Creational Aesthetics & the Challenge of Conceptual Art By

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Creational Aesthetics & the Challenge of Conceptual Art By Creational Aesthetics & The Challenge of Conceptual Art by Steven Félix-Jäger A trend in theological aesthetics is to advocate for a “creational aesthetic” when discussing the ontology and calling of the artist. In its essential form, a creational aesthetic affirms that artists honor the Creator God by creating art. In some way artists are functioning as God’s image when they make art. While this view is popular in the Christian engagement of the arts, it is uncertain if such an observation is the preeminent way of understanding the role of the artist. Can one be considered an artist if he or she is removed from the tactile process of making? In the contemporary artworld, the role of the artist in visual art has come into question with a stronger emphasis on conceptuality over against construction. Is the conceptual art movement of the 1960s, which has influenced so much of contemporary art, at odds with a creational aesthetic? I would like to address this issue first by outlining a sketch of what I have come to call “creational aesthetics.” I will draw on the work of L. Clifton Edwards to show that the Christian narrative of creation is an integral feature of theological aesthetics. I will then engage the work of Donald Brook and artists Henry Flint and Sol LeWitt to discuss the nature of conceptual art. Finally, I will return to the preliminary question concerning conceptualism’s apparent tension with creational aesthetics, and argue for an alternate way of understanding creation that makes room for conceptuality in art. My main dialogue partners in this section are theologians Jeremy Begbie and James Watkins. My thesis is that conceptual art can be incorporated into a more robust creational aesthetic that emphasizes the incarnation and redemption. Steven Félix-Jäger 2 Creational Aesthetics L. Clifton Edwards argues for a creational theology that allows us to grasp beauty and natural revelation as authoritative sources for theological reflection.1 Edwards contends that our knowledge of God is creationally mediated in the created world.2 We are creatures living in a material world, and this world is the arena in which God was ultimately made known in Jesus Christ. While Edwards admits that our experience of God is a “created subjectivity,” creation itself confines our knowledge of God while concurrently making it possible.3 Because creation is aesthetically rich and mediates a new understanding of God,4 we can know God in fresh and profound ways. This occurs by reflecting on the world’s beauty, which echoes the beauty of its Creator. Such enrichment comes from nuanced contemplation of the Creator’s handiwork, and leads one to further explore the implications that surround the doctrine of creation. Herein lies the task of what I am calling a creational aesthetic – the drawing out of principles that concern sense perceptions and the arts in relation to the doctrine of creation. Perhaps one of the clearest articulations of a creational aesthetic was put forth by Abraham Kuyper in his book Wisdom & Wonder when he wrote, “God creates in reality, people create in semblance. God created the living person in the individual of Adam, the artist creates the human image out of marble.”5 Kuyper saw human creativity as an outworking of the imago dei, and since God is the Creator, humans too can create as a fulfillment of their divine purpose. However, since God is the only one who creates ex nihilo, humans create from an already existing created substance. Francis Schaeffer writes, “God, because he is infinite, can create out of nothing by his spoken word. We, because we are finite, must create from something else that Steven Félix-Jäger 3 has already been created.”6 In a creational aesthetic, then, we must understand human creativity as a creaturely act, and as a gift from God.7 The underlying theme that “we create because God creates” is found consistently in a creational aesthetic. Watkins writes, “The desire to pattern one’s creativity after God’s creativity may actually be an attempt to participate in the creative work God is doing in the world.”8 The role of the artist may be more complex than mere imitation, but at the end of the day, the creative acts of a creature reflect those of the first Creator. So if contemplation of the created order leads to a greater understanding of God, and if creation as reproduction allows us to participate in our calling as image-bearers, then what do we make of those artworks that are neither aesthetic nor made? Is it simply the case that such conceptual art is in fact not art, and that those conceptual artists are theorists rather than artists? Avant-garde art, which values concept over percept, seems to have put creational aesthetics at a crossroads: Either one must deem conceptual art as not compatible with creational aesthetics, or one must broaden his or her understanding of creation so as to make room for conceptualism. Before exploring this issue, however, we must take a closer look at the challenge of conceptual art. The Challenge of Conceptual Art As a contrast to the creational propensity towards the physical object, conceptualism claims that art is not indebted to artifactuality, but only to ideas. Donald Brook attempts to explain the meaning of “conceptual art” by distinguishing some defining principles. First, conceptual art is “sensory mode indifferent.” By this Brook means that the concept takes precedence over the percept.9 A percept refers to an object that is perceived, and since aesthetics is a philosophy that deals with perception, conceptualism is an anti-aesthetic form of art. Steven Félix-Jäger 4 Another defining principle is that conceptual art is “sensory mode independent.” By this Brook means that conceptual art is an art of ideas rather than an art of physical objects.10 So conceptual art is indifferent to the senses as it is anti-aesthetic, but is also independent of the senses as it upholds the idea whether or not there is a physical manifestation of it. Finally, conceptual art is a restricted meta-activity.11 This is an essential quality of conceptual art because it properly appreciates the fact that conceptual art comments on the notion of art itself.12 Conceptual art thus carries the mantel of suspicion that grew from the mid-modern meta-discourse concerning the nature and reception of art.13 The conceptual art movement of the 1960s finds its roots in Marcel Duchamp’s concept of the “readymade.” Duchamp famously submitted a urinal as a readymade work of art entitled Fountain to the first exhibition of the American Society of Independent Artists in 1917.14 Duchamp submitted it under the pseudonym “R. MUTT,” in order to conceal his identity so as not to affect the piece’s deliberation. Ultimately Fountain was rejected, as the jury could not find aesthetic value in the work.15 Nevertheless, Fountain has prevailed as a pivotal example of the extent of art in the modern era. In fact, Duchamp was able to radically redefine what is meant when speaking about art. Under Duchamp art no longer needs to exhibit aesthetic value. Duchamp said as much writing, “A point which I want very much to establish is that the choice of these ‘ready-mades’ was never dictated by esthetic [sic] delectation.”16 Duchamp’s agenda was one of destruction by picking apart the concept of art. The first casualty was the idea that art had to require aesthetic value. Duchamp sought to see the word “art” as descriptive rather than evaluative. Art can be good or bad, but the status of a thing’s arthood is not contingent on its aesthetical value.17 He preferred the term “art coefficient” to describe art in its raw state, before its value is assessed.18 A readymade is a work Steven Félix-Jäger 5 of art devoid of aesthetic features, but is nevertheless art as a conceptual object. Urinals are not artworks, but Fountain is. The distinction lies in the appropriation of the object. The distinction is conceptual and intrinsic, not physical and extrinsic. The meaning of the object has changed when it was contemplated as art at an institution of art. When an object’s meaning is changed, the object’s ontology has changed from a piece of plumbing to a work of art. The idea of the readymade caused conceptual artist Joseph Kosuth to make the provocative statement, “All art (after Duchamp) is conceptual (in nature) because art only exists conceptually.”19 Kosuth claimed that readymades changed the nature of art from a question of morphology to a question of function.20 The change from “appearance” to “conception” marked the start of modern art and the conceptual art movement.21 American artist Henry Flynt is commonly associated with the conceptual art movement of the 1960s. This is in part due to his influential 1961 essay entitled “Essay: Concept Art.” In this essay Flynt defines “concept art” as “an art of which the material is ‘concepts,’ as the material for ex. music is sound.”22 Concept art, for Flynt, supersedes the visual sense arena, and can rather embody any form. It is not the artifactuality of concept art that distinguishes it as such, but rather the idea itself.23 Likewise conceptual art is a cerebral endeavor, and visual artifacts are unnecessary, while common, aftereffects. The difference between Flynt’s notion of concept art and conceptual art as a movement is that concept art focuses on the “artist as thinker,” whereas conceptual art is art that explores concepts over and against the object.
Recommended publications
  • The Conceptual Art Game a Coloring Game Inspired by the Ideas of Postmodern Artist Sol Lewitt
    Copyright © 2020 Blick Art Materials All rights reserved 800-447-8192 DickBlick.com The Conceptual Art Game A coloring game inspired by the ideas of postmodern artist Sol LeWitt. Solomon (Sol) LeWitt (1928-2007), one of the key pioneers of conceptual art, noted that, “Each person draws a line differently and each person understands words differently.” When he was working for architect I.M. Pei, LeWitt noted that an architect Materials (required) doesn't build his own design, yet he is still Graph or Grid paper, recommend considered an artist. A composer requires choice of: musicians to make his creation a reality. Koala Sketchbook, Circular Grid, He deduced that art happens before it 8.5" x 8.5", 30 sheets (13848- becomes something viewable, when it is 1085); share two across class conceived in the mind of the artist. Canson Foundation Graph Pad, 8" x 8" grid, 8.5" x 11" pad, 40 He said, “When an artist uses a conceptual sheets, (10636-2885); share two form of art, it means that all of the planning across class and decisions are made beforehand and Choice of color materials, the execution is a perfunctory affair. The recommend: idea becomes a machine that makes the Blick Studio Artists' Colored art.” Pencils, set of 12 (22063-0129); Over the course of his career, LeWitt share one set between two students produced approximately 1,350 designs known as “Wall Drawings” to be completed at specific sites. Faber-Castell DuoTip Washable Markers, set of 12 (22314-0129); The unusual thing is that he rarely painted one share one set between two himself.
    [Show full text]
  • All These Post-1965 Movements Under the “Conceptual Art” Umbrella
    All these post-1965 movements under the “conceptual art” umbrella- Postminimalism or process art, Site Specific works, Conceptual art movement proper, Performance art, Body Art and all combinations thereof- move the practice of art away from art-as-autonomous object, and art-as-commodification, and towards art-as-experience, where subject becomes object, hierarchy between subject and object is critiqued and intersubjectivity of artist, viewer and artwork abounds! Bruce Nauman, Live-Taped Video Corridor, 1970, Conceptual Body art, Postmodern beginning “As opposed to being viewers of the work, once again they are viewers in it.” (“Subject as Object,” p. 199) http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=9IrqXiqgQBo A Postmodern beginning: Body art and Performance art as critique of art-as-object recap: -Bruce Nauman -Vito Acconci focus on: -Chris Burden -Richard Serra -Carolee Schneemann - Hannah Wilke Chapter 3, pp. 114-132 (Carolee Schneemann and Hannah Wilke, First Generation Feminism) Bruce Nauman, Bouncing Two Balls Between the Floor and Ceiling with Changing Rhythms, 1967-1968. 16mm film transferred to video (black and white, sound), 10 min. Body art/Performance art, Postmodern beginning- performed elementary gestures in the privacy of his studio and documented them in a variety of media Vito Acconci, Following Piece, 1969, Body art, Performance art- outside the studio, Postmodern beginning Video documentation of the event Print made from bite mark Vito Acconci, Trademarks, 1970, Body art, Performance art, Postmodern beginning Video and Print documentation
    [Show full text]
  • Untranslating the Neo-Avant-Gardes Luke Skrebowski
    INTRODUCTION UnTranslaTing The neo-aVanT-garDes luke skrebowski This guest-edited issue aims to trouble assumptions about the trans- latability of various global neo-avant-gardes into canonical Anglo- American terms and categories—including Pop, Minimalism, Conceptualism—however problematized and expanded they may be in the process. The assumptions I have in mind tend to prop up the cul- tural hegemony of Western institutions by means of a logic of inclusion that serves to reinforce rather than destabilize the status quo. To this end, this issue foregrounds the problem of translation, and specifi cally the fi gure of “the untranslatable,” to address the mediation of global neo-avant-gardes in a more refl exive way, going beyond the often nebu- lous and frequently one-sided notions of “infl uence,” “interaction,” or “contact” that continue to characterize much of the discourse on the global neo-avant-gardes. The notion of the untranslatable is borrowed from Barbara Cassin, via Emily Apter and Jacques Lezra, and is developed here for comparative work in, but also in a certain sense against, global art his- tory. Cassin’s multilingual philosophical lexicon Vocabulaire européen des philosophies: Dictionnaire des intraduisibles (2004) consists of a select number of terms drawn from particular national and linguistic philosophical traditions which are chosen precisely for their “untrans- latability,” a term that, as Cassin insists, “n’implique nullement que les termes en question . ne soient pas traduits et ne puissent pas 4 © 2018 ARTMargins and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology doi:10.1162/ARTM_e_00206 Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/artm_e_00206 by guest on 26 September 2021 l’être—l’intraduisible c’est plutôt ce qu’on ne cesse pas de (ne pas) traduire.” (“In no way implies that the terms in question .
    [Show full text]
  • Gce History of Art Major Modern Art Movements
    FACTFILE: GCE HISTORY OF ART MAJOR MODERN ART MOVEMENTS Major Modern Art Movements Key words Overview New types of art; collage, assemblage, kinetic, The range of Major Modern Art Movements is photography, land art, earthworks, performance art. extensive. There are over 100 known art movements and information on a selected range of the better Use of new materials; found objects, ephemeral known art movements in modern times is provided materials, junk, readymades and everyday items. below. The influence of one art movement upon Expressive use of colour particularly in; another can be seen in the definitions as twentieth Impressionism, Post Impressionism, Fauvism, century art which became known as a time of ‘isms’. Cubism, Expressionism, and colour field painting. New Techniques; Pointilism, automatic drawing, frottage, action painting, Pop Art, Neo-Impressionism, Synthesism, Kinetic Art, Neo-Dada and Op Art. 1 FACTFILE: GCE HISTORY OF ART / MAJOR MODERN ART MOVEMENTS The Making of Modern Art The Nine most influential Art Movements to impact Cubism (fl. 1908–14) on Modern Art; Primarily practised in painting and originating (1) Impressionism; in Paris c.1907, Cubism saw artists employing (2) Fauvism; an analytic vision based on fragmentation and multiple viewpoints. It was like a deconstructing of (3) Cubism; the subject and came as a rejection of Renaissance- (4) Futurism; inspired linear perspective and rounded volumes. The two main artists practising Cubism were Pablo (5) Expressionism; Picasso and Georges Braque, in two variants (6) Dada; ‘Analytical Cubism’ and ‘Synthetic Cubism’. This movement was to influence abstract art for the (7) Surrealism; next 50 years with the emergence of the flat (8) Abstract Expressionism; picture plane and an alternative to conventional perspective.
    [Show full text]
  • Conceptual Art
    DOI: 10.7816/idil-06-30-03 idil, 2017, Cilt 6, Sayı 30, Volume 6, Issue 30 FROM OBJECT TO IMAGE – IMAGE TO OBJECT: CONCEPTUAL ART Yurdagül KILIÇ1 ABSTRACT Conceptual art considered to have emerged as a new understanding in the late 1960’s and leading to great conflicts within the art world is an understanding which opposes to art’s being limited to such specific categories as painting and sculpture and to art works’ being exhibited in galleries and museums, and is an understanding where object loses its significance and thought becomes vital. The art movements rising with postmodernism from 20th century onwards caused the object which is the main subject of art to bear different meanings at a different place and a different time. In the age of postmodernism art is everywhere and in everything and thus the limitation to image cannot be considered.The starting point of the conceptual art which developed in opposition to commercialization of art and the formalist art theory has been examined in this study. The information and emerging findings as a result of the scanning of related literature, one of qualitative research methods, has been assessed within this context. Keywords: Conceptual Art, Object, Image, Postmodernism Kılıç, Yurdagül . "From Object to Image- Image to Object: Conceptual Art". idil 6.30 (2017): 511-527. Kılıç, Y. (2017). From Object to Image- Image to Object: Conceptual Art. idil, 6 (30), s.511-527. 1 Arş. Gör., Dokuz Eylül Üniv., Güzel Sanatlar Eğitimi Böl., Resim-İş Eğitimi ABD, yurdagul.klc(at)hotmail.com 511 www.idildergisi.com Kılıç, Y.
    [Show full text]
  • Conceptual Art: a Critical Anthology
    Conceptual Art: A Critical Anthology Alexander Alberro Blake Stimson, Editors The MIT Press conceptual art conceptual art: a critical anthology edited by alexander alberro and blake stimson the MIT press • cambridge, massachusetts • london, england ᭧1999 Massachusetts Institute of Technology All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced in any form by any electronic or mechanical means (including photocopying, recording, or information storage and retrieval)without permission in writing from the publisher. This book was set in Adobe Garamond and Trade Gothic by Graphic Composition, Inc. and was printed and bound in the United States of America. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Conceptual art : a critical anthology / edited by Alexander Alberro and Blake Stimson. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-262-01173-5 (hc : alk. paper) 1. Conceptual art. I. Alberro, Alexander. II. Stimson, Blake. N6494.C63C597 1999 700—dc21 98-52388 CIP contents ILLUSTRATIONS xii PREFACE xiv Alexander Alberro, Reconsidering Conceptual Art, 1966–1977 xvi Blake Stimson, The Promise of Conceptual Art xxxviii I 1966–1967 Eduardo Costa, Rau´ l Escari, Roberto Jacoby, A Media Art (Manifesto) 2 Christine Kozlov, Compositions for Audio Structures 6 He´lio Oiticica, Position and Program 8 Sol LeWitt, Paragraphs on Conceptual Art 12 Sigmund Bode, Excerpt from Placement as Language (1928) 18 Mel Bochner, The Serial Attitude 22 Daniel Buren, Olivier Mosset, Michel Parmentier, Niele Toroni, Statement 28 Michel Claura, Buren, Mosset, Toroni or Anybody 30 Michael Baldwin, Remarks on Air-Conditioning: An Extravaganza of Blandness 32 Adrian Piper, A Defense of the “Conceptual” Process in Art 36 He´lio Oiticica, General Scheme of the New Objectivity 40 II 1968 Lucy R.
    [Show full text]
  • Fluxus: the Is Gnificant Role of Female Artists Megan Butcher
    Pace University DigitalCommons@Pace Honors College Theses Pforzheimer Honors College Summer 7-2018 Fluxus: The iS gnificant Role of Female Artists Megan Butcher Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.pace.edu/honorscollege_theses Part of the Contemporary Art Commons, and the Other History Commons Recommended Citation Butcher, Megan, "Fluxus: The iS gnificant Role of Female Artists" (2018). Honors College Theses. 178. https://digitalcommons.pace.edu/honorscollege_theses/178 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Pforzheimer Honors College at DigitalCommons@Pace. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors College Theses by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@Pace. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Abstract The Fluxus movement of the 1960s and early 1970s laid the groundwork for future female artists and performance art as a medium. However, throughout my research, I have found that while there is evidence that female artists played an important role in this art movement, they were often not written about or credited for their contributions. Literature on the subject is also quite limited. Many books and journals only mention the more prominent female artists of Fluxus, leaving the lesser-known female artists difficult to research. The lack of scholarly discussion has led to the inaccurate documentation of the development of Fluxus art and how it influenced later movements. Additionally, the absence of research suggests that female artists’ work was less important and, consequently, keeps their efforts and achievements unknown. It can be demonstrated that works of art created by little-known female artists later influenced more prominent artists, but the original works have gone unacknowledged.
    [Show full text]
  • Sol Lewitt. “Sentences on Conceptual Art”. Art-Language, Coventry, Vol. 1, No
    Sol LeWitt. “Sentences on Conceptual Art”. Art-Language, Coventry, vol. 1, no. 1, May 1969. 1. Conceptual Artists are mystics rather than rationalists. They leap to conclusions that logic cannot reach. 2. Rational judgments repeat rational judgments. 3. Illogical judgments lead to new experience. 4. Formal Art is essentially rational. 5. Irrational thoughts should be followed absolutely and logically. 6. If the artist changes his mind midway through the execution of the piece he compromises the result and repeats past results. 7. The artist’s will is secondary to the process he imitates from idea to completion. His willfulness may only be ego. 8. When words such as painting and sculpture are used, they connote a whole tradition and imply a consequent acceptance of this tradition, thus placing limitations on the artist who would be reluctant to make art that goes beyond the limitations. 9. The concept and idea are different. The former implies a general direction and the latter are the components. Ideas implement the concept. 10. Ideas alone can be works of art; they are in a chain of development that may eventually find some form. All ideas need not be made physical. 11. Ideas do not necessarily proceed in logical order. They may set one off in unexpected directions but an idea must necessarily be completed in the mind before the next one is formed. 12. For each work of art that becomes physical there are many variations that do not. 13. A work of art may be understood as a conductor from the artist’s mind to the viewer’s.
    [Show full text]
  • Kazimir Malevich Was a Russian Artist of Ukrainian Birth, Whose Career Coincided with the Bolshevik Revolution of 1917 and Its Social and Cultural Aftermath
    QUICK VIEW: Synopsis Kazimir Malevich was a Russian artist of Ukrainian birth, whose career coincided with the Bolshevik Revolution of 1917 and its social and cultural aftermath. Malevich was the founder of the artistic and philosophical school of Suprematism, and his ideas about forms and meaning in art would eventually form the theoretical underpinnings of non- objective, or abstract, art making. Malevich worked in a variety of styles, but his most important and famous works concentrated on the exploration of pure geometric forms (squares, triangles, and circles) and their relationships to each other and within the pictorial space. Because of his contacts in the West, Malevich was able to transmit his ideas about painting to his fellow artists in Europe and the U.S., thus profoundly influencing the evolution of non-representational art in both the Eastern and Western traditions. Key Ideas • Malevich worked in a variety of styles, from Impressionism to Cubo-Futurism, arriving eventually at Suprematism - his own unique philosophy of painting and art perception. • Malevich was a prolific writer. His treatises on philosophy of art address a broad spectrum of theoretical problems and laid the conceptual basis for non-objective art both in Europe and the United States. • Malevich conceived of an independent comprehensive abstract art practice before its definitive emergence in the United States. His stress on the independence of geometric form influenced many generations of abstract artists in the West, especially Ad Reinhardt. © The Art Story Foundation – All rights Reserved For more movements, artists and ideas on Modern Art visit www.TheArtStory.org DETAILED VIEW: Childhood Malevich was born in Ukraine to parents of Polish origin, who moved continuously within the Russian Empire in search of work.
    [Show full text]
  • Conceptual Art of the Press Release, Or Art History Without
    Conceptual Art of the Press Release, or Art History without Art Downloaded from http://direct.mit.edu/octo/article-pdf/doi/10.1162/OCTO_a_00276/1753987/octo_a_00276.pdf by guest on 01 October 2021 DAVID JOSELIT On a recent tour of galleries in Chelsea, I mentioned to my two compan - ions—a curator and an artist—that in general I prefer to forego reading the Xeroxed press releases offered to visitors at the front desk until I’ve had a good look at the show. This policy represents a test of sorts—both for myself and for the art on view. Can I apprehend patterns of allusion and palimpsests of codes without the cheat sheet? And conversely, does the art, stripped of its discursive apparatus, hold up? On that day, however, it wasn’t long before I was consulting press releas - es—first, to learn what a certain mystifying material was in a painting at Hauser & Wirth, and then, frankly, just to cut to the chase, to move more efficiently through the ten or so exhibitions we wanted to see that afternoon. My lapse is trivial but nonetheless central to something disturbing both in art practice and in histories and criticism of contemporary art. If the equation of art with information beginning in the late 1960s constituted a profound ontological challenge to the work of art, now Blouinartinfo.com giddily identifies the “25 Most Collectible Conceptual Artists.” 1 As in neoliberal economic theory, where maximal information is said to make markets more efficient, our Conceptual art of the press release (in which artworks are “translated” into text as propositions about their meaning) makes even difficult art easy to consume.
    [Show full text]
  • Conceptual Art, Social Psychology, and Deception – Peter Goldie
    Postgraduate Journal of Aesthetics, Vol. 1, No. 2, August 2004 CONCEPTUAL ART, SOCIAL PSYCHOLOGY, AND DECEPTION PETER GOLDIE KING’S COLLEGE, LONDON ABSTRACT Some works of conceptual art require deception for their appreciation—deception of the viewer of the work. Some experiments in social psychology equally require deception— deception of the participants in the experiment. There are a number of close parallels between the two kinds of deception. And yet, in spite of these parallels, the art world, artists, and philosophers of art, do not seem to be troubled about the deception involved, whereas deception is a constant source of worry for social psychologists. Intuitively, each of these responses might seem appropriate for its sphere, but it is not easy to see what grounds these intuitions. I try to come up with some answers. I Some experiments (indeed the majority) in social psychology require deception. Stanley Milgram’s obedience experiments are perhaps the most famous example, where participants were deceived into believing that they were involved in a learning test, giving real electric shocks to people, when in fact they were involved in experiments on obedience, and the shocks weren’t real. 1 In one of J. M. Darley and C. D. Batson’s experiments, seminarians were 1 See especially Stanley Milgram, Obedience to Authority: An Experimental View, New York: Harper and 32 PETER GOLDIE induced to believe that one of their number, whom they encountered in a walk across the campus to give a talk, was seriously ill, when in fact he was not, and in fact they were, unknown to them, part of an experiment in Samaritarianism—the study of people’s helping behaviour.2 The deception was so effective that one of the seminarians, on his way to give a talk on the parable on the Good Samaritan, actually stepped over the prone body of what he thought to be his suffering colleague.
    [Show full text]
  • A Postmodern Beginning: Conceptual Art Movement Proper As Critique Of
    A Postmodern beginning: Conceptual Art movement proper as critique of art-as-object Sol Lewitt, Installation at Paula Cooper Gallery, October 10- 31, 1980s, Conceptual, A Postmodern beginning Lewitt says his art is, which he terms “conceptual,” is “„made to engage the mind of the viewer rather than his eye or emotions‟”; the conceptual “„making art that doesn‟t have an object as a residue‟” (Sandler, 70) The Conceptual movement proper in post-1965 art emerged from the confluence of two major legacies of modernism: 1. the strain of modernism, which I termed “conceptualism,” embodied in the readymade notion of art as self-definition that emerged out of Dada and was picked up by Fluxus performance art, Happenings and Pop art; “as a continuation of the central thrust in Duchamp‟s art and thinking. Duchamp had said that in introducing mass-produced readymades into an art context, he had added a new idea to the ordinary artifact.” (Sandler, 70) 2. the strain of modernism, which I termed “formalism,” embodied in Minimalism and geometric abstraction that emerged out of the reduction to the literal or physical nature of the support; “the bracketing out of the conceptual component of minimal art” (Sandler, 70) Conceptual art can then be viewed as the “dematerialization” of a minimal object or a readymade, taking either back to the original idea that generated it. Sol Lewitt: A Wall Drawing Retrospective http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=c4cgB4vJ2XY Instructions for the wall drawing from the artist, “anyone can do it”! Incorporates some chance; each time the drawing is installed its slightly different based on who is doing it and their slightly different interpretation.
    [Show full text]