List of Papers for the 2020 Conference in Athens by Panel

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

List of Papers for the 2020 Conference in Athens by Panel List of papers for the 2020 conference in Athens by panel The Divine and the Natural World: Animals, Place, Time, and the Environment in the Platonic Tradition Crystal Addey <[email protected]>, Marilynn Lawrence <[email protected]>, and Rob Berchman <[email protected]> Jonathan Young <[email protected]>, University of Iowa, “Empedocles in the Company of Orpheus, Pythagoras, and Plato: the Births, Lives, and Destinies of Divine, Human, Animal, and Plant Souls.” Brittny Del Bel <[email protected]>, Memorial University of Newfoundland, “Consistency Amidst Controversy: Exploring the Nature of Plato's Animals through the Lens of the Tripartite Soul” Claudia Zatta <[email protected]>, American College of Greece, “From Animals’ Intelligence to God’s Innocence: Porphyry in de Abstinentia 3” Jenny Messenger <[email protected]>, University of St Andrews, “New Narratives: Plotinian Landscapes in the Poetry of Kathleen Raine” Marilynn Lawrence <[email protected]>, Independent Researcher, “Attuning to Hestia and Demeter: Practicing Neoplatonism in the Face of Ecological Disaster” Crystal Addey <[email protected]>, University College Cork, “On the Ecocentric nature of Theurgy and Divination in the Platonic Tradition: Relational Philosophy and the Environmental Crisis” Akindynos Kaniamos <[email protected]>, École Pratique des Hautes Études (EPHE, Paris), “Theurgic Eros and Astral Divinization in Proclus’ In Timaeum” Julio Cesar Moreira <[email protected]>, Pontifícia Universidade Católica de São Paulo, “The daemonic role in the Information of Matter” Proclus and Causes: problems in epistemology, ethics, and metaphysics Sara Ahbel-Rappe <[email protected]> Francois Lortie <[email protected]>, Independent Scholar, Translation Bureau of Canada, "The Encosmic Intellect. The Nature of Dionysus in Proclus' Theology." Andrew Mayo <[email protected]>, University of Michigan, “The TMA in Proclus' Commentary on the Parmenides” Saskia Aerts <[email protected]>, De Wulf-Mansion Centre for Ancient, Medieval, and Renaissance Philosophy, “Proclus on the Cognitive Self-motion of the Soul: A Reply to Aristotle” Tomasz Tiuryn <[email protected]>, University of Warsaw, “Boethius and the Neoplatonic conception of universals” Pablo Rodriguez <[email protected]>, Complutense University of Madrid, “Proclus' VI Hymn: a review of the hypostases of Hecate” Neoplatonism in the late Middle Ages: from Eckhart to Cusanus Oscar Federico Bauchwitz <[email protected]> and Claudia D’Amico <[email protected]> Clelia Attanasio <[email protected]>, University of Cambridge. “The Dionysian Role of Joseph and Benjamin in Richard’s Benjamin Major: Super-Theology and Negative Theology as Human Apex of God’s Understanding” Alessandra Beccarisi <[email protected]>, Università de Salento, “Neoplatonic sources of Meister Eckhart” Oscar Federico Bauchwitz <[email protected]>, Federal University of Rio Grande do Norte, “The topology of Abgeschiedenheit: the neoplatonism of Meister Eckhart” Christian Jung, <[email protected]>, Universität Wien, “Meister Eckhart’s Henology of Spirit” Claudia D’Amico <[email protected]>, Universidad de Buenos Aires, “Proclus and Cusanus’ Metaphysics of Possibility” Neoplatonic Procession and the East: Towards a Comparative Analytics Khashayar Beigi <[email protected]> Khashayar Beigi <[email protected]>, Loyola Marymount University, "Mani and Procession as Religion" Dmitry Biriukov <[email protected]>, National Research University Higher School of Economics, "Hierarchies of divine energies and created beings in the Palamite literature: Gregory Palamas and David Disypatos" Łukasz Piątak <[email protected]>, Adam Mickiewicz University, "Hurakhsh vs. Helios: The image of sun as compared between the prayers of Al-Suhrawardi and the Proclus' Hymns" Prophecy, Divination, and Foreknowledge in Neoplatonism: the God(esse)s of Providence Dylan Burns <[email protected]> and Danielle Layne <[email protected]> Dylan Burns <[email protected]>, “Origen of Alexandria on the Oracle to Laius” Duarte João Venâncio Dos Anjos <[email protected]>, Visions in Proclus and its relation to the threefold division of poetry” Andreea-Maria Lemnaru-Carrez <[email protected]>, “Into the cloven meads of Aphrodite. Empedocles' reception of φιλία as the cosmic force of unification in Iamblichus' De Mysteriis.” Andrei Man <[email protected]>, “Sextus Empiricus and Proclus on the divinatory sign” Christopher Sauder <[email protected]>, “Stoic notions of λόγος in Plotinus’ treatises on Providence” Pablo Rodríguez Valdés <[email protected]>, “Proclus’ Sixth Hymn: a review of the hypostases of Hecate” Neo-Platonic and Gnostic exegeses of late-antique divine revelations: Corpus Hermeticum, Chaldean Oracles, Gnostic revealed texts George-Florin Calian <[email protected]> and Nicola Spanu <[email protected]> Helmut Seng <[email protected]>, Goethe-Universität Frankfurt am Main, “Δύναμις in den Chaldaeischen Orakeln und der neuplatonischen Exegese” Nicola Spanu <[email protected]>, Lucian Blaga University, “The divine Father of the Chaldean Oracles in light of Proclus’ and Damascius’ oracular exegesis” Dimka Gicheva-Gocheva <[email protected]>, University of Sofia, “Philosophical concepts and pseudo-revelations – stirred or shaken in the Stobaei Hermetica?” Gabriel Andrés <[email protected]>, University of Gothenburg, “Are the gnostic beliefs for being non-Christian?” Robert Heller <[email protected]>, King's College London, “Hekate in Proclus and the Chaldean Oracles” Florin George Calian <[email protected]>, Lucian Blaga University, “Divine Revelation and Neoplatonism” Ida Soldini, <[email protected]>, Scuola dottorale in Scienze Religiose, Lugano, Svizzera, “Platone fu prima autore comico e poi filosofo?” Plotinus’ Metaphysics Damian Caluori <[email protected]> and D.M.Hutchinson <[email protected]> Damian Caluori, <[email protected]>, University of Edinburgh, “Plotinus on qualia and qualities in Enn. VI.1.10-12” D. M. Hutchinson <[email protected]>, St. Olaf College, “Plotinus on the Composition of Sensibles” Anna Zhyrkova <[email protected]>, Jesuit University in Krakow, “The Nature of Relation between Genera of Being and Genera of Becoming” Thomas Vidart,<[email protected]>, “The Stoic Genera and the Principles of the Intelligible according to Plotinus” Michèle Anik Stanbury <[email protected]>, Rheinische Friedrich-Wilhelms- Universität Bonn, “Plotinus on the Intellect as dúnamis in VI.2.20” Pauline Sabrier <[email protected]>, “Plotinus' Enn. VI.2 [43]: The Search for the Ultimate Constituents of the Intelligible Realm” Ina Schall <[email protected]>, University of Cologne, “Ideas of Individuals or Individual Ideas? Resolving Confusions” László Bene <[email protected]>, Eötvös Loránd University, Budapest, “Plotinus’ account of time in the treatise On the Genera of Being VI.1–3 [42–44]” Malena Tonelli <[email protected]>, UBA-UNLP, “Unity and multiplicity of the second hypostasis of Plotinus. The genres of being asconstitutive of Noûs.” Svetla Slaveva-Griffin <[email protected]>, Florida State University, “Plotinus on Soul and Number” Alberto Kobec <[email protected]>, De Wulf Mansion Center, Leuven, “'Neither Body nor Bodiless': A Plotinian Argument Against the Existence of a Single Genus of Substances and its Aristotelian Origin” Andrew Payne <[email protected]>, St Joseph’s University, “Abstract for “Elements of Intellect: Plotinus’ Use of ‘Stoicheion’ in Ennead VI.2” Michael Lessman <[email protected]>, Yale University, "The Role of Extension in Plotinus’ anti-Peripatetic Account of Eternity and Time" Riccardo Chiaradonna <[email protected]>, Roma Tre, “Plotinus and Aristotle’s Categories: the distinction of primary and secondary substances.” Neoplatonic Aesthetics Jean-Michel Charrue <[email protected]> Anne Sheppard <[email protected]>, Royal Holloway, University of London, “Neoplatonic views on Choral dancing” Lela Alexidze <[email protected]>, University of Tbilisi, “Actors, author, spectators as a play on the Stage in Plotinus” Achilleas A. Stamatiadis <[email protected]>, Villanova University, “Allegorical and aesthetic appraisals of an ancient goddess: the case in point of Lucretius’ ‘invocation to Venus’ in De Rerum Natura’s proem” Jean-Michel Charrue <[email protected]>, retraité , (ex) académie de Versailles, “Saint- Augustin: l'amour du beau, à propos des Confessions, l'amour des beautés de l'âme” Michele Abbate <[email protected]>, University of Salerne, “The very nature of neoplatonic thought about beauty as a ‘meta-aesthetics’” Panos Eliopoulos <[email protected]>, University of Ioannina, “Plotinus and the Stoïcs: the Aesthetics as a precondition for moral decision making” Sylvana Chrysakopoulou <[email protected]>, University of Ioannina, “How to achieve beauty: the spiritual exercise suggested by Plotinus in I, 6” Tomas N. Castro <[email protected]>, University of Lisbon, “The aesthetics experience in the metaphysics of pseudo-Dionysius the Areopagite” Marsilio Ficino as a Commentator Anna Corrias <[email protected]> and Stephen Gersh <[email protected]> Anna Corrias, [email protected], University of Cambridge and University of Toronto, “Marsilio Ficino as an Interpreter of the Doctrine of Transmigration” Stephen Gersh,
Recommended publications
  • Aquinas on Attributes
    CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by MedievaleCommons@Cornell Philosophy and Theology 11 (2003), 1–41. Printed in the United States of America. Copyright C 2004 Cambridge University Press 1057-0608 DOI: 10.1017/S105706080300001X Aquinas on Attributes BRIAN LEFTOW Oriel College, Oxford Aquinas’ theory of attributes is one of the most obscure, controversial parts of his thought. There is no agreement even on so basic a matter as where he falls in the standard scheme of classifying such theories: to Copleston, he is a resemblance-nominalist1; to Armstrong, a “concept nominalist”2; to Edwards and Spade, “almost as strong a realist as Duns Scotus”3; to Gracia, Pannier, and Sullivan, neither realist nor nominalist4; to Hamlyn, the Middle Ages’ “prime exponent of realism,” although his theory adds elements of nominalism and “conceptualism”5; to Wolterstorff, just inconsistent.6 I now set out Aquinas’ view and try to answer the vexed question of how to classify it. Part of the confusion here is terminological. As emerges below, Thomas believed in “tropes” of “lowest” (infima) species of accidents and (I argue) substances.7 Many now class trope theories as a form of nominalism,8 while 1. F. C. Copleston, Aquinas (Baltimore, MD: Penguin Books, 1955), P. 94. 2. D. M. Armstrong, Nominalism and Realism (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1978), pp. 25, 83, 87. Armstrong is tentative about this. 3. Sandra Edwards, “The Realism of Aquinas,” The New Scholasticism 59 (1985): 79; Paul Vincent Spade, “Degrees of Being, Degrees of Goodness,” in Aquinas’ Moral Theory, ed.
    [Show full text]
  • The Univocity of Substance and the Formal Distinction of Attributes: the Role of Duns Scotus in Deleuze's Reading of Spinoza Nathan Widder
    parrhesia 33 · 2020 · 150-176 the univocity of substance and the formal distinction of attributes: the role of duns scotus in deleuze's reading of spinoza nathan widder This paper examines the role played by medieval theologian John Duns Scotus in Gilles Deleuze’s reading of Spinoza’s philosophy of expressive substance; more generally, it elaborates a crucial moment in the development of Deleuze’s philosophy of sense and difference. Deleuze contends that Spinoza adapts and extends Duns Scotus’s two most influential theses, the univocity of being and formal distinction, despite neither appearing explicitly in Spinoza’s writings. “It takes nothing away from Spinoza’s originality,” Deleuze declares, “to place him in a perspective that may already be found in Duns Scotus” (Deleuze, 1992, 49).1 Nevertheless, the historiographic evidence is clearly lacking, leaving Deleuze to admit that “it is hardly likely that” Spinoza had even read Duns Scotus (359n28). Indeed, the only support he musters for his speculation is Spinoza’s obvious in- terests in scholastic metaphysical and logical treatises, the “probable influence” of the Scotist-informed Franciscan priest Juan de Prado on his thought, and the fact that the problems Duns Scotus addresses need not be confined to Christian thought (359–360n28). The paucity of evidence supporting this “use and abuse” of history, however, does not necessarily defeat the thesis. Like other lineages Deleuze proposes, the one he traces from Duns Scotus to Spinoza, and subsequently to Nietzsche, turns not on establishing intentional references by one thinker to his predecessor, but instead on showing how the borrowings and adaptations asserted to create the connec- tion make sense of the way the second philosopher surmounts blockages he faces while responding to issues left unaddressed by the first.
    [Show full text]
  • Marguerite Porete and the Annihilation of an Identity in Medieval and Modern Representations – a Reassessment
    CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by Sydney eScholarship “The World on the End of a Reed”: Marguerite Porete and the annihilation of an identity in medieval and modern representations – a reassessment. Francesca Caroline Bussey A thesis submitted in total fulfilment of the requirements of Doctor of Philosophy December 2007 School of Philosophical and Historical Inquiry Department of History University of Sydney Abstract This thesis presents a new assessment of the identity and historical significance of Marguerite Porete, burned for heresy in Paris in 1310, and reconnects her to a vigorous, lay, discourse community that threatened the authority of the later medieval church. The thesis argues that a bilateral annihilation of Porete as an historical subject has been brought about by medieval and modern representations, and that this has served to obscure the presence of a subaltern religious discourse in the period. The historiography of Porete has followed distinctive stages of development that reflect, and are affected by, concurrent advances in the study of medieval female religious participation. This interplay has led to the development of a particularly influential hermeneutics that serves to exclude Porete from her contemporaries. Analysis of documentation issuing from Porete‟s condemnation has similarly been influenced by hermeneutic issues that manipulate the ways in which Porete is perceived as an identity. This thesis challenges dominant representations of Porete in the scholarship and argues that Porete‟s identity and discourse reflect a particularly vigorous, fluid and cross-discoursed lay engagement with religiosity that has roots in the precocious socio-religious environment of the Southern Low Countries.
    [Show full text]
  • Normative Political Theology As Intensified Critique
    PENULTIMATE DRAFT : THE DEFINITIVE VERSION WAS PUBLISHED IN Political Theology https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/full/./ X.." Normative Political Theology as Intensified Critique David Newheiser The success of political theology as a field of study depends upon a basic ambivalence. For some, political theology consists in normative theological reflection upon politics, while for others it involves descriptive analysis of the way in which political and theological concepts influence each other.1 This methodological tension is a source of intellectual vitality, and it has allowed political theology to flourish in many corners of the university. However, those who are happy with descriptive analysis are often wary of normative theology. This is one dimension of the question that titles this symposium, “How theological is political theology?” If political theology really is theological, then some will conclude that it does not belong in departments of philosophy, politics, and religious studies. Some theorists are suspicious of normative political theology because they believe it undermines critical rationality. Stathis Gourgouris claims that religious faith constitutes an assertion of certainty that excludes critique. 2 Mark Lilla argues that theology subordinates rational inquiry to divine authority, and so it should be excluded from the public sphere.3 According to Giorgio Agamben, theological reflection on divine glory reinforces mundane government by neutralizing resistance. 4 In my view, however, these theorists neglect theological traditions that resist dogmatism through intensified critique. Because dogmatism is a genuine danger—and not only for religion—normative political theology offers an important contribution to the politics of pluralist societies. 1 Of course, the division between normative and descriptive modes of analysis is unstable: description depends upon normative judgements, while norms rely upon an account of the way things are.
    [Show full text]
  • John Duns Scotus's Metaphysics of Goodness
    University of South Florida Scholar Commons Graduate Theses and Dissertations Graduate School 11-16-2015 John Duns Scotus’s Metaphysics of Goodness: Adventures in 13th-Century Metaethics Jeffrey W. Steele University of South Florida, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd Part of the Medieval History Commons, Philosophy Commons, and the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Scholar Commons Citation Steele, Jeffrey W., "John Duns Scotus’s Metaphysics of Goodness: Adventures in 13th-Century Metaethics" (2015). Graduate Theses and Dissertations. http://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd/6029 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. John Duns Scotus’s Metaphysics of Goodness: Adventures in 13 th -Century Metaethics by Jeffrey Steele A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy College of Arts and Sciences University of South Florida Major Professor: Thomas Williams, Ph.D. Roger Ariew, Ph.D. Colin Heydt, Ph.D. Joanne Waugh, Ph.D Date of Approval: November 12, 2015 Keywords: Medieval Philosophy, Transcendentals, Being, Aquinas Copyright © 2015, Jeffrey Steele DEDICATION To the wife of my youth, who with patience and long-suffering endured much so that I might gain a little knowledge. And to God, fons de bonitatis . She encouraged me; he sustained me. Both have blessed me. “O taste and see that the LORD is good; How blessed is the man who takes refuge in Him!!” --Psalm 34:8 “You are the boundless good, communicating your rays of goodness so generously, and as the most lovable being of all, every single being in its own way returns to you as its ultimate end.” –John Duns Scotus, De Primo Principio Soli Deo Gloria .
    [Show full text]
  • CHAPTER 2.1 Augustine: Commentary
    CHAPTER 2.1 Augustine: Commentary Augustine Aurelius Augustinus Hipponensis (henceforth Augustine) was born in 354 A.D. in the municipium of Thagaste (modern day Souk Ahras, Algeria, close to the border with Tunisia). He died in 430, as the Arian1 Vandals besieged the city of Hippo where he was bishop, marking another stage in the demise of the Roman Empire. Rome had already been sacked in 410 by Alaric the Visigoth, but the slow decline of Roman grandeur took place over a period of about 320 years which culminated in 476 when Romulus Augustus, the last Emperor of the Western Roman Empire, was deposed by Odoacer, a Germanic chieftain. Augustine thus lived at a time which heralded the death knell of the ancient world and the beginnings of mediaeval western European Christendom.2 Augustine‘s great legacy to western civilization is that intellectually he united both worlds in drawing from the ancient thought of Greece and Rome and providing a Christian understanding of the intellectual achievements of the ancients. His new synthesis is a remarkable achievement even today and for those of us, who remain Christians in the West, our debates, agreements and disagreements are still pursued in Augustine‘s shadow.3 1 Arianism was a schismatic sect of Christianity that held the view that the Second Person of the Trinity, Christ, is created and thus does not exist eternally with the Father. 2 See J. M. Rist‘s magnificent Augustine: Ancient Thought Baptized, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2003. Rist notes that, ‗Despite his lack of resources he managed to sit in judgment on ancient philosophy and ancient culture.‘ p.
    [Show full text]
  • Jean Paul Sartre: the Mystical Atheist
    JEAN PAUL SARTRE: THE MYSTICAL ATHEIST JEROME GELLMAN Ben-Gurion University of the Negev Abstract: Within Jean Paul Sartre’s atheistic program, he objected to Christian mysticism as a delusory desire for substantive being. I suggest that a Christian mystic might reply to Sartre’s attack by claiming that Sartre indeed grasps something right about the human condition but falls short of fully understanding what he grasps. Then I argue that the true basis of Sartre’s atheism is neither philosophical nor existentialist, but rather mystical. Sartre had an early mystical atheistic intuition that later developed into atheistic mystical experience. Sartre experienced the non-existence of God. Jean Paul Sartre called himself a “material” atheist, one who not only believes that God does not exist but is profoundly aware of God’s absence. This is to be compared to a group of people who meet regularly at a coffee house in Paris. One evening Pierre does not come. The entire evening, those present feel Pierre’s absence, his absence is tangible, part of the scene, like the tables and the chairs. Pierre is missing. Just so, for Sartre, God’s absence is to be felt everywhere. God is missing. And since God is missing we are to feel the obligation to create ourselves in freedom. Within his program of material atheism, Sartre enunciated a critique of Christian mysticism. In his book on Jean Genet, Sartre defined “mysti- cism,” in general, as follows: “The quest for a state in which subject and object, consciousness and being, the eternal and the particular, merge in an absolute undifferentiation.”1 Elsewhere in the same book, Sartre characterizes Christian mysticism in particular as follows: “It is God who will attain himself in the mystical ecstasy, which is a fusion of the Subject and the Object.
    [Show full text]
  • Overturning the Paradigm of Identity with Gilles Deleuze's Differential
    A Thesis entitled Difference Over Identity: Overturning the Paradigm of Identity With Gilles Deleuze’s Differential Ontology by Matthew G. Eckel Submitted to the Graduate Faculty as partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy Dr. Ammon Allred, Committee Chair Dr. Benjamin Grazzini, Committee Member Dr. Benjamin Pryor, Committee Member Dr. Patricia R. Komuniecki, Dean College of Graduate Studies The University of Toledo May 2014 An Abstract of Difference Over Identity: Overturning the Paradigm of Identity With Gilles Deleuze’s Differential Ontology by Matthew G. Eckel Submitted to the Graduate Faculty as partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy The University of Toledo May 2014 Taking Gilles Deleuze to be a philosopher who is most concerned with articulating a ‘philosophy of difference’, Deleuze’s thought represents a fundamental shift in the history of philosophy, a shift which asserts ontological difference as independent of any prior ontological identity, even going as far as suggesting that identity is only possible when grounded by difference. Deleuze reconstructs a ‘minor’ history of philosophy, mobilizing thinkers from Spinoza and Nietzsche to Duns Scotus and Bergson, in his attempt to assert that philosophy has always been, underneath its canonical manifestations, a project concerned with ontology, and that ontological difference deserves the kind of philosophical attention, and privilege, which ontological identity has been given since Aristotle.
    [Show full text]
  • Pico, Plato, and Albert the Great: the Testimony and Evaluation of Agostino Nifo EDWARD P
    Pico, Plato, and Albert the Great: The Testimony and Evaluation of Agostino Nifo EDWARD P. MAHONEY Giovanni Pico della Mirandola (1463-1494) is without doubt one of the most intriguing figures of the Italian Renaissance. It is thus no surprise that he has attracted the attention of many modern scholars. By reason of the varied interests that are reflected in his writings, contrasting interpretations of Pico have been proposed.1 Our purpose here is not to present a new and different picture of Pico but, rather, to offer a contribution to one fruitful area of research pursued by some recent historians of philosophy, namely, Pico's debt to, and 1. For general presentations of Pico's life and thought, see the classic study of Eugenio Garin, Giovanni Pico della Mirandola: Vita e dottirina (Florence: F. Le Monnier, 1937); Garin's magisterial Storia della filosofia italiana, 2d ed. (Turin: G. Einaudi 1966), 1:458-495. Among more recent general accounts are Pierre-Marie Cordier, Jean Pic de la Mirandole (Paris: Debresse, 1958); Engelbert Monnerjahn, Giovanni Pico della Mirandola (Wiesbaden: F. Steiner, 1960); Paul Oskar Kristeller, Eight Philosophers of the Italian Renaissance (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1964), pp. 54-71; Giovanni di Napoli, Giovanni Pico della Mirandola e laproblemaύca dottrinale del suo tempo (Rome: Desclee, 1965); Charles Trinkaus, In Our Image and Likeness (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970), 2:505-526; and Henri de Lubac, Pic de la Mirandole: Etudes et discussions (Paris: Aubier Montaigne, 1974). 165 166 EDWARD P. MAHONEY use of, medieval philosophy in his overall philosophical enterprise.2 Of particular concern will be the influence of Albert the Great on Pico, which can be established by a connection that has apparently not been noticed by Pico's historians.
    [Show full text]
  • “Anselm of Canterbury,” Pp. 138-151 in Jorge JE Gracia and Timothy B
    Jasper Hopkins, “Anselm of Canterbury,” pp. 138-151 in Jorge J. E. Gracia and Timothy B. Noone, editors, A Companion to Philosophy in the Middle Ages. Malden, Massachusetts: Blackwell, 2003. Reprinted here by permission of the pub- lisher (Blackwell Publishing, Oxford, England). The short bibliography on pp. 150-151 is here excluded. Anselm of Canterbury JASPER HOPKINS Anselm (b. 1033; d. 1109) flourished during the period of the Norman Conquest of England (1066), the call by Pope Urban II to the First Crusade (1095), and the strident Investiture Controversy. This latter dispute pitted Popes Gregory VII, Urban II, and Paschal II against the monarchs of Europe in regard to just who had the right—whether kings or bishops—to invest bishops and archbishops with their ecclesiastical offices. It is not surprising that R. W. Southern, Anselm’s present-day biographer, speaks of Anselm’s life as covering “one of the most momentous periods of change in European history, comparable to the centuries of the Reformation or the Industrial Revolution” (1990, p. 4). Yet it is ironic that Anselm, who began as a simple monk shunning all desire for fame, should nonetheless today have become one of the most famous intellectual figures of the Middle Ages. And it is even more ironic that this judgment holds true in spite of the fact that he wrote only eleven treatises or dia- logues (not to mention his three meditations, nineteen prayers, and 374 letters). Anselm was born in Aosta, today a part of Italy but in Anselm’s time a part of the Kingdom of Burgundy.
    [Show full text]
  • Platonic Mysticism
    CHAPTER ONE Platonic Mysticism n the introduction, we began with the etymology of the word I“mysticism,” which derives from mystes (μύστης), an initiate into the ancient Mysteries. Literally, it refers to “one who remains silent,” or to “that which is concealed,” referring one’s direct inner experi- ence of transcendence that cannot be fully expressed discursively, only alluded to. Of course, it is not clear what the Mysteries revealed; the Mystery revelations, as Walter Burkert suggested, may have been to a significant degree cosmological and magical.1 But it is clear that there is a related Platonic tradition that, while it begins with Plato’s dialogues, is most clearly expressed in Plotinus and is conveyed in condensed form into Christianity by Dionysius the Areopagite. Here, we will introduce the Platonic nature of mysticism. That we focus on this current of mysticism originating with Plato and Platonism and feeding into Christianity should not be understood as suggesting that there is no mysticism in other tradi- tions. Rather, by focusing on Christian mysticism, we will see much more clearly what is meant by the term “mysticism,” and because we are concentrating on a particular tradition, we will be able to recog- nize whether and to what extent similar currents are to be found in other religious traditions. At the same time, to understand Christian mysticism, we must begin with Platonism, because the Platonic tra- dition provides the metaphysical context for understanding its latest expression in Christian mysticism. Plato himself is, of course, a sophisticated author of fiction who puts nearly all of what he wrote into the form of literary dialogues 9 © 2017 Arthur Versluis 10 / Platonic Mysticism between various characters.
    [Show full text]
  • The Trinitarian and Christological Minnemystik of the Flemish Beguine Hadewijch of Antwerp (Fl. 1240)
    HTS Teologiese Studies/Theological Studies ISSN: (Online) 2072-8050, (Print) 0259-9422 Page 1 of 10 Original Research The Trinitarian and Christological Minnemystik of the Flemish beguine Hadewijch of Antwerp (fl. 1240) Author: This article provides an original reappraisal of the notion of Minnemystik in the work of the 1,2 Johann Beukes 13th-century Flemish beguine Hadewijch of Antwerp (fl. 1240), with specific reference to its Affiliation: Trinitarian and Christological orientations. After an introduction to the nature and origins of 1Department of Philosophy, Hadewijch’s work, relating to the discovery of four extant manuscripts (MS.A [2879–2880], University of the Free State, MS.B [2877–2878], BS.C and the incomplete MS.D [385 II]) in Belgium in 1838, followed by an Bloemfontein, South Africa elucidation of the experience-driven epistemology of the Victorians Richard of St Victor (d. 1173) and Hugo of St Victor (1079–1141) as her key early scholastic influences, Hadewijch’s 2Center for the History of Philosophy and Science, Minnemystik is distinguished from Wesenmystik, as encountered in the mystical work of her Radboud University, French contemporary and beguine counterpart, Marguerite Porete (1250–1310). From this Nijmegen, the Netherlands discursive basis, Hadewijch’s Minnemystik is reassessed and represented as pertinently Trinitarian and Christological in orientation, and therefore as a theological (and not merely Corresponding author: Johann Beukes, an enticing ‘mystical-sexual’) presentation from the 13th century. [email protected] Keywords: beguine spirituality; experience-driven epistemology; Hadewijch of Antwerp Dates: (fl. 1240); Hugo of St Victor (1079–1141); Koninklijke Bibliotheek België; manuscripts MS.A Received: 29 Oct.
    [Show full text]