Thinking Beyond the Narrow Horizon of Liberal Justice

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Thinking Beyond the Narrow Horizon of Liberal Justice Rights Discourse and Economic Domination: Thinking Beyond the Narrow Horizon of Liberal Justice by Igor Shoikhedbrod A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Political Science University of Toronto © Copyright by Igor Shoikhedbrod 2018 Rights Discourse and Economic Domination: Thinking Beyond the Narrow Horizon of Liberal Justice Igor Shoikhedbrod Doctor of Philosophy Department of Political Science University of Toronto 2018 Abstract This dissertation offers a theoretical reconstruction of Karl Marx’s materialist conception of right through a re-examination of his critique of liberalism. The liberal conception of justice regards individuals as equal rights-bearers in abstraction from material circumstances and asymmetries of economic power. The dominant interpretation among leading Marxist and Anglo-American political theorists is that Marx’s critique of liberalism culminates with the “withering away” of right and rights in post-capitalist society. Explanations for this view have been framed around the postulation that communist society transcends the “circumstances of justice,” and that the end of class domination would pave the way for the disappearance of juridical relations. The first part of the dissertation questions this longstanding interpretation by reconstructing Marx’s materialist conception of right. The central thesis of the dissertation is that Marx regards right as an essential feature of any mode of production, including the future communist society, and that standards of right undergo transformation throughout history. The historical expansion of human freedom also provides Marx with a normative basis for assessing between higher and lower standards of right across different modes of production. The second part of the dissertation tracks the enduring legacy ii of Marx’s critique of liberal justice by examining how leading contemporary political theorists have responded to Marx’s challenge in the face of global financial capitalism and the hollowing out of democratically-enacted law. The dissertation also reconsiders the relationship between Marxism and the idea of the rule of law in the current era of neoliberal hegemony. Taken together, the dissertation aims at reconstructing Marx’s views on right and rights in ways that resonate with ongoing debates in political theory and the broader public sphere. iii Acknowledgements As I reflect on my doctoral journey in the political science department at the University of Toronto, I am reminded of a pithy saying that is commonly attributed to Isocrates: “The root of education is bitter but its fruit is sweet.” Looking back, I have learned to appreciate the bitterness of the root along with sweetness of the fruit, although this has not been easy. One thing is certain: I would have never ventured as far as I did without the unwavering support, commitment and care of the many people who helped bring this dissertation to fruition. I was fortunate to work with an erudite group of scholars, each of whom challenged me to think rigorously without compromising the intent of the dissertation. I am grateful to Simone Chambers for signing on as supervisor and for having faith in the project throughout. Simone taught me the importance of conveying my thoughts clearly and anticipating the learned critic at every turn. In return, I hope to have made the modest contribution of persuading her that there is a neglected side of Marx that is worth retrieving and defending, now more than ever. Peggy Kohn served as co- supervisor and has been a dedicated mentor since my undergraduate days, encouraging my interest in critical political theory and seeing to it that I did not shed my normative commitments along the way. Alan Brudner made me think long and hard about the place of right and rights in a social context where freedom would be given its proper due. I have benefitted immensely from his insights about the law and have intentionally sought to reaffirm the Hegelian heritage that informs Marx’s social and political thought. Thanks as well to Joseph Carens for serving as the internal reader and to Professor Carol Gould for agreeing to be the external examiner at such short notice. iv Beyond members of my dissertation committee, I thank Edward Andrew, Richard Day and the late Abraham Rotstein for reading early chapters of my thesis and offering valuable feedback. Although I did not work with Ronald Beiner, Ruth Marshall and Melissa Williams, my work benefitted immensely from their critical insights, most of which were articulated in the context of the department’s signature Political Theory Research Workshops. I am also grateful to Markus Dubber, Simon Stern, Peter Russell, Peter Solomon, and Peter Rosenthal for showing an interest in my thesis and taking the time to discuss the law with an aspiring political theorist. From U of T’s philosophy department, thanks are due to Daniel Goldstick for reading scattered parts of my dissertation with great care and offering painstaking commentary; Derek Allen for contributing to a stimulating CPSA panel on “Rethinking the Controversy of Marx on Justice”; and Frank Cunningham for offering sage advice and agreeing to participate in virtually every social justice-themed panel that I helped organize at the University of Toronto. I would also like to express my gratitude to three former instructors. John Duncan could always be counted on to offer around the clock advice on a host of practical issues, proving that the study of ethics is barren without engaging and being engaged by the community around us. I am thankful to David Carvounas for helping instill in me a sober sense of academic reality and demonstrating what it takes to be an animating lecturer. Esteve Morera helped me navigate through the maze of graduate school well after my time at York University and taught me to appreciate normative political philosophy despite its abstract character. Thanks are also due to my colleagues, past and present, who engaged with my work in the most diverse settings and gave me a much needed sense of community. I am especially grateful to Khalid Ahmed, Noaman Ali, Ozlem Aslan, Adrian Atanasescu, Mark Barbisan, Sude Beltan, Sarah v Beamish, Dragana Bodruzic, Robert Ballingall, Kiran Banerjee, Andrea Cassatella, Yi-Chun Chien, Wayne Dealy, Scott Dodds, Alena Drieschova, Kevin Edmonds, Paul Gray, Matthew Hamilton, Teddy Harrison, Xunming Huang, Kyumin Ju, Margaret Hadarer, Olga Kesarchuk, Kate Korycki Simon Lambek, Jaby Matthew, Nicola Milicic, Emma Planinc, Alesha Porisky, Evan Rosevear, Sarah Rich-Zendel, Craig Smith, Jonas Schwab-Pflug, Abraham Singer, Alexander Sodiquov, Mauricio Suchowlansky, Ella Street, Dorina Verli, Tvrtko Vrdoljak, and Constantine Vassilou. Through the course of conference travels, I met with various scholars and kindred spirits that helped make my work better. I thank the organizing committee of the Marx and Philosophy Society in the United Kingdom (especially Andrew Chitty, Sean Sayers, Meade McCloughan and Jan Kandiyali) for allowing me to present early drafts of my work in front of an engaged audience of scholars and activists. I also had the privilege of presenting an early version of my fourth chapter at the workshop on “Recognition and Socialism,” which was held on the occasion of Axel Honneth’s 65th birthday. I thank Professor Honneth for engaging thoughtfully with my spirited, albeit rudimentary critique. At the same workshop, I met Arthur Bueno, Victor Kempf, Mariana Teixeira, with whom I later collaborated on thought-provoking panels in Rome and Calgary. I also received valuable feedback and encouragement from Robert Fine, Melis Menent, and Eleonora Piromalli at the International Critical Theory Conference in Rome. In the spring-summer of 2015, following our extended T.A strike, I was a visiting student scholar at the Normative Orders Cluster of Excellence at the Goethe-Universität in Frankfurt. I am grateful to Professor Rainer Forst for welcoming me into Frankfurt’s political theory community. Julian vi Culp helped me prepare for Frankfurt while I was still immersed in Toronto and was always willing to discuss matters of practical as well as strategic reason. During multiple stays in Frankfurt, I could always count on the good philosophic company and hospitality of Marco Fataf and his flatmates. With the help of the SGS Travel Grant, I conducted research at the Berlin-Brandenburg Academy of Sciences and Humanities and at the Institute of Social History in Amsterdam. While in Berlin, I had the good fortune of meeting Jürgen Herres, researcher for the Marx-Engels-Gesamtausgabe, who drew my attention to important manuscripts and left me with an informative lesson about the legal history of the Rhine province during the revolutionary period of 1848-49. Around the same time, I attended a superb workshop on “Marx und Recht” that was sponsored by the Rosa Luxemburg Stiftung, and in which Professors Sonja Buckel and Christophe Menke delivered engaging lectures. I am grateful to Sonja Buckel and Chrisophe Menke for meeting with me in Frankfurt and offering constructive feedback. It is always encouraging to learn that one’s research interests are shared by leading scholars in the field. I also thank Rolf Hecker for drawing my attention to the Berlin workshop and educating me about the MEGA2 initiative. Closer to home, I had the unwavering support of friends who kept me smiling during the most challenging times. Thank you to Steve Halperin for joining me on at least two memorable expeditions and listening to my gratuitous philosophic rants since the sixth grade. Jaspreet Sahota was an outstanding sparring partner throughout the doctoral programme and helped me surpass self-imposed intellectual and fitness hurdles. Thanks as well to Lima Al-Said, Banafsheh Beizaei, Kristy Bard, Raluca Bejan, Kaveh Boveiri, Susanna Gafarova, Melissa Grisolia, Anna Postelnyak, vii Niloo Mouzafar and Selena Lucien-Shaboian for being there and reminding me about the big picture. I owe the greatest debt to my family: Michael, Irina, Elena, Arik, and Aiden.
Recommended publications
  • Change the World Without Taking Power. the Meaning of Revolution Today
    Change the World without Taking Power. The Meaning of Revolution Today. John Holloway Originally published 2002 by Pluto Press Chapter 1 – The Scream . 2 Chapter 2 – Beyond the State? . 9 Chapter 3 – Beyond Power? . 14 Chapter 4 – Fetishism . 30 Chapter 5 – Fetishism and Fetishisation . 52 Chapter 6 – Anti-fetishism and Criticism . 70 Chapter 7 – The Tradition of Scientific Marxism . 77 Chapter 8 – The Critical-Revolutionary Subject . 91 Chapter 9 – The Material Reality of Anti-Power . .101 Chapter 10 – The Material Reality of Anti-Power and the Crisis of Capital . Chapter 11 – Revolution? . 132 1 Chapter 1 - The Scream I In the beginning is the scream. We scream. When we write or when we read, it is easy to forget that the beginning is not the word, but the scream. Faced with the mutilation of human lives by capitalism, a scream of sadness, a scream of horror, a scream of anger, a scream of refusal: NO. The starting point of theoretical reflection is opposition, negativity, struggle. It is from rage that thought is born, not from the pose of reason, not from the reasoned-sitting-back-and-reflecting-on- the-mysteries-of-existence that is the conventional image of ‘the thinker’. We start from negation, from dissonance. The dissonance can take many shapes. An inarticulate mumble of discontent, tears of frustration, a scream of rage, a confident roar. An unease, a confusion, a longing, a critical vibration. Our dissonance comes from our experience, but that experience varies. Sometimes it is the direct experience of exploitation in the factory, or of oppression in the home, of stress in the office, of hunger and poverty, or of state violence or discrimination.
    [Show full text]
  • Eugen Ehrlich, Evgeny Pashukanis, and Meaningful Freedom Through Incremental Jurisprudential Change
    Journal of Libertarian Studies JLS Volume 23 (2019): 64–90 A Practical Approach to Legal- Pluralist Anarchism: Eugen Ehrlich, Evgeny Pashukanis, and Meaningful Freedom through Incremental Jurisprudential Change Jason M. Morgan2 ABSTRACT: John Hasnas (2008) has famously argued that anarchy is obvious and everywhere. It is less well known, however, that Hasnas also argues that anarchy must be achieved gradually. But how can this work? In this paper, I show that directly confronting state power will never produce viable anarchy (or minarchy). Using the example of Soviet jurist Evgeny Pashukanis, I detail an episode in apparent anti-statism which, by relying on the state, ended in disaster for the putative anti-statist. I next show how combining the theories of Austrian legal thinker Eugen Ehrlich and American political philosopher William Sewell, Jr., can lead to a gradual undoing of state power via case law. Finally, I bring in the example of Japanese jurist and early anti-statist Suehiro Izutarō as a warning. Suehiro also attempted to decrease state power by means of case law, but because he lacked a clear anti-statist teleology he ended up becoming an accomplice of state power, even imperialism. The way to Hasnian anarchy/minarchy lies through the skillful application of case law with an eye always towards the attenuation, and eventual elimination, of the power of the state. Jason M. Morgan ([email protected]) is associate professor of foreign languages at Reitaku University. The author would like to thank Lenore Ealy, Joe Salerno, and Mark Thornton for helpful comments on an early draft of this article.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 David Schweickart's “Economic Democracy”
    David Schweickart’s “Economic Democracy” Loyola University Professor David Schweickart has developed a detailed alternative system model he calls “Economic Democracy.” According to Schweickart, our current economic system—capitalism—rests on three kinds of institutions: markets for goods and services; wage labor; and private control over investment. The problem, he argues, isn’t with markets per se, but with the ownership and management of enterprises and the allocation of the surplus as private investment driven by the overriding interest in profitability. Economic Democracy, therefore, would preserve a role for (regulated) markets in goods and services while extending democracy into the workplace and the linked spheres of finance and investment. In place of private ownership of the means of production with markets in capital, labor, goods and services under capitalism, or state ownership and central planning under various real-world variants of socialism and communism, Economic Democracy has a basic economic structure of socially-owned, worker-controlled firms in a competitive market. The model has neither capital markets nor labor markets in the usual sense. Although workers control their own jobs and workplaces, productive resources would become the collective property of society and there is social control over investment through the allocation of the economic surplus at various levels. Economic Democracy seeks to give workers and local communities greater participatory autonomy, allowing them to more fully influence decisions and shape rules that impact their economic lives. Real-world examples of some of the key institutions of Economic Democracy include the Mondragon network of worker cooperatives in Spain, the practice of worker self-management in the former Yugoslavia, and public and cooperative banks in Germany and in North Dakota.
    [Show full text]
  • Marxist and Soviet Law Stephen C
    Saint Louis University School of Law Scholarship Commons All Faculty Scholarship 2014 Marxist and Soviet Law Stephen C. Thaman Saint Louis University School of Law Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.slu.edu/faculty Part of the Comparative and Foreign Law Commons, Criminal Law Commons, Criminal Procedure Commons, and the European Law Commons Recommended Citation Thaman, Stephen C., Marxist and Soviet Law (2014). The Oxford Handbook of Criminal Law (Markus D. Dubber and Tatjana Hörnle, eds.), Chpt. 14, 2014. This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarship Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in All Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of Scholarship Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. No. 2015-2 Marxist and Soviet Law The Oxford Handbook of Criminal Law Stephen C. Thaman Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2570530 The Oxford Handbook of CRIMINAL LAW Edited by MARKUS D. DUBBER and TATJANA HÖRNLE 1 9780199673599_Hornle_Book.indb 3 Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=257053010/28/2014 1:05:38 PM 1 Great Clarendon Street, Oxford, ox2 6dp, United Kingdom Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries © The several contributors 2014 The moral rights of the authors have been asserted First Edition published in 2014 Impression: 1 All rights reserved.
    [Show full text]
  • Legal Naturalism Is a Disjunctivism Roderick T. Long Legal Positivists
    Legal Naturalism Is a Disjunctivism Roderick T. Long Auburn University aaeblog.com | [email protected] Abstract: Legal naturalism is the doctrine that a rule’s status as law depends on its moral content; or, in its strongest form, that “an unjust law is not a law.” By drawing an analogy between legal naturalism and perceptual disjunctivism, I argue that this doctrine is more defensible than is generally thought, and in particular that it entails no conflict with ordinary usage. Legal positivists hold that a rule’s status as law never depends on its moral content. In Austin’s famous formulation: “The existence of law is one thing; its merit or demerit is another. Whether a law be is one enquiry; whether it ought to be, or whether it agree with a given or assumed test, is another and different inquiry.”1 There seems to be no generally accepted term for the opposed view, that a rule’s status as law does (sometimes or always) depend on its moral content. Legal moralism would be the natural choice, but that name is already taken to mean the view that the law should impose social standards of morality on private conduct. Legal normativisim, another natural choice, is, somewhat perversely, already in use to denote a species of legal positivism.2 The position in question is sometimes referred to as “the natural law view,” but this is not really accurate; although the view has been held by many natural law theorists, it has not been held by all of them, and is not strictly implied by the natural law position.
    [Show full text]
  • Copyright © and Moral Rights for This Phd Thesis Are Retained by the Author And/Or Other Copyright Owners. a Copy Can Be Downlo
    Taylor, Owen (2014) International law and revolution. PhD Thesis. SOAS, University of London. http://eprints.soas.ac.uk/id/eprint/20343 Copyright © and Moral Rights for this PhD Thesis are retained by the author and/or other copyright owners. A copy can be downloaded for personal non‐commercial research or study, without prior permission or charge. This PhD Thesis cannot be reproduced or quoted extensively from without first obtaining permission in writing from the copyright holder/s. The content must not be changed in any way or sold commercially in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holders. When referring to this PhD Thesis, full bibliographic details including the author, title, awarding institution and date of the PhD Thesis must be given e.g. AUTHOR (year of submission) "Full PhD Thesis title", name of the School or Department, PhD PhD Thesis, pagination. INTERNATIONAL LAW AND REVOLUTION OWEN TAYLOR Thesis submitted for the degree of PhD 2014 Law Department SOAS, University of London 1 Declaration for SOAS PhD thesis I have read and understood regulation 17.9 of the Regulations for students of the SOAS, University of London concerning plagiarism. I undertake that all the material presented for examination is my own work and has not been written for me, in whole or in part, by any other person. I also undertake that any quotation or paraphrase from the published or unpublished work of another person has been duly acknowledged in the work which I present for examination. Signed: ____________________________ Date: _________________23/10/2014 2 ABSTRACT: This thesis aims to provide an investigation into how revolutionary transformation aimed to affect the international legal order itself, rather than what the international order might have to say about a revolution.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of International Law H
    Anthony Carty is Professor of Public Law at the Philosophy of University of Aberdeen. P Philosophy of International Law h i ANTHONY CARTY l o s A fundamental challenge to the foundations o International Law of the discipline of international law. p This book offers an internal critique of the h discipline of international law whilst showing y the necessary place for philosophy within this o ANTHONY CARTY subject area. By reintroducing philosophy into f the heart of the study of international law, I Anthony Carty explains how traditionally n philosophy has always been an integral part of t the discipline. However, this has been driven e out by legal positivism, which has, in turn, r n become a pure technique of law. He explores the extent of the disintegration and confusion a in the discipline and offers various ways of t i renewing philosophical practice. o n A range of approaches are covered – post- Jacket design: River Design, Edinburgh a structuralism, neo-Marxist geopolitics, social- Jacket image: Kurt Hutton/Hulton Archive/ l democratic constitutional theory and Getty Images L existential phenomenology – encouraging the Shawcross at the Hague Court in 1948: ‘[ . ] a reader to think afresh about how far to bring Parties to litigation are not entitled to use w order to, or find order in, contemporary merely those documents which they think will international society. assist their case and to suppress others which Key Features are inimical to it. [ . ] As it is, we retain great A misgivings about the propriety of what is being N • Offers a broad survey of possible done, which we can only justify on the T philosophical approaches to international principle “my country [ .
    [Show full text]
  • The Situation on the International Legal Theory Front: the Power of Rules and the Rule of Power
    q EJIL 2000 ............................................................................................. The Situation on the International Legal Theory Front: The Power of Rules and the Rule of Power Gerry Simpson* Abstract The rejuvenation of international law in the last decade has its source in two developments. On the one hand, ‘critical legal scholarship’ has infiltrated the discipline and provided it with a new sensibility and self-consciousness. On the other hand, liberal international lawyers have reached out to International Relations scholarship to recast the ways in which rules and power are approached. Meanwhile, the traditional debates about the source and power of norms have been invigorated by these projects. This review article considers these developments in the light of a recent contribution to international legal theory, Michael Byers’ Custom, Power and the Power of Rules. The article begins by entering a number of reservations to Byers’ imaginative strategy for reworking customary law and his distinctive approach to the enigma of opinio juris. The discussion then broadens by placing Byers’ book in the expanding dialogue between International Relations and International Law. Here, the article locates the mutual antipathy of the two disciplines in two moments of intellectual hubris: Wilson’s liberal certainty in 1919 and realism’s triumphalism in the immediate post-World War II era. The article then goes on to suggest that, despite a valiant effort, Byers cannot effect a reconciliation between the two disciplines and, in particular, the power of rules and the three theoretical programmes against which he argues: realism, institutionalism and constructivism. Finally, Byers’ book is characterized as a series of skirmishes on the legal theory front; a foray into an increasingly rich, adversarial and robust dialogue about the way to approach the study of international law and the goals one might support within the * Law Department, London School of Economics.
    [Show full text]
  • CURRICULUM VITAE July 2007
    CURRICULUM VITAE January 2013 FRANK CUNNINGHAM Date of Birth: 5 August, 1940. Cities Centre 130 Carlton St. University of Toronto unit 905 455 Spadina Ave. Toronto, Ontario Toronto, Ontario Canada M5A 4K3 Canada M5S 2G8 416-962-9788 416-978-5590 E-mail: [email protected] web: http://individual.utoronto.ca/frankcunningham ACADEMIC HISTORY Ph.D. University of Toronto 1970 M.A. University of Chicago 1965 B.A. Indiana University 1962 University of Toronto Appointments Philosophy Department: Lecturer 1967; Assistant Professor, 1970; Associate Professor, 1974; Professor, 1986. Department of Political Science: Cross Appointment, 2000. Associate Instructor of History and Philosophy of Education, OISE, University of Toronto, 2007 - . Cities Centre, University of Toronto, 2007 - . Emeritus Professor of Philosophy and Political Science, University of Toronto, 2009 - . Visiting Positions University of Amsterdam, Fall 1990 Lanzhou University (PRC), Spring, 199l Ritsumeikan University (Kyoto), Fall 1994, Fall 1997, Spring 2007 University of Rome (I), Spring 1999 Posts Interim Director, Centre for Ethics, University of Toronto, 2011. Principal, Innis College, University of Toronto, 2000- 2005 President, Canadian Philosophical Association, 1997-98 (Vice President, 1996-97) Chair, Department of Philosophy, University of Toronto, 1982- 88 (Associate Chair, 1977-8; Acting Chair, 1991-92) HONOURS Recipient, SAC/APUS Undergraduate Teaching Award, 2005 Recipient, Queen’s Golden Jubilee Medal, 2002 Senior Fellow, Massey College, University of Toronto, 1999 - Fellow of the Royal Society of Canada, 1995 - Faculty Teaching Fellow, University of Toronto, 1974-75 Mary Beatty Fellowship, University of Toronto, 1965-66 School of Letters Fellowship, Indiana University, 1964-5 Woodrow Wilson Fellowship, 1962-63 Phi Beta Kappa, 1962 Ford Foundation Fellowship, 1961-62 2 TEACHING Introductory Courses: Introduction to Philosophy, Political Philosophy, Science and Society (in the Faculty of Applied Science and Engineering), Environmental Ethics.
    [Show full text]
  • SOCIOLOGY 9191A Social Science in the Marxian Tradition Fall 2020
    SOCIOLOGY 9191A Social Science in the Marxian Tradition Fall 2020 DRAFT Class times and location Wednesday 10:30am -12:30pm Virtual synchronous Instructor: David Calnitsky Office Hours by appointment Department of Sociology Office: SSC 5402 Email: [email protected] Technical Requirements: Stable internet connection Laptop or computer Working microphone Working webcam “The philosophers have only interpreted the world, in various ways. The point, however, is to change it.” – Karl Marx That is the point, it’s true—but not in this course. This quote, indirectly, hints at a deep tension in Marxism. If we want to change the world we need to understand it. But the desire to change something can infect our understanding of it. This is a pervasive dynamic in the history of Marxism and the first step is to admit there is a problem. This means acknowledging the presence of wishful thinking, without letting it induce paralysis. On the other hand, if there are pitfalls in being upfront in your desire to change the world there are also virtues. The normative 1 goal of social change helps to avoid common trappings of academia, in particular, the laser focus on irrelevant questions. Plus, in having a set of value commitments, stated clearly, you avoid the false pretense that values don’t enter in the backdoor in social science, which they often do if you’re paying attention. With this caveat in place, Marxian social science really does have a lot to offer in understanding the world and that’s what we’ll analyze in this course. The goal is to look at the different hypotheses that broadly emerge out of the Marxian tradition and see the extent to which they can be supported both theoretically and empirically.
    [Show full text]
  • Reconstructing Structural Marxism
    REVIEWS Reconstructing Structural Marxism Ted Benton, The Rise and Fall of Structural Marxism; The charge of Stalinism, together with the current Althusser and his Influence, Macmillan, London, 1984, state of disarray amongst Althusserians, provides 259pp lI8.00 hc, 1.6.95 pb Benton with one of the two major reasons for writing Rise and Fall; namely to defend Structural Marxism Benton's book has many facets: it is an introductory against post-structuralist and other critics (the other text, a re-evaluation and reconstruction of Structural reason being the need for an introductory text in the Marxism, an argument for theoretical progress lying area). One way in which .8enton accomplishes this def­ through the synthesis of Structural Marxism with do­ ence is by laying bare Structural Marxism'S sociological mains such as the ecological, biological and psycho­ complexi ty. This completely appears as the obverse side logical. Of immediate political relevance is its claim of the process of displacement,· as decentr ing, of human that theorisation of socialist strategy requires a recog­ agency by the Althusserian paradigm. The stratagem of nition by the Marxist tradition of non class-based decentring, an anti-reificatory device, denies that the emancipatory social movements. AU these strands are individual agent is onto logically prior to social. struc­ brought together in the major objective of the book - a tures, events and processes. This refutation of the critical defence of Structural Marxism. 'social substantiality' of the individual subject is the Rise and Fall is divided into three thematic parts. basis of Althusser's anti-humanism. The first centres on questions of epistemology as they surface in Structural Marxism: the science-ideology dis­ Sociological complexity tinction, the epistemological break, the concept of a problematic, Marxism and philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Educational Philosophy: from Classical Marxism to Critical Pedagogy
    Marxian Perspectives on Educational Philosophy: From Classical Marxism to Critical Pedagogy By Douglas Kellner (http://www.gseis.ucla.edu/faculty/kellner/) It is surely not difficult to see that our time is a time of birth and transition to a new period. The spirit has broken with what was hitherto the world of its existence and imagination and is about to submerge all this in the past; it is at work giving itself a new form. To be sure, the spirit is never at rest but always engaged in ever progressing motion.... the spirit that educates itself matures slowly and quietly toward the new form, dissolving one particle of the edifice of its previous world after the other,.... This gradual crumbling... is interrupted by the break of day that, like lightning, all at once reveals the edifice of the new world. Hegel 1965 [1807]: 380. The theory associated with Marxism was developed in mid-19th century Europe by Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels. Although Marx and Engels did not write widely about education, they developed theoretical perspectives on modern societies that have been used to highlight the social functions of education and their concepts and methods have served to both theorize and criticize education in the reproduction of capitalist societies, and to support projects of alternative education. In this study, I will first briefly sketch the classical perspectives of Marx and Engels, highlighting the place of education in their work. Then, I lay out the way that Marxian perspectives on education were developed in the Frankfurt School critical theory, British cultural studies, and other neo- Marxian and post-Marxian approaches grouped under the label of critical pedagogy, that emerged from the work of Paulo Freire and is now global in scope.
    [Show full text]