The New Classical Economics: Theory in the Slipstream of Neoliberalism
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Violence Cycle Theory Will Be Introduced in Analogy to the Praxeological Business Cycle Theory (According to Ludwig Von Mises)
The VOL. 19 | NO. 4 | 330–344 QUArtERLY WINTER 2016 JOURNAL of AUSTRIAN ECONOMICS THE PRAXEOLOGY OF COERCION: A NEW THEORY OF VIOLENCE CYCLES RAHIM TAGHIZADEGAN AND MARC-FELIX Otto ABSTRACT: As the first application of the praxeological discipline of “Cratics” (Taghizadegan and Otto, 2015), a theory of the supply and demand of bads is developed. On this foundation, a violence cycle theory will be introduced in analogy to the praxeological business cycle theory (according to Ludwig von Mises). Central to this approach are the subjective perceptions of threats and possible bluffs regarding the backing of those threats. Such a violence cycle theory can explain the stability of structures of violence and reveal new interpretations of the “long peace” hypothesis. KEYWORDS: Austrian school, praxeology, catallactics, coercion JEL CLASSIFICATION: B53 hose actions and things which render a marginal utility to men can be described as goods. In analogy, those actions and things Twhich cause to expect a “marginal disutility” can be described as bads. Catallactics, i.e., the economics of direct and indirect Rahim Taghizadegan ([email protected]) is director of the academic research institute Scholarium (scholarium.at) in Vienna, Austria, lecturer at several univer- sities and faculty member at the International Academy of Philosophy in Liech- tenstein. Marc-Felix Otto ([email protected]) is equity partner at the consulting firm The Advisory House in Zürich, Switzerland. Both authors would like to thank the research staff at the Scholarium for their help and input. 330 Rahim Taghizadegan and Marc-Felix Otto: The Praxeology of Coercion… 331 exchange, can describe the process of the interaction of men who mutually promise and transfer goods to each other. -
Orthodox and Heterodox Economics in Recent Economic Methodology
Erasmus Journal for Philosophy and Economics, Volume 8, Issue 1, Spring 2015, pp. 61-81. http://ejpe.org/pdf/8-1-art-4.pdf Orthodox and heterodox economics in recent economic methodology D. WADE HANDS University of Puget Sound Abstract: This paper discusses the development of the field of economic methodology during the last few decades emphasizing the early influence of the “shelf” of Popperian philosophy and the division between neoclassical and heterodoX economics. It argues that the field of methodology has recently adopted a more naturalistic approach focusing primarily on the “new pluralist” subfields of experimental economics, behavioral economics, neuroeconomics, and related subjects. Keywords: orthodoX, heterodoX, neoclassical, economic theory, economic methodology JEL Classification: A12, B41, B49, B50 Myself when young did have ambition to contribute to the growth of social science. At the end, I am more interested in having less nonsense posing as knowledge (Frank Knight, 1956). At the time I was finishing graduate school, there was no real “field” of economic methodology. There were of course methodological writings by influential economists (e.g., Robbins 1932, 1952; Friedman 1953; Samuelson 1964, 1965), but these works were seldom of the same intellectual quality as the research that had made these economists famous as economists. There were also brief discussions of economics in influential books on the philosophy of science (e.g., Hempel 1965, AUTHOR’S NOTE: This paper began as a lecture delivered at the XVII Meeting on Epistemology of the Economic Sciences, School of Economic Sciences, University of Buenos Aires, Buenos Aires, Argentina, October 6-7, 2011. It was subsequently published in Perspectives on epistemology of economics: essays on methodology of economics (Lazzarini and Weisman 2012). -
Collective Action and Rational Choice Explanations
Collective Action and Rational Choice Explanations Randall Harp University of Vermont 70 South Williams St, Burlington, VT 05401 [email protected] ABSTRACT In order for traditional rational choice theory (RCT) to explain the production of collective action, it must be able to distinguish between two behaviorally identical possibilities: one, that all of the agents in a group are each performing behaviors in pursuit of a set of individual actions; and two, that all of those agents are performing those behaviors in pursuit of a collective action. I argue that RCT does not have the resources necessary to distinguish between these two possibilities. RCT could distinguish between these possibilities if it were able to account for commitments. I argue that successful rational choice explanations of collective action appeal to commitments, and distinguish this way of explaining collective action from a general class of explanations called plural subject (or team reasoning) theories. I. INTRODUCTION One virtue of a good explanatory model is that it is capable of explaining why event � occurs rather than event �", for some domain of events � which is within the explanatory purview of the model. For certain domains of events, rational choice theory (RCT) is a good explanatory model in this respect. Given a set of actions �, where every � ∈ � is an individual action, RCT can be an important part of a good explanation for why agent � performed action �( rather than action �): namely, because � is rational, and because � judges that �( is more likely to produce a more highly-valued outcome than action �). As I argue in this paper, however, for another domain of events RCT is not a very good explanatory model. -
Behavioral Inattention
Behavioral Inattention Xavier Gabaix∗ December 4, 2017 Abstract Inattention is a central, unifying theme for much of behavioral economics. It per- meates such disparate fields as microeconomics, macroeconomics, finance, public eco- nomics, and industrial organization. It enables us to think in a rather consistent way about behavioral biases, speculate about their origins, and trace out their implications for market outcomes. This survey first discusses the most basic models of attention, using a fairly unified framework. Then, it discusses the methods used to measure attention, which present a number of challenges on which much progress has been done. It then examines the various theories of attention, both behavioral and more Bayesian. It finally discusses some applications. For instance, inattention offers a way to write a behavioral version of basic microeconomics, as in consumer theory, producer theory, and Arrow-Debreu. A last section is devoted to open questions in the attention literature. This chapter is a pedagogical guide to the literature on attention. Derivations are self-contained. ∗[email protected]. Draft chapter for the Handbook of Behavioral Economics, edited by Douglas Bernheim, Stefano DellaVigna and David Laibson. Comments solicited. Please email me if you see an important reference that's missing (including your own papers). I thank Vu Chau and Antonio Coppola for excellent research assistance. For comments and suggestions, I thank the editors of this Handbook, Hunt Allcott, and Gautam Rao. For sharing their with data, I thank Stefano DellaVigna, Josh Pollet, and Devin Pope. I thank the Sloan Foundation for support. 1 Contents 1 Motivation 5 2 A Simple Framework for Modeling Attention 6 2.1 An introduction: Anchoring and adjustment via Gaussian signal extraction7 2.2 Models with deterministic attention and action . -
Positivism and the Separation of Law and Economics
Columbia Law School Scholarship Archive Faculty Scholarship Faculty Publications 1996 Positivism and the Separation of Law and Economics Avery W. Katz Columbia Law School, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.columbia.edu/faculty_scholarship Part of the Business Organizations Law Commons, and the Law and Economics Commons Recommended Citation Avery W. Katz, Positivism and the Separation of Law and Economics, 94 MICH. L. REV. 2229 (1996). Available at: https://scholarship.law.columbia.edu/faculty_scholarship/610 This Essay is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Publications at Scholarship Archive. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of Scholarship Archive. For more information, please contact [email protected]. POSITIVISM AND THE SEPARATION OF LAW AND ECONOMICS Avery Wiener Katz* INTRODUCION The modem field of law and economics - that is, the application of economic analysis to legal subjects other than trade and business reg- ulation - is now over thirty years old, but it remains controversial in the legal academy and, to a lesser extent, in the profession at large. Since its beginnings in the early 1960s, the economic approach has pro- voked substantial opposition and antagonism. The sources of this resis- tance, however, are a matter of dispute. Many economists and economi- cally influenced lawyers attribute it to more traditional lawyers' reluctance to learn a new and unfamiliar set of concepts and techniques. Critics of the economic approach offer a variety of other explanations. Some are skeptical of the utility of abstract theoretical modeling in the social sciences,' others object to economics' central behavioral assump- tion of rational choice,2 still others criticize economics' supposed liber- tarian politics and ideological allegiance to laissez-faire. -
FALL 2015 Journal of Austrian Economics
The VOL. 18 | NO. 3 | 294–310 QUArtERLY FALL 2015 JOURNAL of AUSTRIAN ECONOMICS PRAXEOLOGY OF COERCION: CATALLACTICS VS. CRATICS RAHIM TAGHIZADEGAN AND MARC-FELIX Otto ABSTRACT: Ludwig von Mises’s most important legacy is the foundation and analysis of catallactics, i.e. the economics of interpersonal exchange, as a sub-discipline of praxeology, the science of human action. In this paper, based both on Mises’s methodical framework and on insights by Tadeusz Kotarbinski and Max Weber, a “praxeology of coercion,” or, more precisely, an analysis of interpersonal actions involving threats, is developed. Our investigation yields both a reviewed taxonomy of human action and a first analysis of the elements of this theory, which we term cratics. This shall establish the basis for adjacent studies, furthering Mises’s project regarding the science of human action. KEYWORDS: Austrian school, praxeology, catallactics, coercion JEL CLASSIFICATION: B53 Rahim Taghizadegan ([email protected]) is director of the academic research institute Scholarium (scholarium.at) in Vienna, Austria, lecturer at several univer- sities and faculty member at the International Academy of Philosophy in Liech- tenstein. Marc-Felix Otto ([email protected]) is equity partner at the consulting firm The Advisory House in Zurich, Switzerland. Both authors would like to thank the research staff at the Scholarium for their help and input, in particular Johannes Leitner and Andreas M. Kramer. 294 Rahim Taghizadegan and Marc-Felix Otto: Praxeology Of Coercion… 295 INTRODUCTION he Austrian economist Ludwig von Mises intended to re-establish economics on a deductive basis, with the subjective Tvaluations, expectations, and goals of acting humans at the center, following the tradition of the “Austrian School” (see Mises, 1940 and 1962). -
Hayek and the Departure from Praxeology
LIBERTARIAN PAPERS VOL. 2, ART. NO. 24 (2010) HAYEK AND THE DEPARTURE FROM PRAXEOLOGY JAKUB WOZINSKI* TIMES OF UNCRITICALLY ACCEPTING the application of methods of natural science to human science are seemingly gone. In the present age, we usually deal with so-called “crypto-positivism,” which revised certain assumptions, but is still stuck in the ideal of science professed more geometrico. Hans-Hermann Hoppe is a philosopher whose theoretical effort proves that the errors of naturalism and empiricism can be overcome only by praxeology based on a priori argumentation. Historians of philosophy very often note the influence that Epicurus had on Karl Marx. The title of his doctoral thesis was The Difference Between the Democritean and Epicurean Philosophy of Nature. The father of communism was especially interested in the theory of clinamen, i.e. a minimal indeterminacy in the motion of atoms. For Epicurus, this theory was supposed to form a basis for helping him avoid absolute determinism, whereas for Marx it served as an explanation for the exceptional role played by the leaders of the proletariat. Clinamen was an important part of the overall structure of the world and society. But even more relevant were atoms: discrete, undifferentiated elements forming individuals known to us from sensory experience. One may ask here: why do we mention Epicurus in a text that is supposed to deal with Hayek? It is because Epicurus played an important role in shaping his theory as well—indirectly and directly. Hayek’s epistemology and ontology are based directly on philosophical assumptions developed by the founder of the Garden. -
Three Dimensions of Classical Utilitarian Economic Thought ––Bentham, J.S
July 2012 Three Dimensions of Classical Utilitarian Economic Thought ––Bentham, J.S. Mill, and Sidgwick–– Daisuke Nakai∗ 1. Utilitarianism in the History of Economic Ideas Utilitarianism is a many-sided conception, in which we can discern various aspects: hedonistic, consequentialistic, aggregation or maximization-oriented, and so forth.1 While we see its impact in several academic fields, such as ethics, economics, and political philosophy, it is often dragged out as a problematic or negative idea. Aside from its essential and imperative nature, one reason might be in the fact that utilitarianism has been only vaguely understood, and has been given different roles, “on the one hand as a theory of personal morality, and on the other as a theory of public choice, or of the criteria applicable to public policy” (Sen and Williams 1982, 1-2). In this context, if we turn our eyes on economics, we can find intimate but subtle connections with utilitarian ideas. In 1938, Samuelson described the formulation of utility analysis in economic theory since Jevons, Menger, and Walras, and the controversies following upon it, as follows: First, there has been a steady tendency toward the removal of moral, utilitarian, welfare connotations from the concept. Secondly, there has been a progressive movement toward the rejection of hedonistic, introspective, psychological elements. These tendencies are evidenced by the names suggested to replace utility and satisfaction––ophélimité, desirability, wantability, etc. (Samuelson 1938) Thus, Samuelson felt the need of “squeezing out of the utility analysis its empirical implications”. In any case, it is somewhat unusual for economists to regard themselves as utilitarians, even if their theories are relying on utility analysis. -
Can Resources Save Rationality? “Anti-Bayesian”
Commentary/Lieder and Griffiths: Resource-rational analysis 31 want to draw inspiration from the theory of optimal feedback formalisms, and finding ways to decide which ones are more control, in which more precise control incurs greater metabolic applicable to particular settings. expenses at the organismal level (Todorov and Jordan 2002). The time scale over which resources are allocated.Attentioncanbe efficiently allocated in response to trial-to-trial variations in reward Can resources save rationality? or priority (Bays 2014;Sims2003;vandenBergandMa2018), in Anti-Bayesian updating in other words, on a timescale of seconds. By contrast, efficient neural “ ” codes are often assumed to be optimized with respect to natural sta- cognition and perception tistics (Barlow 1961;Laughlin1981), which vary on a much longer timescale. This distinction seems largely aligned with the one made under (1), with shorter timescales being associated with task Eric Mandelbauma, Isabel Wonc, Steven Grossb specificity. Resource-rational models are often non-committal and Chaz Firestonec about the timescales over which the optimization occurs. Recent work on efficient codes in nonstationary environments (Młynarski aBaruch College, CUNY Graduate Center, Department of Philosophy, New York, and Hermundstad 2018)holdspromiseforbridgingthedivide. NY10016; bDepartment of Philosophy, Johns Hopkins University, Baltimore, Learning to be resource-rational. A question that is not often MD 21218; and cDepartment of Psychological & Brain Sciences, Johns Hopkins asked is how resource-rational mechanisms are learned. The target University, Baltimore, MD 21218 article simply defines a constrained optimum and supposes that [email protected] “evolution, cognitive development, and life-long learning” have [email protected] somehow solved it, without saying how. -
Economic Theory, Ideal Types, and Rationality
Lansana Keita Economic Theory, Ideal Types, and Rationality Abstract: Contemporary economic theory is generally regarded as a scien tific or at least potentially so. The replacing of the cardinal theory of utility measurement by the ordinal theory was supposed to prepare the groundwork for economics as a genuine science. But in adopting the ordinal approach, theorists saw fit to anchor ordinal theory to axioms of choice founded on principles of rational behavior. Behavior according to these axioms was embodied in the ideal type model of rational economic man. This model served the basis for scientific explanation of the choices made by actual economic agents. I argue though that the postulate of rationality is a normative principle and that this compromises the scientific pre tensions of economic theory. Yet the theorist must rely on this principle to formulate predictive and explanatory theories. This raises questions as to whether it is possible that economic theory satisfy the same kind of scientific criteria set down for research in the natural sciences. I. It is generally assumed that of all the social sciences, econom ics is the most promising candidate for acceptance as a science. Theories in economics conform to the formal requirements de manded of theories in natural science in the sense that they possess basic postulates, axioms and laws whose function is to describe at a fundamental level some segment of the empir ical world particular to the discipline itself. Predictive and explanatory theories are then constructed from these posited axioms and postulates. For example, microeconomic theory which is founded on a set of axioms of choice purports to predict and explain the behavior of the consumer and that of the entre preneur. -
Praxeology As Law & Economics
Journal of Libertarian Studies Volume 18, no. 2 (Spring 2004), pp. 73Ð89 2004 Ludwig von Mises Institute www.mises.org PRAXEOLOGY AS LAW & ECONOMICS Josef Sima* [The law] has acted in a way contrary to its own end; it has destroyed its own object: it has been employed in abolishing the justice which it was supposed to maintain, in effacing that limit between rights which it was its mis- sion to respect, it has put the collective force at the service of those who desire to exploit, without risk and without scruple, the person, liberty, or property of others; it has converted plunder into a right, in order to protect it, and legitimate defense into a crime, in order to punish it. How has this perversion of the law been accomplished? What have been the consequences of it? Ð FrŽdŽric Bastiat1 The law & economics movement has become one of the most dynamic schools within economics. Its origin is often dated back to the University of Chicago in the 1950s and 1960s, but insights about the interconnections of economics and the law can be found in the works of earlier economists. OLDER APPROACHES TO LAW & ECONOMICS Despite this contemporary idea that the law & economics move- ments started in the 1950s, older scholarly works touched upon the problem of economics and the law, and make cases for other scholars *Deputy Department Chair, Department of Economic Policy, Prague Univer- sity of Economics; and Director for Publications, Liberalni Institut, Prague, Czech Republic. [email protected]. 1FrŽdŽric Bastiat, The Law, in FrŽdŽric Bastiat, Selected Essays on Political Economy (Irvington-on-Hudson, N.Y.: Foundation for Economic Education, 2001), p. -
Liberty, Property and Rationality
Liberty, Property and Rationality Concept of Freedom in Murray Rothbard’s Anarcho-capitalism Master’s Thesis Hannu Hästbacka 13.11.2018 University of Helsinki Faculty of Arts General History Tiedekunta/Osasto – Fakultet/Sektion – Faculty Laitos – Institution – Department Humanistinen tiedekunta Filosofian, historian, kulttuurin ja taiteiden tutkimuksen laitos Tekijä – Författare – Author Hannu Hästbacka Työn nimi – Arbetets titel – Title Liberty, Property and Rationality. Concept of Freedom in Murray Rothbard’s Anarcho-capitalism Oppiaine – Läroämne – Subject Yleinen historia Työn laji – Arbetets art – Level Aika – Datum – Month and Sivumäärä– Sidoantal – Number of pages Pro gradu -tutkielma year 100 13.11.2018 Tiivistelmä – Referat – Abstract Murray Rothbard (1926–1995) on yksi keskeisimmistä modernin libertarismin taustalla olevista ajattelijoista. Rothbard pitää yksilöllistä vapautta keskeisimpänä periaatteenaan, ja yhdistää filosofiassaan klassisen liberalismin perinnettä itävaltalaiseen taloustieteeseen, teleologiseen luonnonoikeusajatteluun sekä individualistiseen anarkismiin. Hänen tavoitteenaan on kehittää puhtaaseen järkeen pohjautuva oikeusoppi, jonka pohjalta voidaan perustaa vapaiden markkinoiden ihanneyhteiskunta. Valtiota ei täten Rothbardin ihanneyhteiskunnassa ole, vaan vastuu yksilöllisten luonnonoikeuksien toteutumisesta on kokonaan yksilöllä itsellään. Tutkin työssäni vapauden käsitettä Rothbardin anarko-kapitalistisessa filosofiassa. Selvitän ja analysoin Rothbardin ajattelun keskeisimpiä elementtejä niiden filosofisissa,