who takes every property and every part to be had essentially — should agree with the in-principle distinction while arguing that certain metaphysical considerations mean that the second way of having properties is not, and cannot be, exemplified. Such a view would contrast with the view of an anti-essentialist like Willard van Orman Quine who repudiates the very distinction between the two ways of having properties. Quine’s view is not that all properties are accidental, for that would be to use what he calls the “invidious distinction” (1953), rather than repudiate it. His view is that there is not even in principle these two ways of having properties (or satisfying predicates, as he would put it), about which we can ask “Which of these two ways do things have properties?” What then ostensibly distinguishes the essential way of having properties from the accidental way? An object’s essential properties are conditions on what it is to be that object, and this set of conditions fixes just which possibilities or possible worlds the object exists in, namely just those in which it satisfies those conditions. An object’s essential properties also fix how long it exists, namely only at those times at which it satisfies those conditions.
    [Show full text]
  • INTENTIONALITY Past and Future VIBS
    INTENTIONALITY Past and Future VIBS Volume 173 Robert Ginsberg Founding Editor Peter A. Redpath Executive Editor Associate Editors G. John M. Abbarno Matti Häyry Mary-Rose Barral Steven V. Hicks Gerhold K. Becker Richard T. Hull Raymond Angelo Belliotti Mark Letteri Kenneth A. Bryson Vincent L. Luizzi C. Stephen Byrum Alan Milchman H. G. Callaway George David Miller Robert A. Delfino Alan Rosenberg Rem B. Edwards Arleen L. F. Salles Andrew Fitz-Gibbon John R. Shook Francesc Forn i Argimon Eddy Souffrant William Gay Tuija Takala Dane R. Gordon Anne Waters J. Everet Green John R. Welch Heta Aleksandra Gylling Thomas F. Woods a volume in Cognitive Science CS Francesc Forn i Argimon, Editor INTENTIONALITY Past and Future Edited by Gábor Forrai and George Kampis Amsterdam - New York, NY 2005 Cover Design: Studio Pollmann The paper on which this book is printed meets the requirements of “ISO 9706:1994, Information and documentation - Paper for documents - Requirements for permanence”. ISBN: 90-420-1817-8 ©Editions Rodopi B.V., Amsterdam - New York, NY 2005 Printed in the Netherlands CONTENTS Preface vii List of Abbreviations ix ONE The Necessity and Nature of Mental Content 1 LAIRD ADDIS TWO Reading Brentano on the Intentionality of the Mental 15 PHILIP J. BARTOK THREE Emotions, Moods, and Intentionality 25 WILLIAM FISH FOUR Lockean Ideas as Intentional Contents 37 GÁBOR FORRAI FIVE Normativity and Mental Content 51 JUSSI HAUKIOJA SIX The Ontological and Intentional Status of Fregean Senses: An Early Account of External Content 63 GREG JESSON
    [Show full text]
  • Jeff Buechner.POMSIGMAA 2017 Invited Address
    Computers, mathematical proof, and the nature of the human mind POMSIGMAA Keynote Address Philosophy of Mathematics American Mathematical Society and Mathematical Association of America Joint Meetings Jeff Buechner Rutgers University-Newark and The Saul Kripke Center, CUNY, The Graduate Center January 6th, 2017 1 1976 Appel and Haken prove the four- color theorem • June 21, 1976 Wolfgang Haken and Kenneth Appel, with the aid of John Koch, completed their proof of the Four-Color Theorem (4CT). (Haken turned 48 years old on that day.) • Their proof was published in 1977: “Every planar map is four colorable,” Parts 1 and II, and Supplements I and II, Illinois Journal of Mathematics, XXI, 84, September 1977 2 1976 Appel and Haken prove the four- color theorem • At one place in the proof of the 4CT, Appel and Haken need to find a finite list of reducible configurations with the property that every graph contains at least one configuration in the list. To do this, a lemma must be proved: that every configuration in an unavoidable set is reducible. A computer is needed to prove that all of the configurations are reducible. For instance, to show that one kind of configuration in the set is reducible requires 1,000,000 steps. 3 1976 Appel and Haken prove the four- color theorem • Although computers had already been used to prove theorems in mathematics before the Appel-Haken proof, the importance of the 4CT brought the use of a computer in proving it to the forefront of attention of mathematicians, as well as a lay public.
    [Show full text]
  • Neurath's Boat, Theseus' Ship and Chisholm's Nonintactly Persisting Universe ABSTRACT
    1 Neurath’s Boat, Theseus’ Ship and Chisholm’s Nonintactly Persisting Universe ABSTRACT: Neurath’s famous boat metaphor paints a picture of a coherentist system of knowledge where every statement (protocol or otherwise) is always open to revision. However, his total rejection of correspondence theory, I argue, raises questions about what “statements” actually are, since they can no longer be defined with reference to an external world. I believe that, if Neurath’s coherentism is taken seriously, statements must be ontological entities that make up a universe that is a nonintactly persisting object, in Roderick Chisolm’s sense. I explain this concept with recourse to the classic metaphysical riddle of the ship of Theseus. Otto Neurath famously compared our experience of the world to our being on a ship at sea that never reaches land. Instead, we have to constantly make repairs on the open water. His point was that we don’t have the benefit of being able to stop and check our theories of the world from a detached perspective. There are no absolute, indubitable certainties to which our theories must conform. We must be prepared to revise anything and everything as necessary, in order to maintain the coherence of our world system—to stay afloat: “We are like sailors who must rebuild their ship on the open sea, never able to dismantle it in dry-dock and to reconstruct it there out of the best materials” (Neurath 1932/33, 201). Neurath’s metaphor is reminiscent of the ancient metaphysical riddle of Theseus’ ship: if the parts of a ship are slowly replaced over time, until the ship has none of its original parts, would it still be the same ship? In what follows, I use Roderick Chisholm’s language to suggest that, if Neurath’s metaphor is accurate, our world is a nonintactly persisting object, dropping and gaining parts over time according to the pragmatic needs of coherence.
    [Show full text]
  • The Oberlin Colloquium in Philosophy: Program History
    The Oberlin Colloquium in Philosophy: Program History 1960 FIRST COLLOQUIUM Wilfrid Sellars, "On Looking at Something and Seeing it" Ronald Hepburn, "God and Ambiguity" Comments: Dennis O'Brien Kurt Baier, "Itching and Scratching" Comments: David Falk/Bruce Aune Annette Baier, "Motives" Comments: Jerome Schneewind 1961 SECOND COLLOQUIUM W.D. Falk, "Hegel, Hare and the Existential Malady" Richard Cartwright, "Propositions" Comments: Ruth Barcan Marcus D.A.T. Casking, "Avowals" Comments: Martin Lean Zeno Vendler, "Consequences, Effects and Results" Comments: William Dray/Sylvan Bromberger PUBLISHED: Analytical Philosophy, First Series, R.J. Butler (ed.), Oxford, Blackwell's, 1962. 1962 THIRD COLLOQUIUM C.J. Warnock, "Truth" Arthur Prior, "Some Exercises in Epistemic Logic" Newton Garver, "Criteria" Comments: Carl Ginet/Paul Ziff Hector-Neri Castenada, "The Private Language Argument" Comments: Vere Chappell/James Thomson John Searle, "Meaning and Speech Acts" Comments: Paul Benacerraf/Zeno Vendler PUBLISHED: Knowledge and Experience, C.D. Rollins (ed.), University of Pittsburgh Press, 1964. 1963 FOURTH COLLOQUIUM Michael Scriven, "Insanity" Frederick Will, "The Preferability of Probable Beliefs" Norman Malcolm, "Criteria" Comments: Peter Geach/George Pitcher Terrence Penelhum, "Pleasure and Falsity" Comments: William Kennick/Arnold Isenberg 1964 FIFTH COLLOQUIUM Stephen Korner, "Some Remarks on Deductivism" J.J.C. Smart, "Nonsense" Joel Feinberg, "Causing Voluntary Actions" Comments: Keith Donnellan/Keith Lehrer Nicholas Rescher, "Evaluative Metaphysics" Comments: Lewis W. Beck/Thomas E. Patton Herbert Hochberg, "Qualities" Comments: Richard Severens/J.M. Shorter PUBLISHED: Metaphysics and Explanation, W.H. Capitan and D.D. Merrill (eds.), University of Pittsburgh Press, 1966. 1965 SIXTH COLLOQUIUM Patrick Nowell-Smith, "Acts and Locutions" George Nakhnikian, "St. Anselm's Four Ontological Arguments" Hilary Putnam, "Psychological Predicates" Comments: Bruce Aune/U.T.
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphysics (Core Seminar)
    Metaphysics (Core Seminar) Christian W¨uthrich Phil 205A, Winter 2013 Class schedule: Tu 2:00-4:50pm, HSS 7077 (Philosophy seminar room) Website: http://philosophy.ucsd.edu/faculty/wuthrich/ Christian W¨uthrich: Office hours are Th 2-4, and by appointment Room 8047 HSS T 858-534-6548 B [email protected] Metaphysics, it has been claimed, is the study of the most fundamental aspects of the struc- ture of reality, and in this sense precedes empirical science. So what is metaphysics, and how does it relate to science? Before we conclude the course by considering its relation to science, we will discuss many questions that can be thought to delineate metaphysics. The topics to be covered (although there is some flexibility about this) include existence, identity and change, universals and particulars, modality, causation, space, time and persistence, freedom and determinism, and metaphysics and science. This class will engage these topics with an emphasis on contemporary views and debates. Accordingly, our approach will be topic-oriented, rather than historical. Prerequisites: Graduate standing or permission of the instructor. Distribution requirements: This course can be counted towards the fulfillment of the distri- bution requirement in metaphysics. Required texts All mandatory (and perhaps some recommended) readings will be made available through e-reserves or online. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (http://plato.stanford.edu/) has many excellent background and survey papers. Go to the course web page for links. Course requirements and evaluation The following are necessary and jointly sufficient conditions to obtain letter grade credit for this seminar: 1. Participation: You are expected to attend all classes and to actively participate in discussions.
    [Show full text]
  • The Problem of the Criterion1
    The Problem of the Criterion1 Introduction: The problem of the criterion in epistemology raises certain fundamental questions concerning the methods a philosopher ought to use in arriving at both analyses of epistemic concepts and conclusions concerning legitimate principles of reasoning and justification. The answers one gives to these questions are thought to bear directly on the challenge of skepticism. The outcome of battles is often determined by the ground occupied by opposing forces. Interest in the problem of the criterion is often a function of the desire to occupy favorable ground in the battle with the skeptic. Despite the title of this paper, there are, I believe, at least two different problems one might associate with “the criterion.” One is, perhaps, best known through the work of Roderick Chisholm, whose various editions of Theory of Knowledge all devote a chapter to it. As Chisholm develops the problem, it concerns methodological questions concerning how to identify sources of knowledge or justified belief. But there is a closely related question concerning how to identify necessary and sufficient conditions for the application of epistemic concepts like knowledge and justified belief. In the following discussion I’ll distinguish these two methodological issues, and I’ll begin by looking at the question of how one should go about discovering the correct analysis of epistemic concepts. Metaepistemology and the Problem of the Criterion: Metaepistemological questions seek to uncover through philosophical analysis the nature of fundamental epistemic concepts or properties. In metaepistemology, we are interested in getting an account of what knowledge, evidence, justified belief, and so on are.
    [Show full text]
  • Showing and Self-Presentation of Experiences – Some Philosophical Cases
    Showing and Self-Presentation of Experiences – Some Philosophical Cases Johann Christian Marek, Graz Experiences Experiences (Erlebnisse in German) are of phenomenal character. There is something it is like to be in a conscious mental state; there is something it feels like to be in pain, and there is something different it feels like to be glad. Some experiences are purely phenomenal – pains and moods, for instance –, and some are intentional, i.e. directed to something – for example, you are glad about your good company or you are glad to get home. Intentional states such as being glad about someone (or worshipping something) are purely objectual, whereas intentional states such as being glad to get somewhere (or believing that something is the case) are propositional. You can distinguish between the mode and content of intentional experiences. When you entertain the belief that it is raining, believing is the mode and that it is raining is its content. When you hate that it is rain- ing the content stays the same but the mode has changed into an emotional experience. It is controversial which mental phenomena count as experiences, especially whether there is the experience of the mode on the one hand and the experience of the content on the other hand. Ludwig Wittgenstein, for example, was always skeptical about both of these accounts. He questioned the view that there is an experience of meaning as well as the view that willing, understanding and conviction respectively would be experiences. Although Wittgenstein objected to the idea of the experiential reality of mental acts and contents, he did not fully deny the existence of experiences.
    [Show full text]
  • Hegel's Solution to the Pyrrhonian Dilemma of the Criterion
    CHAPTER 10 Hegel’s Solution to the Pyrrhonian Dilemma of the Criterion 60 INTRODUCTION. Rather recently, problems about epistemic circularity, and more recently, Sextus Empiricus’ ‘Dilemma of the Criterion’ have been receiving thoughtful attention from contemporary epistemologists. Epistemic circularity is in- volved in using a source of belief in the process of assessing or justifying that source of belief; the Dilemma of the Criterion (quoted below, §61) concerns establishing basic criteria of justification in highly disputed domains. Because there are diverse and controversial views on this issue, how can basic criteria of justification be established without infinite regress, vicious circularity, or petitio principii? These problems deserve careful attention; I don’t believe contemporary epistemologists have fully realised how sophisticated a re- sponse Pyrrhonian skepticism requires.1 Roderick Chisholm (1982, 65–6) contends that there are three kinds of response to what he calls the ‘Problem’ of the Criterion’: Particularists believe they have various particular instances of knowledge, on the basis of which they can construct a general account of the nature and criteria of knowledge. Methodists believe they know the nature and criteria of knowledge, and on that basis can distinguish genuine from illegitimate particular instances of knowledge. Skeptics believe that no particular cases of knowledge can be identified without knowing the nature or criteria of knowledge, and that the nature or criteria of knowledge cannot be known without identifying particu- lar cases of genuine knowledge. Chisholm (1982, 75, cf. 67) favours particular- ism, but thinks that any attempt to solve the problem must beg the question.2 1 The main points of Pyrrhonian scepticism are summarised in HER, 11–6.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction
    Introduction Smiles, talks, runs, arrivals and departures, births and deaths, thunder and lightning: the va- riety of the world seems to lie not only in the assortment of its ordinary and less ordinary inhabitants—animals and physical objects, or perhaps minds, sets, atoms—but also in the sort of things that happen to or are performed by them. In the last three decades this view has been a focus of considerable debate in philosophy, with implications reaching far into the concern of other disciplines as well (above all linguistics and cognitive science). It is a view that many authors have accepted, mostly on account of the prominent role played by the concept of event in the formulation and analysis of a wide variety of philosophical is- sues. However, there has not been much agreement as to the precise nature of such entities, and a range of alternative theories (along with a corresponding variety of identity and indi- viduation criteria for events) have been put forward. This volume brings together a selection of essays that have deeply influenced this debate, paving the way to an understanding of the role played by events in our representation of the world. The material is organized in five sections: (i) the role of events in the logical analysis of natural language; (ii) the metaphysical status of events; (iii) their identity and individua- tion criteria; (iv) their role in the analysis of space, time and causality; and (v) the distinction and classification of various types of events and event-like entities (such as processes and states).
    [Show full text]