Chapter 7 Logical Positivism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Chapter 7 Logical Positivism Chapter Logical Positivism Iwant neither that pluto cracy grasping and mean nor that demo cracy go o dy and medio cre o ccupied solely in turning the other cheek where would dwell sages without curiosity who shunning excess would not die of disease but would surely die of ennui Poincare quoted in Runes ToP p Science itself therefore may b e regarded as a minimal problem consisting of the completest p ossible presentment of facts with the least possible expenditure of thought Mach Newman WMVol p Historical Background In this chapter wewilllookat logical positivism the most inuential philosophy of science in the twentieth century In spite of the fact that logical p ositivism has b een abandoned by most philosophers of science its inuence continues in many disciplines including physics linguistics and psychologyWe will b e esp ecially concerned with logical p ositivisms view of knowledge which is roughly the only real CHAPTER LOGICAL POSITIVISM knowledge is scientic knowledge by a pro cess of logical analysis scientic knowledge can b e reduced to symb olic formulas constructed from atomic facts Certainly assertion is nothing new So crates said as much when he distinguished scientic knowledge episteme from a practice empeiria see Section Furthermore assertion is implicit in Pythagorianism and is a continuous theme in most Western epistemology from Plato and Aristotle through Hobb es and Leibnitz to Bo ole and Hilb ert In this sense logical p ositivism is just the continuation of this long tradition The ma jor innovation of logical p ositivism follows from a new under standing of scientic knowledge and in the resulting view of the atomic constituents of knowledge Throughout most of these years sci entic knowledge was viewed rationalisticallyanditwas assumed that the atomic constituents were some kind of selfevident axioms involving basic categories that required no denition However b eginning in the Renaissance there was a growing recognition of the value of observa tion and exp eriment activeintervention in nature and a corresp onding increase in scepticism ab out the self evidence of any prop osition In deed if empiricist philosophers were willing to grant selfevidence to anything it was to sense data rather than to the metaphysical prop o sitions favored by the rationalists In the past the ideal of knowledge had b een Euclidean geometry but the new empiricism to ok physics as its ideal Although logical p ositivism originated in Germany in the s a many of its ro ots are AngloAmerican First there is empiricism strong theme in British philosophybacktoDavid Hume Thomas Hobb es and Francis Bacon Second there is American pragmatism originated byCSPeirce William James and John Dewey with its em phasis on the observable consequences of actions Finally there was logical analysis strongly represented in the Continental idealist tradi tion but turned into a technical to ol by the British philosophers G E Mo ore and Bertrand Russell Logical p ositivism combined these AngloAmerican developments with the existing p ositivist tradition on the Continent which originated with the French philosopher Auguste Comte He argued that each branchofhuman understanding went through three stages HISTORICAL BACKGROUND in the theological stage explanations are based on the volition of go ds in the metaphysical stage explanations are based on abstract forces in the positive or scientic stage phenomena are not explained at all but are simply connected bylaws Comte says FinallyinthePositive state the human mind recogniz ing the imp ossibility of obtaining absolute truth gives up the search after the origin and destination of the universe and a knowledge of the nal causes of phenomena It only endeavors nowtodiscover bya wellcombined use of rea soning and observation the actual laws of phenomena that is to say their invariable relations of succession and likeness quoted in Runes ToPp The famous French mathematician and philosopher Jules Henri Poincare applied p ositivist ideas to physics and was con cerned with the construction of basic physical concepts out of our sen sations and p erceptions In this way he prepared the way for Einsteins reconstruction of space time and gravity in his sp ecial and general relativity theories see p The Austrian physicist Ernst Mach to ok a very sim ilar view and argued that the laws of physics as of all the sciences are just shorthand summaries of relationships b etween the observers exp eriences y It is the ob ject of science to replace or save exp eriences b the repro duction and anticipation of facts in thought This economical oce of science which lls its whole life is apparent at rst glance and with its full recognition all mysticism in science disapp ears Every scientic law and concept mass energy atoms must b e reduced to relations b etween observable quantities These in turn are relationships among sense data Prop erly sp eaking the world is not comp osed of things as its elements but of colors tones pressures spaces times in short what we ordinarily call individual sensations A relevant selection from Machs ScienceofMechanics from whichthese quotations are taken is reprinted in Newman WMVol pp CHAPTER LOGICAL POSITIVISM This view led Mach to detailed investigations of sensation and p ercep tion for example in his Space and Geometry he carefully distin guishes the space of physics from the physiological space up on which its based and in the latter category he analyzes the space of vision and the space of touch which of course are not the same These analyses formed a starting p oint for Einsteins relativitywork p Muchlike Comte Machsaw science as an advance over metaphysics Where neither conrmation nor refutation is p ossible science is not concerned He rejected anything not reducible to exp erience as not true knowledge a characteristic attitude of p ositivism and by reducing statements to exp erience he hop ed to exp ose the real sig nicance of the matter and get rid of metaphysical obscurities As Hume said long b efore If we take in our hand anyvolume of divinityorscho ol metaphysics for instance let us ask Does is contain any ab stract reasoning concerning quantity or number No Does it contain any experimental reasoning concerning matter of fact and existence No Commit it then to the ames for it can contain nothing but sophistry and illusion Enq Conc Human Underst sec pt In Mach b ecame a professor of physics at the University of Vi enna and with him we come to the do orstep of the Vienna Circle the fountainhead of the logical p ositivist movement However b efore we discuss it wemust consider imp ortantcontributions from the analytic tradition up on which the logical p ositivists also dep ended Logical Atomism Russell Knowledge by Acquaintance and Description In many resp ects logical p ositivism was motivated by the same desires for p erfect clarity and absolute certaintythathave driven muchofthe progress of epistemology from the time of Pythagoras The particular form that this quest has taken in the analytic traditionwhich has LOGICAL ATOMISM dominated AngloAmerican philosophy in the twentieth century and which includes logical p ositivism is the b elief that analysis can b e pursued down to certain indivisible elements which are in some way incorrigible and hence justify the intellectual edice constructed from them One form of this is the theory of logical atomism develop ed by Bertrand Russell in the rst decades of the twentieth century He distinguished know ledge by acquaintancewhich is indubitable from know ledge by description whichmay b e in error Examples of knowl edge by acquaintance are sense data and the contents of our own mem ory So for example if I were p erceiving a patchofyellow color in a certain place in my visual eld Russell would take that fact to b e unassailable though I could certainly b e incorrect in assuming that Im seeing a yellow ob ject since it could b e a hallucination I might have jaundice or b e wearing yellow sunglasses etc etc Similarly my memory that a certain p erson attended my fth birthdayparty might b e mistaken but I cannot b e mistaken in the fact of having that recollection A common logical fallacy is the use of descriptions to which nothing answers The classic example is the presentKingofFrance since France do es not have a king Therefore when I make an assertion such as the presentKingofFrance is bald it is neither true nor false since it is not an assertion ab out anything Suchknowledge by description is fallible since it contains descriptions that mayfailin their reference that is they do not refer to anything In contrast an ob ject of acquaintance acts likea logical ly proper name and cannot fail in its reference by virtue of my p erceiving it the sp ot of yellowIm The logical atomism of Russell diers from that of Leibnitz p in that the former is empirical whereas the latter is rationalistic though interestingly b oth to ok the self to b e an elementary given Sources for this section include Russell LA and Russell PLA The pitfalls of reference are illustrated by the fo otnoted sentence for had I said they refer to nothing it mighthave implied that there is a thing Nothing to which descriptions refer when nothing else answers the description We could then make a career out of investigating the prop erties of this Nothing Indeed Alexis Meinong did precisely that since he gave a kind of logical realitytoany intentional object that is any ob ject of consciousness Consideration of Meinongs work led Russell
Recommended publications
  • Denying a Dualism: Goodman's Repudiation of the Analytic/Synthetic Distinction
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 28, 2004, 226-238. Denying a Dualism: Goodman’s Repudiation of the Analytic/Synthetic Distinction Catherine Z. Elgin The analytic synthetic/distinction forms the backbone of much modern Western philosophy. It underwrites a conception of the relation of representations to reality which affords an understanding of cognition. Its repudiation thus requires a fundamental reconception and perhaps a radical revision of philosophy. Many philosophers believe that the repudiation of the analytic/synthetic distinction and kindred dualisms constitutes a major loss, possibly even an irrecoverable loss, for philosophy. Nelson Goodman thinks otherwise. He believes that it liberates philosophy from unwarranted restrictions, creating opportunities for the development of powerful new approaches to and reconceptions of seemingly intractable problems. In this article I want to sketch some of the consequences of Goodman’s reconception. My focus is not on Goodman’s reasons for denying the dualism, but on some of the ways its absence affects his position. I do not contend that the Goodman obsessed over the issue. I have no reason to think that the repudiation of the distinction was a central factor in his intellectual life. But by considering the function that the analytic/synthetic distinction has performed in traditional philosophy, and appreciating what is lost and gained in repudiating it, we gain insight into Goodman’s contributions. I begin then by reviewing the distinction and the conception of philosophy it supports. The analytic/synthetic distinction is a distinction between truths that depend entirely on meaning and truths that depend on both meaning and fact. In the early modern period, it was cast as a distinction between relations of ideas and matters of fact.
    [Show full text]
  • Would ''Direct Realism'' Resolve the Classical Problem of Induction?
    NOU^S 38:2 (2004) 197–232 Would ‘‘Direct Realism’’ Resolve the Classical Problem of Induction? MARC LANGE University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill I Recently, there has been a modest resurgence of interest in the ‘‘Humean’’ problem of induction. For several decades following the recognized failure of Strawsonian ‘‘ordinary-language’’ dissolutions and of Wesley Salmon’s elaboration of Reichenbach’s pragmatic vindication of induction, work on the problem of induction languished. Attention turned instead toward con- firmation theory, as philosophers sensibly tried to understand precisely what it is that a justification of induction should aim to justify. Now, however, in light of Bayesian confirmation theory and other developments in epistemology, several philosophers have begun to reconsider the classical problem of induction. In section 2, I shall review a few of these developments. Though some of them will turn out to be unilluminating, others will profitably suggest that we not meet inductive scepticism by trying to justify some alleged general principle of ampliative reasoning. Accordingly, in section 3, I shall examine how the problem of induction arises in the context of one particular ‘‘inductive leap’’: the confirmation, most famously by Henrietta Leavitt and Harlow Shapley about a century ago, that a period-luminosity relation governs all Cepheid variable stars. This is a good example for the inductive sceptic’s purposes, since it is difficult to see how the sparse background knowledge available at the time could have entitled stellar astronomers to regard their observations as justifying this grand inductive generalization. I shall argue that the observation reports that confirmed the Cepheid period- luminosity law were themselves ‘‘thick’’ with expectations regarding as yet unknown laws of nature.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Science and Philosophy of Chemistry
    Philosophy of Science and Philosophy of Chemistry Jaap van Brakel Abstract: In this paper I assess the relation between philosophy of chemistry and (general) philosophy of science, focusing on those themes in the philoso- phy of chemistry that may bring about major revisions or extensions of cur- rent philosophy of science. Three themes can claim to make a unique contri- bution to philosophy of science: first, the variety of materials in the (natural and artificial) world; second, extending the world by making new stuff; and, third, specific features of the relations between chemistry and physics. Keywords : philosophy of science, philosophy of chemistry, interdiscourse relations, making stuff, variety of substances . 1. Introduction Chemistry is unique and distinguishes itself from all other sciences, with respect to three broad issues: • A (variety of) stuff perspective, requiring conceptual analysis of the notion of stuff or material (Sections 4 and 5). • A making stuff perspective: the transformation of stuff by chemical reaction or phase transition (Section 6). • The pivotal role of the relations between chemistry and physics in connection with the question how everything fits together (Section 7). All themes in the philosophy of chemistry can be classified in one of these three clusters or make contributions to general philosophy of science that, as yet , are not particularly different from similar contributions from other sci- ences (Section 3). I do not exclude the possibility of there being more than three clusters of philosophical issues unique to philosophy of chemistry, but I am not aware of any as yet. Moreover, highlighting the issues discussed in Sections 5-7 does not mean that issues reviewed in Section 3 are less im- portant in revising the philosophy of science.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophical Logic 2018 Course Description (Tentative) January 15, 2018
    Philosophical Logic 2018 Course description (tentative) January 15, 2018 Valentin Goranko Introduction This 7.5 hp course is mainly intended for students in philosophy and is generally accessible to a broad audience with basic background on formal classical logic and general appreciation of philosophical aspects of logic. Practical information The course will be given in English. It will comprise 18 two-hour long sessions combining lectures and exercises, grouped in 2 sessions per week over 9 teaching weeks. The weekly pairs of 2-hour time slots (incl. short breaks) allocated for these sessions, will be on Mondays during 10.00-12.00 and 13.00-15.00, except for the first lecture. The course will begin on Wednesday, April 4, 2018 (Week 14) at 10.00 am in D220, S¨odra huset, hus D. Lecturer's info: Name: Valentin Goranko Email: [email protected] Homepage: http://www2.philosophy.su.se/goranko Course webpage: http://www2.philosophy.su.se/goranko/Courses2018/PhilLogic-2018.html Prerequisites The course will be accessible to a broad audience with introductory background on classical formal logic. Some basic knowledge of modal logics would be an advantage but not a prerequisite. Brief description Philosophical logic studies a variety of non-classical logical systems intended to formalise and reason about various philosophical concepts and ideas. They include a broad family of modal logics, as well as many- valued, intuitionistic, relevant, conditional, non-monotonic, para-consistent, etc. logics. Modal logics extend classical logic with additional intensional logical operators, reflecting different modes of truth, including alethic, epistemic, doxastic, temporal, deontic, agentive, etc.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Philosophy. Social Studies--Language Arts: 6414.16. INSTITUTION Dade County Public Schools, Miami, Fla
    DOCUMENT RESUME ED 086 604 SO 006 822 AUTHOR Norris, Jack A., Jr. TITLE Introduction to Philosophy. Social Studies--Language Arts: 6414.16. INSTITUTION Dade County Public Schools, Miami, Fla. PUB DATE 72 NOTE 20p.; Authorized Course of Instruction for the Quinmester Program EDRS PRICE MF-$0.65 HC-$3.29 DESCRIPTORS Course Objectives; Curriculum Guides; Grade 10; Grade 11; Grade 12; *Language Arts; Learnin4 Activities; *Logic; Non Western Civilization; *Philosophy; Resource Guides; Secondary Grades; *Social Studies; *Social Studies Units; Western Civilization IDENTIFIERS *Quinmester Program ABSTRACT Western and non - western philosophers and their ideas are introduced to 10th through 12th grade students in this general social studies Quinmester course designed to be used as a preparation for in-depth study of the various schools of philosophical thought. By acquainting students with the questions and categories of philosophy, a point of departure for further study is developed. Through suggested learning activities the meaning of philosopky is defined. The Socratic, deductive, inductive, intuitive and eclectic approaches to philosophical thought are examined, as are three general areas of philosophy, metaphysics, epistemology,and axiology. Logical reasoning is applied to major philosophical questions. This course is arranged, as are other quinmester courses, with sections on broad goals, course content, activities, and materials. A related document is ED 071 937.(KSM) FILMED FROM BEST AVAILABLE COPY U S DEPARTMENT EDUCATION OF HEALTH. NAT10N41
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae
    BAS C. VAN FRAASSEN Curriculum Vitae Last updated 3/6/2019 I. Personal and Academic History .................................................................................................................... 1 List of Degrees Earned ........................................................................................................................................................ 1 Title of Ph.D. Thesis ........................................................................................................................................................... 1 Positions held ..................................................................................................................................................................... 1 Invited lectures and lecture series ........................................................................................................................................ 1 List of Honors, Prizes ......................................................................................................................................................... 4 Research Grants .................................................................................................................................................................. 4 Non-Academic Publications ................................................................................................................................................ 5 II. Professional Activities .................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Life with Augustine
    Life with Augustine ...a course in his spirit and guidance for daily living By Edmond A. Maher ii Life with Augustine © 2002 Augustinian Press Australia Sydney, Australia. Acknowledgements: The author wishes to acknowledge and thank the following people: ► the Augustinian Province of Our Mother of Good Counsel, Australia, for support- ing this project, with special mention of Pat Fahey osa, Kevin Burman osa, Pat Codd osa and Peter Jones osa ► Laurence Mooney osa for assistance in editing ► Michael Morahan osa for formatting this 2nd Edition ► John Coles, Peter Gagan, Dr. Frank McGrath fms (Brisbane CEO), Benet Fonck ofm, Peter Keogh sfo for sharing their vast experience in adult education ► John Rotelle osa, for granting us permission to use his English translation of Tarcisius van Bavel’s work Augustine (full bibliography within) and for his scholarly advice Megan Atkins for her formatting suggestions in the 1st Edition, that have carried over into this the 2nd ► those generous people who have completed the 1st Edition and suggested valuable improvements, especially Kath Neehouse and friends at Villanova College, Brisbane Foreword 1 Dear Participant Saint Augustine of Hippo is a figure in our history who has appealed to the curiosity and imagination of many generations. He is well known for being both sinner and saint, for being a bishop yet also a fellow pilgrim on the journey to God. One of the most popular and attractive persons across many centuries, his influence on the church has continued to our current day. He is also renowned for his influ- ence in philosophy and psychology and even (in an indirect way) art, music and architecture.
    [Show full text]
  • Brsq #142-144
    THE BERTRAND RUSSELL SOCIETY QUARTERLY Fall 2009 Issue Numbers 142 -144 / May -November 2009 THE ROAD TO CONNECTICUT Published by The Bertrand Russell Society with the support of Lehman College - City University of New York THE BERTRAND RUSSELL SoCIET¥ QUARTERLY is the official organ of the THE BERTRAND RUSSELL SOCIETY Bertrand Russell Society. It publishes Society news and proceedings, and QUARTERLY articles on the history of analytic philosophy, especially those on Russell's life and works, including historical materials and reviews of recent work on Fall 2009 Issue Russell. Scholarly articles appearing in the a"crrfer/,v are peer-reviewed. Numbers 142-144 / May -November 2009 Co-EDITORS: Rosalind Carey and John Ongley ASSOCIATE EDITOR: Ray Perkins Jr. EDITORIAL BOARD Rosalind Carey, Lehman College-CUNY THE ROAD TO CONNECTICUT John Ongley, Bloomsburg University Raymond Perkins, Jr., Plymouth State University Christopher Pincock, Purdue University David Hyder, University of Ottawa CONTENTS Anat Biletzki, Tel Aviv University SuBMISsloNS : All communications to the Ber/ra#cJ Rwssc// Soci.edy gwcrr/er- In This Issue /y, including manuscripts. book reviews, and letters to the editor, should be Society News sent to: Prof. Rosalind Carey, Philosophy Department, Lehman College- ln Memoriam: Theo Meijer CUNY, 250 Bed ford Park Blvd. West, Bronx, NY 10468, USA, or by email to: [email protected]. Feature SuBSCRlpTloNS: The BRS gwc}rfedy is free to members of the Bertrand Rus- sell Society. Society membership is $35 a year for individuals, $40 for cou- Nicholas Griffin Speaks His Mind: An Interview by ples, and $20 for students and limited income individuals.
    [Show full text]
  • The Etienne Gilson Series 21
    The Etienne Gilson Series 21 Remapping Scholasticism by MARCIA L. COLISH 3 March 2000 Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies This lecture and its publication was made possible through the generous bequest of the late Charles J. Sullivan (1914-1999) Note: the author may be contacted at: Department of History Oberlin College Oberlin OH USA 44074 ISSN 0-708-319X ISBN 0-88844-721-3 © 2000 by Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies 59 Queen’s Park Crescent East Toronto, Ontario, Canada M5S 2C4 Printed in Canada nce upon a time there were two competing story-lines for medieval intellectual history, each writing a major role for scholasticism into its script. Although these story-lines were O created independently and reflected different concerns, they sometimes overlapped and gave each other aid and comfort. Both exerted considerable influence on the way historians of medieval speculative thought conceptualized their subject in the first half of the twentieth cen- tury. Both versions of the map drawn by these two sets of cartographers illustrated what Wallace K. Ferguson later described as “the revolt of the medievalists.”1 One was confined largely to the academy and appealed to a wide variety of medievalists, while the other had a somewhat narrower draw and reflected political and confessional, as well as academic, concerns. The first was the anti-Burckhardtian effort to push Renaissance humanism, understood as combining a knowledge and love of the classics with “the discovery of the world and of man,” back into the Middle Ages. The second was inspired by the neo-Thomist revival launched by Pope Leo XIII, and was inhabited almost exclusively by Roman Catholic scholars.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Chemistry: an Emerging Field with Implications for Chemistry Education
    DOCUMENT RESUME ED 434 811 SE 062 822 AUTHOR Erduran, Sibel TITLE Philosophy of Chemistry: An Emerging Field with Implications for Chemistry Education. PUB DATE 1999-09-00 NOTE 10p.; Paper presented at the History, Philosophy and Science Teaching Conference (5th, Pavia, Italy, September, 1999). PUB TYPE Opinion Papers (120) Speeches/Meeting Papers (150) EDRS PRICE MF01/PC01 Plus Postage. DESCRIPTORS *Chemistry; Educational Change; Foreign Countries; Higher Education; *Philosophy; Science Curriculum; *Science Education; *Science Education History; *Science History; Scientific Principles; Secondary Education; Teaching Methods ABSTRACT Traditional applications of history and philosophy of science in chemistry education have concentrated on the teaching and learning of "history of chemistry". This paper considers the recent emergence of "philosophy of chemistry" as a distinct field and explores the implications of philosophy of chemistry for chemistry education in the context of teaching and learning chemical models. This paper calls for preventing the mutually exclusive development of chemistry education and philosophy of chemistry, and argues that research in chemistry education should strive to learn from the mistakes that resulted when early developments in science education were made separate from advances in philosophy of science. Contains 54 references. (Author/WRM) ******************************************************************************** Reproductions supplied by EDRS are the best that can be made from the original document. ******************************************************************************** 1 PHILOSOPHY OF CHEMISTRY: AN EMERGING FIELD WITH IMPLICATIONS FOR CHEMISTRY EDUCATION PERMISSION TO REPRODUCE AND U.S. DEPARTMENT OF EDUCATION DISSEMINATE THIS MATERIAL HAS Office of Educational Research and improvement BEEN GRANTED BY RESOURCES INFORMATION SIBEL ERDURAN CENTER (ERIC) This document has been reproducedas ceived from the person or organization KING'S COLLEGE, UNIVERSITYOF LONDON originating it.
    [Show full text]
  • Is Truth an Epistemic Value?∗
    Is Truth an Epistemic Value?∗ Mar´ıa J. Fr´apolli Departamento de Filosof´ıa Universidad de Granada (Espana)˜ [email protected] Introduction That truth is an epistemic value is a thesis that at least has the following two interpretations: Truth can be defined through, or identified with, some epistemic notion or other. This is the epistemic side Truth is something that science, or research, should pursue. Truth is some- thing valuable. This is the value side. Whereas interpretation (i) makes a false statement, interpretation (ii) ex- presses something that is true, although empty. But both interpretations have a grain of truth, and both are, in their own way, somewhat misleading. Their confusing offsprings have been epistemic and metaphysical theories of truth, respectively. The grain of truth in (i) is that the truth predicate is omnipresent when we deal with epistemic notions, and so that not even the most basic theses in epis- temology can be stated without using the truth predicate essentially. Besides, the endorsement role that the truth predicate performs in natural languages is applied in many cases to the items that have passed the kind of justificatory filters sanctioned by epistemology. The grain of truth in (ii) is that the best, and shortest, way of codifying the infinity of contents to whose knowledge science is aimed to is by the help of sentences that involve the truth predicate. The misleading aspect of (i) is that it suggests that truth should be identified with some item out of a set of epistemic situations: ideal justification, results of reliable processes, what the best scientific theories say, etc., and all this in order to seal the gap through which the sceptical menaces to slip in.
    [Show full text]
  • Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz Papers, 1646-1716
    http://oac.cdlib.org/findaid/ark:/13030/kt2779p48t No online items Finding Aid for the Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz Papers, 1646-1716 Processed by David MacGill; machine-readable finding aid created by Caroline Cubé © 2003 The Regents of the University of California. All rights reserved. Finding Aid for the Gottfried 503 1 Wilhelm Leibniz Papers, 1646-1716 Finding Aid for the Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz Papers, 1646-1716 Collection number: 503 UCLA Library, Department of Special Collections Manuscripts Division Los Angeles, CA Processed by: David MacGill, November 1992 Encoded by: Caroline Cubé Online finding aid edited by: Josh Fiala, October 2003 © 2003 The Regents of the University of California. All rights reserved. Descriptive Summary Title: Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz Papers, Date (inclusive): 1646-1716 Collection number: 503 Creator: Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, Freiherr von, 1646-1716 Extent: 6 oversize boxes Repository: University of California, Los Angeles. Library. Dept. of Special Collections. Los Angeles, California 90095-1575 Abstract: Leibniz (1646-1716) was a philosopher, mathematician, and political advisor. He invented differential and integral calculus. His major writings include New physical hypothesis (1671), Discourse on metaphysics (1686), On the ultimate origin of things (1697), and On nature itself (1698). The collection consists of 35 reels of positive microfilm of more than 100,000 handwritten pages of manuscripts and letters. Physical location: Stored off-site at SRLF. Advance notice is required for access to the collection. Please contact the UCLA Library, Department of Special Collections Reference Desk for paging information. Language: English. Restrictions on Use and Reproduction Property rights to the physical object belong to the UCLA Library, Department of Special Collections.
    [Show full text]