The Competitive Ultimatum Game

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Competitive Ultimatum Game The Competitive Ultimatum Game When Competition Matters, Although It Should Not, and Backward Induction Appears Through the Backdoor Klaus Abbinkb, Ron Darzivj, Zohar Gilulaj, Harel Gorenj, Bernd Irlenbusche, Arnon Kerenj, Bettina Rockenbache, Abdolkarim Sadrieht, Reinhard Seltenb, and Shmuel Zamirj University of Bonnb, Hebrew University Jerusalemj, University of Erfurte, Tilburg Universityt Preliminary version, April 2000. Comments are welcome. Abstract A game is introduced and experimented that allows for a direct comparison of the two predominant equilibrium concepts of economic theory: the competitive versus the strategic equilibrium. Neither of the two extreme and completely disjoint equilibrium predictions fully explains the data. Observed outcomes, however, are closer to the competitive than the subgame perfect (sequential) equilibrium predictions. As subjects gain experience in repeated plays of the game, outcomes move even closer to the competitive equilibrium. But, within play behavior frequently exhibits patterns that qualitatively correspond to the game theoretic predictions. Thus, although the competitive equilibrium concept clearly is the better predictor of behavior in the given environment, the strategic equilibrium concept also retains some of its behavioral relevance. Keywords Competition, backward induction, equilibrium concepts, experimental economics JEL Classification Codes C78, C91, C92, D82 Acknowledg ements The authors thank the teams of the RatioLab at the Hebrew University of Jerusalem and the Laboratorium für experimentelle Wirtschaftsforschung at the University of Bonn for their aid in collecting the data. Many thanks also to the seminar participants at the ENDEAR Bari workshop and summer school (1999) as well as at the IAES meeting in Munich (2000) for many helpful comments. Support by the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft through the Sonderforschungsbereich 303, by the German-Israeli Foundation ! GIF !, by the European Union through the TMR program ENDEAR (FMRX-CT98-0238), and by the Land Nordrhein-Westfalen is gratefully acknowledged. Correspondence Karim Sadrieh, Dept. of Economics, Tilburg University, POBox 90153, 5000 LE Tilburg, Netherlands - [email protected] 1 1. Introduction Ever since game theory introduced a new equilibrium concept to economic theory, the game-theoretic strategic equilibrium has co-existed with the traditional competitive equilibrium. The co-existence has been “friendly” in the sense that the followers of neither concept have seriously attempted to extinguish the application of the concept they do not fancy. One reason for this persistent duality lies in the fact that the theoretic delineation of the concepts has proven to be intricate. Not only do both concepts (in principle) allow for multiplicity of equilibria with a given set of assumptions, but both also allow an application to models with a broad range of possible assumptions. Perhaps it is due to these difficulties, that general results concerning the relationship of the strategic and the competitive equilibrium have not been derived so far. Generally, it seems possible to devise economic institutions in which the two equilibrium concepts produce any constellation of conclusions: equilibrium outcome sets that coincide, equilibrium outcome sets that are disjoint, or equilibrium outcome sets of which one is partially or wholly contained in the other. Clearly, the exciting case for research is the case in which equilibrium predictions do not coincide. In such cases, when the equilibrium concepts are in competition with one another, the problem of comparing and evaluating the conflicting equilibrium concepts emerges. This is the issue that is at the heart of the present paper. Instead of taking an axiomatic approach to tackle the issue of equilibrium concept evaluation, an empirical approach is attempted with this research. Using the method of experimentation, we study a game in which the set of outcomes predicted by the competitive equilibrium and the set of outcomes predicted by the strategic equilibrium are disjoint. The goal is to evaluate the two equilibrium predictions in terms of their behavioral relevance. Obviously, if one of the equilibrium outcomes predominates our experimental observations, conclusions concerning the behavioral relevance of the concepts in our setting will be apparent. Our design, however, also will allow us to draw more intricate conclusions from the comparison of observed decision paths. Finally, the robustness of the results with respect to changes in the informational setting will be explored by comparing the results of experimental sessions with a perfect to those of sessions with an imperfect information version of the underlying game. To our knowledge, this is the first systematic experimental study concerned with the evaluation of the competing equilibrium concepts. However, an interesting benchmark for our work is supplied by PRASNIKAR and ROTH (???). Interested in tests of an adaptive learning model, they conducted experi- ments with a game in which the predictions of the two equilibrium concepts coincide at an extreme outcome. They find that subjects’ behavior rapidly converges to this jointly strategic and competitive equilibrium of the game. In a way, we find this result comforting, since it confirms the behavioral validity of at least one of the two equilibrium concepts. But, since the predicted outcomes fully overlap, it is not clear whether observed behavior is actually driven by competition or by the backward induction logic of the sub-game perfect equilibrium. 2 In the competitive ultimatum game, which is introduced in this paper, the competitive and the strategic equilibrium predictions are separated at the two extreme ends of the range of possible outcomes. In this game, three proposers, one after the other, can make an offer to a single responder. If the responder accepts the first offer for the division of the cake, the game ends. Otherwise, the second proposers makes an offer, and so forth. The third stage of the game, when only one proposer is left, corresponds to a common ultimatum game. Backward induction implies that the strategic bargaining power of the responder is very limited in this game. Anticipating that the responder will accept any non-negative amount that is proposed in the last stage, the last proposer will offer no more than the smallest money unit. Anticipating this, the one to last proposer will offer no more than two times the smallest money unit. Finally, the backward induction logic predicts that the responder accepts the first proposer’s offer that is no more than three times the smallest money unit. Thus, in subgame perfect (or sequential) equilibrium, the responder receives a tiny piece of the cake, while the first proposer receives almost the entire cake. From a competitive equilibrium perspective, however, the responder has an extremely strong monopolis- tic position, while the three proposers face sharp competition. Only one of the proposers can succeed. In fact, supposing that the three proposers are three sellers and the responder is a buyer and looking at the corresponding demand and supply curves, we find that the competitive equilibrium price is zero, since the marginal cost of all sellers is zero. Thus, in competitive equilibrium, the responder, who is predicted to receive almost nothing in the strategic equilibrium, receives almost the entire cake, leaving the pro- poser with close to nothing. The experiments show that the competitive pressure on the proposers is clearly greater than the bargain- ing power that the game theoretic reasoning attributes to them. The competition amongst proposers leads to high offers: On average more than half of the cake is offered to the responder. Furthermore, as the subjects gain experience with the game, the offers to the responder tend to rise. The stiff competition pushes first proposer offers from slightly above 50% in the first round to well over 60% in round 35. Since an upward trend in the offers can be clearly seen in 22 of 24 independent subject groups, the conclusion seems justified that observed outcomes develop in the direction predicted by the competitive equilibrium concept, although the competitive equilibrium outcome is not reached. However, a second strong regularity appears in the data. In general, the observed offers in a game decline as the game enters later stages, going from one proposer to the next. In the last stage, most observed offers are in the range that is typically also observed in ultimatum bargaining experiments. Thus, as the responder’s threat of rejection loses its credibility, because the end of the game comes closer, the proposers' offers drop. It is in this effect that the backward induction reasoning strongly reappears in our data. 3 The rest of the paper is organized as follows. First, in section 2, the competitive ultimatum game is defined precisely and analyzed game-theoretically. Then, after the experimental design is described in section 3, the results are reported in section 4. 2. The Competitive Ultimatum Game The competitive ultimatum game is an extension of the 'classical' ultimatum game (GÜTH, SCHMITTBERGER, and SCHWARZE 1982) with three (potential) proposers P1, P2, and P3 and one responder R. The three proposers sequentially propose an allocation of the cake C to the responder. First, P1 proposes an allocation a1=(x1,C-x1) of C to R, where x1 denotes the proposed payoff for the responder R and C-x1 denotes the own payoff desired by P1. The game ends if R accepts the proposal of P1. Otherwise, if P1's proposal is rejected by R, P2 proposes an allocation a2=(x2,C-x2) of C to R. If R accepts P2's proposal, the game ends. Otherwise, if R also turns down P2's proposal, it is P3's turn to propose an allocation a3=(x3,C-x3) of C to R. If R accepts the proposal of proposer P3, R receives x3, P3 receives C-x3, and each of both other proposers receives 0. If R rejects all three proposals all four players receive 0. Suppose that each proposer Pi is completely informed about the proposal(s) of the proposer(s) who have decided before Pi.
Recommended publications
  • Uniqueness and Symmetry in Bargaining Theories of Justice
    Philos Stud DOI 10.1007/s11098-013-0121-y Uniqueness and symmetry in bargaining theories of justice John Thrasher Ó Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013 Abstract For contractarians, justice is the result of a rational bargain. The goal is to show that the rules of justice are consistent with rationality. The two most important bargaining theories of justice are David Gauthier’s and those that use the Nash’s bargaining solution. I argue that both of these approaches are fatally undermined by their reliance on a symmetry condition. Symmetry is a substantive constraint, not an implication of rationality. I argue that using symmetry to generate uniqueness undermines the goal of bargaining theories of justice. Keywords David Gauthier Á John Nash Á John Harsanyi Á Thomas Schelling Á Bargaining Á Symmetry Throughout the last century and into this one, many philosophers modeled justice as a bargaining problem between rational agents. Even those who did not explicitly use a bargaining problem as their model, most notably Rawls, incorporated many of the concepts and techniques from bargaining theories into their understanding of what a theory of justice should look like. This allowed them to use the powerful tools of game theory to justify their various theories of distributive justice. The debates between partisans of different theories of distributive justice has tended to be over the respective benefits of each particular bargaining solution and whether or not the solution to the bargaining problem matches our pre-theoretical intuitions about justice. There is, however, a more serious problem that has effectively been ignored since economists originally J.
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture Notes
    GRADUATE GAME THEORY LECTURE NOTES BY OMER TAMUZ California Institute of Technology 2018 Acknowledgments These lecture notes are partially adapted from Osborne and Rubinstein [29], Maschler, Solan and Zamir [23], lecture notes by Federico Echenique, and slides by Daron Acemoglu and Asu Ozdaglar. I am indebted to Seo Young (Silvia) Kim and Zhuofang Li for their help in finding and correcting many errors. Any comments or suggestions are welcome. 2 Contents 1 Extensive form games with perfect information 7 1.1 Tic-Tac-Toe ........................................ 7 1.2 The Sweet Fifteen Game ................................ 7 1.3 Chess ............................................ 7 1.4 Definition of extensive form games with perfect information ........... 10 1.5 The ultimatum game .................................. 10 1.6 Equilibria ......................................... 11 1.7 The centipede game ................................... 11 1.8 Subgames and subgame perfect equilibria ...................... 13 1.9 The dollar auction .................................... 14 1.10 Backward induction, Kuhn’s Theorem and a proof of Zermelo’s Theorem ... 15 2 Strategic form games 17 2.1 Definition ......................................... 17 2.2 Nash equilibria ...................................... 17 2.3 Classical examples .................................... 17 2.4 Dominated strategies .................................. 22 2.5 Repeated elimination of dominated strategies ................... 22 2.6 Dominant strategies ..................................
    [Show full text]
  • The Role of Self-Interest in Elite Bargaining
    The role of self-interest in elite bargaining Brad L. LeVecka,b, D. Alex Hughesa,c, James H. Fowlera,c,d, Emilie Hafner-Burtona,c, and David G. Victora,1 aLaboratory on International Law and Regulation, School of International Relations and Pacific Studies, cDepartment of Political Science, and dDivision of Medical Genetics, University of California, San Diego, La Jolla, CA 92093; and bDepartment of Political Science, University of California, Merced, CA 95343 Edited by David G. Rand, Yale University, New Haven, CT, and accepted by the Editorial Board November 11, 2014 (received for review May 28, 2014) One of the best-known and most replicated laboratory results in evident in less experienced populations (16, 17). Some research behavioral economics is that bargainers frequently reject low has examined whether leaders are psychologically or physiolog- offers, even when it harms their material self-interest. This finding ically different from nonelite populations—for example, research could have important implications for international negotiations on anxiety levels in leaders (18) and work on how leaders may be on many problems facing humanity today, because models of selected for skills in coordination, leadership, and followership international bargaining assume exactly the opposite: that policy (19). The few existing studies that have empirically examined makers are rational and self-interested. However, it is unknown actual decision making by elites in highly particular roles—such whether elites who engage in diplomatic bargaining will similarly as professional tennis players, soccer players, and traders—sug- reject low offers because past research has been based almost gest that, through a combination of learning and attrition, elites exclusively on convenience samples of undergraduates, members are more likely to exhibit self-interested, profit-maximizing be- of the general public, or small-scale societies rather than highly havior than their less experienced counterparts (20–23).
    [Show full text]
  • Nash Equilibrium
    Lecture 3: Nash equilibrium Nash equilibrium: The mathematician John Nash introduced the concept of an equi- librium for a game, and equilibrium is often called a Nash equilibrium. They provide a way to identify reasonable outcomes when an easy argument based on domination (like in the prisoner's dilemma, see lecture 2) is not available. We formulate the concept of an equilibrium for a two player game with respective 0 payoff matrices PR and PC . We write PR(s; s ) for the payoff for player R when R plays 0 s and C plays s, this is simply the (s; s ) entry the matrix PR. Definition 1. A pair of strategies (^sR; s^C ) is an Nash equilbrium for a two player game if no player can improve his payoff by changing his strategy from his equilibrium strategy to another strategy provided his opponent keeps his equilibrium strategy. In terms of the payoffs matrices this means that PR(sR; s^C ) ≤ P (^sR; s^C ) for all sR ; and PC (^sR; sC ) ≤ P (^sR; s^C ) for all sc : The idea at work in the definition of Nash equilibrium deserves a name: Definition 2. A strategy s^R is a best-response to a strategy sc if PR(sR; sC ) ≤ P (^sR; sC ) for all sR ; i.e. s^R is such that max PR(sR; sC ) = P (^sR; sC ) sR We can now reformulate the idea of a Nash equilibrium as The pair (^sR; s^C ) is a Nash equilibrium if and only ifs ^R is a best-response tos ^C and s^C is a best-response tos ^R.
    [Show full text]
  • Bounded Rationality in Bargaining Games: Do Proposers Believe That Responders Reject an Equal Split?
    No. 11 UNIVERSITY OF COLOGNE WORKING PAPER SERIES IN ECONOMICS BOUNDED RATIONALITY IN BARGAINING GAMES: DO PROPOSERS BELIEVE THAT RESPONDERS REJECT AN EQUAL SPLIT? BEN GREINER Department of Economics University of Cologne Albertus-Magnus-Platz D-50923 Köln Germany http://www.wiso.uni-koeln.de Bounded Rationality in Bargaining Games: Do Proposers Believe That Responders Reject an Equal Split?∗ Ben Greiner† June 19, 2004 Abstract Puzzled by the experimental results of the ’impunity game’ by Bolton & Zwick (1995) we replicate the game and alter it in a systematic manner. We find that although almost nobody actually rejects an offered equal split in a bargaining game, proposers behave as if there would be a considerably large rejection rate for equal splits. This result is inconsistent with existing models of economic decision making. This includes models of selfish play- ers as well as models of social utility and reciprocity, even when combined with erroneous decision making. Our data suggests that subjects fail to foresee their opponent’s decision even for one step in our simple bargaining games. We consider models of bounded rational decision making such as rules of thumb as explanations for the observed behavioral pattern. Keywords: ultimatum game, dictator game, impunity game, social utility, bounded rationality JEL Classification: C72, C92, D3 ∗I thank Bettina Bartels, Hakan Fink and Ralica Gospodinova for research assistance, the Strategic Interaction Group at MPI Jena for comments and serving as pilot participants, especially Susanne B¨uchner, Sven Fischer, Katinka Pantz and Carsten Schmidt for support in the conduction of the experiment, and Werner G¨uth, Axel Ockenfels, Ro’i Zultan, participants at the European ESA Meeting in Erfurt and at the Brown Bag seminars in Jena and Cologne for discussions and valuable comments.
    [Show full text]
  • Minimally Acceptable Altruism and the Ultimatum Game
    A Service of Leibniz-Informationszentrum econstor Wirtschaft Leibniz Information Centre Make Your Publications Visible. zbw for Economics Rotemberg, Julio J. Working Paper Minimally acceptable altruism and the ultimatum game Working Papers, No. 06-12 Provided in Cooperation with: Federal Reserve Bank of Boston Suggested Citation: Rotemberg, Julio J. (2006) : Minimally acceptable altruism and the ultimatum game, Working Papers, No. 06-12, Federal Reserve Bank of Boston, Boston, MA This Version is available at: http://hdl.handle.net/10419/55606 Standard-Nutzungsbedingungen: Terms of use: Die Dokumente auf EconStor dürfen zu eigenen wissenschaftlichen Documents in EconStor may be saved and copied for your Zwecken und zum Privatgebrauch gespeichert und kopiert werden. personal and scholarly purposes. Sie dürfen die Dokumente nicht für öffentliche oder kommerzielle You are not to copy documents for public or commercial Zwecke vervielfältigen, öffentlich ausstellen, öffentlich zugänglich purposes, to exhibit the documents publicly, to make them machen, vertreiben oder anderweitig nutzen. publicly available on the internet, or to distribute or otherwise use the documents in public. Sofern die Verfasser die Dokumente unter Open-Content-Lizenzen (insbesondere CC-Lizenzen) zur Verfügung gestellt haben sollten, If the documents have been made available under an Open gelten abweichend von diesen Nutzungsbedingungen die in der dort Content Licence (especially Creative Commons Licences), you genannten Lizenz gewährten Nutzungsrechte. may exercise further usage rights as specified in the indicated licence. www.econstor.eu No. 06‐12 Minimally Acceptable Altruism and the Ultimatum Game Julio J. Rotemberg Abstract: I suppose that people react with anger when others show themselves not to be minimally altruistic. With heterogeneous agents, this can account for the experimental results of ultimatum and dictator games.
    [Show full text]
  • Econs 424 % Bargaining Games and an Introduction to Repeated Games
    EconS 424 - Bargaining Games and an Introduction to Repeated Games Félix Muñoz-García Washington State University [email protected] March 25, 2014 Félix Muñoz-García (WSU) EconS 424 - Recitation 6 March25,2014 1/44 Watson, Ch. 19 # 8 In experimental tests of the ultimatum bargaining game, subjects who propose the split rarely o¤er a tiny share of the surplus to the other party. Furthermore, sometimes subjects reject positive o¤ers. These …ndings seem to contradict our standard analysis of the ultimatum bargaining game. Many scholars conclude that the payo¤s speci…ed in the basic model do not represent the actual preferences of the people who participate in the experiments. In reality, people care about more than their own monetary rewards. Félix Muñoz-García (WSU) EconS 424 - Recitation 6 March25,2014 2/44 Watson, Ch. 19 # 8 For example, people also act on feelings of spite and the ideal of fairness. Suppose that, in the ultimatum game, the responder’spayo¤ is y + a(y z), where y is the responder’smonetary reward, z is the proposer’smonetary take, and a is a positive constant. That is, the responder cares about how much money he gets and he cares about relative monetary amounts (the di¤erence between the money he gets and the money the other player gets). Assume that the proposer’spayo¤ is as in the basic model. Represent this game in the extensive form, writing the payo¤s in terms of m, the monetary o¤er of the proposer, and the parameter a. Félix Muñoz-García (WSU) EconS 424 - Recitation 6 March25,2014 3/44 Watson, Ch.
    [Show full text]
  • Bargaining Under a Deadline: Evidence from the Reverse Ultimatum Game ✩
    Games and Economic Behavior 45 (2003) 347–368 www.elsevier.com/locate/geb Bargaining under a deadline: evidence from the reverse ultimatum game ✩ Uri Gneezy,a,b Ernan Haruvy,c and Alvin E. Roth d,e,∗ a University of Chicago Graduate School of Business, Chicago, IL, USA b Technion, Israel Institute of Technology, Haifa, Israel c School of Management, University of Texas at Dallas, Richardson, TX, USA d Department of Economics, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA, USA e Harvard Business School, Boston, MA, USA Received 8 January 2003 Abstract We study a “reverse” ultimatum game, in which proposers have multiple chances to offer responders a division of some fixed pie. The game ends if the responder accepts an offer, or if, following a rejection, the proposer decides not to make a better offer. The unique subgame perfect equilibrium gives the proposer the minimum possible payoff. Nevertheless, the experimental results are not too different from those of the standard ultimatum game, although proposers generally receive slightly less than half of the surplus. We use the reverse ultimatum game to study deadlines experimentally. With a deadline, the subgame perfect equilibrium prediction is that the proposer gets the entire surplus. Deadlines are used strategically to influence the outcome, and agreements are reached near the deadline. Strategic considerations are evident in the differences in observed behavior between the deadline and no deadline conditions, even though agreements are substantially less extreme than predicted by perfect equilibrium. 2003 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved. JEL classification: C7; C9 ✩ Accompanying materials to be found at http://www.utdallas.edu/~eharuvy/deadline/.
    [Show full text]
  • Reciprocity and Overoptimism in Public Goods Games
    Biased Beliefs and Reciprocal Behavior in Social Dilemmas Von der Fakultät für Wirtschaftswissenschaften der Rheinisch-Westfälischen Technischen Hochschule Aachen zur Erlangung des akademischen Grades eines Doktors der Wirtschafts- und Sozialwissenschaften genehmigte Dissertation vorgelegt von Dipl.-Ing. Anselm Hüwe Berichter: Univ.-Prof. Dr. rer. pol. Wolfgang Breuer Univ.-Prof. Dr. rer. pol. Christine Harbring Tag der mündlichen Prüfung: 21.04.2015 Diese Dissertation ist auf den Internetseiten der Hochschulbibliothek online verfügbar. Table of Contents 1 Introduction ............................................................................................................................. 1 2 Economic Experiments ........................................................................................................... 3 3 Game Theory and (Common) Belief in Rationality ................................................................ 8 3.1 Boundedly Rational Behavior ........................................................................................ 11 3.2 Biased Beliefs ................................................................................................................. 14 4 Social Preferences ................................................................................................................. 15 4.1 When Social Preferences Should Be Assumed, and When Not ..................................... 16 4.2 Evolutionary Analysis ...................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Theory and Evidence on Bargaining University of Oxford, Michaelmas
    Behavioural Economics: Theory and Evidence on Bargaining University of Oxford, Michaelmas Term 2013 and Asia Summer Institute in Behavioral Economics National University of Singapore, 22 July-2 August 2013 Vincent P. Crawford, University of Oxford, All Souls College, and University of California, San Diego (with thanks to Sergei Izmalkov, Paul Milgrom, Al Roth and Muhamet Yildiz) Revised 3 July 2013 1 Bargaining Bargaining is at the heart of game-theoretic microeconomics. There are two prominent strands of theory, and some important experiments that raise questions about the theory, still unresolved. The theory includes the unstructured/cooperative theory of Nash (1950 Eonometrica), the structured/cooperative theory of Nash (1953 Econometrica) and the structured/noncooperative theory of Rubinstein (1982 Econometrica). The experiments include the unstructured bargaining experiments of Roth, Murnighan, and collaborators, culminating in Roth and Murnighan (1982 Econometrica), and structured bargaining experiments. In these slides I briefly consider both theory and experiments. 2 Rubinstein’s structured/noncooperative theory of bargaining Rubinstein’s theory postulates that bargaining proceeds via a given noncooperative game, in which two bargainers make alternating offers to each other on a fixed schedule until they reach an agreement. In Rubinstein’s version of the model there is no time limit. (Ingolf Stahl earlier studied a finite-horizon version, of which an extreme case is the one-period ultimatum game.) Delay is assumed to be costly (except in the ultimatum game, where delayed agreements are impossible anyway). The model allows the agreement to be about anything or things that are continuously variable, but I assume for simplicity that the bargainers are bargaining over the division of a dollar.
    [Show full text]
  • Backward Induction, Or SPNE’S
    LECTURE 10: GAMES IN EXTENSIVE FORM Jan Zouhar Games and Decisions Sequential Move Games 2 so far, we have only dealt with simultaneous games (players make the decisions at the same time, or simply without knowing what the action of their opponent is) in most games played for amusement (cards, chess, other board games), players make moves in turns → sequential move games many economic problems are in the sequential form: English auctions price competition: firms repeatedly charge prices executive compensation (contract signed; then executive works) monetary authority and firms (continually observe and learn actions) … formally, we describe these as games in extensive form (representation using a game tree) Games and Decisions Jan Zouhar Class Game: Century Mark 3 rules: played by fixed pairs of players taking turns at each turn, each player chooses a number (integer) between 1 and 10 inclusive this choice is added to sum of all previous choices (initial sum is 0) the first player to take the cumulative sum above 100 (century) loses the game prize: 5 extra points for the final test (!!!) Volunteers? Games and Decisions Jan Zouhar Class Game: Century Mark (cont’d) 4 Analysis of the game what’s the winning strategy? broadly speaking, bring the sum to 89; then your opponent can’t possibly win actually, it’s enough to bring it to 78; then you can make sure to make it 89 later reasoning like this, the winning positions are: 100, 89, 78, 67, 56, 45, 34, 23, 12, 1 → the first mover can guarantee a win! winning strategy: in
    [Show full text]
  • Section Note 3
    Section Note 3 Ariella Kahn-Lang and Guthrie Gray-Lobe∗ February 13th 2013 Agenda 1. Game Trees 2. Writing out Strategies and the Strategy Space 3. Backwards Induction 1 Game Trees Let's review the basic elements of game trees (extensive form games). Remember, we can write any game in either its normal (matrix) form or its extensive (tree) form - which representation we use is mainly a question of which solution concept we want to implement. Game trees are particularly useful for representing dynamic (sequential) games, primarily be- cause they easily allow us to implement the simple solution concept of backwards induction (see later). 1.1 Dynamic Games vs. Simultaneous Games Many important economic applications in game theory cannot be described by a simultaneous move game. Recall that a simultaneous game is one where all players were choosing their actions without any information about actions chosen by other players. A dynamic game, in contrast, is one where at least one player at some point of the game is choosing his action with some information about actions chosen previously. While dynamic games are often sequential over time, what matters is not the timing, but the information a player holds about previous moves in the game, because this is what enables them to condition their strategy on previous moves. For this reason, the `order' in which we draw a game tree matters only in getting the flow of information correctly. In simultaneous games, we can draw the game tree either way round and it represents the same game. ∗Thanks to previous years' TF's for making their section materials available for adaptation.
    [Show full text]