Josh Hammer, “Common Good Originalism: Our Tradition and Our

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Josh Hammer, “Common Good Originalism: Our Tradition and Our COMMON GOOD ORIGINALISM: OUR TRADITION AND OUR PATH FORWARD JOSH HAMMER* Herewith, a paradox. On the one hand, legal conservatism, original- ism, and textualism have never been more ascendant and better-posi- tioned within the legal academy and mainstream political discourse. But on the other hand, the state of conservative jurisprudence in America has reached a crisis point.1 The crisis point did not arrive overnight. The modern Republican Party’s judicial nominations apparatus has often failed conservatives and constitutionalists, dating all the way back to President Dwight D. Eisenhower’s fateful twin Supreme Court nominations of Justice Wil- liam Brennan and Chief Justice Earl Warren. “I made two mistakes, and both of them are sitting on the Supreme Court,” President Eisen- hower famously said.2 Justice Harry Blackmun, author of Roe v. Wade,3 * Josh Hammer is a Newsweek opinion editor and a research fellow with the Edmund Burke Foundation. He previously worked at Kirkland & Ellis LLP, clerked for Judge James C. Ho of the U.S. Court of Appeals for the Fifth Circuit, and served as a John Marshall Fellow with the Claremont Institute. He holds a B.S. from Duke University and a J.D. from the University of Chicago Law School. This essay was written with the support of the Edmund Burke Foundation, for which he is very grateful. 1. See, e.g., Josh Hammer, The Crisis of the Conservative Legal Movement, AM. GREAT- NESS (July 30, 2020), https://amgreatness.com/2020/07/30/the-crisis-of-the-conservative- legal-movement/ [https://perma.cc/J9H8-UKJZ]; see also Josh Hammer, Undoing the Court’s Supreme Transgression, AM. MIND (June 19, 2020), https://american- mind.org/memo/undoing-the-courts-supreme-transgression/ [https://perma.cc/2ULQ- WM4A]. 2. Raymond J. de Souza, Supremacy of the Court, FIRST THINGS (Dec. 4, 2020), https://www.firstthings.com/web-exclusives/2020/12/supremacy-of-the-court [https://perma.cc/65E6-PCXM]. 3. 410 U.S. 113 (1973). 918 Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy [Vol. 4 the twentieth century’s moral and jurisprudential successor4 to the Dred Scott5 case, was a President Richard Nixon nominee. Justice John Paul Stevens, liberal lion of the Court for three and a half decades, was nominated by President Gerald Ford. President Ronald Reagan nom- inated the moderate Justice Sandra Day O’Connor and the idiosyn- cratic Justice Anthony Kennedy, the latter of whom would encapsu- late both a gnostic relativism in metaphysics6 and a jurisprudential commitment to individual autonomy maximalism7 over the course of his Court tenure. President George H.W. Bush greatly erred in nomi- nating Justice David Souter—he of the eponymous “No more Souters” fame—to the Supreme Court in lieu of the stalwart Edith H. Jones. President George W. Bush was similarly mistaken in selecting John G. Roberts over J. Michael Luttig for the position of Chief Justice of the Supreme Court. Suffice it to say that this is hardly a track record of sustained excellence. According to prevailing mythology, everything changed when Donald Trump became President. At long last, conservatives and constitutionalists had a White House that was unambiguously, pas- sionately committed to stacking the federal judiciary with princi- pled originalists and textualists. This purported well-oiled ma- chine, aided by outside actors with putative expertise in separating the would-be Souters from the true believers, was finally to deliver conservatives to the judicial promised land. 4. See, e.g., Robert P. George, A Republic . if You Can Keep It, FIRST THINGS (Jan. 22, 2016), https://www.firstthings.com/blogs/firstthoughts/2016/01/a-republic-if-you-can- keep-it [https://perma.cc/9ST2-DHQR]; Josh Hammer, Abortion Is a Grave Injustice. We Must Treat Roe Just Like Dred Scott., DAILY WIRE (Jan. 25, 2020), https://www.dai- lywire.com/news/hammer-abortion-is-a-grave-injustice-we-must-treat-roe-just-like- dred-scott [https://perma.cc/929T-3NAY]. See generally JUSTIN DYER, SLAVERY, ABOR- TION, AND THE POLITICS OF CONSTITUTIONAL MEANING (2013). 5. 60 U.S. (19 How.) 393 (1857). 6. See, e.g., William Haun, The “Mystery of Life” Makes Law a Mystery, PUB. DISCOURSE (July 26, 2013), https://www.thepublicdiscourse.com/2013/07/10091/ [https://perma.cc/N6C7-GZHF]. 7. See, e.g., Obergefell v. Hodges, 576 U.S. 644 (2015); Windsor v. United States, 570 U.S. 744 (2013); Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003); Romer v. Evans, 517 U.S. 620 (1996). No. 3] Common Good Originalism 919 Then came Bostock v. Clayton County,8 last summer’s bitter disap- pointment in which the Court implausibly9 wove both sexual ori- entation and transgenderism into a key plank of the nation’s civil rights statutory edifice. The opinion, of course, was written by none other than the President Trump’s first nominee to the Court and the man who replaced Justice Antonin Scalia himself, Justice Neil M. Gorsuch. With one stroke of a pen, the Justice Gorsuch-led Court majority misconstrued the proscription of private employment dis- crimination on the basis of “sex” in Title VII of the 1964 Civil Rights Act as encompassing not merely “sex,” but also “sexual orienta- tion” and “gender identity.”10 In so doing, this highly touted prod- uct of the conservative legal movement evinced and highlighted for all the shortcomings of a literalist, acontextual, overtly positivist ju- risprudence.11 That a man like Justice Gorsuch—closely vetted, with sterling ac- ademic credentials, formal natural law training, and top-flight so- cial conservative support at the time of his nomination12—could 8. 140 S. Ct. 1731 (2020). 9. See, e.g., Ryan T. Anderson, The Simplistic Logic of Justice Neil Gorsuch’s Account of Sex Discrimination, SCOTUSBLOG (June 16, 2020), https://www.sco- tusblog.com/2020/06/symposium-the-simplistic-logic-of-justice-neil-gorsuchs-account- of-sex-discrimination/ [https://perma.cc/3J44-YXQ2]; Josh Hammer, Neil Gorsuch Slapped Conservatives by Creating New Gay Rights, N.Y. POST (June 15, 2020, 8:28 PM), https://nypost.com/2020/06/15/neil-gorsuch-slapped-conservatives-by-creating-new- gay-rights/ [https://perma.cc/4RBZ-RSF8]. 10. See Bostock, 140 S. Ct. at 1755 (Alito, J., dissenting) (“The Court tries to convince readers that it is merely enforcing the terms of the statute, but that is preposterous.”). 11. See, e.g., Hadley Arkes, Josh Hammer, Matt Peterson, & Garrett Snedeker, A Better Originalism, AM. MIND (Mar. 18, 2021), https://americanmind.org/features/a-new-con- servatism-must-emerge/a-better-originalism/ [https://perma.cc/XY3U-7T8W]; Hadley Arkes, A Morally Empty Jurisprudence, FIRST THINGS (June 17, 2020), https://www.firstthings.com/web-exclusives/2020/06/a-morally-empty-jurisprudence [https://perma.cc/U4HM-BLA5]; Hadley Arkes, Conservative Jurisprudence Without Truth, FIRST THINGS (July 20, 2020), https://www.firstthings.com/web-exclu- sives/2020/07/conservative-jurisprudence-without-truth [https://perma.cc/UPE9- JJGM]; Hadley Arkes, What Hath Gorsuch Wrought?, FIRST THINGS (Oct. 13, 2020), https://www.firstthings.com/web-exclusives/2020/10/what-hath-gorsuch-wrought [https://perma.cc/H5P3-3DST]. 12. See, e.g., Robert P. George, Ignore the Attacks on Neil Gorsuch. He’s an Intellectual 920 Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy [Vol. 4 write an opinion like Bostock ought to serve as a wake-up call not only for those who prize the necessity of interpreting legal texts ac- cording to those texts’ original public meaning, but also for all con- servatives who prioritize above all the pursuit of the classical sub- stantive goals of politics qua politics: justice, human flourishing, and the common good.13 The time has indeed come for those in Amer- ica’s modern legal conservative movement to engage in sober, con- templative self-reflection—to reassess our first principles, retire our outmoded bromides, and rebalance prudence and dogma14 anew to reach a jurisprudence that actually serves our substantive goals.15 Too often, contemporary “legal conservatism”—as a methodology, not necessarily a specific judicial result—redounds against the in- terests of substantive conservatism itself. Legal conservatives too often pat themselves on the back for seizing a purported moral high ground of positivist neutrality,16 content to brush aside every high- profile defection as an unfortunate but inevitable byproduct of our sacrosanct neutrality principle. By contrast, legal progressives, marching in lockstep to the inherently outcome-oriented method- ology of Dworkinian living constitutionalism, never make such a first-order confusion of substance and “neutrality.” Perhaps those Giant—and a Good Man., WASH. POST (Feb. 1, 2017, 7:50 AM), https://www.washing- tonpost.com/posteverything/wp/2017/02/01/ignore-the-attacks-on-neil-gorsuch-hes- an-intellectual-giant-and-a-good-man/ [https://perma.cc/2CHU-K8DR]. 13. See, e.g., Josh Hammer, Who’s Afraid of the Common Good?, AM. MIND (Nov. 23, 2020), https://americanmind.org/salvo/whos-afraid-of-the-common-good/ [https://perma.cc/J4JK-8SB8]. 14. See, e.g., Josh Hammer, Conservatism Must Be Chastened by Humility, AM. COMPASS (Oct. 14, 2020), https://americancompass.org/the-commons/conservatism-must-be- chastened-by-humility/ [https://perma.cc/6E5J-RKFE]. 15. See, e.g., Josh Hammer, Judicial Carnage, AM. MIND (Oct. 30, 2020), https://ameri- canmind.org/features/what-comes-next/judicial-carnage/ [https://perma.cc/4TN4- D2TT]. 16. See, e.g., Ed Whelan, The Unsoundness and Imprudence of “Common-Good Original- ism”, PUB. DISCOURSE (Mar. 1, 2021), https://www.thepublicdis- course.com/2021/03/74424/ [https://perma.cc/FF7F-E5EK]; Ilya Shapiro, After Bostock, We’re All Textualists Now, NAT’L REV. (June 15, 2020), https://www.nationalre- view.com/2020/06/supreme-court-decision-bostock-v-clayton-county-we-are-all-textu- alists-now/ [https://perma.cc/7WCU-4L8B].
Recommended publications
  • Culture Wars' Reloaded: Trump, Anti-Political Correctness and the Right's 'Free Speech' Hypocrisy
    The 'Culture Wars' Reloaded: Trump, Anti-Political Correctness and the Right's 'Free Speech' Hypocrisy Dr. Valerie Scatamburlo-D'Annibale University of Windsor, Windsor, Ontario, Canada Abstract This article explores how Donald Trump capitalized on the right's decades-long, carefully choreographed and well-financed campaign against political correctness in relation to the broader strategy of 'cultural conservatism.' It provides an historical overview of various iterations of this campaign, discusses the mainstream media's complicity in promulgating conservative talking points about higher education at the height of the 1990s 'culture wars,' examines the reconfigured anti- PC/pro-free speech crusade of recent years, its contemporary currency in the Trump era and the implications for academia and educational policy. Keywords: political correctness, culture wars, free speech, cultural conservatism, critical pedagogy Introduction More than two years after Donald Trump's ascendancy to the White House, post-mortems of the 2016 American election continue to explore the factors that propelled him to office. Some have pointed to the spread of right-wing populism in the aftermath of the 2008 global financial crisis that culminated in Brexit in Europe and Trump's victory (Kagarlitsky, 2017; Tufts & Thomas, 2017) while Fuchs (2018) lays bare the deleterious role of social media in facilitating the rise of authoritarianism in the U.S. and elsewhere. Other 69 | P a g e The 'Culture Wars' Reloaded: Trump, Anti-Political Correctness and the Right's 'Free Speech' Hypocrisy explanations refer to deep-rooted misogyny that worked against Hillary Clinton (Wilz, 2016), a backlash against Barack Obama, sedimented racism and the demonization of diversity as a public good (Major, Blodorn and Blascovich, 2016; Shafer, 2017).
    [Show full text]
  • Public Goods in Everyday Life
    Public Goods in Everyday Life By June Sekera A GDAE Teaching Module on Social and Environmental Issues in Economics Global Development And Environment Institute Tufts University Medford, MA 02155 http://ase.tufts.edu/gdae Copyright © June Sekera Reproduced by permission. Copyright release is hereby granted for instructors to copy this module for instructional purposes. Students may also download the reading directly from https://ase.tufts.edu/gdae Comments and feedback from course use are welcomed: Global Development And Environment Institute Tufts University Somerville, MA 02144 http://ase.tufts.edu/gdae E-mail: [email protected] PUBLIC GOODS IN EVERYDAY LIFE “The history of civilization is a history of public goods... The more complex the civilization the greater the number of public goods that needed to be provided. Ours is far and away the most complex civilization humanity has ever developed. So its need for public goods – and goods with public goods aspects, such as education and health – is extraordinarily large. The institutions that have historically provided public goods are states. But it is unclear whether today’s states can – or will be allowed to – provide the goods we now demand.”1 -Martin Wolf, Financial Times 1 Martin Wolf, “The World’s Hunger for Public Goods”, Financial Times, January 24, 2012. 2 PUBLIC GOODS IN EVERYDAY LIFE TABLE OF CONTENTS 1. INTRODUCTION .........................................................................................................4 1.1 TEACHING OBJECTIVES: .....................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • A Critique of John Stuart Mill Chris Daly
    Southern Illinois University Carbondale OpenSIUC Honors Theses University Honors Program 5-2002 The Boundaries of Liberalism in a Global Era: A Critique of John Stuart Mill Chris Daly Follow this and additional works at: http://opensiuc.lib.siu.edu/uhp_theses Recommended Citation Daly, Chris, "The Boundaries of Liberalism in a Global Era: A Critique of John Stuart Mill" (2002). Honors Theses. Paper 131. This Dissertation/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the University Honors Program at OpenSIUC. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors Theses by an authorized administrator of OpenSIUC. For more information, please contact [email protected]. r The Boundaries of Liberalism in a Global Era: A Critique of John Stuart Mill Chris Daly May 8, 2002 r ABSTRACT The following study exanunes three works of John Stuart Mill, On Liberty, Utilitarianism, and Three Essays on Religion, and their subsequent effects on liberalism. Comparing the notion on individual freedom espoused in On Liberty to the notion of the social welfare in Utilitarianism, this analysis posits that it is impossible for a political philosophy to have two ultimate ends. Thus, Mill's liberalism is inherently flawed. As this philosophy was the foundation of Mill's progressive vision for humanity that he discusses in his Three Essays on Religion, this vision becomes paradoxical as well. Contending that the neo-liberalist global economic order is the contemporary parallel for Mill's religion of humanity, this work further demonstrates how these philosophical flaws have spread to infect the core of globalization in the 21 st century as well as their implications for future international relations.
    [Show full text]
  • Liberalism and the Common Good a Hayekian Perspective on Communitarianism
    SUBSCRIBE NOW AND RECEIVE CRISIS AND LEVIATHAN* FREE! “The Independent Review does not accept “The Independent Review is pronouncements of government officials nor the excellent.” conventional wisdom at face value.” —GARY BECKER, Noble Laureate —JOHN R. MACARTHUR, Publisher, Harper’s in Economic Sciences Subscribe to The Independent Review and receive a free book of your choice* such as the 25th Anniversary Edition of Crisis and Leviathan: Critical Episodes in the Growth of American Government, by Founding Editor Robert Higgs. This quarterly journal, guided by co-editors Christopher J. Coyne, and Michael C. Munger, and Robert M. Whaples offers leading-edge insights on today’s most critical issues in economics, healthcare, education, law, history, political science, philosophy, and sociology. Thought-provoking and educational, The Independent Review is blazing the way toward informed debate! Student? Educator? Journalist? Business or civic leader? Engaged citizen? This journal is for YOU! *Order today for more FREE book options Perfect for students or anyone on the go! The Independent Review is available on mobile devices or tablets: iOS devices, Amazon Kindle Fire, or Android through Magzter. INDEPENDENT INSTITUTE, 100 SWAN WAY, OAKLAND, CA 94621 • 800-927-8733 • [email protected] PROMO CODE IRA1703 Liberalism and the Common Good A Hayekian Perspective on Communitarianism —————— ✦ —————— LINDA C. RAEDER In the end, given liberty to learn, men will find out that freedom means community. —William Aylott Orton n recent years, a spirited
    [Show full text]
  • The Person and the Common Good*
    The Person and the Common Good* By Jacques Maritain Among the truthsof whichcontemporary thought stands in partic- ular need and from which it could draw substantialprofiit, is the doctrineof the distinctionbetween individuality and personality. The essentialimportance of this distinctionis revealedin the principlesof St. Thomas. Unfortunately,a right understandingof it is difficultto achieveand requiresan exerciseof metaphysicalinsight to whichthe contemporarymind is hardlyaccustomed. Does societyexist for each one of us, or does each one of us exist for society?Does the parishexist for the parishioneror the parishioner for the parish?This question,we feel immediately,involves two aspects, in each of which there must be some elementof truth. A unilateral answerwould only plunge us into error. Hence, we must disengage the formalprinciples of a truly comprehensiveanswer and describethe precisehierarchies of valueswhich it implies. The NineteenthCentury experiencedthe errorsof individualism. We have witnessedthe de- of velopment of a totalitarian or exclusively communal conception that societywhich took placeby way of reaction. It was natural,then, in a simultaneousreaction against both totalitarianand individualistic into errorsthe concept of the human person, incorporatedas such and that be opposed to both the idea of the totalitarian state society, to of the sovereigntyof the individual. In consequence,minds related uneven in widely differingschools of philosophicthought and quite intellectualexactitude and precisionhave sensed in the notionand term current of "person"the solution sought. Whence, the "personalist" remote which has developedin our time. Yet nothing can be more two We have undertaken in this paper a reconsideration and development of Deneke conferences: the first one, entitled "The Human Person and Society," was the Lecture, given at Oxford May 9, 1939, and published in a limited edition (Paris, Desclee de Brouver.
    [Show full text]
  • Rethinking Judicial Minimalism: Abortion Politics, Party Polarization, and the Consequences of Returning the Constitution to Elected Government Neal Devins
    Vanderbilt Law Review Volume 69 | Issue 4 Article 3 5-2016 Rethinking Judicial Minimalism: Abortion Politics, Party Polarization, and the Consequences of Returning the Constitution to Elected Government Neal Devins Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.vanderbilt.edu/vlr Part of the Supreme Court of the United States Commons Recommended Citation Neal Devins, Rethinking Judicial Minimalism: Abortion Politics, Party Polarization, and the Consequences of Returning the Constitution to Elected Government, 69 Vanderbilt Law Review 935 (2019) Available at: https://scholarship.law.vanderbilt.edu/vlr/vol69/iss4/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarship@Vanderbilt Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Vanderbilt Law Review by an authorized editor of Scholarship@Vanderbilt Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Rethinking Judicial Minimalism: Abortion Politics, Party Polarization, and the Consequences of Returning the Constitution to Elected Government Neal Devins* IN TROD U CTION ............................................................................... 935 I. MINIMALISM THEORY AND ABORTION ................................. 939 II. WHAT ABORTION POLITICS TELLS US ABOUT JUDICIAL M INIMALISM ........................................................ 946 A . R oe v. W ade ............................................................. 947 B . From Roe to Casey ................................................... 953 C. Casey and Beyond ..................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Samuel Alito: Populist William Araiza Brooklyn Law School, [email protected]
    Brooklyn Law School BrooklynWorks Faculty Scholarship 2017 Samuel Alito: Populist William Araiza Brooklyn Law School, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://brooklynworks.brooklaw.edu/faculty Part of the Law and Politics Commons, and the Other Law Commons Recommended Citation 103 Cornell Law Review Online 101 (2017) This Article is brought to you for free and open access by BrooklynWorks. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of BrooklynWorks. ESSAY SAMUEL ALITO: POPULIST William D. Araiza† I. EVALUATIONS OF JUSTICE ALITO ............................ 103 II. THE EVIDENCE ..................................................... 107 A. Brown v. Entertainment Merchants ............... 107 B. Caetano v. Massachusetts ............................ 111 C. Snyder v. Phelps ........................................... 113 D. Fisher v. University of Texas ......................... 116 E. Ricci v. DeStefano ......................................... 118 III. EVALUATING THE OPINIONS .................................... 120 A. Differences, Similarities, and Caveats .......... 120 B. Justice Alito’s Rhetorical Style ..................... 123 IV. SAMUEL ALITO: POPULIST ...................................... 130 In 2015, the tenth anniversary of Justice Samuel Alito’s ascension to the Court passed without the level of attention lavished on the same milestone reached that year by Chief Justice John Roberts.1 The difference in attention is understandable: the Chief Justiceship has given John Roberts † Professor of Law, Brooklyn Law School. Thanks to participants at the Loyola University Chicago Law School’s Constitutional Law Colloquium, and in particular Eric Berger and Corinna Lain, for helpful comments on an earlier version of this Essay. Thanks also to Mark Potkewitz for fine research assistance. 1 See, e.g., Symposium, Ten Years as the Chief: Examining a Decade of John Roberts on the Supreme Court, 38 CARDOZO L.
    [Show full text]
  • Saint Augustine's Sermons 355 &
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by CONCEPT (E-Journal, Villanova University) [CONCEPT, Vol. XXXIV (2011)] Clerical Misconduct, Charity, and the Common Good: Saint Augustine’s Sermons 355 & 356 Rachel Claire Kondro Theology Introduction Anyone who believes that clerical scandals are unique to recent decades need look no further than Saint Augustine‟s late-fourth and early-fifth century sermons and letters to refute that opinion. Although the precise details of clerical misconduct incidents vary depending upon historical and cultural contexts, the basic, underlying issues and impact upon the community do not. This article assesses and analyzes Augustine‟s public commentary on the topic of clerical scandal as recorded in Sermons 355 and 356. I argue that the principles guiding this discourse at the end of Augustine‟s life are the very same principles that defined his pastoral vocation as a young priest very recently and quite reluctantly ordained,1 and as the founder of multiple monastic communities. Specifically, I contend that concern for promoting charity and the common good are the two primary principles at work in Augustine‟s public handling of an incident of clerical misconduct involving one of his priests. First, the notion of the common good, or the salvation of the many, is epitomized in a brief, urgent letter Augustine addressed to the bishop who ordained him in 391. There, Augustine asks Valerius, “But how am I to exercise this ministry for the salvation of others, not seeking what is beneficial for me, but for the many, that they may be saved (1 Cor.
    [Show full text]
  • Four Basic Notions of the Common Good
    St. John's Law Review Volume 75 Number 2 Volume 75, Spring 2001, Number 2 Article 16 Four Basic Notions of the Common Good Brother Daniel P. Sulmasy O.F.M. Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.stjohns.edu/lawreview This Symposium is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at St. John's Law Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in St. John's Law Review by an authorized editor of St. John's Law Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. FOUR BASIC NOTIONS OF THE COMMON GOOD BROTHER DANIEL P. SULMASY, O.F.M.t INTRODUCTION I am delighted to be here among lawyers-it is a rare opportunity for a physician. I am very grateful to John Coughlin, my brother, for asking me to think about the common good. I told him that I never think about the common good and in trying to get me to be a better Franciscan he asked me to do so. I think it flows well from what Professor Harper just spoke to us about. I am going to talk about different ways of thinking about this term common good. The term is frequently tossed about these days, both inside and outside Catholic circles. The term "common good" has a lot of different kinds of meanings and they are not always clearly distinguished. I would like to try to bring a little more conceptual clarity by describing four basic notions of the common good. Each is going to have two subtypes; this makes it a little complex.
    [Show full text]
  • Democracy and the Common Good FINAL
    Democracy and the Common Good A Study of the Weighted Majority Rule Katharina Berndt Rasmussen ©Katharina Berndt Rasmussen, Stockholm 2013 ISBN 978-91-7447-738-2 Printed in Sweden by US-AB, Stockholm 2013 Distributor: Department of Philosophy, Stockholm University To Nika Contents 1 Introduction ............................................................................................... 11 1.1 Majority conundrums .............................................................................................. 11 1.2 The ubiquity of the unequal vote ............................................................................ 15 1.3 The value of democracy ......................................................................................... 17 1.4 Main thesis and disposition .................................................................................... 19 2 The basics ................................................................................................. 23 2.1 Introduction ............................................................................................................. 23 2.2 The weighted majority rule ..................................................................................... 23 2.2.1 The weighted majority rule and democratic theory ........................................ 25 2.3 Individual well-being and the common good .......................................................... 31 2.3.1 Individual well-being ......................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Why a Federal Wealth Tax Is Constitutional
    WHY A FEDERAL WEALTH TAX IS CONSTITUTIONAL ISSUE BRIEF BY ARI GLOGOWER, DAVID GAMAGE, AND KITTY RICHARDS FEBRUARY 2021 INTRODUCTION The 2020 Democratic presidential primaries brought national attention to a new direction for the tax system: a federal wealth tax for the wealthiest taxpayers. During their campaigns, Senators Elizabeth Warren (D-MA) and Bernie Sanders (I-VT) both introduced proposals to tax the wealth of multimillionaires and billionaires, and to use the revenue for public investments, including in health care and education. These reforms generated broad public support—even among many Republicans1—and broadened the conversation over the future of progressive tax reform. A well-designed, high-end wealth tax can level the playing field in an unequal society and promote shared economic prosperity. Critics have argued, however, that a wealth tax would be unconstitutional because of the Constitution’s apportionment rule, which requires certain taxes to be apportioned among the states according to their populations. These critics advance maximalist interpretations of the apportionment rule and reconstruct the rule as a significant limit on Congress’s constitutional taxing power. In response to these objections, this brief explains why these critics misinterpret the role of the apportionment rule, and why the Constitution grants Congress broad taxing powers that allow for a wealth tax, whether it is apportioned or not. The maximalist interpretations misapprehend the role of apportionment in the constitutional structure, and improperly elevate a peripheral rule into a major barrier to tax reform. This brief explains why constitutional history and Supreme Court precedents instead support a measured interpretation of the apportionment rule.
    [Show full text]
  • Supreme Court Riddle: Who Voted to Hear the Sports- Betting Case?
    Supreme Court Riddle: Who Voted To Hear The Sports- Betting Case? 22ND FEB 2018 | WRITTEN BY: TONY BATT The mystery surrounding the U.S. Supreme Court’s decision to hear New Jersey’s appeal of a federal sports-betting ban is almost as intriguing as how the court will rule on the case later this year. Out of 10,000 petitions for certiorari every year, the Supreme Court agrees to hear about 80 appeals, or less than 1 percent, according to the website FindLaw. For an appeal to overcome these astronomical odds, four justices must vote to hear the case. The votes are revealed in a private conference of the nine members of the Supreme Court. The least senior justice begins the voting process which continues according to seniority until the most senior justice’s vote is recorded. The votes are included in notes taken by the least senior justice who gives them to the clerk of the Supreme Court after the conference. New Jersey failed to gain four votes when the Supreme Court denied the state’s first sports-betting appeal on June 23, 2014. But three years and four days later, the Supreme Court announced it would hear New Jersey’s second sports-betting appeal and a ruling is expected before the end of June. The only justice who did not participate in the 2014 vote is Neil Gorsuch, who succeeded the deceased Antonin Scalia last year. Gorsuch seems to be at the top of the list of justices who might have voted to hear New Jersey’s appeal.
    [Show full text]