On Amenability of Constraint Satisfaction Problems

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

On Amenability of Constraint Satisfaction Problems On amenability of constraint satisfaction problems Michal R. Przybylek Faculty of Mathematics, Informatics and Mechanics University of Warsaw Poland [email protected] Abstract the theory) is crucial for our proof, as one can find coun- The authors of [22] showed that a constraint satisfaction terexamples to the claim in Intuitionistic Set Theories. problem (CSP) defined over rational numbers with their nat- These highly-theoretical results are of a great practical ural ordering has a solution if and only if it has a definable interest. Very many real-world decision problems of high solution. Their proof uses advanced results from topology computational complexity can be abstractly specified as the and modern model theory. The aim of this paper is threefold. classical constraint satisfaction problems (CSP): hardware (1) We give a simple purely-logical proof of their theorem verification and diagnosis: [9], [12], automated planning and and show that the advanced results from topology and model scheduling [10], [11], temporal and spatial reasoning [31], theory are not needed; (2) we introduce an intrinsic char- [7], air traffic managment [1], to name a few. Such problems acterisation of the statement “definable CSP has a solution are inherently finite. Although their computational cost is iff it has a definable solution” and investigate it ingeneral high (i.e. the problems are usualy NP-hard), they can be 2 intuitionistic set theories (3) we show that the results from solved in a finite time by a machine . This is in contrast with modern model theory are indeed needed, but for the implica- problems concerning behaviours of autonomous systems, tion reversed: we prove that “definable CSP has a solution iff where the classical variant of CSP is too restrictive. Such it has a definable solution” holds over a countable structure problems can be naturally specified as CSP with infinite sets if and only if the automorphism group of the structure is of variables (corresponding to the states of a system) and extremely amenable. infinite sets of constraints (corresponding to the transitions between the states of a system). These problems are, in gen- CCS Concepts • Theory of computation Constraint eral, undecidable — no machine can solve them in a finite and logic programming; time. In fact, depending on the choice of the specification lan- Keywords set theory with atoms, intuitionistic set theory, guage, such problems may be very high in the undecidability constraint satisfaction problem, Ramsey property, extremely hierarchy. For example, if we consider problems definable amenable group, Boolean prime ideal theorem in the First-Order theory of natural numbers, then every problem from the arithmetical hierarchy can be expressed as a definable CSP. Up until recently, we had known very little 1 Introduction about methods that can be used to solve infinite CSP. The In 1964 James D. Halpern [14] by using some combinato- first breakthought was at the begining of the century (see rial properties of the ordered Fraenkel-Mostowski model of [8] and also a survey article [6]), where researches applied set theory with atoms solved a long-standing open prob- algebraic and model-theoretic tools to analyze CSP over, so lem about independence of the Axiom of Choice from the called, infinite templates. This research inspired the Warsaw Boolean Prime Ideal Theorem. In 2015 Bartek Klin, Eryk Logical Group to investigate locally finite CSP — i.e. infinite Kopczynski, Joanna Ochremiak, and Szymon Torunczyk [22] CSP whose constraints are finite relations (see [22] and [27]). by using advanced results from topology and modern model They found that a locally finite CSP defined in the theory of theory, proved that in the ordered Fraenkel-Mostowski model rational numbers with their natural ordering can be solved of set theory with atoms an equivariant (constrained1) lo- effectively. cally finite constraint satisfaction problem has a solution if and only if it has an equivariant solution. In this paper we Example 1.1 (Finite memory machine). An important type prove that these two results are essentially the same, and, in of autonomyous systems has been defined by Kaminski, Michael fact, equivalent to many other well-known axioms/theorems and Francez [20]. The authors called these type of systems “fi- of Boolean Set Theories. The assertion of Booleaness of the nite memory machines”, or “register machines”. A finite mem- Set Theory (i.e. that the law of excluded middle holds inside ory machine is a finite automaton augmented with a finite number of registers '8 that can store natural numbers. The 1Every variable appears in at least one constraint. movement of the machine can depend on the control state, on the letter and on the content of the registers. The dependency on , ver. 1.2, 2020 2020. 2For a general reference on solving classical CSP see: [32] 1 , ver. 1.2, 2020 Michal R. Przybylek '1 B = This graph is known as infinite Kneser graph [22]. An example = < '1? '2 B '1 of a (constrained) locally finite CSP problem is the question whether a graph like G is 3-colorable. By the compactness of the first-order logic G is 3-colorable if and only if every start ( finite subgraph of G is 3-colorable. Figure 2 exhibits an ex- ample of a finite subgraph of G which cannot be colored by three colors fred, green, blueg. Theorem 19 in [22] implies that ' = 3-colourability of any graph generated by finite memory ma- = ' 2 B < 2? chines can be solved effectively. '1 B '2 Figure 1. A non-deterministic machine with two registers and a single control state (. SET PASSW ' , , : 1 2 5 1 = G , 2 5 START , , 3 1 1 4 ' < G ? , ' 2, 3 4, 5 := ? 4, 2 5, 3 , 3 4 ' : ' < G? ' < G? = AUTH AUTH AUTH G TRY 1 TRY 2 TRY 3 Figure 2. A finite counterexample to 3-colorability of infinite ' Kneser graph. = ' G ? = ? G G = ? ' the content of the registers is, however, limited — the machine GRANT can only test for equality (no formulas involving successor, AUTH addition, multiplication, etc. are allowed). Figure 1 shows a 2-register machine with a single control state (. This machine starts with a given content of the registers '1 and '2 and then at every step non-deterministically chooses a register '8 and a natural number = such that = < '8 . Value = EXIT CHNG AUTH PASSW is then stored in register '8 , whilst register '1−8 gets the value previously stored in '8 . Observe that in contrast to finite automata, the graph of Figure 3. A register machine that models access control to possible configurations in the machine from Figure 1 is infinite. some parts of the system. If we run the machine with '8 B 8, then its states + (i.e. single control state ( together with the content of the registers) will Example 1.2 . Continuing span an infinite graph G = h+, 퐸i with edges 퐸 induced by the (Access-control register machine) Example 1.1, Figure 3 presents an example of a finite memory movements of the machine: machine with one register ', whose task is to model access + = f¹(, =,<º : = 2 '1,< 2 '2g control to the red part of the system. The machine starts in 0 0 0 0 control state “SET PASW”, where it awaits for the user to pro- 퐸 = f¹¹(, =,<º, ¹(, = ,< ºº 2 + × + : ¹= = < ^ < < = º vide a password G. This password is then stored in register ', = <0 < =0 _ ¹ < ^ = ºg and the machine enters control state “START”. Inside the blue rectangle the machine can perform actions that do not require 2 On amenability of constraint satisfaction problems , ver. 1.2, 2020 authentication, whereas the actions that require authentication Tychonoff topology) is extremely amenable3 by the main theo- are presented inside the red rectangle. The red rectangle can rem in [28]. be entered by the control state “GRANT AUTH”, which can be accessed from one of three authentication states. In order to Example 1.4 (Rational numbers with finitely many con- Q t & authorise, the machine moves to control state “AUTH TRY 1”, stants). Let 0 be the structure from Example 1.3 over an @ 2 & where it gets input G from the user. If the input is the same extended signature consisting of all constants 0 for some & ⊆ & as the value previously stored in register ', then the machine finite 0 . Like in the previous example, the first order Q t & l enters control state “GRANT AUTH”. Otherwise, it moves to theory of 0 is -categorical and the topological group of ¹Q t & º control state “AUTH TRY 2” and repeats the procedure. Upon automorphisms Aut 0 is extremely amenable. second unsuccessful authorisation, the machine moves to con- Example 1.5 (Ordered vector space). Let 퐻퐹 be the free @0- trol state “AUTH TRY 3”. But if the user provides a wrong dimensional vector space over a finite field 퐹. By definition 퐻 password when the machine is in control state “AUTH TRY 3”, has a base that can be enumerated by any countable set. There- ' the register is erased (replaced with a value that is outside of fore, we can assume that there is a base hU@i@2Q enumerated the user’s alphabet) — preventing the machine to reach any of by rational numbers4 @ 2 Q. In fact we can give an explicit the control states from the red rectangle. Inside the red rectan- description of space 퐻퐹 with its standard base as follows. Let gle any action that requires authentication can be performed. & us identify 퐻퐹 with a subspace of 퐹 consisting of functions For example, the user may request the change of the password. that have finite support — i.e. functions E : & ! 퐹 with the Example of problems that we may like to ask, which can be property that the set f@ 2 & : E ¹@º < 0g is finite.
Recommended publications
  • Structural Reflection and the Ultimate L As the True, Noumenal Universe Of
    Scuola Normale Superiore di Pisa CLASSE DI LETTERE Corso di Perfezionamento in Filosofia PHD degree in Philosophy Structural Reflection and the Ultimate L as the true, noumenal universe of mathematics Candidato: Relatore: Emanuele Gambetta Prof.- Massimo Mugnai anno accademico 2015-2016 Structural Reflection and the Ultimate L as the true noumenal universe of mathematics Emanuele Gambetta Contents 1. Introduction 7 Chapter 1. The Dream of Completeness 19 0.1. Preliminaries to this chapter 19 1. G¨odel'stheorems 20 1.1. Prerequisites to this section 20 1.2. Preliminaries to this section 21 1.3. Brief introduction to unprovable truths that are mathematically interesting 22 1.4. Unprovable mathematical statements that are mathematically interesting 27 1.5. Notions of computability, Turing's universe and Intuitionism 32 1.6. G¨odel'ssentences undecidable within PA 45 2. Transfinite Progressions 54 2.1. Preliminaries to this section 54 2.2. Gottlob Frege's definite descriptions and completeness 55 2.3. Transfinite progressions 59 3. Set theory 65 3.1. Preliminaries to this section 65 3.2. Prerequisites: ZFC axioms, ordinal and cardinal numbers 67 3.3. Reduction of all systems of numbers to the notion of set 71 3.4. The first large cardinal numbers and the Constructible universe L 76 3.5. Descriptive set theory, the axioms of determinacy and Luzin's problem formulated in second-order arithmetic 84 3 4 CONTENTS 3.6. The method of forcing and Paul Cohen's independence proof 95 3.7. Forcing Axioms, BPFA assumed as a phenomenal solution to the continuum hypothesis and a Kantian metaphysical distinction 103 3.8.
    [Show full text]
  • The Journal of Symbolic Logic a Definable Nonstandard Model of the Reals
    Sh:825 The Journal of Symbolic Logic http://journals.cambridge.org/JSL Additional services for The Journal of Symbolic Logic: Email alerts: Click here Subscriptions: Click here Commercial reprints: Click here Terms of use : Click here A denable nonstandard model of the reals Vladimir Kanovei and Saharon Shelah The Journal of Symbolic Logic / Volume 69 / Issue 01 / March 2004, pp 159 - 164 DOI: 10.2178/jsl/1080938834, Published online: 12 March 2014 Link to this article: http://journals.cambridge.org/abstract_S0022481200008094 How to cite this article: Vladimir Kanovei and Saharon Shelah (2004). A denable nonstandard model of the reals . The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 69, pp 159-164 doi:10.2178/jsl/1080938834 Request Permissions : Click here Downloaded from http://journals.cambridge.org/JSL, IP address: 128.210.126.199 on 19 May 2015 Sh:825 THE JOURNAL OF SYMBOLIC LOGIC Volume 69, Number 1. March 2004 A DEFINABLE NONSTANDARD MODEL OF THE REALS VLADIMIR KANOVEIf AND SAHARON SHELAH * Abstract. We prove, in ZFC, the existence of a definable, countably saturated elementary extension of the reals. §1. Introduction. It seems that it has been taken for granted that there is no distinguished, definable nonstandard model of the reals. (This means a countably saturated elementary extension of the reals.) Of course if V = L then there is such an extension (just take the first one in the sense of the canonical well-ordering of L), but we mean the existence provably in ZFC. There were good reasons for this: without Choice we cannot prove the existence of any elementary extension of the reals containing an infinitely large integer.' 2 Still there is one.
    [Show full text]
  • Extending Modal Logic
    Extending Modal Logic Maarten de Rijke Extending Modal Logic ILLC Dissertation Series 1993-4 institute [brlogic, language andcomputation For further information about ILLC-publications, please contact: Institute for Logic, Language and Computation Universiteit van Amsterdam Plantage Muidergracht 24 1018 TV Amsterdam phone: +31-20-5256090 fax: +31—20-5255101 e-mail: [email protected] Extending Modal Logic Academisch Proefschrift ter verkrijging van de graad van doctor aan de Universiteit van Amsterdam, op gezag van de Rector Magnificus Prof. Dr. P.W.M. de Meijer in het openbaar te verdedigen in de Aula der Universiteit (Oude Lutherse Kerk, ingang Singel 411, hoek Spui) op vrijdag 3 december 1993 te 15.00 uur door Maarten de Rijke geboren te Vlissingen. Promotor: Prof.dr. J.F.A.K. van Benthem Faculteit Wiskunde en Informatica Universiteit van Amsterdam Plantage Muidergracht 24 1018 TV Amsterdam The investigations were supported by the Philosophy Research Foundation (SWON), which is subsidized by the Netherlands Organization for Scientific Research (NWO). Copyright © 1993 by ‘.\/Iaarten de Rijke Cover design by Han Koster. Typeset in LATEXbythe author. Camera-ready copy produced at the Faculteit der Wiskunde en Informatica, Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam. Printed and bound by Haveka B.V., Alblasserdam. ISBN: 90-800 769—9—6 Contents Acknowledgments vii I Introduction 1 1 What this dissertation is about 3 1.1 Modal logic . 3 1.2 Extending modal logic . 3 1.3 A look ahead . 4 2 What is Modal Logic? 6 2.1 Introduction . 6 2.2 A framework for modal logic 7 2.3 Examples . 10 2.4 Questions and comments .
    [Show full text]
  • Relation 2016 08 27.Pdf
    For updated version of this document see http://imechanica.org/node/19709 Zhigang Suo RELATION Binary Relation Relation. A binary relation is a collection of ordered pairs. If there is no danger for confusion, we will simply call a binary relation a relation. Thus, a relation is a set, each element of which is an ordered pair. If an ordered pair x,y belongs to a relation R, we write ( ) x,y ∈R . ( ) We say that the items x and y stand in the relation R. Specify a relation by a collection of ordered pairs. We specify a relation in the same way as we specify any set, by specifying the elements of the set. Here is a collection of three ordered pairs: red, blue , conservative, libral , elephant, donkey . {( ) ( ) ( )} Do we call this collection a relation? Yes, any collection of any ordered pairs defines a relation. This set may or may not be a useful relation, but it surely fits the definition of a relation. We can, of course, try to discover the “meaning” of this relation, or the property that specifies this relation. But we do not have to do anything to call the set a relation. Specify a relation by a property. This said, we do want to know the “meaning” of a relation. Like a useful set, a useful relation is often specified by a property, a rule that picks the ordered pairs in the relation. Consider a collection of two ordered pairs: Lisa, Eric , Daniel, Michael . {( ) ( )} By talking to the people, we learn that this relation is specified by a property: each ordered pair is a pair of siblings.
    [Show full text]
  • A Characterization of Finitary Bisimulation Basic Research in Computer Science
    BRICS Basic Research in Computer Science BRICS RS-97-26 Aceto & Ing A Characterization of Finitary Bisimulation olfsd ´ ottir: A Characterization of Finitary Bisimulation ´ Luca Aceto Anna Ingolfsd´ ottir´ BRICS Report Series RS-97-26 ISSN 0909-0878 October 1997 Copyright c 1997, BRICS, Department of Computer Science University of Aarhus. All rights reserved. Reproduction of all or part of this work is permitted for educational or research use on condition that this copyright notice is included in any copy. See back inner page for a list of recent BRICS Report Series publications. Copies may be obtained by contacting: BRICS Department of Computer Science University of Aarhus Ny Munkegade, building 540 DK–8000 Aarhus C Denmark Telephone: +45 8942 3360 Telefax: +45 8942 3255 Internet: [email protected] BRICS publications are in general accessible through the World Wide Web and anonymous FTP through these URLs: http://www.brics.dk ftp://ftp.brics.dk This document in subdirectory RS/97/26/ A Characterization of Finitary Bisimulation Luca Aceto∗ † BRICS, Department of Computer Science, Aalborg University Fredrik Bajersvej 7E, 9220 Aalborg Ø, Denmark Email: [email protected] Anna Ing´olfsd´ottir‡ Dipartimento di Sistemi ed Informatica, Universit`a di Firenze Via Lombroso 6/17, 50134 Firenze, Italy Email: [email protected] Keywords and Phrases: Concurrency, labelled transition system with di- vergence, bisimulation preorder, finitary relation. 1 Introduction Following a paradigm put forward by Milner and Plotkin, a primary criterion to judge the appropriateness of denotational models for programming and specifi- cation languages is that they be in agreement with operational intuition about program behaviour.
    [Show full text]
  • Outline of Lecture 2 First Order Logic and Second Order Logic Basic Summary and Toolbox
    LogicalMethodsinCombinatorics,236605-2009/10 Lecture 2 Outline of Lecture 2 First Order Logic and Second Order Logic Basic summary and Toolbox • Vocabularies and structures • Isomorphisms and substructures • First Order Logic FOL, a reminder. • Completeness and Compactness • Second Order Logic SOL and SOLn and Monadic Second Order Logic MSOL. • Definability 1 LogicalMethodsinCombinatorics,236605-2009/10 Lecture 2 Vocabularies We deal with (possibly many-sorted) relational structures. Sort symbols are Uα : α ∈ IN Relation symbols are Ri,α : i ∈ Ar, α ∈ IN where Ar is a set of arities, i.e. of finite sequences of sort symbols. In the case of one-sorted vocabularies, the arity is just of the form hU,U,...n ...,Ui which will denoted by n. A vocabulary is a finite set of finitary relation symbols, usually denoted by τ, τi or σ. 2 LogicalMethodsinCombinatorics,236605-2009/10 Lecture 2 τ-structures Structures are interpretations of vocabularies, of the form A = hA(Uα), A(Ri,α): Uα, Ri,α ∈ τi with A(Uα)= Aα sets, and, for i =(Uj1 ,...,Ujr ) A(Ri,α) ⊆ Aj1 × ... × Ajr . Graphs: hV ; Ei with vertices as domain and edges as relation. hV ⊔ E, RGi with two sorted domain of vertices and edges and incidence relation. Labeled Graphs: As graphs but with unary predicates for vertex labels and edge labels depending whether edges are elements or tuples. Binary Words: hV ; R<,P0i with domain lineraly ordered by R< and colored by P0, marking the zero’s. τ-structures: General relational structures. 3 LogicalMethodsinCombinatorics,236605-2009/10 Lecture 2 τ-Substructures Let A, B be two τ-structures.
    [Show full text]
  • Lionel Vaux 1. Introduction
    Theoretical Informatics and Applications Will be set by the publisher Informatique Théorique et Applications A NON-UNIFORM FINITARY RELATIONAL SEMANTICS OF SYSTEM T ∗ Lionel Vaux1 Abstract. We study iteration and recursion operators in the denota- tional semantics of typed λ-calculi derived from the multiset relational model of linear logic. Although these operators are defined as fixpoints of typed functionals, we prove them finitary in the sense of Ehrhard’s finiteness spaces. 1991 Mathematics Subject Classification. 03B70, 03D65, 68Q55. 1. Introduction Since its inception in the late 1960’s, denotational semantics has proved to be a valuable tool in the study of programming languages, by recasting the equal- ities between terms induced by the operational semantics into an more abstract algebraic setting. By the Curry–Howard correspondence between proofs and pro- grams, this concept also provided important contributions to the design of logical systems. Notably, the invention of linear logic by Girard [1] followed from his introduction of coherences spaces as a refinement of Scott’s continuous semantics of the λ-calculus [2], moreover taking into account the property of stability put forward by Berry [3]. The design of coherence spaces was moreover largely based on the ideas pre- viously developed by Girard about a quantitative semantics of the λ-calculus [4]: the property that the behaviour of a program is specified by its action on finite approximants of its argument can be related with the fact that analytic functions are given by power series. This suggests interpreting types by particular topologi- cal vector spaces, and terms by analytic functions between them: Girard proposed Keywords and phrases: Higher order primitive recursion — Denotational semantics ∗ This work has been partially funded by the French ANR projet blanc “Curry Howard pour la Concurrence” CHOCO ANR-07-BLAN-0324.
    [Show full text]
  • Relationally Defined Clones of Tree Functions Closed Under Selection Or
    Acta Cybernetica 16 (2004) 411–425. Relationally defined clones of tree functions closed under selection or primitive recursion Reinhard P¨oschel,∗ Alexander Semigrodskikh,† and Heiko Vogler‡ Abstract We investigate classes of tree functions which are closed under composition and primitive recursion or selection (a restricted form of recursion). The main result is the characterization of those finitary relations (on the set of all trees of a fixed signature) for which the clone of tree functions preserving is closed under selection. Moreover, it turns out that such clones are closed also under primitive recursion. Introduction Classes of tree functions and primitive recursion for such functions were inves- tigated, e.g., in [F¨ulHVV93], [EngV91], [Hup78], [Kla84]. In this paper a tree function will be an operation f : T n → T on the set T of all trees of a given finite signature (in general one allows trees of different signature). If a class of operations is a clone (i.e. if it contains all projections and is closed with respect to composition), then it can be described by invariant relations (cf. e.g. [P¨osK79], [P¨os80], [P¨os01]). In this paper we apply such results from clone theory and ask which finitary relations characterize clones of tree functions that in addition are closed under primitive recursion. The answer is given in Theorem 2.1 and shows that such relations are easy to describe: they are direct products of order ideals of trees (an order ideal contains with a tree also all its subtrees). Moreover it turns out that for such clones the closure under primitive recursion is equivalent to a much weaker closure (the so-called selection or S-closure, cf.
    [Show full text]
  • Primitive Recursion in Finiteness Spaces
    Primitive recursion in niteness spaces Lionel Vaux? Laboratoire de Mathématiques de l'Université de Savoie UFR SFA, Campus Scientique, 73376 Le Bourget-du-Lac Cedex, France E-mail: [email protected] Abstract. We study iteration and recursion operators in the multiset relational model of linear logic and prove them nitary in the sense of the niteness spaces recently introduced by Ehrhard. This provides a denotational semantics of Gödel's system T and paves the way for a systematic study of a large class of algorithms, following the ideas of Girard's quantitative semantics in a standard algebraic setting. 1 Introduction The category Fin of niteness spaces and nitary relations was introduced by Ehrhard [1], rening the purely relational model of linear logic. A niteness space is a set equipped with a niteness structure, i.e. a particular set of subsets which are said to be nitary; and the model is such that the usual relational denotation of a proof in linear logic is always a nitary subset of its conclusion. By the usual co-Kleisli construction, this also provides a model of the simply typed lambda-calculus: the cartesian closed category . Fin! The main property of niteness spaces is that the intersection of two nitary subsets of dual types is always nite. This feature allows to reformulate Gi- rard's quantitative semantics in a standard algebraic setting, where morphisms interpreting typed λ-terms are analytic functions between the topological vector spaces generated by vectors with nitary supports. This provided the seman- tical foundations of Ehrhard-Regnier's dierential λ-calculus [2] and motivated the general study of a dierential extension of linear logic [3].
    [Show full text]
  • A Non-Uniform Finitary Relational Semantics of System T∗
    RAIRO-Theor. Inf. Appl. 47 (2013) 111–132 Available online at: DOI: 10.1051/ita/2012031 www.rairo-ita.org A NON-UNIFORM FINITARY RELATIONAL SEMANTICS OF SYSTEM T ∗ Lionel Vaux1 Abstract. We study iteration and recursion operators in the denota- tional semantics of typed λ-calculi derived from the multiset relational model of linear logic. Although these operators are defined as fixpoints of typed functionals, we prove them finitary in the sense of Ehrhard’s finiteness spaces. Mathematics Subject Classification. 03B70, 03D65, 68Q55. 1. Introduction Since its inception in the late 1960s, denotational semantics has proved to be a valuable tool in the study of programming languages, by recasting the equal- ities between terms induced by the operational semantics into an more abstract algebraic setting. By the Curry–Howard correspondence between proofs and pro- grams, this concept also provided important contributions to the design of logical systems. Notably, the invention of linear logic by Girard [17] followed from his introduction of coherences spaces as a refinement of Scott’s continuous semantics of the λ-calculus [26], moreover taking into account the property of stability put forward by Berry [5]. The design of coherence spaces was moreover largely based on the ideas previ- ously developed by Girard about a quantitative semantics of the λ-calculus [18]: the property that the behaviour of a program is specified by its action on finite ap- proximants of its argument can be related with the fact that analytic functions are given by power series. This suggests interpreting types by particular topological Keywords and phrases.
    [Show full text]
  • Finitary Filter Pairs and Propositional Logics
    South American Journal of Logic Vol. 4, n. 2, pp. 257{280, 2018 ISSN: 2446-6719 Finitary Filter Pairs and Propositional Logics Peter Arndt1, Hugo L. Mariano and Darllan C. Pinto Abstract We present the notion of filter pair as a tool for creating and analyzing logics. We show that every Tarskian logic arises from a filter pair and that translations of logics arise from morphisms of filter pairs, establishing a categorial connection. Keywords: Abstract Algebraic Logic, Category Theory. Introduction In this work we present the notion of filter pair, introduced in [28], as a tool for creating and analyzing logics. We sketch the basic idea of this notion: Throughout the article the word logic will mean a pair (Σ; `) where Σ is a signature, i.e. a collection of connectives with finite arities, and ` is a Tarskian consequence relation, i.e. an idempotent, increasing, monotonic, finitary and structural relation between subsets and elements of the set of formulas F mΣ(X) built from Σ and a set X of variables. It is well-known that every Tarskian logic gives rise to an algebraic lattice contained in the powerset }(F mΣ(X)), namely the lattice of theories. This lattice is closed under arbitrary intersections and directed unions. Conversely an algebraic lattice L ⊆ }(F mΣ(X)) that is closed under arbi- trary intersections and directed unions gives rise to a finitary closure operator (assigning to a subset A ⊆ F mΣ(X) the intersection of all members of L con- taining A). This closure operator need not be structural | this is an extra requirement.
    [Show full text]
  • Transport of Finiteness Structures and Applications
    Transport of finiteness structures and applications Christine Tasson1∗ and Lionel Vaux2∗ 1 Preuves, Programmes et Systèmes, CNRS UMR 7126, Paris, France. 2 Institut de Mathématiques de Luminy, CNRS UMR 6206, Marseille, France. December 31, 2010 Abstract We describe a general construction of finiteness spaces which subsumes the interpretations of all positive connectors of linear logic. We then show how to apply this construction to prove the existence of least fixpoints for particular functors in the category of finiteness spaces: these include the functors involved in a relational interpretation of lazy recursive algebraic datatypes along the lines of the coherence semantics of system T. 1 Introduction Finiteness spaces were introduced by Ehrhard (2005), refining the purely relational model of linear logic. A finiteness space is a set equipped with a finiteness structure, i.e. a particular set of subsets which are said to be finitary; and the model is such that the relational denotation of a proof in linear logic is always a finitary subset of its conclusion. Applied to this finitary relational model of linear logic, the usual co-Kleisli construction provides a cartesian closed category, hence a model of the simply typed λ-calculus (see, e.g., Bierman (1995)). The crucial property of finiteness spaces is that the intersection of two finitary subsets of dual types is always finite. This feature allows to reformulate the quantitative semantics of Girard (1988) in a standard algebraic setting, where morphisms interpreting typed λ-terms are analytic functions between the topological vector spaces generated by vectors with finitary supports. This provided the semantic foundations of the differential λ-calculus of Ehrhard and Regnier (2003) and motivated the general study of a differential extension of linear logic (Ehrhard and Regnier; 2005, 2006; Ehrhard and Laurent; 2007; Tranquilli; 2008; Vaux; 2009b; Tasson; 2009; Pagani and Tasson; 2009, etc.).
    [Show full text]