Path Integrals and Parastatistics Alexios P. Polychronakosy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Path Integrals and Parastatistics Alexios P. Polychronakosy View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by CERN Document Server SHS-96-4 UUITP-08/96 25 March 1996 Path Integrals and Parastatistics y Alexios P. Polychronakos Centre for Advanced Study, Norwegian Academy of Science and Letters, 0205 Oslo, Norway and Theoretical Physics Dept., Uppsala University S-751 08 Uppsala, Sweden ABSTRACT The propagator and corresp onding path integral for a system of identical par- ticles ob eying parastatistics are derived. It is found that the statistical weights of top ological sectors of the path integral for parafermions and parab osons are sim- ply related through multiplication by the parity of the p ermutation of the nal p ositions of the particles. Appropriate generalizations of statistics are prop osed ob eying unitarity and factorizability (strong cluster decomp osition). The realiza- tion of simple maximal o ccupancy (Gentile) statistics is shown to require ghost states. y p [email protected] Permanent address Generalizations of the standard concepts of fermions and b osons have b een extensively considered in the last few decades. These can b e broadly divided into \phenomenological" (anyons [1-4], exclusion statistics [5]), which are meanttogive a b etter description or understanding of systems of otherwise ordinary fermions or b osons, and \fundamental," whichwould b e genuinely new kinds of particles. A nice review of these approaches can b e found in [6], and a short and concise resume of some relevant results can b e found in [7]. The rst ever consistent extension of fundamental statistics, given by Green [8], is parastatistics. In that, the standard b osonic or fermionic elds whichwould create identical particles are replaced by comp osite elds whose comp onents com- mute with themselves and anticommute with each other for parab osons, or vice versa for parafermions. The numb er of comp onents of the elds p de nes the \or- der" of parastatistics. In general, one can put at most p parafermions in a totally symmetric wavefunction, and at most p parab osons in a totally antisymmetric one. The degeneracies of o ccupation of more general multiparticle states are in princi- ple calculable but rather complicated. Parastatistics in this approach has b een well-studied [9-12]. The ab ove is a eld theoretic realization of parastatistics. Just as in the case of fermions or b osons, one can deal with a parastatistical system at a xed particle numb er in a rst-quantized formalism. In this approach, due mainly to Messiah and Greenb erg [13,14], the N -b o dy Hilb ert space is decomp osed into irreducible representations (irreps) of the particle p ermutation group S . Since the particles N are indistinguish abl e, this group should b e viewed as a \gauge" symmetry of the system, and states transforming in the same representation have to b e identi ed. Moreover, since all physical op erators are required to commute with the p ermuta- tion group, each irreducible comp onent is a sup erselection sector. Therefore, one can pro ject the Hilb ert space to only some of the irreps of S .Further, only one N state in each irrep need b e kept as a representative of the multiplet of physically equivalent states. The resulting reduced space constitutes a consistent quantiza- tion of N indistingui shabl e particles. The choice of included irreps constitutes a 2 choice of quantum statistics. In particular, parab osons corresp ond to including only irreps with up to p rows in their Young tableau, while parafermions to ones with up to p columns. Clearly the cases p = 1 reduce to ordinary fermions and b osons. This description relies on a canonical quantization of the many-b o dy system. It is of interest to also have a path-integral formulation of a quantum system, since this complements and completes the conceptual framework and usually o ers orthogonal intuition in several cases. For ordinary statistics this question was studied by Laidlaw and DeWitt [15]. In this pap er, we provide such a realization for parastatistics, or, in general, for any statistics where the Hilb ert space is emb edded in the tensor pro duct of N one-particle Hilb ert spaces (note that this excludes anyons and braid statistics). The starting p oint will b e the co ordinate representation of the full (unpro- jected) Hilb ert space, spanned by the p osition eigenstates jx ;:::x >jx> 1 N (where x can b e in a space of any dimension). The collection of such states for a i set of distinct x transforms in the N !-dimensional de ning representation of S i N P jx>jPx >= jx 1 ;:::x 1 > (1) P (1) P (N) 1 where P is a p ermutation (the app earance of P in the ab ove is necessary so that pro ducts of p ermutations b e represented in the right order). If anyofthe co ordinates x coincide the ab ove is not the full de ning representation any more. i The set of such states, however, is of measure zero (the co ordinate space assumed continuous) and thus they can b e safely ignored. (We assume that there are no interactions singular at coincidence p oints that might dynamically make such states of nonzero weight.) Pro jecting the Hilb ert space to an irrep R of S amounts to keeping only linear N combinations of states within this multiplet transforming in R, that is, X ja; x>= C (P)Pjx> ; a=1;:::d ; d = dim(R): (2) a R R P 3 where the sum is over all elements of the p ermutation group and C (P ) are appro- a priately chosen co ecients. If we denote with R (P ) the matrix elements of the ab p ermutation P in the representations R, X 1 P ja; x >= R (P )jb; x > (3) ab b The de ning representation decomp oses into irreducible comp onents, classi ed by Young tableaux, each app earing with a certain multiplicity. Should wekeep only one irrep out of eachmultiplicity or the whole multiplet? To decide it, note that if instead of the base state jx>for the construction of the states ja; x > we cho ose a di erent p ermutation P jx>, then although the new states ja; P x> o o constructed through (2) still transform in the irrep R, in general they are not linear combinations of ja; x > but rather span a di erent copyof R. Since we can continuously move in the con guration space from jx> to P jx>,we conclude o that wemust keep al l irreps R within eachmultiplet. (In other words, although for each p oint in the Hilb ert space jx> this multiplet is reducible, the b er of these representations over the Hilb ert space is connected and irreducible.) To realize explicitly the ab ove, we construct the states r X d R jab; x >= R (P )P jx> (4) ab N ! P Using the group prop erty of the representation R(P )R(P )=R(P P ), we deduce 1 2 1 2 that under the action of the group S and under change of base p oint x the ab ove N states transform as: X X 1 1 P jab; x >= R (P )jcb; x > ; jab; P x >= R (P )jac; x > (5) ac cb c c Thus we see that the rst index in these states lab els the di erent elements of a single irrep R, while the second index lab els the di erent equivalent irreps in the 4 multiplet. Since b oth indices take d values, we recover the standard result that R each irrep of S is emb edded in the de ning representation a numb er of times N equal to its dimension. Consider now the matrix element < ab; xjAjcd; y >, where A is anyphysical op erator, that is, any op erator commuting with all elements P of S . Substituting N y 1 (P )= the de nition (4) and using the unitarityofP (P =P ) and of R (R ab 1 R (P )) we obtain, after a change in summation variable, ba X d R 0 1 0 < ab; xjAjcd; y >= R (P )R (P )R (P ) <xjAP jy> (6) ea be cd N ! 0 P;P ;e Using further the orthogonality (Shur's) relation (see, e.g., [16]) X N! 1 R (P )R (P )= (7) ab cd ad bc d R P we nally obtain X < ab; xjAjcd; y >= R (P ) <xjAjPy > (8) ac bd P Let us rst cho ose A = 1. Then the ab ove provides the overlap b etween the states X < ab; xjcd; y >= R (P ) (x Py) (9) ac bd P For x in the neighb orho o d of y it is P = 1 which contributes to the normalization, for which R (1) = and we recover the standard continuous normalization bd bd between the states. iH t Nowwe can cho ose A = e , where H is the hamiltonian, and thus nd the propagator G(ab; x; cd; y jt)between the states of the system. It is clear from (8) that the rst index a in the state jab; x > propagates trivially. Since this is the index that corresp onds to the di erent but physically equivalent states within each irrep 5 R,we conclude that the required pro jection of the Hilb ert space to the physical subspace amounts to simply omitting this index from all states. (That is, freeze this index to the same xed value for all states of the theory; no physical quantity will ever dep end on the choice of this value.) On the other hand, the second index, corresp onding to di erent equivalent irreps, do es not propagate trivially and must, as argued b efore, b e kept.
Recommended publications
  • Probability and Statistics, Parastatistics, Boson, Fermion, Parafermion, Hausdorff Dimension, Percolation, Clusters
    Applied Mathematics 2018, 8(1): 5-8 DOI: 10.5923/j.am.20180801.02 Why Fermions and Bosons are Observable as Single Particles while Quarks are not? Sencer Taneri Private Researcher, Turkey Abstract Bosons and Fermions are observable in nature while Quarks appear only in triplets for matter particles. We find a theoretical proof for this statement in this paper by investigating 2-dim model. The occupation numbers q are calculated by a power law dependence of occupation probability and utilizing Hausdorff dimension for the infinitely small mesh in the phase space. The occupation number for Quarks are manipulated and found to be equal to approximately three as they are Parafermions. Keywords Probability and Statistics, Parastatistics, Boson, Fermion, Parafermion, Hausdorff dimension, Percolation, Clusters There may be particles that obey some kind of statistics, 1. Introduction generally called parastatistics. The Parastatistics proposed in 1952 by H. Green was deduced using a quantum field The essential difference in classical and quantum theory (QFT) [2, 3]. Whenever we discover a new particle, descriptions of N identical particles is in their individuality, it is almost certain that we attribute its behavior to the rather than in their indistinguishability [1]. Spin of the property that it obeys some form of parastatistics and the particle is one of its intrinsic physical quantity that is unique maximum occupation number q of a given quantum state to its individuality. The basis for how the quantum states for would be a finite number that could assume any integer N identical particles will be occupied may be taken as value as 1<q <∞ (see Table 1).
    [Show full text]
  • Physics Abstracts CLASSIFICATION and CONTENTS (PACC)
    Physics Abstracts CLASSIFICATION AND CONTENTS (PACC) 0000 general 0100 communication, education, history, and philosophy 0110 announcements, news, and organizational activities 0110C announcements, news, and awards 0110F conferences, lectures, and institutes 0110H physics organizational activities 0130 physics literature and publications 0130B publications of lectures(advanced institutes, summer schools, etc.) 0130C conference proceedings 0130E monographs, and collections 0130K handbooks and dictionaries 0130L collections of physical data, tables 0130N textbooks 0130Q reports, dissertations, theses 0130R reviews and tutorial papers;resource letters 0130T bibliographies 0140 education 0140D course design and evaluation 0140E science in elementary and secondary school 0140G curricula, teaching methods,strategies, and evaluation 0140J teacher training 0150 educational aids(inc. equipment,experiments and teaching approaches to subjects) 0150F audio and visual aids, films 0150H instructional computer use 0150K testing theory and techniques 0150M demonstration experiments and apparatus 0150P laboratory experiments and apparatus 0150Q laboratory course design,organization, and evaluation 0150T buildings and facilities 0155 general physics 0160 biographical, historical, and personal notes 0165 history of science 0170 philosophy of science 0175 science and society 0190 other topics of general interest 0200 mathematical methods in physics 0210 algebra, set theory, and graph theory 0220 group theory(for algebraic methods in quantum mechanics, see
    [Show full text]
  • The Conventionality of Parastatistics
    The Conventionality of Parastatistics David John Baker Hans Halvorson Noel Swanson∗ March 6, 2014 Abstract Nature seems to be such that we can describe it accurately with quantum theories of bosons and fermions alone, without resort to parastatistics. This has been seen as a deep mystery: paraparticles make perfect physical sense, so why don't we see them in nature? We consider one potential answer: every paraparticle theory is physically equivalent to some theory of bosons or fermions, making the absence of paraparticles in our theories a matter of convention rather than a mysterious empirical discovery. We argue that this equivalence thesis holds in all physically admissible quantum field theories falling under the domain of the rigorous Doplicher-Haag-Roberts approach to superselection rules. Inadmissible parastatistical theories are ruled out by a locality- inspired principle we call Charge Recombination. Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 Paraparticles in Quantum Theory 6 ∗This work is fully collaborative. Authors are listed in alphabetical order. 1 3 Theoretical Equivalence 11 3.1 Field systems in AQFT . 13 3.2 Equivalence of field systems . 17 4 A Brief History of the Equivalence Thesis 20 4.1 The Green Decomposition . 20 4.2 Klein Transformations . 21 4.3 The Argument of Dr¨uhl,Haag, and Roberts . 24 4.4 The Doplicher-Roberts Reconstruction Theorem . 26 5 Sharpening the Thesis 29 6 Discussion 36 6.1 Interpretations of QM . 44 6.2 Structuralism and Haecceities . 46 6.3 Paraquark Theories . 48 1 Introduction Our most fundamental theories of matter provide a highly accurate description of subatomic particles and their behavior.
    [Show full text]
  • A Scientific Metaphysical Naturalisation of Information
    1 A Scientific Metaphysical Naturalisation of Information With a indication-based semantic theory of information and an informationist statement of physicalism. Bruce Long A thesis submitted to fulfil requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Faculty of Arts and Social Sciences The University of Sydney February 2018 2 Abstract The objective of this thesis is to present a naturalised metaphysics of information, or to naturalise information, by way of deploying a scientific metaphysics according to which contingency is privileged and a-priori conceptual analysis is excluded (or at least greatly diminished) in favour of contingent and defeasible metaphysics. The ontology of information is established according to the premises and mandate of the scientific metaphysics by inference to the best explanation, and in accordance with the idea that the primacy of physics constraint accommodates defeasibility of theorising in physics. This metaphysical approach is used to establish a field ontology as a basis for an informational structural realism. This is in turn, in combination with information theory and specifically mathematical and algorithmic theories of information, becomes the foundation of what will be called a source ontology, according to which the world is the totality of information sources. Information sources are to be understood as causally induced configurations of structure that are, or else reduce to and/or supervene upon, bounded (including distributed and non-contiguous) regions of the heterogeneous quantum field (all quantum fields combined) and fluctuating vacuum, all in accordance with the above-mentioned quantum field-ontic informational structural realism (FOSIR.) Arguments are presented for realism, physicalism, and reductionism about information on the basis of the stated contingent scientific metaphysics.
    [Show full text]
  • The Connection Between Spin and Statistics
    Sudarshan: Seven Science Quests IOP Publishing Journal of Physics: Conference Series 196 (2009) 012011 doi:10.1088/1742-6596/196/1/012011 The connection between spin and statistics Luis J. Boya Departamento de Física Teórica, Universidad de Zaragoza E - 50 009, Zaragoza, Spain E-Mail: [email protected] Abstract. After some brief historical remarks we recall the first demonstration of the Spin-Statistics theorem by Pauli, and some further developments, like Streater- Wightman’s, in the axiomatic considerations. Sudarshan’s short proof then follows by considering only the time part of the kinetic term in the lagrangian: the identity SU(2)=Sp(1,C) is crucial for the argument. Possible generalization to arbitrary dimensions are explored, and seen to depend crucially on the type of spinors, obeying Bott´s periodicity 8. In particular, it turns out that for space dimentions (7, 8, or 9) modulo 8, the conventional result does not automatically hold: there can be no Fermions in these dimensions. 1. Introduction The idea of this work came from discussions with Sudarshan in Zaragoza some years ago. George was surprised to learn that the properties of spinors crucial for the ordinary connection between spin and statistics would not hold in arbitrary dimensions, because of periodicity 8 of real Clifford algebras. After many discussions and turnarounds, I am happy today to present this collaboration, and I also apologize for the delay, for which I am mainly responsible. In any case, the priviledge to work and discuss physics with Sudarshan is a unique experience, for which I have been most fortunate.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae
    DAVID JOHN BAKER CURRICULUM VITAE Department of Philosophy [email protected] 2215 Angell Hall http://www-personal.umich.edu/~djbaker 435 S State St. Ann Arbor, MI 48109-1003 APPOINTMENTS Associate Professor of Philosophy, University of Michigan, 2014-present. Assistant Professor of Philosophy, University of Michigan, 2008-2014. EDUCATION PhD. in Philosophy, Princeton University, September 2008. Advisor: Hans Halvorson. B.S. in Philosophy (with Highest Honors) and Physics, University of Michigan, April 2003. AREAS OF SPECIALIZATION Philosophy of Physics, Philosophy of Science, Metaphysics. AREAS OF COMPETENCE Moral Philosophy, Logic, Philosophy of Religion, Epistemology. PUBLICATIONS “Does String Theory Posit Extended Simples?” Philosophers’ Imprint 16 (2016): Issue 18. “The Philosophy of Quantum Field Theory.” Oxford Handbooks Online (2016): DOI 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199935314.013.33 “The Conventionality of Parastatistics,” with Hans Halvorson and Noel Swanson. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 66 (2015): 929-976. “How is spontaneous symmetry breaking possible? Understanding Wigner’s theorem in light of unitary inequivalence,” with Hans Halvorson. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 44 (2013): 464-469. “Identity, Superselection Theory and the Statistical Properties of Quantum Fields.” Philosophy of Science 80 (2013): 262-285. “‘The Experience of Left and Right’ Meets the Physics of Left and Right.” Nous 46 (2012): 483-498. “Broken Symmetry and Spacetime.” Philosophy of Science 78 (2011): 128-148. “Symmetry and the Metaphysics of Physics.” Philosophy Compass 5 (2010): 1157-1166. “Antimatter,” with Hans Halvorson. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 61 (2010): 93-121. DAVID JOHN BAKER – CURRICULUM VITAE 2 “Against Field Interpretations of Quantum Field Theory.” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 60 (2009): 585-609.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:0805.0285V1
    Generalizations of Quantum Statistics O.W. Greenberg1 Center for Fundamental Physics Department of Physics University of Maryland College Park, MD 20742-4111, USA, Abstract We review generalizations of quantum statistics, including parabose, parafermi, and quon statistics, but not including anyon statistics, which is special to two dimensions. The general principles of quantum theory allow statistics more general than bosons or fermions. (Bose statistics and Fermi statistics are discussed in separate articles.) The restriction to Bosons or Fermions requires the symmetrization postu- late, “the states of a system containing N identical particles are necessarily either all symmetric or all antisymmetric under permutations of the N particles,” or, equiv- alently, “all states of identical particles are in one-dimensional representations of the symmetric group [1].” A.M.L. Messiah and O.W. Greenberg discussed quantum mechanics without the symmetrization postulate [2]. The spin-statistics connec- arXiv:0805.0285v1 [quant-ph] 2 May 2008 tion, that integer spin particles are bosons and odd-half-integer spin particles are fermions [3], is an independent statement. Identical particles in 2 space dimensions are a special case, “anyons.” (Anyons are discussed in a separate article.) Braid group statistics, a nonabelian analog of anyons, are also special to 2 space dimensions All observables must be symmetric in the dynamical variables associated with identical particles. Observables can not change the permutation symmetry type of the wave function; i.e. there is a superselection rule separating states in inequivalent representations of the symmetric group and when identical particles can occur in states that violate the spin-statistics connection their transitions must occur in the same representation of the symmetric group.
    [Show full text]
  • ${\Mathbb Z} 2\Times {\Mathbb Z} 2 $-Graded Parastatistics In
    Z2 ˆ Z2-graded parastatistics in multiparticle quantum Hamiltonians Francesco Toppan∗ August 27, 2020 CBPF, Rua Dr. Xavier Sigaud 150, Urca, cep 22290-180, Rio de Janeiro (RJ), Brazil. Abstract The recent surge of interest in Z2 Z2-graded invariant mechanics poses the challenge of ˆ understanding the physical consequences of a Z2 Z2-graded symmetry. In this paper it is shown that non-trivial physicsˆ can be detected in the multiparticle sector of a theory, being induced by the Z2 Z2-graded parastatistics obeyed by the particles. ˆ The toy model of the N 4 supersymmetric/ Z2 Z2-graded oscillator is used. In this set-up the one-particle energy“ levels and their degenerationsˆ are the same for both supersymmetric and Z2 Z2-graded versions. Nevertheless, in the multiparticle sector, a measurement of an observableˆ operator on suitable states can discriminate whether the system under consideration is composed by ordinary bosons/fermions or by Z2 Z2-graded ˆ particles. Therefore, Z2 Z2-graded mechanics has experimentally testable consequences. ˆ Furthermore, the Z2 Z2-grading constrains the observables to obey a superselection rule. ˆ As a technical tool, the multiparticle sector is encoded in the coproduct of a Hopf algebra defined on a Universal Enveloping Algebra of a graded Lie superalgebra with a braided tensor product. arXiv:2008.11554v1 [hep-th] 26 Aug 2020 CBPF-NF-007/20 ∗E-mail: [email protected] 1 1 Introduction This paper presents a theoretical test of the physical consequences of the Z2 Z2-graded paras- ˆ tatistics in a toy model case of a quantum Hamiltonian.
    [Show full text]
  • Generalized Field Quantization and the Pauli Principle
    объединенный ИНСТИТУТ ядерных исследований дубна Е2-90-364 А. В.Covorkov THE GENERALIZED FIELD QUANTIZATION AND THE PAULI PRINCIPLE Submitted to "Fifth International Conference on Hadroniс Mechanics and Nonpotentiai Interactions", 13-17 August,1990, USA 1990 1. Introduction. The identical particles and the second quantization Our experience teaches us that all particles, which can be imagined as point-like objects, obey either Fermi-Dirac or Bose-Einstein statistics. This law can be applied to par­ ticles really observed in our laboratories (electrons, photons, nucleons, mesons, and so on) or to only imaginary particles such as quarks and gluons which cannot be outside hadrons in principle. The reason for this Law of Nature, we may expect, lies in deep properties of the Matter such as its identity and reproduction. There is the famous Pauli theorem on the connection bet­ ween a particle spin and particle statistics: particles with integer spins obey Bose statistics and particles with half-integer spins obey Fermi statistics. However, a question arises: are there any other possibi­ lities for particle statistics besides the ordinary Fermi and Bose statistics? For example, can we have a small violation of the Pauli principle (for electrons)? - the question which has been raised recently by Ignatiev and Kuzmin again (For a previous history of this problem see a remarkable review/г/ ),. In this report 1 shall try to derive possible statistics of identical particles from their indistinguishability and to answer the question: how high is the price for a very small violation of the Pauli principle? The usual way of defining the indistinguishability of identical particles consists in the following: "we use the word identical to describe particles that can be substituted for each other under the most general possible circumstances with no change in the physical situation"'3'.
    [Show full text]
  • Appendixes Appendix I Physical Constants and Conversion Factors
    Appendixes Appendix I Physical Constants and Conversion Factors Numerical values for the constants are from B. N. Taylor, W. H. Parker, and D. N. Langenberg, Revs. Mod. Phys., 41, 375 (1969). Units are quoted in mksa (Systeme International) and in cgs. Physical Quantity Symbol Value Units (51) Units (cgs) I. Speed of light c 2.9979250 108 meters sec-I 10 10 cm sec-I 2. Electron charge e 1.6021918 10-19 C 10-20 emu 4.803250 10-10 esu 3. Planck's constant h 6.6261965 10-34 joule sec 10-27 erg sec n = h/27T 1.05459198 10-34 joule sec I 0-27 erg sec 4. Avogadro's number No 6.022169 1026 kmole-' 10 23 mole-I 5. Electron rest mass me 9.109559 10-31 kg 10-28 gm 0.5110041 MeV 6. Proton rest mass mp 1.672614 10-27 kg 10-24 gm 938.2592 MeV 7. Neutron rest mass mn 1.674920 10-27 kg 10-24 gm 939.5528 MeV 8. Faraday's constant F 9.648671 107 coul kmole-' 10 3 emu mole-I 2.892599 1014 esu mole-I 9. Gas constant R 8.31434 103 joule kmole-' K-' 10 7 erg mole-I K-I 10. Boltzmann's constant k 1.380623 10-23 joule K-I 10-16 erg K-' II. Gravitational constant G 6.6732 IO- llnewt meter2 kgm-2 10-8 dyne cm 2 gm-2 Clusters of Constants In many atomic and nuclear calculations the above constants appear in clusters, the evaluation of which can become tedious.
    [Show full text]
  • Intermediate Statistics, Parastatistics, Fractionary Statistics and Gentilionic Statistics
    Intermediate Statistics, Parastatistics, Fractionary Statistics and Gentilionic Statistics. M. Cattani (*) and J. M. F. Bassalo (**) (*) Instituto de Física da Universidade de São Paulo. C.P. 66318, CEP 05315 - 970 São Paulo, SP, Brasil. E-mail < [email protected] > (**)Fundação Minerva,R.Serzedelo Correa 347,1601-CEP 66035-400 Belém-Pará -Brasil E-mail < [email protected] > Abstract We made in this paper a brief analysis of the following statistics: Intermediate Statistics, Parastatistics, Fractionary Statistics and Gentilionic Statistics that predict the existence of particles which are different from bosons, fermions and maxwellons. We shown the fundamental hypothesis assumed in each one of the above mentioned statistics and their main predictions and compared them with experimental results. Taking into account the works done about these statistics we could say that there is a tendency to believe that real particles, that is, those that can be observed freely, can be only bosons, fermions and maxwellons and that all other particles, different from these would be quasiparticles. Up to date in 3-dim systems only bosons, fermions and maxwellons have been detected freely. Recently in 2-dim systems have been detected the quasiparticles named anyons that have fractionary charges and spins. (1)Introduction. Many works have been published about statistics that are different from the traditional bosonic, fermionic and maxwellonic. We do not intend to perform an extensive analysis about this theme but only to do a brief review of the following statistics: Intermediate , Parastatistics , Fractionary and Gentileonic. Since in these works we study systems composed by “particles” it is necessary to define what we understand by this word.
    [Show full text]
  • 2 Jul 2015 Symmetries, Symmetry Breaking, Gauge Symmetries
    Symmetries, Symmetry Breaking, Gauge Symmetries∗ F. Strocchi INFN, Sezione di Pisa, Pisa, Italy Abstract The concepts of symmetry, symmetry breaking and gauge symmetries are discussed, their operational meaning being dis- played by the observables and the (physical) states. For infinitely extended systems the states fall into physically disjoint phases characterized by their behavior at infinity or boundary condi- tions, encoded in the ground state, which provide the cause of symmetry breaking without contradicting Curie Principle. Global gauge symmetries, not seen by the observables, are nev- ertheless displayed by detectable properties of the states (su- perselected quantum numbers and parastatistics). Local gauge symmetries are not seen also by the physical states; they ap- pear only in non-positive representations of field algebras. Their role at the Lagrangian level is merely to ensure the validity on the physical states of local Gauss laws, obeyed by the currents which generate the corresponding global gauge symmetries; they are responsible for most distinctive physical properties of gauge quantum field theories. The topological invariants of a local gauge group define superselected quantum numbers, which ac- arXiv:1502.06540v2 [physics.hist-ph] 2 Jul 2015 count for the θ vacua. ∗Talk at the Triennial International Conference “New Developments in Logic and Philosophy of Science”, Rome 18-20 June, 2014 1 2 1 Introduction The concepts of symmetries, symmetry breaking and gauge symme- tries, at the basis of recent developments in theoretical physics, have given rise to discussions from a philosophical point of view.1 Critical issues are the meaning of spontaneous symmetry breaking (appearing in conflict with the Principle of Sufficient Reason) and the physical or operational meaning of gauge symmetries.
    [Show full text]