And Redemption in the Thought of Martin Heidegger and Jacques Lacan

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

And Redemption in the Thought of Martin Heidegger and Jacques Lacan University of Denver Digital Commons @ DU Electronic Theses and Dissertations Graduate Studies 1-1-2015 “Fall” and Redemption in the Thought of Martin Heidegger and Jacques Lacan Tyler Akers University of Denver Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.du.edu/etd Part of the Philosophy Commons, and the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Recommended Citation Akers, Tyler, "“Fall” and Redemption in the Thought of Martin Heidegger and Jacques Lacan" (2015). Electronic Theses and Dissertations. 1006. https://digitalcommons.du.edu/etd/1006 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate Studies at Digital Commons @ DU. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ DU. For more information, please contact [email protected],[email protected]. “Fall” and Redemption in the Thought of Martin Heidegger and Jacques Lacan __________ A Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the University of Denver and the Iliff School of Theology Joint PhD Program University of Denver __________ In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy __________ by Tyler Akers August 2015 Advisor: Carl Raschke Author: Tyler Akers Title: “Fall” and Redemption in the Thought of Martin Heidegger and Jacques Lacan Advisor: Carl Raschke Degree Date: August 2015 Abstract This dissertation examines and develops Martin Heidegger’s concept of “falling” as a significant historical-philosophical principle. Falling, however, is primarily understood as a concept of the early Heidegger, whereas I argue that Heidegger continues to rely upon it, both explicitly and implicitly, throughout his career. Falling is a description of philosophical and Western history, known as metaphysics, and the description of man’s relationship to Being. Thus, falling relates to the most significant streams in Heidegger’s later thought, too, including the truth of Being, the death of God, the gods, the overcoming of metaphysics, and meditative thinking. I then reinterpret the traditional theology of the Fall narrative from Genesis in light of falling as philosophical concept, extending Heidegger’s own “destruction” of Western metaphysics in relation to one of its grounding myths. I move on to demonstrate the significance of a falling understanding in a rereading of the death of God and the end of metaphysics by examining Heidegger’s engagement with Nietzsche. I conclude by incorporating Jacques Lacan’s psychoanalysis as a further extension of Heidegger’s discourse on falling, showing that the subject’s discourse and relationship to the truth of Being is at the core of his constitution and neurosis. ii Table of Contents Introduction 1 My Project in Context 11 Chapter 1: The History of Metaphysics and the History of Being 33 1.1 Introduction: Being and Metaphysics 33 1.2 Falling Persists Through Heidegger’s Thinking 36 1.3 Destruction and Recollection of the question of the meaning of being 41 1.4 The Meaning of Overcoming Metaphysics 44 1.5 The Preface to Falling in Being and Time 50 1.6 Heidegger’s Concept of Falling 68 1.7 Falling and Death 71 1.8 Additions to a Phenomenology of Falling 73 1.9 Conclusion 83 Chapter 2: Augustine’s Theology of the Fall 87 2.1 Introduction 87 2.2 Heidegger on the Theology of the Fall 91 2.3 The Classic Augustinian Model of the Fall 93 2.4 Augustine’s Fall as Entry of Death Into Life 94 2.5 Death of the Soul, Death of the Body 100 2.6 The Fall and the Itinerary of the Soul in Two Cities 102 2.7 Conclusion 108 Chapter 3: Heidegger and the Genesis of Truth 113 3.1 Introduction 113 3.2 The Truth of Plato, and Beyond 117 3.3 Truth from Proposition to the Freedom to Let Beings Be 124 3.4 The Essence of Truth as Untruth 130 3.5. The Truth of Being as Thing and World 135 3.6 Conclusion 155 Chapter 4: Heidegger and the Truth of Genesis 164 4.1 Introduction 164 4.2 The Truth of Genesis 179 4.3 Conclusion 196 Chapter 5: Falling at the End of Metaphysics: the Death of God and the Will to Power 207 5.1 Introduction 207 5.2 Nietzsche’s Metaphysics: Death of God and the Will to Power 209 5.3 Nietzsche’s Entrenchment of Metaphysics 219 5.4 Nietzsche’s Metaphysics in Relation to Falling 226 5.5 Heidegger’s First Corrective: Affirmation of Being-History 229 iii Chapter 6: The Humiliation of Metaphysics and The Waiting for a God 236 6.1 Introduction 237 6.2 Nietzsche’s Fall 240 6.3 Heidegger and the Question of God 248 6.4 Falling—“Only a God Can Save Us.” 251 6.5 Conclusion 259 Chapter 7: The Lacanian Fall: Psychoanalysis as Metaphysical Diagnosis 267 7.1 Introduction 267 7.2 Freud and the Original Fall in Psychoanalysis 269 7.3 The Broader Heideggerian Context of Lacan’s Theory 272 7.4 Lacan’s Phenomenological Analysis 276 7.5 Lacanian Subjectivity 277 7.6 The Truth of the Subject is the Truth of Metaphysics 283 7.7 The Habitus of the Subject 288 7.8 The Aletheia of the Subject 292 7.9 Conclusion 308 Chapter 8: Antiphony of Death: The Freedom and the Work of the Metaphysical Subject 314 8.1 Introduction 315 8.2 Death—Man’s Absolute Master 327 8.3 Death: the Word of Man’s Freedom 333 Conclusion 345 Bibliography 351 iv Introduction Phenomenology returns thinking to the investigation of phenomena as they appear in their “givenness.”1 The first, Husserlian phenomenological reduction attempts to take reflection, via a step back, prior to any ideas or presuppositions related to the phenomena that present themselves. As Maurice Merleau-Ponty puts it, phenomenology tries to give a direct description of our experience as it is, without taking account of its psychological origin and the causal explanations which the scientist, the historian or the sociologist may be able to provide.2 Following Husserl’s initial formulations, Martin Heidegger states in Being and Time—his own expansion of the phenomenological project—phenomenology aims to “let that which shows itself be seen from itself in the very way in which it shows itself from itself.”3 Thus phenomenology seeks to lay bare the nature or essence of a phenomenon in its appearing without recourse to prior philosophical or scientific ideation. 1 Cf. Moran, Dermot. Introduction to Phenomenology (New York: Routledge, 2000), 11: the phenomenological epoché, or suspension of the natural attitude . This bracketing meant that all scientific, philosophical, cultural, and everyday assumptions had to be put aside – not so much negated as to be put out of court . Indeed, in genuine phenomenological viewing, we are not permitted any scientific or philosophical hypotheses. We should attend only to the phenomena in the manner of their being given to us, in their modes of givenness.” 2 Merleau-Ponty. Phenomenology of Perception, trans. Donald A. Landes (New York: Routledge, 2013), vii. 3 Heidegger, Martin, Being and Time, trans. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson (New York: HarperSanFrancisco, 2002), H34, p. 58. 1 In his landmark phenomenological work, Being and Time, Heidegger argues that it is Being itself which conditions and provides for every phenomenon. Yet Being has never even been raised as a philosophical question except to the extent that it is either subsumed under or confused with some characteristic of beings, or as the ground (reason) for all beings, which leads naturally enough to the metaphysical conceiving of Being as the Highest Being. Phenomenology immediately challenges these conclusions as insufficiently primordial, i.e., already presumptuous, imposing a number of preconceived rational or ideational structures upon the phenomenon of Being itself. Being remains unique and difficult as a matter of thought, for while every phenomenon is given by virtue of Being, Being is not simply present to experience and reflection in the same manner beings are, and it cannot be conflated with beings or their qualities. The question is, how does Being show itself or appear, if it cannot be reduced to the qualities of beings or as their ground reason (the latter of which necessitates an imposition of human logic upon “something’ that first makes logos possible)? Obviously, Being, in one way or another, appears to us, so it must in some as yet non-thematized way present itself to us. Thus, Heidegger argues, a phenomenology of our own human factical experience might lead philosophy to the place of posing the question of Being again, just as it was raised at the outset of Western philosophy—but was long since forgotten and abandoned as a question.4 To do this, Heidegger investigates human existence in terms of its own unique Being, such that, as Da-sein (being-there/here), we as humans take our Being up into our concern and investigation. 4 As we will see, Being is dismissed as the most general, universal, abstract, self-evident, etc. of concepts. 2 Husserl was compelled to leave every phenomenon “bracketed” in order to achieve something akin to an original “seeing” of the thing itself as it presents itself. Phenomenology, the art that evolved under the aegis of Edmund Husserl, with the explicit purpose of returning our philosophical investigations back to phenomena themselves as they appear and show themselves, includes those phenomena which had been precluded from rational discourse since the onset of modernity. As Heidegger’s own phenomenological investigations expanded, however, he began to discover that a more original sense of the self-manifestation of phenomena could be found as a principle of Greek thinking and experience—in Aristotle in particular—in the form of aletheia as the unconcealment of what-is present, its being revealed, its showing itself.
Recommended publications
  • The Real Estate Marketplace Glossary: How to Talk the Talk
    Federal Trade Commission ftc.gov The Real Estate Marketplace Glossary: How to Talk the Talk Buying a home can be exciting. It also can be somewhat daunting, even if you’ve done it before. You will deal with mortgage options, credit reports, loan applications, contracts, points, appraisals, change orders, inspections, warranties, walk-throughs, settlement sheets, escrow accounts, recording fees, insurance, taxes...the list goes on. No doubt you will hear and see words and terms you’ve never heard before. Just what do they all mean? The Federal Trade Commission, the agency that promotes competition and protects consumers, has prepared this glossary to help you better understand the terms commonly used in the real estate and mortgage marketplace. A Annual Percentage Rate (APR): The cost of Appraisal: A professional analysis used a loan or other financing as an annual rate. to estimate the value of the property. This The APR includes the interest rate, points, includes examples of sales of similar prop- broker fees and certain other credit charges erties. a borrower is required to pay. Appraiser: A professional who conducts an Annuity: An amount paid yearly or at other analysis of the property, including examples regular intervals, often at a guaranteed of sales of similar properties in order to de- minimum amount. Also, a type of insurance velop an estimate of the value of the prop- policy in which the policy holder makes erty. The analysis is called an “appraisal.” payments for a fixed period or until a stated age, and then receives annuity payments Appreciation: An increase in the market from the insurance company.
    [Show full text]
  • Johnston Publications List--April 2018
    !1 Publications A. Monographs 1. (2005). Time Driven: Metapsychology and the Splitting of the Drive [with a foreword by Slavoj "i#ek], Evanston: Northwestern University Press. 2. (2008). Žižek’s Ontology: A Transcendental Materialist Theory of Subjectivity, Evanston: Northwestern University Press. 3. (2009). Badiou, Žižek, and Political Transformations: The Cadence of Change, Evanston: Northwestern University Press. 4. (2013). Prolegomena to Any Future Materialism, Volume One: The Outcome of Contemporary French Philosophy, Evanston: Northwestern University Press. 5. (2014). Adventures in Transcendental Materialism: Dialogues with Contemporary Thinkers, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. 6. (2017). Irrepressible Truth: On Lacan’s ‘The Freudian Thing’, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. 7. (2018). A New German Idealism: Hegel, Žižek, and Dialectical Materialism, New York: Columbia University Press. 8. (2019). Prolegomena to Any Future Materialism, Volume Two: A Weak Nature Alone, Evanston: Northwestern University Press (forthcoming). 9. Infinite Greed: Money, Marxism, Psychoanalysis (in preparation; to be submitted to Columbia University Press). 10. Prolegomena to Any Future Materialism, Volume Three: Substance Also as Subject (in preparation; to be submitted to Northwestern University Press). B. Co-authored Books 1. (2013). with Catherine Malabou, Self and Emotional Life: Philosophy, Psychoanalysis, and Neuroscience, New York: Columbia University Press. C. Chapters in Books 1. (2002). “Jacques Lacan,” The Freud Encyclopedia: Theories, Therapies, and Culture [ed. Edward Erwin], New York: Routledge, pp. 315-319. !2 2. (2006). “Ghosts of Substance Past: Schelling, Lacan, and the Denaturalization of Nature,” Lacan: The Silent Partners [ed. Slavoj "i#ek], London: Verso Books, pp. 34-55. 3. (2007). “From the Spectacular Act to the Vanishing Act: Badiou, "i#ek, and the Politics of Lacanian Theory,” Did Somebody Say Ideology?: Slavoj Žižek in a Post-Ideological Universe [ed.
    [Show full text]
  • Virulence and Digital Culture
    Virulence and Digital Culture Ryan E. Artrip Dissertation submitted to the faculty of the Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy In ASPECT: Alliance for Social, Political, Ethical, and Cultural Thought François Debrix, Chair Timothy W. Luke Brian Britt Patricia Nickel April 18, 2016 Blacksburg, VA Keywords: Technology; Digitality; Digital Culture; Production; Information; Representation; Referentiality; Virtuality; Viral Media; Virulence; Sexuality; Linguistic Theory; Baudrillard; Hyperreality; Virtual Reality; Implosion; Critical Theory; Political Theory; Cultural Theory; Critical Media Studies; Poststructuralism; Epistemology; Ontology; Metaphysics Copyright 2016 Virulence and Digital Culture Ryan E. Artrip ABSTRACT (academic) This dissertation is a theoretical study of the role of virality/virulence as a predominant technological term in the reproduction of social and cultural information in the digital age. I argue that viral media are not new phenomena, only the name is new. Media have always behaved as viruses; it is only when they become hyper-intensified in digital technology that their virulent function surfaces in language and culture. The project examines processes of self-replication and evolution undergone by various new media phenomena as they relate back to the global profusion of social networks, data centers, and cybernetic practices. Drawing from several contributions in media theory, political and social theory, and critical media studies, I argue that digital media have a hyper-intensifying effect on whatever objects, subjects, or realities they mediate or represent; thus networked societies are virulently swarmed by their own signs and images in information. Through an examination of three primary categories of digital proliferation—language, visuality, and sexuality—I situate digital culture in a framework of virulence, arguing that the digital may be best understood as an effect of cultural hyper-saturation and implosion.
    [Show full text]
  • Depopulation: on the Logic of Heidegger's Volk
    Research research in phenomenology 47 (2017) 297–330 in Phenomenology brill.com/rp Depopulation: On the Logic of Heidegger’s Volk Nicolai Krejberg Knudsen Aarhus University [email protected] Abstract This article provides a detailed analysis of the function of the notion of Volk in Martin Heidegger’s philosophy. At first glance, this term is an appeal to the revolutionary mass- es of the National Socialist revolution in a way that demarcates a distinction between the rootedness of the German People (capital “P”) and the rootlessness of the modern rabble (or people). But this distinction is not a sufficient explanation of Heidegger’s position, because Heidegger simultaneously seems to hold that even the Germans are characterized by a lack of identity. What is required is a further appropriation of the proper. My suggestion is that this logic of the Volk is not only useful for understanding Heidegger’s thought during the war, but also an indication of what happened after he lost faith in the National Socialist movement and thus had to make the lack of the People the basis of his thought. Keywords Heidegger – Nazism – Schwarze Hefte – Black Notebooks – Volk – people Introduction In § 74 of Sein und Zeit, Heidegger introduces the notorious term “the People” [das Volk]. For Heidegger, this term functions as the intersection between phi- losophy and politics and, consequently, it preoccupies him throughout the turbulent years from the National Socialist revolution in 1933 to the end of WWII in 1945. The shift from individual Dasein to the Dasein of the German People has often been noted as the very point at which Heidegger’s fundamen- tal ontology intersects with his disastrous political views.
    [Show full text]
  • 52 Philosophy in a Dark Time: Martin Heidegger and the Third Reich
    52 Philosophy in a Dark Time: Martin Heidegger and the Third Reich TIMOTHY O’HAGAN Like Oscar Wilde I can resist everything except temptation. So when I re- ceived Anne Meylan’s tempting invitation to contribute to this Festschrift for Pascal Engel I accepted without hesitation, before I had time to think whether I had anything for the occasion. Finally I suggested to Anne the text of a pub- lic lecture which I delivered in 2008 and which I had shown to Pascal, who responded to it with his customary enthusiasm and barrage of papers of his own on similar topics. But when I re-read it, I realized that it had been written for the general public rather than the professional philosophers who would be likely to read this collection of essays. So what was I to do with it? I’ve decided to present it in two parts. In Part One I reproduce the original lecture, unchanged except for a few minor corrections. In Part Two I engage with a tiny fraction of the vast secondary literature which has built up over the years and which shows no sign of abating. 1. Part One: The 2008 Lecture Curtain-Raiser Let us start with two dates, 1927 and 1933. In 1927 Adolf Hitler’s Mein Kampf (volume II) was published. So too was Martin Heidegger’s magnum opus Being and Time. In 1933 two appointments were made: Hitler as Chancellor of the German Reich and Heidegger as Rector of Freiburg University. In 1927 it was a case of sheer coincidence; in 1933 the two events were closely linked.
    [Show full text]
  • Temporality and Historicality of Dasein at Martin Heidegger
    Sincronía ISSN: 1562-384X [email protected] Universidad de Guadalajara México Temporality and historicality of dasein at martin heidegger. Javorská, Andrea Temporality and historicality of dasein at martin heidegger. Sincronía, no. 69, 2016 Universidad de Guadalajara, México Available in: https://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=513852378011 This work is licensed under Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International. PDF generated from XML JATS4R by Redalyc Project academic non-profit, developed under the open access initiative Filosofía Temporality and historicality of dasein at martin heidegger. Andrea Javorská [email protected] Constantine the Philosopher University in Nitra, Eslovaquia Abstract: Analysis of Heidegger's work around historicity as an ontological problem through the existential analytic of Being Dasein. It seeks to find the significant structure of temporality represented by the historicity of Dasein. Keywords: Heidegger, Existentialism, Dasein, Temporality. Resumen: Análisis de la obra de Heidegger en tornoa la historicidad como problema ontológico a través de la analítica existencial del Ser Dasein. Se pretende encontrar la estructura significativa de temporalidad representada por la historicidad del Dasein. Palabras clave: Heidegger, Existencialismo, Dasein, Temporalidad. Sincronía, no. 69, 2016 Universidad de Guadalajara, México Martin Heidegger and his fundamental ontology shows that the question Received: 03 August 2015 Revised: 28 August 2015 of history belongs among the most fundamental questions of human Accepted:
    [Show full text]
  • INTUITION .THE PHILOSOPHY of HENRI BERGSON By
    THE RHYTHM OF PHILOSOPHY: INTUITION ·ANI? PHILOSO~IDC METHOD IN .THE PHILOSOPHY OF HENRI BERGSON By CAROLE TABOR FlSHER Bachelor Of Arts Taylor University Upland, Indiana .. 1983 Submitted ~o the Faculty of the Graduate College of the · Oklahoma State University in partial fulfi11ment of the requirements for . the Degree of . Master of Arts May, 1990 Oklahoma State. Univ. Library THE RHY1HM OF PlllLOSOPHY: INTUITION ' AND PfnLoSOPlllC METHOD IN .THE PHILOSOPHY OF HENRI BERGSON Thesis Approved: vt4;;. e ·~lu .. ·~ests AdVIsor /l4.t--OZ. ·~ ,£__ '', 13~6350' ii · ,. PREFACE The writing of this thesis has bee~ a tiring, enjoyable, :Qustrating and challenging experience. M.,Bergson has introduced me to ·a whole new way of doing . philosophy which has put vitality into the process. I have caught a Bergson bug. His vision of a collaboration of philosophers using his intuitional m~thod to correct, each others' work and patiently compile a body of philosophic know: ledge is inspiring. I hope I have done him justice in my description of that vision. If I have succeeded and that vision catches your imagination I hope you Will make the effort to apply it. Please let me know of your effort, your successes and your failures. With the current challenges to rationalist epistemology, I believe the time has come to give Bergson's method a try. My discovery of Bergson is. the culmination of a development of my thought, one that started long before I began my work at Oklahoma State. However, there are some people there who deserv~. special thanks for awakening me from my ' "''' analytic slumber.
    [Show full text]
  • The Male Gaze Interpretive Guide
    Interpretive Guide & Hands-on Activities The Alberta Foundation for the Arts Travelling Exhibition Program The Male Gaze The Alberta Foundation for the Arts Travelling Exhibition Program The Interpretive Guide The Art Gallery of Alberta is pleased to present your community with a selection from its Travelling Exhibition Program. This is one of several exhibitions distributed by The Art Gallery of Alberta as part of the Alberta Foundation for the Arts Travelling Exhibition Program. This Interpretive Guide has been specifically designed to complement the exhibition you are now hosting. The suggested topics for discussion and accompanying activities can act as a guide to increase your viewers’ enjoyment and to assist you in developing programs to complement the exhibition. Questions and activities have been included at both elementary and advanced levels for younger and older visitors. At the Elementary School Level the Alberta Art Curriculum includes four components to provide students with a variety of experiences. These are: Reflection: Responses to visual forms in nature, designed objects and artworks Depiction: Development of imagery based on notions of realism Composition: Organization of images and their qualities in the creation of visual art Expression: Use of art materials as a vehicle for expressing statements The Secondary Level focuses on three major components of visual learning. These are: Drawings: Examining the ways we record visual information and discoveries Encounters: Meeting and responding to visual imagery Composition: Analyzing the ways images are put together to create meaning The activities in the Interpretive Guide address one or more of the above components and are generally suited for adaptation to a range of grade levels.
    [Show full text]
  • Can We All Really Have It? Loving Gaze As an Anti-Oppressive Beauty
    The Perfect Bikini Body: Can We All Really Have It? Loving Gaze as an Anti-Oppressive Beauty Ideal Forthcoming in Thought: A Journal of Philosophy (please cite the final version) Abstract In this paper I ask whether there is a defensible philosophical view according to which every body is beautiful. I review two purely aesthetical versions of this claim. The No Standards View claims that every body is maximally and equally beautiful. The Multiple Standards View encourages us to widen our standards of beauty. I argue that both approaches are problematic. The former fails to be aspirational and empowering, while the latter fails to be sufficiently inclusive. I conclude by presenting a hybrid ethical-aesthetical view according to which everybody is beautiful in the sense that every body can be perceived through a loving gaze (with the exception of evil individuals who are wholly unworthy of love). I show that this view is inclusive, aspirational and empowering, and authentically aesthetical. As soon as the summer season approaches, the internet is inundated with articles and slideshows with such titles as: “37 Totally Perfect Bikini Bodies. Rule No.1: there are no rules”1 or “9 Stunning Bodies That Shatter Society’s Stereotypes About the ‘Perfect’ Body”.2 These popular articles are ultimately grounded in the feminist imperative of dismantling sexist and oppressive aesthetic norms that harm women3 in a myriad of ways, among which: damaging their self-esteem and affecting their psychological and physical health, exposing 1 https://www.buzzfeed.com/kirstenking/all-your-perfect- imperfections?utm_term=.aoxkvwvz2#.qwJzDJD9G Last accessed on 02/16/2017.
    [Show full text]
  • The Crisis of Representation Jg. 04 Heft 02
    Interdisciplinary Journal for Religion and Transformation (2018), Heft 7, doi.org/10.14220/jrat.2018.4.issue-2 The Kingdom, the Power, the Glory,and the Tawdry: Neoliberal Hegemony and the “Undoing” of the Demos Carl Raschke This article explores Giorgio Agambenscelebrated “double paradigmofsovereignty”, which introduces the Christian idea of oikonomia (“economy”)asafoundational polit- ical concept in Western thinking. It argues that Agambensfar-ranging discussion im- proves our understanding of how Foucaultsnotion of biopoweractually develops his- torically from the matrix of earlyChristian theology and how it becomes its own kind of “political theology” to undergird the contemporarydynamics,structure,and rhetoricof neoliberalism. FollowingAgamben, the argument also builds on his thesis that “eco- nomic sovereignty” today is cemented through the power of modern forms of media in much the same way that the critical theorists of the interwar period identified the “culture industry” as the genuine hegemon of capitalism. Finally, it devotes extensive attention to the work of the French social philosopher and media theorist Bernard Stiegler and his notion of “cognitive capitalism.” GiorgioAgamben;MichelFoucault;Carl Schmitt;Oikonomia;Trinity; Biopolitics; Pastorate;Karl Marx;Wendy Brown;Jean-Jacques Rousseau;Jürgen Habermas;Ber- nard Stiegler;Cognitive Capitalism;Neoliberalism;Social Media Carl Raschke is Professor of Religious Studiesatthe University of Denver and senior editor for TheJournalfor Cultural and Religious Theory.His most recent
    [Show full text]
  • Heidegger, Being and Time
    Heidegger's Being and Time 1 Karsten Harries Heidegger's Being and Time Seminar Notes Spring Semester 2014 Yale University Heidegger's Being and Time 2 Copyright Karsten Harries [email protected] Heidegger's Being and Time 3 Contents 1. Introduction 4 2. Ontology and Fundamental Ontology 16 3. Methodological Considerations 30 4. Being-in-the-World 43 5. The World 55 6. Who am I? 69 7. Understanding, Interpretation, Language 82 8. Care and Truth 96 9. The Entirety of Dasein 113 10. Conscience, Guilt, Resolve 128 11. Time and Subjectivity 145 12. History and the Hero 158 13. Conclusion 169 Heidegger's Being and Time 4 1. Introduction 1 In this seminar I shall be concerned with Heidegger's Being and Time. I shall refer to other works by Heidegger, but the discussion will center on Being and Time. In reading the book, some of you, especially those with a reading knowledge of German, may find the lectures of the twenties helpful, which have appeared now as volumes of the Gesamtausgabe. Many of these have by now been translated. I am thinking especially of GA 17 Einführung in die phänomenologische Forschung (1923/24); Introduction to Phenomenological Research, trans. Daniel O. Dahlstrom (Bloomington, Indiana University Press, 2005) GA 20 Prolegomena zur Geschichte des Zeitbegriffs (1925); History of the Concept of Time, trans. Theodore Kisiel (Bloomington, Indiana University Press, 1985) GA 21 Logik. Die Frage nach der Wahrheit (1925/26). Logic: The Question of Truth, trans. Thomas Sheehan GA 24 Die Grundprobleme der Phänomenologie (1927); The Basic Problems of Phenomenology, trans.
    [Show full text]
  • Between Heidegger and Derrida: on the Impossible Futures of Techne
    KIR KUIKEN Between Heidegger and Derrida: On the Impossible Futures of Techne This paper is not the first to interrogate the term “legacies” in the title of this conference, implying as it does the vast problems of inheritance, of debt and even of mourning. A conference on the “Legacies of Theory” necessarily provokes a meditation on the notion of “legacy” itself. What I do not wish to take issue with in this term is what is implied by the plural: “legacies.” If the concept of “legacy” implies inheritance, then there is the possibility of inheritance only where its contingencies are multiple, contested and even contradictory. This multiplicity is in fact the precondition of inheriting, its very chance or possibility. What I do want to contest, however, is a certain relation to time that the term “legacies” implies. At a moment when the term “post-theory” has entered the academic lexicon, and when books with titles such as Life After Theory (Derrida et al.)1 have begun to mark its retreat or displacement within the institution, the term “legacies” risks collusion with a discourse that seeks to extirpate any real encounter with its “legacy,” multiple, contested or otherwise. And if I might be permitted to replace the term “theory” with the term “deconstruction,” the problematic nature of the concept of “legacy” makes itself clearer. Insofar as the term “legacy” implies a certain “temporality of presence,” with a clear, single, undivided border 1 The book contains an interview with Derrida, who addresses the question of “what comes after” theory very differently than the other contributors.
    [Show full text]