Probabilities and Partial Observation from Probabilistic Omega-Automata to Stochastic Games of Imperfect Information

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Probabilities and Partial Observation from Probabilistic Omega-Automata to Stochastic Games of Imperfect Information Introduction Probabilistic ω-automata Stochastic games of imperfect information Conclusion Probabilities and partial observation From probabilistic omega-automata to stochastic games of imperfect information Nathalie Bertrand Inria Rennes + Liverpool visitor based on joint work with Christel Baier & Marcus Großer¨ Blaise Genest & Hugo Gimbert Probabilities and partial observation OUCL Verification seminar 1 Monty Hall problem Ethernet protocol: random choice slot, collisions, maximum nb of trials Introduction Probabilistic ω-automata Stochastic games of imperfect information Conclusion Motivation Adversarial situations with I probabilities: random choices, uncertainties, losses I partial observation: distributed Probabilities and partial observation OUCL Verification seminar 2 Ethernet protocol: random choice slot, collisions, maximum nb of trials Introduction Probabilistic ω-automata Stochastic games of imperfect information Conclusion Motivation Adversarial situations with I probabilities: random choices, uncertainties, losses I partial observation: distributed Monty Hall problem Probabilities and partial observation OUCL Verification seminar 2 Introduction Probabilistic ω-automata Stochastic games of imperfect information Conclusion Motivation Adversarial situations with I probabilities: random choices, uncertainties, losses I partial observation: distributed Monty Hall problem Ethernet protocol: random choice slot, collisions, maximum nb of trials Probabilities and partial observation OUCL Verification seminar 2 Problems for POMDPs Given a POMDP ( , ), an LTL formula ϕ and p [0, 1] M ∼ ∈ Question is there a based scheduler with P (ϕ) ./ p? ∼ U U State of the art (back in 2008) I based, P (F) > 0 is EXPTIME-Comp. [de Alfaro 99] ∃U ∼ U I based, P (^F) ./ p is undecidable [Giro D’Argenio 07] ∃U ∼ (p U(0, 1) and ./ , , = ) ∈ ∈ {≤ ≥ } Introduction Probabilistic ω-automata Stochastic games of imperfect information Conclusion Partially observable MDP Partially Observable MDP A POMDP ( , ) consists of an MDP equipped with an equiva- lence relationM ∼over states of . M ∼ M Probabilities and partial observation OUCL Verification seminar 3 State of the art (back in 2008) I based, P (F) > 0 is EXPTIME-Comp. [de Alfaro 99] ∃U ∼ U I based, P (^F) ./ p is undecidable [Giro D’Argenio 07] ∃U ∼ (p U(0, 1) and ./ , , = ) ∈ ∈ {≤ ≥ } Introduction Probabilistic ω-automata Stochastic games of imperfect information Conclusion Partially observable MDP Partially Observable MDP A POMDP ( , ) consists of an MDP equipped with an equiva- lence relationM ∼over states of . M ∼ M Problems for POMDPs Given a POMDP ( , ), an LTL formula ϕ and p [0, 1] M ∼ ∈ Question is there a based scheduler with P (ϕ) ./ p? ∼ U U Probabilities and partial observation OUCL Verification seminar 3 Introduction Probabilistic ω-automata Stochastic games of imperfect information Conclusion Partially observable MDP Partially Observable MDP A POMDP ( , ) consists of an MDP equipped with an equiva- lence relationM ∼over states of . M ∼ M Problems for POMDPs Given a POMDP ( , ), an LTL formula ϕ and p [0, 1] M ∼ ∈ Question is there a based scheduler with P (ϕ) ./ p? ∼ U U State of the art (back in 2008) I based, P (F) > 0 is EXPTIME-Comp. [de Alfaro 99] ∃U ∼ U I based, P (^F) ./ p is undecidable [Giro D’Argenio 07] ∃U ∼ (p U(0, 1) and ./ , , = ) ∈ ∈ {≤ ≥ } Probabilities and partial observation OUCL Verification seminar 3 Introduction Probabilistic ω-automata Stochastic games of imperfect information Conclusion Outline 1 Introduction 2 Probabilistic ω-automata Examples and expressiveness Emptiness problem Positive semantics (PBA>0) Almost-sure semantics (PBA=1) 3 Stochastic games of imperfect information Framework Qualitative determinacy Memory requirements Decidability 4 Conclusion Probabilities and partial observation OUCL Verification seminar 4 Introduction Probabilistic ω-automata Stochastic games of imperfect information Conclusion Probabilistic Buchi-automata¨ [Baier Großer¨ 05] Probabilistic Buchi¨ Automata NBA where nondeterminism is resolved by probabilities ω >0( ) = w Σ P( ρ Runs(w) ρ = ^F ) > 0 L A { ∈ ω | { ∈ | | } } =1( ) = w Σ P( ρ Runs(w) ρ = ^F ) = 1 L A { ∈ | { ∈ | | } } Probabilities and partial observation OUCL Verification seminar 5 Introduction Probabilistic ω-automata Stochastic games of imperfect information Conclusion Probabilistic Buchi-automata¨ [Baier Großer¨ 05] Probabilistic Buchi¨ Automata NBA where nondeterminism is resolved by probabilities ω >0( ) = w Σ P( ρ Runs(w) ρ = ^F ) > 0 L A { ∈ ω | { ∈ | | } } =1( ) = w Σ P( ρ Runs(w) ρ = ^F ) = 1 L A { ∈ | { ∈ | | } } PBA are POMDP with trivial equivalence relation: p, q p q. ∀ ∼ word for PBA deterministic blind scheduler for MDP ≡ Probabilities and partial observation OUCL Verification seminar 5 Introduction Probabilistic ω-automata Stochastic games of imperfect information Conclusion Probabilistic Buchi-automata¨ [Baier Großer¨ 05] Probabilistic Buchi¨ Automata NBA where nondeterminism is resolved by probabilities ω >0( ) = w Σ P( ρ Runs(w) ρ = ^F ) > 0 L A { ∈ ω | { ∈ | | } } =1( ) = w Σ P( ρ Runs(w) ρ = ^F ) = 1 L A { ∈ | { ∈ | | } } Example 1 ω >0 = (a + b)∗a = NBA L ω L =1 = b∗a L Probabilities and partial observation OUCL Verification seminar 5 Introduction Probabilistic ω-automata Stochastic games of imperfect information Conclusion Probabilistic Buchi-automata¨ [Baier Großer¨ 05] Probabilistic Buchi¨ Automata NBA where nondeterminism is resolved by probabilities ω >0( ) = w Σ P( ρ Runs(w) ρ = ^F ) > 0 L A { ∈ ω | { ∈ | | } } =1( ) = w Σ P( ρ Runs(w) ρ = ^F ) = 1 L A { ∈ | { ∈ | | } } Example 2 ω NBA = ((ac)∗(ab)) L ω >0 = (ab + ac)∗(ab) L ω =1 = (ab) L Probabilities and partial observation OUCL Verification seminar 5 Introduction Probabilistic ω-automata Stochastic games of imperfect information Conclusion Probabilistic Buchi-automata¨ [Baier Großer¨ 05] Probabilistic Buchi¨ Automata NBA where nondeterminism is resolved by probabilities ω >0( ) = w Σ P( ρ Runs(w) ρ = ^F ) > 0 L A { ∈ ω | { ∈ | | } } =1( ) = w Σ P( ρ Runs(w) ρ = ^F ) = 1 L A { ∈ | { ∈ | | } } Example 3 ω NBA = (ab + ac) L 0 = =1 = L> L ∅ Probabilities and partial observation OUCL Verification seminar 5 Introduction Probabilistic ω-automata Stochastic games of imperfect information Conclusion Expressiveness: PBA vs NBA Expressiveness PBA>0 are more expressive than NBA. PBA=1 and NBA are incomparable. Probabilities and partial observation OUCL Verification seminar 6 Introduction Probabilistic ω-automata Stochastic games of imperfect information Conclusion Expressiveness: PBA vs NBA Expressiveness PBA>0 are more expressive than NBA. PBA=1 and NBA are incomparable. I any NBA can be turned into an equivalent PBA first turn NBA into an equivalent one deterministic in the limit → I example of a PBA>0 whose language is not ω-regular Probabilities and partial observation OUCL Verification seminar 6 Introduction Probabilistic ω-automata Stochastic games of imperfect information Conclusion Expressiveness: PBA vs NBA Expressiveness PBA>0 are more expressive than NBA. PBA=1 and NBA are incomparable. Probabilities and partial observation OUCL Verification seminar 6 Lemma For 0 < λ < µ < 1, ( ) ) ( ). L Pλ L Pµ Introduction Probabilistic ω-automata Stochastic games of imperfect information Conclusion Probabilities matter Y ( ) = ak1 bak2 b (1 λki ) > 0) L Pλ { · · · | − } i Probabilities and partial observation OUCL Verification seminar 7 Introduction Probabilistic ω-automata Stochastic games of imperfect information Conclusion Probabilities matter Y ( ) = ak1 bak2 b (1 λki ) > 0) L Pλ { · · · | − } i Lemma For 0 < λ < µ < 1, ( ) ) ( ). L Pλ L Pµ Probabilities and partial observation OUCL Verification seminar 7 Proof sketch Reduction of the modified emptiness problem for PFA w P (w) ε or PFA with ∀ R ≤ R w P (w) > 1 ε ∃ R − 1 and↓ 2 PBA s.t. P P >ε ( ) = ( 1) ( 2) = L R ∅ ⇔ L P ∩ L P ∅ Introduction Probabilistic ω-automata Stochastic games of imperfect information Conclusion Emptiness for PBA>0 [Baier B. Großer¨ 08] Theorem The emptiness problem is undecidable for PBA. Probabilities and partial observation OUCL Verification seminar 8 Introduction Probabilistic ω-automata Stochastic games of imperfect information Conclusion Emptiness for PBA>0 [Baier B. Großer¨ 08] Theorem The emptiness problem is undecidable for PBA. Proof sketch Reduction of the modified emptiness problem for PFA w P (w) ε or PFA with ∀ R ≤ R w P (w) > 1 ε ∃ R − 1 and↓ 2 PBA s.t. P P >ε ( ) = ( 1) ( 2) = L R ∅ ⇔ L P ∩ L P ∅ Probabilities and partial observation OUCL Verification seminar 8 First undecidability results in qualitative verification of POMDP. Introduction Probabilistic ω-automata Stochastic games of imperfect information Conclusion Consequences for POMDP Undecidability results for POMDP The following problems are undecidable I Given ( , ) and F set of states of , is there a deterministic M ∼ M based such that P (^F) > 0. ∼ U U I Given ( , ) and F set of states of , is there a deterministic M ∼ M based such that P (^F) = 1. ∼ U U Probabilities and partial observation OUCL Verification seminar 9 Introduction Probabilistic ω-automata Stochastic games of imperfect information Conclusion Consequences for POMDP Undecidability results for POMDP The following problems are undecidable I Given ( , ) and F set of states of , is there a deterministic M ∼ M based such that P (^F) > 0. ∼ U U I Given ( , ) and F set of states of , is there a deterministic M ∼ M based such that P (^F) = 1. ∼ U U First undecidability results in qualitative verification of POMDP. Probabilities and partial observation
Recommended publications
  • Game Theory Lecture Notes
    Game Theory: Penn State Math 486 Lecture Notes Version 2.1.1 Christopher Griffin « 2010-2021 Licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-Share Alike 3.0 United States License With Major Contributions By: James Fan George Kesidis and Other Contributions By: Arlan Stutler Sarthak Shah Contents List of Figuresv Preface xi 1. Using These Notes xi 2. An Overview of Game Theory xi Chapter 1. Probability Theory and Games Against the House1 1. Probability1 2. Random Variables and Expected Values6 3. Conditional Probability8 4. The Monty Hall Problem 11 Chapter 2. Game Trees and Extensive Form 15 1. Graphs and Trees 15 2. Game Trees with Complete Information and No Chance 18 3. Game Trees with Incomplete Information 22 4. Games of Chance 24 5. Pay-off Functions and Equilibria 26 Chapter 3. Normal and Strategic Form Games and Matrices 37 1. Normal and Strategic Form 37 2. Strategic Form Games 38 3. Review of Basic Matrix Properties 40 4. Special Matrices and Vectors 42 5. Strategy Vectors and Matrix Games 43 Chapter 4. Saddle Points, Mixed Strategies and the Minimax Theorem 45 1. Saddle Points 45 2. Zero-Sum Games without Saddle Points 48 3. Mixed Strategies 50 4. Mixed Strategies in Matrix Games 53 5. Dominated Strategies and Nash Equilibria 54 6. The Minimax Theorem 59 7. Finding Nash Equilibria in Simple Games 64 8. A Note on Nash Equilibria in General 66 Chapter 5. An Introduction to Optimization and the Karush-Kuhn-Tucker Conditions 69 1. A General Maximization Formulation 70 2. Some Geometry for Optimization 72 3.
    [Show full text]
  • Frequently Asked Questions in Mathematics
    Frequently Asked Questions in Mathematics The Sci.Math FAQ Team. Editor: Alex L´opez-Ortiz e-mail: [email protected] Contents 1 Introduction 4 1.1 Why a list of Frequently Asked Questions? . 4 1.2 Frequently Asked Questions in Mathematics? . 4 2 Fundamentals 5 2.1 Algebraic structures . 5 2.1.1 Monoids and Groups . 6 2.1.2 Rings . 7 2.1.3 Fields . 7 2.1.4 Ordering . 8 2.2 What are numbers? . 9 2.2.1 Introduction . 9 2.2.2 Construction of the Number System . 9 2.2.3 Construction of N ............................... 10 2.2.4 Construction of Z ................................ 10 2.2.5 Construction of Q ............................... 11 2.2.6 Construction of R ............................... 11 2.2.7 Construction of C ............................... 12 2.2.8 Rounding things up . 12 2.2.9 What’s next? . 12 3 Number Theory 14 3.1 Fermat’s Last Theorem . 14 3.1.1 History of Fermat’s Last Theorem . 14 3.1.2 What is the current status of FLT? . 14 3.1.3 Related Conjectures . 15 3.1.4 Did Fermat prove this theorem? . 16 3.2 Prime Numbers . 17 3.2.1 Largest known Mersenne prime . 17 3.2.2 Largest known prime . 17 3.2.3 Largest known twin primes . 18 3.2.4 Largest Fermat number with known factorization . 18 3.2.5 Algorithms to factor integer numbers . 18 3.2.6 Primality Testing . 19 3.2.7 List of record numbers . 20 3.2.8 What is the current status on Mersenne primes? .
    [Show full text]
  • The Monty Hall Problem in the Game Theory Class
    The Monty Hall Problem in the Game Theory Class Sasha Gnedin∗ October 29, 2018 1 Introduction Suppose you’re on a game show, and you’re given the choice of three doors: Behind one door is a car; behind the others, goats. You pick a door, say No. 1, and the host, who knows what’s behind the doors, opens another door, say No. 3, which has a goat. He then says to you, “Do you want to pick door No. 2?” Is it to your advantage to switch your choice? With these famous words the Parade Magazine columnist vos Savant opened an exciting chapter in mathematical didactics. The puzzle, which has be- come known as the Monty Hall Problem (MHP), has broken the records of popularity among the probability paradoxes. The book by Rosenhouse [9] and the Wikipedia entry on the MHP present the history and variations of the problem. arXiv:1107.0326v1 [math.HO] 1 Jul 2011 In the basic version of the MHP the rules of the game specify that the host must always reveal one of the unchosen doors to show that there is no prize there. Two remaining unrevealed doors may hide the prize, creating the illusion of symmetry and suggesting that the action does not matter. How- ever, the symmetry is fallacious, and switching is a better action, doubling the probability of winning. There are two main explanations of the paradox. One of them, simplistic, amounts to just counting the mutually exclusive cases: either you win with ∗[email protected] 1 switching or with holding the first choice.
    [Show full text]
  • Game, Set, and Match Carl W
    Game, Set, and Match Carl W. Lee September 2016 Note: Some of the text below comes from Martin Gardner's articles in Scientific American and some from Mathematical Circles by Fomin, Genkin, and Itenberg. 1 1 Fifteen This is a two player game. Take a set of nine cards, numbered one (ace) through nine. They are spread out on the table, face up. Players alternately select a card to add their hands, which they keep face up in front of them. The goal is to achieve a subset of three cards in your hand so that the values of these three cards sum to exactly fifteen. (The ace counts as 1.) This is an example of a game that is isomorphic to (the \same as") a well-known game: Tic-Tac-Toe. Number the cells of a tic-tac-toe board with the integers from 1 to 9 arranged in the form of a magic square. 8 1 6 3 5 7 4 9 2 Then winning combinations correspond exactly to triples of numbers that sum to 15. This is a combinatorial two person game (but one that permits ties). There is no hidden information (e.g., cards that one player has that the other cannot see) and no random elements (e.g., rolling of dice). 2 2 Ones and Twos Ten 1's and ten 2's are written on a blackboard. In one turn, a player may erase (or cross out) any two numbers. If the two numbers erased are identical, they are replaced with a single 2.
    [Show full text]
  • Subgame-Perfect Ε-Equilibria in Perfect Information Games With
    Subgame-Perfect -Equilibria in Perfect Information Games with Common Preferences at the Limit Citation for published version (APA): Flesch, J., & Predtetchinski, A. (2016). Subgame-Perfect -Equilibria in Perfect Information Games with Common Preferences at the Limit. Mathematics of Operations Research, 41(4), 1208-1221. https://doi.org/10.1287/moor.2015.0774 Document status and date: Published: 01/11/2016 DOI: 10.1287/moor.2015.0774 Document Version: Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Document license: Taverne Please check the document version of this publication: • A submitted manuscript is the version of the article upon submission and before peer-review. There can be important differences between the submitted version and the official published version of record. People interested in the research are advised to contact the author for the final version of the publication, or visit the DOI to the publisher's website. • The final author version and the galley proof are versions of the publication after peer review. • The final published version features the final layout of the paper including the volume, issue and page numbers. Link to publication General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Probability 1 Monty Hall
    Massachusetts Institute of Technology Course Notes, Week 12 6.042J/18.062J, Fall ’05: Mathematics for Computer Science November 21 Prof. Albert R. Meyer and Prof. Ronitt Rubinfeld revised November 29, 2005, 1285 minutes Introduction to Probability Probability is the last topic in this course and perhaps the most important. Many algo­ rithms rely on randomization. Investigating their correctness and performance requires probability theory. Moreover, many aspects of computer systems, such as memory man­ agement, branch prediction, packet routing, and load balancing are designed around probabilistic assumptions and analyses. Probability also comes up in information theory, cryptography, artificial intelligence, and game theory. Beyond these engineering applica­ tions, an understanding of probability gives insight into many everyday issues, such as polling, DNA testing, risk assessment, investing, and gambling. So probability is good stuff. 1 Monty Hall In the September 9, 1990 issue of Parade magazine, the columnist Marilyn vos Savant responded to this letter: Suppose you’re on a game show, and you’re given the choice of three doors. Behind one door is a car, behind the others, goats. You pick a door, say number 1, and the host, who knows what’s behind the doors, opens another door, say number 3, which has a goat. He says to you, ”Do you want to pick door number 2?” Is it to your advantage to switch your choice of doors? Craig. F. Whitaker Columbia, MD The letter roughly describes a situation faced by contestants on the 1970’s game show Let’s Make a Deal, hosted by Monty Hall and Carol Merrill.
    [Show full text]
  • Tic-Tac-Toe Is Not Very Interesting to Play, Because If Both Players Are Familiar with the Game the Result Is Always a Draw
    CMPSCI 250: Introduction to Computation Lecture #27: Games and Adversary Search David Mix Barrington 4 November 2013 Games and Adversary Search • Review: A* Search • Modeling Two-Player Games • When There is a Game Tree • The Determinacy Theorem • Searching a Game Tree • Examples of Games Review: A* Search • The A* Search depends on a heuristic function, which h(y) = 6 2 is a lower bound on the 23 s distance to the goal. x 4 If x is a node, and g is the • h(z) = 3 nearest goal node to x, the admissibility condition p(y) = 23 + 2 + 6 = 31 on h is that 0 ≤ h(x) ≤ d(x, g). p(z) = 23 + 4 + 3 = 30 Review: A* Search • Suppose we have taken y off of the open list. The best-path distance from the start s to the goal g through y is d(s, y) + d(y, h(y) = 6 g), and this cannot be less than 2 23 d(s, y) + h(y). s x 4 • Thus when we find a path of length k from s to y, we put y h(z) = 3 onto the open list with priority k p(y) = 23 + 2 + 6 = 31 + h(y). We still record the p(z) = 23 + 4 + 3 = 30 distance d(s, y) when we take y off of the open list. Review: A* Search • The advantage of A* over uniform-cost search is that we do not consider entries x in the closed list for which d(s, x) + h(x) h(y) = 6 is greater than the actual best- 2 23 path distance from s to g.
    [Show full text]
  • The Monty Hall Problem
    The Monty Hall Problem Richard D. Gill Mathematical Institute, University of Leiden, Netherlands http://www.math.leidenuniv.nl/∼gill 17 March, 2011 Abstract A range of solutions to the Monty Hall problem is developed, with the aim of connecting popular (informal) solutions and the formal mathematical solutions of in- troductory text-books. Under Riemann's slogan of replacing calculations with ideas, we discover bridges between popular solutions and rigorous (formal) mathematical solutions by using various combinations of symmetry, symmetrization, independence, and Bayes' rule, as well as insights from game theory. The result is a collection of intuitive and informal logical arguments which can be converted step by step into formal mathematics. The Monty Hall problem can be used simultaneously to develop probabilistic intuition and to give a deeper understanding of the paradox, not just to provide a routine exercise in computation of conditional probabilities. Simple insights from game theory can be used to prove probability inequalities. Acknowledgement: this text is the result of an evolution through texts written for three internet encyclopedias (wikipedia.org, citizendium.org, statprob.com) and each time has benefitted from the contributions of many other editors. I thank them all, for all the original ideas in this paper. That leaves only the mistakes, for which I bear responsibility. 1 Introduction Imagine you are a guest in a TV game show. The host, a certain Mr. Monty Hall, shows you three large doors and tells you that behind one of the doors there is a car while behind the other two there are goats. You want to win the car.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Game Theory I
    Introduction to Game Theory I Presented To: 2014 Summer REU Penn State Department of Mathematics Presented By: Christopher Griffin [email protected] 1/34 Types of Game Theory GAME THEORY Classical Game Combinatorial Dynamic Game Evolutionary Other Topics in Theory Game Theory Theory Game Theory Game Theory No time, doesn't contain differential equations Notion of time, may contain differential equations Games with finite or Games with no Games with time. Modeling population Experimental / infinite strategy space, chance. dynamics under Behavioral Game but no time. Games with motion or competition Theory Generally two player a dynamic component. Games with probability strategic games Modeling the evolution Voting Theory (either induced by the played on boards. Examples: of strategies in a player or the game). Optimal play in a dog population. Examples: Moves change the fight. Chasing your Determining why Games with coalitions structure of a game brother across a room. Examples: altruism is present in or negotiations. board. The evolution of human society. behaviors in a group of Examples: Examples: animals. Determining if there's Poker, Strategic Chess, Checkers, Go, a fair voting system. Military Decision Nim. Equilibrium of human Making, Negotiations. behavior in social networks. 2/34 Games Against the House The games we often see on television fall into this category. TV Game Shows (that do not pit players against each other in knowledge tests) often require a single player (who is, in a sense, playing against The House) to make a decision that will affect only his life. Prize is Behind: 1 2 3 Choose Door: 1 2 3 1 2 3 1 2 3 Switch: Y N Y N Y N Y N Y N Y N Y N Y N Y N Win/Lose: L W W L W L W L L W W L W L W L L W The Monty Hall Problem Other games against the house: • Blackjack • The Price is Right 3/34 Assumptions of Multi-Player Games 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Constructing Stationary Sunspot Equilibria in a Continuous Time Model*
    A Note on Woodford's Conjecture: Constructing Stationary Title Sunspot Equilibria in a Continuous Time Model(Nonlinear Analysis and Mathematical Economics) Author(s) Shigoka, Tadashi Citation 数理解析研究所講究録 (1994), 861: 51-66 Issue Date 1994-03 URL http://hdl.handle.net/2433/83844 Right Type Departmental Bulletin Paper Textversion publisher Kyoto University 数理解析研究所講究録 第 861 巻 1994 年 51-66 51 A Note on Woodford’s Conjecture: Constructing Stationary Sunspot Equilibria in a Continuous Time Model* Tadashi Shigoka Kyoto Institute of Economic Research, Kyoto University, Yoshidamachi Sakyoku Kyoto 606 Japan 京都大学 経済研究所 新後閑 禎 Abstract We show how to construct stationary sunspot equilibria in a continuous time model, where equilibrium is indeterninate near either a steady state or a closed orbit. Woodford’s conjecture that the indeterminacy of equilibrium implies the existence of stationary sunspot equilibria remains valid in a continuous time model. 52 Introduction If for given equilibrium dynamics there exist a continuum of non-stationary perfect foresight equilibria all converging asymptoticaUy to a steady state (a deterministic cycle resp.), we say the equilibrium dynamics is indeterminate near the steady state (the deterministic cycle resp.). Suppose that the fundamental characteristics of an economy are deterministic, but that economic agents believe nevertheless that equihibrium dynamics is affected by random factors apparently irrelevant to the fundamental characteristics (sunspots). This prophecy could be self-fulfilling, and one will get a sunspot equilibrium, if the resulting equilibrium dynamics is subject to a nontrivial stochastic process and confirns the agents’ belief. See Shell [19], and Cass-Shell [3]. Woodford [23] suggested that there exists a close relation between the indetenninacy of equilibrium near a deterministic steady state and the existence of stationary sunspot equilibria in the immediate vicinity of it.
    [Show full text]
  • The Monty Hall Problem Yurixy Lopez Martinez a Project Presented for The
    The Monty Hall Problem Yurixy Lopez Martinez A project presented for the degree of Bachelors of Arts, Mathematics Mathematics Department Whitman College Walla Walla, WA May 10, 2019 Abstract This paper begins by offering a detailed explanation of the solution to the Monty Hall Problem utilizing decision trees and mathematical concepts of conditional probability, mainly Bayes' Theorem. We will proceed to investigate the various versions of the problem that have risen throughout the years among scholars, mainly focusing on the benefits of a particular strategies. We will conclude by briefly discussing some applications of the Monty Hall Problem to other disciplines, mainly the probabilistic aspects. 1 Contents 1 Introduction 3 2 Monty Hall Problem 4 3 Why Switch? 5 4 Conditional Probability: Bayes' Theorem 7 5 Bayesian Monty 9 6 Variations of the Monty Hall Problem 10 6.1 Monty Chooses Randomly . 10 6.2 Highest-Ordered Selection . 11 6.3 Many doors . 14 6.3.1 Alternative Solution . 16 6.4 Many Doors, Many Cars . 17 6.5 Random Car Placement . 18 6.6 Two Contestants . 19 7 Applications of Monty Hall Problem 19 7.1 Philosophy . 20 7.2 Physics . 20 7.3 Economics . 21 7.4 Cognitive Science and Psychology . 21 8 Conclusion 21 9 Acknowledgements 22 2 1 Introduction The Monty Hall Problem is a recognized probability problem. The canonical, classical version of the problem is described as follows: A contestant is shown three identical doors. Behind one of them is a car. The other two conceal goats. The contestant is asked to choose, but not open, one of the doors.
    [Show full text]
  • Strategies in Games: a Logic-Automata Study
    Strategies in games: a logic-automata study S. Ghosh1 and R. Ramanujam2 1 Indian Statistical Institute SETS Campus, Chennai 600 113, India. [email protected] 2 The Institute of Mathematical Sciences C.I.T. Campus, Chennai 600 113, India. [email protected] 1 Introduction Overview. There is now a growing body of research on formal algorithmic mod- els of social procedures and interactions between rational agents. These models attempt to identify logical elements in our day-to-day social activities. When in- teractions are modeled as games, reasoning involves analysis of agents' long-term powers for influencing outcomes. Agents devise their respective strategies on how to interact so as to ensure maximal gain. In recent years, researchers have tried to devise logics and models in which strategies are “first class citizens", rather than unspecified means to ensure outcomes. Yet, these cover only basic models, leaving open a range of interesting issues, e.g. communication and coordination between players, especially in games of imperfect information. Game models are also relevant in the context of system design and verification. In this article we will discuss research on logic and automata-theoretic models of games and strategic reasoning in multi-agent systems. We will get acquainted with the basic tools and techniques for this emerging area, and provide pointers to the exciting questions it offers. Content. This article consists of 5 sections apart from the introduction. An outline of the contents of the other sections is given below. 1. Section 2 (Exploring structure in strategies): A short introduction to games in extensive form, and strategies.
    [Show full text]