MATH 671 : Topology Homework Solutions

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

MATH 671 : Topology Homework Solutions Byeongho Ban [email protected] MATH 671 : Topology Homework Solutions :Taught by R. Inanc Baykur Lastly updated on May 10, 2019 Mathematics & Statistics University of Massachusetts, Amherst Byeong Ho Ban 1 MATH 671 Editor : Byeongho Ban Due date : September 18th, 2018 2.4 Let X be a topological space and let A be a collection of subsets of X. Prove the following containment. (d) ! [ [ Int A ⊇ IntA A2A A2A Proof. Suppose that [ x 2 IntA =) 9A 2 A such that x 2 IntA A2A =) 9U 3 x such that U is open and U ⊂ A: [ =) 9U 3 x such that U is open and U ⊂ A A2A ! [ =) x 2 Int A : A2A Therefore, ! [ [ Int A ⊇ IntA: A2A A2A Page 2 MATH 671 Editor : Byeongho Ban 2.1 Let X be an infinite set. (a) Show that T1 = fU ⊆ X : U = ; or X n U is finite.g is a topology on X, called the finite complement topology. (c) Let p be an arbitrary point in X, and show that T3 = fU ⊆ X : U = ; or p 2 Ug is a topology on X, called the particular point topology. (e) Determine whether T5 = fU ⊆ X : U = X or X n U is infiniteg is a topology on X. Proof. (a) Clearly ; 2 T1. Observe that X n X = ; is finite, so X 2 T1. Suppose that fUαgα2A ⊆ T1, where A is an arbitrary set. If Uα = ; for every α 2 A, [ Uα = ; 2 T1: α2A Suppose 9β 2 A such that Uβ 6= ;, then observe that ! [ \ X n Uα = (X n Uα) ⊂ X n Uβ : finite. α2A α2A Thus, [ Uα 2 T1 α2A and T1 is closed under arbitrary union. N Lastly, suppose fUngn=1 ⊂ T1. If X n Un is finite for all n = 1; 2;:::;N, observe that N ! N \ [ X n Un = (X n Un) : finite n=1 n=1 since finite union of finite sets is finite. Thus, N \ Un 2 T1: n=1 If 9j 2 f1; 2;:::;Ng such that Uj = ;, then N \ Un = ; 2 T1: n=1 Thus, T1 is closed under finite intersection. Therefore, T1 is a topology. Page 3 MATH 671 Editor : Byeongho Ban Proof. (c) Clearly ; 2 T3 and X 2 T3 since p 2 X. Let fUαgα2A ⊆ T3 where A is an arbitrary set be given. If Uα = ; 8α 2 A, [ Uα = ; 2 T3: α2A If 9β 2 A such that Uβ 6= ;, since Uβ 2 T3, we have p 2 Uβ. Thus, [ [ p 2 Uβ ⊆ Uα =) Uα 2 T3: α2A α2A Thus, T3 is closed under arbitrary union. N Let fUngn=1 ⊆ T3 be given. If Un 6= ; 8 n = 1; 2;:::;N, then p 2 Un 8n, thus N N \ \ p 2 Un =) Un 2 T3: n=1 n=1 If 9j 2 f1; 2;:::;Ng such that Uj = ;, N \ Un = ; 2 T3: n=1 Thus, T3 is closed under finite intersection. Therefore, T3 is a topology. (e) It is not a topology. Let y 2 X be given, and note that for each x 2 X, fxg 2 T5 since X n fxg is infinite. However, [ fxg = X n fyg 62 T5 x2Xnfyg since X n fyg 6= X and X n (X n fyg) = fyg is not infinite set. Thus, T5 is not closed under arbitrary union so T5 is not a topology. Page 4 MATH 671 Editor : Byeongho Ban 2.5 For each of the following properties, give an example consisting of two subsets X; Y ⊆ R2, both considered as topological spaces with their Euclidean topologies, together with a map f : X ! Y that has the indicated property. (a) f is open but neither closed nor continuous. (b) f is closed but neither open nor continuous. (c) f is continuous but neither open nor closed. (d) f is continuous and open but not closed. (e) f is continuous and closed but not open. (f) f is open and closed but not continuous. Proof. (a) Consider fa : A = B2(0; 0) n @B1(0; 0) ! B = B4(0; 0) defined by ( (x; y) if (x; y) 2 B1(0; 0); fa(x; y) = (2x; 2y) if (x; y) 2 A n B1(0; 0): Clearly, fa is not continuous. Note that fa(B 3 (0; 0)) = B1(0; 0) [ B3(0; 0) n B2(0; 0) is not closed. Thus, fa is not closed. 2 Observe that, for any U ⊂ A open, f(U) = (U \ B1(0; 0)) [ (2U \ (2A n B2(0; 0)) is open. So, fa is open. (b) 2 2 Consider fb(x; y): R ! R defined by ( (0; 0) x ≥ 0; fb(x; y) = (1; 0) x < 0: Clearly, fb is not continuous. Note that only possible images of fb are f(0; 0); (1; 0)g, f(0; 0)g, f(1; 0)g and ; which are closed. 2 2 2 Thus, fb is closed. However, since fb(R ) = f(0; 0); (1; 0)g is not open in R even if R is open, fb is not open. (c) 2 Consider the function fc : R ! R × f0g defined by 1 f (x; y) = ; 0 : c 1 + x2 + y2 2 2 Clearly, fc is continuous. However, note that fc(R ) = (0; 1] × f0g is neither open nor closed even if R is open and closed set. Thus, fc is neither open nor closed. (d) Consider X = B1(0; 0) and Y = B2(0; 0) and let fd : X,! Y be an inclusion map. Then clearly, fd is continuous open map. However, it is not closed since fd(X) = B1(0; 0) which is not closed even if X is closed and open. (e) 2 2 2 Consider fe : R ! R defined by fe(x; y) = (a; b) where (a; b) is a constant point in R . Then, clearly fe is continuous. 2 2 Also, since any possible image of fe is f(a; b)g or ;, it is closed map. However, since fe(R ) = f(a; b)g is not open even if R is open, fe is not open. (f) 2 Consider ff : R ! f(0; 0); (1; 0)g = A defined by ff = fb. Clearly, ff is not continuous. Note that any images of ff are open and closed in A at the sametime. Thus, ff is open and closed. Page 5 MATH 671 Editor : Byeongho Ban 2.6 Prove Proposition 2:30 (characterization of continuity, openness, and closedness in terms of closure and interior.) Proposition 2.30 Suppose X and Y are topological spaces, and f : X ! Y is any map. (a) f is continuous if and only if f(A) ⊆ f(A) for all A ⊆ X. (b) f is closed if and only if f(A) ⊇ f(A) for all A ⊆ X. (c) f is continuous if and only if f −1(B˚) ⊆ f −1˚(B) for all B ⊆ Y . (d) f is open if and only if f −1(B˚) ⊇ f −1˚(B) for all B ⊆ Y . Proof. (a) Suppose that f is continuous. Let A ⊆ X be given. Then, f −1 f(A) is closed. Also, observe that A ⊆ f −1 f(A) , so A ⊆ f −1 f(A) since f −1 f(A) is closed. Thus, observe that f(A) ⊆ f f −1 f(A) = f(A): Conversely, suppose that f(A) ⊆ f(A) 8A ⊆ X. And let a closed subset C ⊆ Y be given. Now, observe that f f −1(C) ⊆ f (f −1(C)) = C = C and that f −1(C) ⊆ f −1(C) ⊆ f −1 f f −1(C) = f −1(C): Therefore, f −1(C) is closed for any closed subset C ⊆ Y and so f is continuous. (b) Suppose that f is closed and let A ⊆ X be given. Observe that A ⊆ A, so f(A) ⊆ f(A): Note that f is closed map so f(A) is closed. Thus, f(A) ⊆ f(A): Conversely, suppose that f(A) ⊇ f(A) 8A ⊆ X and let a closed subset C ⊆ X be given. Now, note that f(C) ⊆ f(C) = f(C) ⊆ f(C): Thus, f(C) = f(C) and f(C) is closed. Therefore, f is closed map. Page 6 MATH 671 Editor : Byeongho Ban Proof. (c) Suppose that f is continuous and let a subset B ⊆ X be given. Since B˚ ⊆ B, note that f −1(B˚) ⊆ f −1(B): Since f −1˚(B) is a union of all open subsets of f −1(B) and f −1(B˚) is open, f −1(B˚) ⊆ f −1˚(B): Conversely, suppose that f −1(B˚) ⊆ f −1˚(B) 8B ⊆ X. Let an open subset U ⊆ X be given. And observe that f −1(U) = f −1(U˚) ⊆ f −1˚(U) ⊂ f −1(U): Therefore, f −1(U) = f −1˚(U), so f −1(U) is open, It implies that f is continuous. (d) Suppose that f is open and let B ⊆ Y be given. Then note that f(f −1˚(B)) is open and f(f −1˚(B)) ⊆ f(f −1(B)) = B, so f(f −1˚(B)) ⊆ B:˚ Since f is open, observe that f −1˚(B) ⊆ f −1(f(f −1˚(B))) ⊆ f −1(B˚): Conversely, suppose that f −1˚(B) ⊆ f −1(B˚) 8B ⊆ Y and let an open subset U ⊆ X be given. Now observe that U = U˚ ⊆ f −1(˚f(U)) ⊆ f −1(f(˚U)): And it implies that f(˚U) ⊆ f(U) ⊆ f(f −1(f(˚U))) = f(˚U): Thus, f(U) = f(˚U) and it means that f(U) is open. Therefore, f is open. 2.8 Let X be a Hausdorff space, let A ⊆ X and let A0 denote the set of limit points of A.
Recommended publications
  • [Math.DG] 1 Feb 2002
    The BIC of a conical fibration. Martintxo Saralegi-Aranguren∗ Robert Wolak† Universit´ed’Artois Uniwersytet Jagiellonski November 14, 2018 Abstract In the paper we introduce the notions of a singular fibration and a singular Seifert fi- bration. These notions are natural generalizations of the notion of a locally trivial fibration to the category of stratified pseudomanifolds. For singular foliations defined by such fibra- tions we prove a de Rham type theorem for the basic intersection cohomology introduced the authors in a recent paper. One of important examples of such a structure is the natural projection onto the leaf space for the singular Riemannian foliation defined by an action of a compact Lie group on a compact smooth manifold. The failure of the Poincar´eduality for the homology and cohomology of some singular spaces led Goresky and MacPherson to introduce a new homology theory called intersection homology which took into account the properties of the singularities of the considered space (cf. [10]). This homology is defined for stratified pseudomanifolds. The initial idea was generalized in several ways. The theories of simplicial and singular homologies were developed as well as weaker notions of the perversity were proposed (cf. [11, 12]). Several versions of the Poincar´eduality were proved taking into account the notion of dual perversities. Finally, the deRham intersection cohomology was defined by Goresky and MacPherson for Thom-Mather stratified spaces. The first written reference is the paper by J.L. Brylinski, cf. [6]. This led to the search for the ”de Rham - type” theorem for the intersection cohomology. The first author in his thesis and several subsequent publications, (cf.
    [Show full text]
  • TOPOLOGY and ITS APPLICATIONS the Number of Complements in The
    TOPOLOGY AND ITS APPLICATIONS ELSEVIER Topology and its Applications 55 (1994) 101-125 The number of complements in the lattice of topologies on a fixed set Stephen Watson Department of Mathematics, York Uniuersity, 4700 Keele Street, North York, Ont., Canada M3J IP3 (Received 3 May 1989) (Revised 14 November 1989 and 2 June 1992) Abstract In 1936, Birkhoff ordered the family of all topologies on a set by inclusion and obtained a lattice with 1 and 0. The study of this lattice ought to be a basic pursuit both in combinatorial set theory and in general topology. In this paper, we study the nature of complementation in this lattice. We say that topologies 7 and (T are complementary if and only if 7 A c = 0 and 7 V (T = 1. For simplicity, we call any topology other than the discrete and the indiscrete a proper topology. Hartmanis showed in 1958 that any proper topology on a finite set of size at least 3 has at least two complements. Gaifman showed in 1961 that any proper topology on a countable set has at least two complements. In 1965, Steiner showed that any topology has a complement. The question of the number of distinct complements a topology on a set must possess was first raised by Berri in 1964 who asked if every proper topology on an infinite set must have at least two complements. In 1969, Schnare showed that any proper topology on a set of infinite cardinality K has at least K distinct complements and at most 2” many distinct complements.
    [Show full text]
  • Paracompactness and C2 -Paracompactness
    Turkish Journal of Mathematics Turk J Math (2019) 43: 9 – 20 http://journals.tubitak.gov.tr/math/ © TÜBİTAK Research Article doi:10.3906/mat-1804-54 C -Paracompactness and C2 -paracompactness Maha Mohammed SAEED∗,, Lutfi KALANTAN,, Hala ALZUMI, Department of Mathematics, King Abdulaziz University, Jeddah, Saudi Arabia Received: 17.04.2018 • Accepted/Published Online: 29.08.2018 • Final Version: 18.01.2019 Abstract: A topological space X is called C -paracompact if there exist a paracompact space Y and a bijective function f : X −! Y such that the restriction fjA : A −! f(A) is a homeomorphism for each compact subspace A ⊆ X .A topological space X is called C2 -paracompact if there exist a Hausdorff paracompact space Y and a bijective function f : X −! Y such that the restriction fjA : A −! f(A) is a homeomorphism for each compact subspace A ⊆ X . We investigate these two properties and produce some examples to illustrate the relationship between them and C -normality, minimal Hausdorff, and other properties. Key words: Normal, paracompact, C -paracompact, C2 -paracompact, C -normal, epinormal, mildly normal, minimal Hausdorff, Fréchet, Urysohn 1. Introduction We introduce two new topological properties, C -paracompactness and C2 -paracompactness. They were defined by Arhangel’skiĭ. The purpose of this paper is to investigate these two properties. Throughout this paper, we denote an ordered pair by hx; yi, the set of positive integers by N, the rational numbers by Q, the irrational numbers by P, and the set of real numbers by R. T2 denotes the Hausdorff property. A T4 space is a T1 normal space and a Tychonoff space (T 1 ) is a T1 completely regular space.
    [Show full text]
  • Base-Paracompact Spaces
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector Topology and its Applications 128 (2003) 145–156 www.elsevier.com/locate/topol Base-paracompact spaces John E. Porter Department of Mathematics and Statistics, Faculty Hall Room 6C, Murray State University, Murray, KY 42071-3341, USA Received 14 June 2001; received in revised form 21 March 2002 Abstract A topological space is said to be totally paracompact if every open base of it has a locally finite subcover. It turns out this property is very restrictive. In fact, the irrationals are not totally paracompact. Here we give a generalization, base-paracompact, to the notion of totally paracompactness, and study which paracompact spaces satisfy this generalization. 2002 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved. Keywords: Paracompact; Base-paracompact; Totally paracompact 1. Introduction A topological space X is paracompact if every open cover of X has a locally finite open refinement. A topological space is said to be totally paracompact if every open base of it has a locally finite subcover. Corson, McNinn, Michael, and Nagata announced [3] that the irrationals have a basis which does not have a locally finite subcover, and hence are not totally paracompact. Ford [6] was the first to give the definition of totally paracompact spaces. He used this property to show the equivalence of the small and large inductive dimension in metric spaces. Ford also showed paracompact, locally compact spaces are totally paracompact. Lelek [9] studied totally paracompact and totally metacompact separable metric spaces. He showed that these two properties are equivalent in separable metric spaces.
    [Show full text]
  • Differential Geometry: Curvature and Holonomy Austin Christian
    University of Texas at Tyler Scholar Works at UT Tyler Math Theses Math Spring 5-5-2015 Differential Geometry: Curvature and Holonomy Austin Christian Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.uttyler.edu/math_grad Part of the Mathematics Commons Recommended Citation Christian, Austin, "Differential Geometry: Curvature and Holonomy" (2015). Math Theses. Paper 5. http://hdl.handle.net/10950/266 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Math at Scholar Works at UT Tyler. It has been accepted for inclusion in Math Theses by an authorized administrator of Scholar Works at UT Tyler. For more information, please contact [email protected]. DIFFERENTIAL GEOMETRY: CURVATURE AND HOLONOMY by AUSTIN CHRISTIAN A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Science Department of Mathematics David Milan, Ph.D., Committee Chair College of Arts and Sciences The University of Texas at Tyler May 2015 c Copyright by Austin Christian 2015 All rights reserved Acknowledgments There are a number of people that have contributed to this project, whether or not they were aware of their contribution. For taking me on as a student and learning differential geometry with me, I am deeply indebted to my advisor, David Milan. Without himself being a geometer, he has helped me to develop an invaluable intuition for the field, and the freedom he has afforded me to study things that I find interesting has given me ample room to grow. For introducing me to differential geometry in the first place, I owe a great deal of thanks to my undergraduate advisor, Robert Huff; our many fruitful conversations, mathematical and otherwise, con- tinue to affect my approach to mathematics.
    [Show full text]
  • Math 501. Homework 2 September 15, 2009 ¶ 1. Prove Or
    Math 501. Homework 2 September 15, 2009 ¶ 1. Prove or provide a counterexample: (a) If A ⊂ B, then A ⊂ B. (b) A ∪ B = A ∪ B (c) A ∩ B = A ∩ B S S (d) i∈I Ai = i∈I Ai T T (e) i∈I Ai = i∈I Ai Solution. (a) True. (b) True. Let x be in A ∪ B. Then x is in A or in B, or in both. If x is in A, then B(x, r) ∩ A , ∅ for all r > 0, and so B(x, r) ∩ (A ∪ B) , ∅ for all r > 0; that is, x is in A ∪ B. For the reverse containment, note that A ∪ B is a closed set that contains A ∪ B, there fore, it must contain the closure of A ∪ B. (c) False. Take A = (0, 1), B = (1, 2) in R. (d) False. Take An = [1/n, 1 − 1/n], n = 2, 3, ··· , in R. (e) False. ¶ 2. Let Y be a subset of a metric space X. Prove that for any subset S of Y, the closure of S in Y coincides with S ∩ Y, where S is the closure of S in X. ¶ 3. (a) If x1, x2, x3, ··· and y1, y2, y3, ··· both converge to x, then the sequence x1, y1, x2, y2, x3, y3, ··· also converges to x. (b) If x1, x2, x3, ··· converges to x and σ : N → N is a bijection, then xσ(1), xσ(2), xσ(3), ··· also converges to x. (c) If {xn} is a sequence that does not converge to y, then there is an open ball B(y, r) and a subsequence of {xn} outside B(y, r).
    [Show full text]
  • Isolated Points, Duality and Residues
    JOURNAL OF PURE AND APPLIED ALGEBRA Journal of Pure and Applied Algebra 117 % 118 (1997) 469-493 Isolated points, duality and residues B . Mourrain* INDIA, Projet SAFIR, 2004 routes des Lucioles, BP 93, 06902 Sophia-Antipolir, France This work is dedicated to the memory of J. Morgenstem. Abstract In this paper, we are interested in the use of duality in effective computations on polynomials. We represent the elements of the dual of the algebra R of polynomials over the field K as formal series E K[[a]] in differential operators. We use the correspondence between ideals of R and vector spaces of K[[a]], stable by derivation and closed for the (a)-adic topology, in order to construct the local inverse system of an isolated point. We propose an algorithm, which computes the orthogonal D of the primary component of this isolated point, by integration of polynomials in the dual space K[a], with good complexity bounds. Then we apply this algorithm to the computation of local residues, the analysis of real branches of a locally complete intersection curve, the computation of resultants of homogeneous polynomials. 0 1997 Elsevier Science B.V. 1991 Math. Subj. Class.: 14B10, 14Q20, 15A99 1. Introduction Considering polynomials as algorithms (that compute a value at a given point) in- stead of lists of terms, has lead to recent interesting developments, both from a practical and a theoretical point of view. In these approaches, evaluations at points play an im- portant role. We would like to pursue this idea further and to study evaluations by themselves.
    [Show full text]
  • Math 3283W: Solutions to Skills Problems Due 11/6 (13.7(Abc)) All
    Math 3283W: solutions to skills problems due 11/6 (13.7(abc)) All three statements can be proven false using counterexamples that you studied on last week's skills homework. 1 (a) Let S = f n jn 2 Ng. Every point of S is an isolated point, since given 1 1 1 n 2 S, there exists a neighborhood N( n ; ") of n that contains no point of S 1 1 1 different from n itself. (We could, for example, take " = n − n+1 .) Thus the set P of isolated points of S is just S. But P = S is not closed, since 0 is a boundary point of S which nevertheless does not belong to S (every neighbor- 1 hood of 0 contains not only 0 but, by the Archimedean property, some n , thus intersects both S and its complement); if S were closed, it would contain all of its boundary points. (b) Let S = N. Then (as you saw on the last skills homework) int(S) = ;. But ; is closed, so its closure is itself; that is, cl(int(S)) = cl(;) = ;, which is certainly not the same thing as S. (c) Let S = R n N. The closure of S is all of R, since every natural number n is a boundary point of R n N and thus belongs to its closure. But R is open, so its interior is itself; that is, int(cl(S)) = int(R) = R, which is certainly not the same thing as S. (13.10) Suppose that x is an isolated point of S, and let N = (x − "; x + ") (for some " > 0) be an arbitrary neighborhood of x.
    [Show full text]
  • DEFINITIONS and THEOREMS in GENERAL TOPOLOGY 1. Basic
    DEFINITIONS AND THEOREMS IN GENERAL TOPOLOGY 1. Basic definitions. A topology on a set X is defined by a family O of subsets of X, the open sets of the topology, satisfying the axioms: (i) ; and X are in O; (ii) the intersection of finitely many sets in O is in O; (iii) arbitrary unions of sets in O are in O. Alternatively, a topology may be defined by the neighborhoods U(p) of an arbitrary point p 2 X, where p 2 U(p) and, in addition: (i) If U1;U2 are neighborhoods of p, there exists U3 neighborhood of p, such that U3 ⊂ U1 \ U2; (ii) If U is a neighborhood of p and q 2 U, there exists a neighborhood V of q so that V ⊂ U. A topology is Hausdorff if any distinct points p 6= q admit disjoint neigh- borhoods. This is almost always assumed. A set C ⊂ X is closed if its complement is open. The closure A¯ of a set A ⊂ X is the intersection of all closed sets containing X. A subset A ⊂ X is dense in X if A¯ = X. A point x 2 X is a cluster point of a subset A ⊂ X if any neighborhood of x contains a point of A distinct from x. If A0 denotes the set of cluster points, then A¯ = A [ A0: A map f : X ! Y of topological spaces is continuous at p 2 X if for any open neighborhood V ⊂ Y of f(p), there exists an open neighborhood U ⊂ X of p so that f(U) ⊂ V .
    [Show full text]
  • Categories of Certain Minimal Topological Spaces
    CATEGORIES OF CERTAIN MINIMAL TOPOLOGICAL SPACES MANUEL P. BERRI1 (received 9 September 1963) The main purpose of this paper is to discuss the categories of the minimal topological spaces investigated in [1], [2], [7], and [8]. After these results are given, an application will be made to answer the following question: If 2 is the lattice of topologies on a set X and % is a Hausdorff (or regular, or completely regular, or normal, or locally compact) topology does there always exist a minimal Hausdorff (or minimal regular, or minimal com- pletely regular, or minimal normal, or minimal locally compact) topology weaker than %1 The terminology used in this paper, in general, will be that found in Bourbaki: [3], [4], and [5]. Specifically, Tx and Fre"chet spaces are the same; T2 and Hausdorff spaces are the same; regular spaces, completely regular spaces, normal spaces, locally compact spaces, and compact spaces all satisfy the Hausdorff separation axiom. An open (closed) filter-base is one composed exclusively of open (closed) sets. A regular filter-base is an open filter-base which is equivalent to a closed filter-base. Finally in the lattice of topologies on a given set X, a topology is said to be minimal with respect to some property P (or is said to be a minimal P-topology) if there exists no other weaker (= smaller, coarser) topology on X with property P. The following theorems which characterize minimal Hausdorff topo- logies and minimal regular topologies are proved in [1], [2], and [5]. THEOREM 1. A Hausdorff space is minimal Hausdorff if, and only if, (i) every open filter-base has an adherent point; (ii) if such an adherent point is unique, then the filter-base converges to it.
    [Show full text]
  • On Locally Trivial Extensions of Topological Spaces by a Pseudogroup
    ON LOCALLY TRIVIAL EXTENSIONS OF TOPOLOGICAL SPACES BY A PSEUDOGROUP Andre Haefliger and Ana Maria Porto F. Silva Abstract. In this paper we restrict ourselves to the particular case where the pseu- dogroup is Γ ⋉ G given by the action of a dense subgroup Γ of a Lie group G acting on G by left translations. For a Riemannian foliation F on a complete Riemannian manifold M which is transversally parallelizable in the sense of Molino, let X be the space of leaves closures. The holonomy pseudogroup of F is an example of a locally trivial extension of X by Γ ⋉ G. The study of a generalization of this particular case shall be the main purpose of this paper. Introduction Inspired by Molino theory of Riemmanian foliations [6], the general study of pseudogroups of local isometries was sketched in [4]. In the present paper we restrict ourselves to the study of the holonomy pseudogroups which appear in the particular case of Riemannian foliations which are transversally complete (see [5]). In this case, the holonomy pseudogroupF of the closure of a leaf is the pseudogroup Γ ⋉ G given by the action of a dense subgroup Γ of a Lie group G acting on G by left translations. Let X be the space of orbit closures of the holonomy pseudogroup of . Then, in our terminology, is a locally trivial extension of X by Γ ⋉ G andG it isF called a (Γ ⋉ G)-extension ofG X. We write ρ : Γ G for the inclusion of Γ in G. → This paper presents most of the results contained in the thesis of the second arXiv:1706.01551v1 [math.AT] 5 Jun 2017 author [10] and announced in [11], but, sometimes, with different notations and other proofs.
    [Show full text]
  • A First Course in Topology: Explaining Continuity (For Math 112, Spring 2005)
    A FIRST COURSE IN TOPOLOGY: EXPLAINING CONTINUITY (FOR MATH 112, SPRING 2005) PAUL BANKSTON CONTENTS (1) Epsilons and Deltas ................................... .................2 (2) Distance Functions in Euclidean Space . .....7 (3) Metrics and Metric Spaces . ..........10 (4) Some Topology of Metric Spaces . ..........15 (5) Topologies and Topological Spaces . ...........21 (6) Comparison of Topologies on a Set . ............27 (7) Bases and Subbases for Topologies . .........31 (8) Homeomorphisms and Topological Properties . ........39 (9) The Basic Lower-Level Separation Axioms . .......46 (10) Convergence ........................................ ..................52 (11) Connectedness . ..............60 (12) Path Connectedness . ............68 (13) Compactness ........................................ .................71 (14) Product Spaces . ..............78 (15) Quotient Spaces . ..............82 (16) The Basic Upper-Level Separation Axioms . .......86 (17) Some Countability Conditions . .............92 1 2 PAUL BANKSTON (18) Further Reading . ...............97 TOPOLOGY 3 1. Epsilons and Deltas In this course we take the overarching view that the mathematical study called topology grew out of an attempt to make precise the notion of continuous function in mathematics. This is one of the most difficult concepts to get across to beginning calculus students, not least because it took centuries for mathematicians themselves to get it right. The intuitive idea is natural enough, and has been around for at least four hundred years. The mathematically precise formulation dates back only to the ninteenth century, however. This is the one involving those pesky epsilons and deltas, the one that leaves most newcomers completely baffled. Why, many ask, do we even bother with this confusing definition, when there is the original intuitive one that makes perfectly good sense? In this introductory section I hope to give a believable answer to this quite natural question.
    [Show full text]