BROUWER VERSUS WITTGENSTEIN on the INFINITE and the LAW of EXCLUDED MIDDLE Ian RUMFITT Birkbeck College, University of London Ac

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

BROUWER VERSUS WITTGENSTEIN on the INFINITE and the LAW of EXCLUDED MIDDLE Ian RUMFITT Birkbeck College, University of London Ac Grazer Philosophische Studien 89 (2014), 93–108. BROUWER VERSUS WITTGENSTEIN ON THE INFINITE AND THE LAW OF EXCLUDED MIDDLE Ian RUMFITT Birkbeck College, University of London Summary Wittgenstein and Brouwer were agreed that some of the higher mathematics of their day rested upon a projection into the in nite of methods that legitimately apply only within nite domains. In this paper I compare and assess the di er- ent treatments the two philosophers give of problematic cases involving in n- ity. For Brouwer, certain claims about in nite sequences provide exceptions to the law of excluded middle; while Wittgenstein argues that the same claims are without sense, since for him the law of excluded middle is a criterion of being a proposition. I end the paper by outlining how the intuitionist might respond to Wittgenstein’s arguments. According to Herbert Feigl, who was with him on the day, Wittgenstein was provoked into returning to philosophy by hearing L. E. J. Brouwer’s lecture, ‘Mathematik, Wissenschaft und Sprache’, in Vienna on 10 March 1928 (see the quotation from Feigl in Pitcher 1964, 8n). While Wittgen- stein’s later writings reject several central Brouwerian theses, a compari- son between these thinkers is instructive. As I hope this paper will show, Wittgenstein accepts one of Brouwer’s key negative contentions—namely, that some of the higher mathematics of their day rests upon an illegitimate projection into the in nite of methods that properly apply only within nite domains. While they di er over the remedy, agreement on that nega- tive point and Wittgenstein’s close engagement with Brouwer’s positive theory belie the widespread view—inspired by a notorious obiter dictum in the transcript of a 1939 lecture—that, for Wittgenstein, ‘Intuitionism is all bosh—entirely’ (LFM 237).1 1. e account of intuitionism that directly precedes this dictum in the lecture notes (which were taken down by some students) is in any case eccentric. 1. e intuitionists on in nity Nowadays, under the in uence of the late Sir Michael Dummett, we are apt to associate the intuitionist critique of classical mathematics and logic with the adoption of veri cationist semantic theories, in which the meaning of a declarative sentence (henceforth, a statement) is given by specifying the conditions in which a speaker would be entitled to assert it, rather than by specifying the conditions under which it would be true. It is important to set these associations aside in reading the early intuitionists, for the founding fathers of the school were not veri cationists. In a paper of 1923, Brouwer wrote that ‘a complete empirical corroboration of the inferences drawn [about the “world of perception”] is usually materially excluded a priori and there cannot be any question of even a partial cor- roboration in the case of (juridical and other) inferences about the past’ (Brouwer 1923, 336). A veri cationist would conclude from that claim that talk about the past is meaningless; Brouwer, though, expressly holds that it is meaningful. Indeed, he allows that the laws of classical logic, including Excluded Middle, may validly be applied in reasoning about the world of perception, as long as we are able to think of the ‘objects and mechanisms of [that] world … as (possibly partly unknown) nite discrete systems’ (ibid., emphasis in the original). More exactly, it is the possibility of projecting ‘a nite discrete system upon the objects in question’ that is the ‘condition of the applicability’ of Excluded Middle to judgements concerning those objects. We see here a fundamental di erence between Brouwer and Dummett. For Dummett, the basic mistake of the classical mathematicians is that they apply a realist or truth-conditional semantic theory to the language of mathematics. For Brouwer, by contrast, their error was to apply distinctively classical logical rules ‘even in the math- ematics of in nite systems’, where the rules’ condition of applicability does not obtain. A. N. Kolmogorov, another pioneer of intuitionism, agreed with Brouwer. He understood Brouwer’s writing to have ‘revealed that it is illegitimate to use the principle of excluded middle in the domain of trans nite argument’ (Kolmogorov 1925, 416). As Brouwer’s reference to ‘in nite systems’ implies, the early intuition- ists did not impugn as unintelligible expressions, such as ‘the sequence of natural numbers’, that purport to designate in nite mathematical structures. ey did, however, claim that talk about such structures, if it makes sense at all, is disguised talk about the mathematical principles that characterize them. us, to say that the natural number sequence 94.
Recommended publications
  • Classifying Material Implications Over Minimal Logic
    Classifying Material Implications over Minimal Logic Hannes Diener and Maarten McKubre-Jordens March 28, 2018 Abstract The so-called paradoxes of material implication have motivated the development of many non- classical logics over the years [2–5, 11]. In this note, we investigate some of these paradoxes and classify them, over minimal logic. We provide proofs of equivalence and semantic models separating the paradoxes where appropriate. A number of equivalent groups arise, all of which collapse with unrestricted use of double negation elimination. Interestingly, the principle ex falso quodlibet, and several weaker principles, turn out to be distinguishable, giving perhaps supporting motivation for adopting minimal logic as the ambient logic for reasoning in the possible presence of inconsistency. Keywords: reverse mathematics; minimal logic; ex falso quodlibet; implication; paraconsistent logic; Peirce’s principle. 1 Introduction The project of constructive reverse mathematics [6] has given rise to a wide literature where various the- orems of mathematics and principles of logic have been classified over intuitionistic logic. What is less well-known is that the subtle difference that arises when the principle of explosion, ex falso quodlibet, is dropped from intuitionistic logic (thus giving (Johansson’s) minimal logic) enables the distinction of many more principles. The focus of the present paper are a range of principles known collectively (but not exhaustively) as the paradoxes of material implication; paradoxes because they illustrate that the usual interpretation of formal statements of the form “. → . .” as informal statements of the form “if. then. ” produces counter-intuitive results. Some of these principles were hinted at in [9]. Here we present a carefully worked-out chart, classifying a number of such principles over minimal logic.
    [Show full text]
  • Two Sources of Explosion
    Two sources of explosion Eric Kao Computer Science Department Stanford University Stanford, CA 94305 United States of America Abstract. In pursuit of enhancing the deductive power of Direct Logic while avoiding explosiveness, Hewitt has proposed including the law of excluded middle and proof by self-refutation. In this paper, I show that the inclusion of either one of these inference patterns causes paracon- sistent logics such as Hewitt's Direct Logic and Besnard and Hunter's quasi-classical logic to become explosive. 1 Introduction A central goal of a paraconsistent logic is to avoid explosiveness { the inference of any arbitrary sentence β from an inconsistent premise set fp; :pg (ex falso quodlibet). Hewitt [2] Direct Logic and Besnard and Hunter's quasi-classical logic (QC) [1, 5, 4] both seek to preserve the deductive power of classical logic \as much as pos- sible" while still avoiding explosiveness. Their work fits into the ongoing research program of identifying some \reasonable" and \maximal" subsets of classically valid rules and axioms that do not lead to explosiveness. To this end, it is natural to consider which classically sound deductive rules and axioms one can introduce into a paraconsistent logic without causing explo- siveness. Hewitt [3] proposed including the law of excluded middle and the proof by self-refutation rule (a very special case of proof by contradiction) but did not show whether the resulting logic would be explosive. In this paper, I show that for quasi-classical logic and its variant, the addition of either the law of excluded middle or the proof by self-refutation rule in fact leads to explosiveness.
    [Show full text]
  • 'The Denial of Bivalence Is Absurd'1
    On ‘The Denial of Bivalence is Absurd’1 Francis Jeffry Pelletier Robert J. Stainton University of Alberta Carleton University Edmonton, Alberta, Canada Ottawa, Ontario, Canada [email protected] [email protected] Abstract: Timothy Williamson, in various places, has put forward an argument that is supposed to show that denying bivalence is absurd. This paper is an examination of the logical force of this argument, which is found wanting. I. Introduction Let us being with a word about what our topic is not. There is a familiar kind of argument for an epistemic view of vagueness in which one claims that denying bivalence introduces logical puzzles and complications that are not easily overcome. One then points out that, by ‘going epistemic’, one can preserve bivalence – and thus evade the complications. James Cargile presented an early version of this kind of argument [Cargile 1969], and Tim Williamson seemingly makes a similar point in his paper ‘Vagueness and Ignorance’ [Williamson 1992] when he says that ‘classical logic and semantics are vastly superior to…alternatives in simplicity, power, past success, and integration with theories in other domains’, and contends that this provides some grounds for not treating vagueness in this way.2 Obviously an argument of this kind invites a rejoinder about the puzzles and complications that the epistemic view introduces. Here are two quick examples. First, postulating, as the epistemicist does, linguistic facts no speaker of the language could possibly know, and which have no causal link to actual or possible speech behavior, is accompanied by a litany of disadvantages – as the reader can imagine.
    [Show full text]
  • How the Law of Excluded Middle Pertains to the Second Incompleteness Theorem and Its Boundary-Case Exceptions
    How the Law of Excluded Middle Pertains to the Second Incompleteness Theorem and its Boundary-Case Exceptions Dan E. Willard State University of New York .... Summary of article in Springer’s LNCS 11972, pp. 268-286 in Proc. of Logical Foundations of Computer Science - 2020 Talk was also scheduled to appear in ASL 2020 Conference, before Covid-19 forced conference cancellation S-0 : Comments about formats for these SLIDES 1 Slides 1-15 were presented at LFCS 2020 conference, meeting during Janaury 4-7, 2020, in Deerfield Florida (under a technically different title) 2 Published as refereed 19-page paper in Springer’s LNCS 11972, pp. 268-286 in Springer’s “Proceedings of Logical Foundations of Computer Science 2020” 3 Second presentaion of this talk was intended for ASL-2020 conference, before Covid-19 cancelled conference. Willard recommends you read Item 2’s 19-page paper after skimming these slides. They nicely summarize my six JSL and APAL papers. Manuscript is also more informative than the sketch outlined here. Manuscript helps one understand all of Willard’s papers 1. Main Question left UNANSWERED by G¨odel: 2nd Incomplet. Theorem indicates strong formalisms cannot verify their own consistency. ..... But Humans Presume Their Own Consistency, at least PARTIALLY, as a prerequisite for Thinking ? A Central Question: What systems are ADEQUATELY WEAK to hold some type (?) knowledge their own consistency? ONLY PARTIAL ANSWERS to this Question are Feasible because 2nd Inc Theorem is QUITE STRONG ! Let LXM = Law of Excluded Middle OurTheme: Different USES of LXM do change Breadth and LIMITATIONS of 2nd Inc Theorem 2a.
    [Show full text]
  • Logic, Ontological Neutrality, and the Law of Non-Contradiction
    Logic, Ontological Neutrality, and the Law of Non-Contradiction Achille C. Varzi Department of Philosophy, Columbia University, New York [Final version published in Elena Ficara (ed.), Contradictions. Logic, History, Actuality, Berlin: De Gruyter, 2014, pp. 53–80] Abstract. As a general theory of reasoning—and as a theory of what holds true under every possi- ble circumstance—logic is supposed to be ontologically neutral. It ought to have nothing to do with questions concerning what there is, or whether there is anything at all. It is for this reason that tra- ditional Aristotelian logic, with its tacit existential presuppositions, was eventually deemed inade- quate as a canon of pure logic. And it is for this reason that modern quantification theory, too, with its residue of existentially loaded theorems and inferential patterns, has been claimed to suffer from a defect of logical purity. The law of non-contradiction rules out certain circumstances as impossi- ble—circumstances in which a statement is both true and false, or perhaps circumstances where something both is and is not the case. Is this to be regarded as a further ontological bias? If so, what does it mean to forego such a bias in the interest of greater neutrality—and ought we to do so? Logic in the Locked Room As a general theory of reasoning, and especially as a theory of what is true no mat- ter what is the case (or in every “possible world”), logic is supposed to be ontolog- ically neutral. It should be free from any metaphysical presuppositions. It ought to have nothing substantive to say concerning what there is, or whether there is any- thing at all.
    [Show full text]
  • 8 Nov 2012 Copies of Classical Logic in Intuitionistic Logic
    Copies of classical logic in intuitionistic logic Jaime Gaspar∗ 8 November 2012 Abstract Classical logic (the logic of non-constructive mathematics) is stronger than intuitionistic logic (the logic of constructive mathematics). Despite this, there are copies of classical logic in intuitionistic logic. All copies usually found in the literature are the same. This raises the question: is the copy unique? We answer negatively by presenting three different copies. 1 Philosophy 1.1 Non-constructive and constructive proofs Mathematicians commonly use an indirect method of proof called non-constructive proof: they prove the existence of an object without presenting (constructing) the object. However, may times they can also use a direct method of proof called constructive proof: to prove the existence of an object by presenting (constructing) the object. Definition 1. A non-constructive proof is a proof that proves the existence of an object with- • out presenting the object. arXiv:1211.1850v1 [math.LO] 8 Nov 2012 A constructive proof is a proof that proves the existence of an object by pre- • senting the object. From a logical point of view, a non-constructive proof uses the law of excluded middle while a constructive proof does not use the law of excluded middle. Definition 2. The law of excluded middle is the assertion “every statement is true or false”. ∗INRIA Paris-Rocquencourt, πr2, Univ Paris Diderot, Sorbonne Paris Cit´e, F-78153 Le Ches- nay, France. [email protected], www.jaimegaspar.com. Financially supported by the French Fondation Sciences Math´ematiques de Paris. This article is essentially a written version of a talk given at the 14th Congress of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science (Nancy, France, 19–26 July 2011), reporting on results in a PhD thesis [1, chapter 14] and in an article [2].
    [Show full text]
  • Three-Valued Modal Logic and the Problem of Future Contingents
    faculteit Wiskunde en Natuurwetenschappen Three-valued modal logic and the problem of future Contingents Bachelorthesis Mathematics August 2014 Student: R. C. Sterkenburg First supervisor: prof. dr. G.R. Renardel de Lavalette Second supervisor: prof. dr. H. L. Trentelman Contents 1 Introduction 3 2 Formulating the problem of future contingents 4 2.1 Aristotle's problem . .4 2.2 Criteria any solutions should meet . .5 3Lukasiewicz' three-valued system 7 3.1 The system . .7 3.2Lukasiewicz' system and the problem of future contingents . .8 4 The system Q 10 4.1 Prior's system Q . 10 4.2 Possible world semantics for Q . 14 4.3 Q and the problem of future contingents . 16 5 The system Qt 19 5.1 Expansion of Q to a temporal system Qt . 19 5.2 Qt and the problem of future contingents . 20 6 Conclusion 23 7 Literature 24 2 1 Introduction Consider the statement `It will rain tomorrow'. Is it true now? Or false? And if it is already true now, is it then possible that is does not rain tomorrow, or has the fact that it will rain tomorrow become a necessity? And if it is necessary, why do we perceive it as if it is not, as if it just as easily could not have rained tomorrow? And if we decide it is not true nor false now, is `it will rain tomorrow or not' then still true, or is that also neither true nor false? These questions were raised by Aristotle in the famous chapter 9 of his work Περ`ι `Eρµην"´ια&, De Interpretatione in Latin, and have come to be known as the problem of future contingents.
    [Show full text]
  • Modal Logic NL for Common Language
    Modal logic NL for common language William Heartspring Abstract: Despite initial appearance, paradoxes in classical logic, when comprehension is unrestricted, do not go away even if the law of excluded middle is dropped, unless the law of noncontradiction is eliminated as well, which makes logic much less powerful. Is there an alternative way to preserve unrestricted comprehension of common language, while retaining power of classical logic? The answer is yes, when provability modal logic is utilized. Modal logic NL is constructed for this purpose. Unless a paradox is provable, usual rules of classical logic follow. The main point for modal logic NL is to tune the law of excluded middle so that we allow for φ and its negation :φ to be both false in case a paradox provably arises. Curry's paradox is resolved dierently from other paradoxes but is also resolved in modal logic NL. The changes allow for unrestricted comprehension and naïve set theory, and allow us to justify use of common language in formal sense. Contents 1 Expressiveness of Language, No-no paradox1 2 Renements to classical logic2 2.1 Role of : in Rened Not-1' 6 3 Paradoxes of classical logic examined in NL6 3.1 Liar, Russell's, Barber paradox7 3.2 Curry's paradox, Then-4 7 3.3 No-no paradox8 3.4 Knower and Fitch's Paradox9 4 Conclusion 10 1 Expressiveness of Language, No-no paradox Ideally, logic underlies both language and mathematics. However, dierent paradoxes in logic, such as the liar paradox, Russell's paradox and Fitch's paradox[1], suggest expres- siveness of common language must be restricted.
    [Show full text]
  • Existence, Meaning and the Law of Excluded Middle. a Dialogical Approach to Hermann Weyl's Philosophical Considerations
    Existence, Meaning and the Law of Excluded Middle. A dialogical approach to Hermann Weyl’s philosophical considerations Zoe Mcconaughey To cite this version: Zoe Mcconaughey. Existence, Meaning and the Law of Excluded Middle. A dialogical approach to Hermann Weyl’s philosophical considerations. Klesis - Revue philosophique, Klesis, 2020, ”Le tiers exclu” à travers les âges, 46. hal-03036825 HAL Id: hal-03036825 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-03036825 Submitted on 14 Dec 2020 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Klēsis – 2020 : 46 – « Le tiers exclu » à travers les âges EXISTENCE, MEANING AND THE LAW OF EXCLUDED MIDDLE. A DIALOGICAL APPROACH TO HERMANN WEYL’S PHILOSOPHICAL CONSIDERATIONS Zoe McConaughey (Université de Lille, UMR 8163 STL, and UQÀM)1 Abstract Intuitionistic logic is often presented as a proof-based approach to logic, where truth is defined as having a proof. I shall stress another dimension which is also important: that of the constitution of meaning. This dimension of meaning does not reduce to proof, be it actual or potential, as standard presentations of intuitionistic logic put it. The law of ex- cluded middle sits right at the junction between these two dimensions, proof and mean- ing: in intuitionistic logic, there is no proof for the law of excluded middle, but the law of excluded middle is a proposition that does have meaning.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein's Diagonal Argument
    Chapter 2 1 Wittgenstein’s Diagonal Argument: A Variation 2 1 on Cantor and Turing 3 Juliet Floyd 4 2.1 Introduction 5 On 30 July 1947 Wittgenstein began writing what I call in what follows his “1947 6 2 remark” : 7 Turing’s ‘machines’. These machines are humans who calculate. And one might express 8 what he says also in the form of games. And the interesting games would be such as brought 9 one via certain rules to nonsensical instructions. I am thinking of games like the “racing 10 game”.3 One has received the order “Go on in the same way” when this makes no sense, 11 1Thanks are due to Per Martin-Löf and the organizers of the Swedish Collegium for Advanced Studies (SCAS) conference in his honor in Uppsala, May 2009. The audience, especially the editors of the present volume, created a stimulating occasion without which this essay would not have been written. Helpful remarks were given to me there by Göran Sundholm, Sören Stenlund, Anders Öberg, Wilfried Sieg, Kim Solin, Simo Säätelä, and Gisela Bengtsson. My understanding of the significance of Wittgenstein’s Diagonal Argument was enhanced during my stay as a fellow 2009– 2010 at the Lichtenberg-Kolleg, Georg August Universität Göttingen, especially in conversations with Felix Mühlhölzer and Akihiro Kanamori. Wolfgang Kienzler offered helpful comments before and during my presentation of some of these ideas at the Collegium Philosophicum, Friedrich Schiller Universität, Jena, April 2010. The final draft was much improved in light of comments providedUNCORRECTED by Sten Lindström, Sören Stenlund and William Tait.
    [Show full text]
  • Future Contingents, Non-Contradiction and the Law of Excluded Middle Muddle
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by University of Hertfordshire Research Archive Originally published in Analysis (Volume 64, No. 2, April 2004: 122-8). An extended version of this paper appears in chapter 3 of my A Future for Presentism (Oxford University Press, 2006) © Craig Bourne Future Contingents, Non-Contradiction and the Law of Excluded Middle Muddle For whatever reason, we might think that contingent statements about the future have no determinate truth value. Aristotle, in De interpretatione IX, for instance, held that only those propositions about the future which are either necessarily true, or necessarily false, or ‘predetermined’ in some way have a determinate truth-value. This led Łukasiewicz in 1920 to construct a three-valued logic in an attempt to formalize Aristotle’s position by giving the truth-value ½ = indeterminate to future contingents and defining ‘~’, ‘&’ and ‘ ’, where 1 = true and 0 = false, as: ~ 1 0 ½ ½ 0 1 Fig 1: Łukasiewicz Negation & 1 ½ 0 1 1 ½ 0 ½ ½ ½ 0 0 0 0 0 Fig 2: Łukasiewicz Conjunction 1 ½ 0 1 1 1 1 ½ 1 ½ ½ 0 1 ½ 0 Fig 3: Łukasiewicz Disjunction 1 Originally published in Analysis (Volume 64, No. 2, April 2004: 122-8). An extended version of this paper appears in chapter 3 of my A Future for Presentism (Oxford University Press, 2006) © Craig Bourne We can see that the purely determinate entries match the tables of the classical two-valued system; thus, what needs justification are the other entries. Let us take negation to illustrate. We may treat indeterminateness as something to be resolved one way or the other: it will eventually be either true or false.
    [Show full text]
  • Humans Do Not Reason from Contradictory Premises. the Psychological Aspects of Paraconsistency
    Synthese manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) Humans do not reason from contradictory premises. The psychological aspects of paraconsistency. Konrad Rudnicki Received: date / Accepted: date Abstract The creation of paraconsistent logics have expanded the boundaries of formal logic by introducing coherent systems that tolerate contradictions without triviality. Thanks to their novel approach and rigorous formaliza- tion they have already found many applications in computer science, linguis- tics and mathematics. As a natural next step, some philosophers have also tried to answer the question if human everyday reasoning could be accurately modelled with paraconsistent logics. The purpose of this article is to argue against the notion that human reasoning is paraconsistent. Numerous findings in the area of cognitive psychology and cognitive neuroscience go against the hypothesis that humans tolerate contradictions in their inferences. Humans experience severe stress and confusion when confronted with contradictions (i.e., the so-called cognitive dissonance). Experiments on the ways in which humans process contradictions point out that the first thing humans do is remove or modify one of the contradictory statements. From an evolutionary perspective, contradiction is useless and even more dangerous than lack of in- formation because it takes up resources to process. Furthermore, it appears that when logicians, anthropologists or psychologists provide examples of con- tradictions in human culture and behaviour, their examples very rarely take the form of: (p ^ :p). Instead, they are often conditional statements, proba- bilistic judgments, metaphors or seemingly incompatible beliefs. At different points in time humans are definitely able to hold contradictory beliefs, but within one reasoning leading to a particular behaviour, contradiction is never tolerated.
    [Show full text]