Stable and Simple Theories (Lecture Notes)

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Stable and Simple Theories (Lecture Notes) Stable and simple theories (Lecture Notes) Enrique Casanovas Universidad de Barcelona September 5, 2007 2 Contents 1 Preliminaries 7 2 ϕ-types, stability and simplicity 9 3 ∆-types and the local rank D(π, ∆, k) 15 4 Forking 19 5 Independence 23 6 The local rank CB∆(π) 27 7 Heirs and coheirs 31 8 Stable forking 35 9 Lascar strong types 41 10 The independence theorem 45 11 Canonical bases 49 12 More on independence 55 13 Supersimple theories 63 14 More ranks 71 15 Hyperimaginaries 77 16 Forking for hyperimaginaries 83 17 Canonical bases revisited 91 3 4 CONTENTS 18 Elimination of hyperimaginaries 97 Preface These are lecture notes from a seminar imparted the academic years 2005-06 and 2006-07 at the Department of Logic of the University of Barcelona. They are incomplete, in process of revision and enlargement. In particular, the preliminaries contain only a few statements. Advanced knowledge of Model Theory is throughout assumed. The notes are based on the work of many modeltheorists. The names of John Baldwin, Byunghan Kim, Daniel Lascar, Anand Pillay, Bruno Poizat, Saharon Shelah, Frank Wagner and Martin Ziegler deserve special mention. I thank to the participants in the Seminar, Hans Adler, Silvia Barbina, Javier Moreno, Rodrigo Pel´aez, Juan Francisco Pons, and Joris Potier for their patience and their remarks. Of course, I am the only responsible for the mistakes or inaccuracies that might appear in the text. 5 6 CONTENTS Chapter 1 Preliminaries T is a complete theory of language L with infinite models and C is its monster model. A, B, C are subsets of C and a, b, c are sequences of elements of C. a ∈ A means that all the elements in the sequence a belong to A. We use x,y for single variables but also for sequences of variables. The existence of indiscernible sequences is usually established using Ramsey’s Theorem. It is convenient to introduce here a more powerful method based on Erd¨os-Rado Theorem. Proposition 1.1 If κ ≥ |T | is a cardinal number, λ = i(2κ)+ , |A| ≤ κ and (ai : i < λ) + is a sequence of sequences ai of fixed length α < κ , then there is an A-indiscernible sequence (bi : i < ω) such that for each n < ω there are i0 < . < in < λ such that b0, . , bn ≡A ai0 , . , ain . In most of the applications α is a natural number and therefore the cardinal number λ depends only on |T | and |A|. Corollary 1.2 1. If (ai : i < λ) is indiscernible over A, there is some model M ⊇ A such that (ai : i < λ) is indiscernible over M. eq 2. If (ai : i < λ) is indiscernible over A, then it is also indiscernible over acl (A). A canonical parameter of a definable relation R is an imaginary element c such that for all f ∈ Aut(C), f(R) = R if and only if f(c) = c. It is unique up to interdefinability and it can be constructed starting with some ϕ(x, y) such that ϕ(C, a) = R by c = a/E where E is the 0-definable equivalence relation given by E(b, d) ⇔ ϕ(C, b) = ϕ(C, d) The following result on definability and imaginaries will be useful: Proposition 1.3 The following are equivalent for any definable relation R: 1. R is definable over any model M ⊇ A. 2. R has only finitely many A-conjugates. 3. R is a union of equivalence classes of some A-definable finite (i.e. with finitely many classes) equivalence relation. 4. R is definable over acleq(A). 7 8 CHAPTER 1. PRELIMINARIES Chapter 2 ϕ-types, stability and simplicity Definition 2.1 Let ϕ(x, y) ∈ L.A ϕ-formula over A is a formula of the form ϕ(x, a) or ¬ϕ(x, a) with a ∈ A.A ϕ-type over A is a consistent set of ϕ-formulas over A.A ϕ-type p(x) over A is complete if for every a ∈ A either ϕ(x, a) ∈ p or ¬ϕ(x, a) ∈ p. The set of all complete ϕ-types over A is Sϕ(A). Definition 2.2 Let ϕ(x, y) ∈ L. A complete ϕ-type p(x) over A is definable over B if there is a formula ψ(y) ∈ L(B) such that for all a ∈ A, ϕ(x, a) ∈ p ⇔ |= ψ(a) If B is not mentioned we understand that A = B. A complete type p(x) ∈ S(A) is definable if all its restrictions p ϕ are definable. Lemma 2.3 Let p(x) ∈ Sϕ(M) be definable. Then for each A ⊇ M there is a unique q ∈ Sϕ(A) extending p which is definable over M. Proof: Let ψ(y) ∈ L(M) be a definition of p. It is easy to check that {ϕ(x, a): a ∈ A, |= ψ(a)} ∪ {¬ϕ(x, a): a ∈ A, |= ¬ψ(a)} is consistent and it is in fact a complete ϕ- type over A extending p. On the other hand, if q1, q2 ∈ Sϕ(A) are M-definable extensions of p with definitions ψ1(y), ψ2(y) ∈ L(M), then M |= ∀y(ψ1(y) ↔ ψ2(y)), which implies C |= ∀y(ψ1(y) ↔ ψ2(y)) and therefore q1 = q2. 2 Definition 2.4 Let λ be an infinite cardinal number. We say that ϕ is λ-stable or stable in λ if for any set A, |A| ≤ λ ⇒ |Sϕ(A)| ≤ λ It is said that ϕ is stable if it is stable in some λ. Otherwise ϕ is called unstable. Proposition 2.5 The following conditions are equivalent for ϕ = ϕ(x, y) ∈ L. 1. ϕ(x, y) is stable. 2. Γϕ(ω) is inconsistent, where for any ordinal α, Γ (α) = {ϕ(x , y )ν(i) : ν ∈ 2α, i < α} ϕ ν νi and where ϕ0 = ϕ and ϕ1 = ¬ϕ. 9 10 CHAPTER 2. ϕ-TYPES, STABILITY AND SIMPLICITY 3. For any set A, any type p(x) ∈ Sϕ(A) is definable. 4. ϕ(x, y) is λ-stable for all λ. Moreover in 3. one can add that p is definable by a formula of the form ψ(y) = ∃x1 . xn∃y1 . ymχ(y, x1, . , xn, y1, . ym) where χ is a conjunction of formulas of the form ϕ(xi, yj), ¬ϕ(xi, yj), ϕ(xi, y) and ϕ(xi, y)- formulas over A. Proof: 1. ⇒ 2. Assume Γϕ(ω) is consistent. Let λ be an infinite cardinal number and µ <µ let µ be the least cardinal number such that 2 > λ. Then 2 ≤ λ. Since Γϕ(µ) is also <µ µ consistent, there is a sequence (bν : ν ∈ 2 ) such that for every ν ∈ 2 the set of ϕ-formulas ν(i) p (x) = {ϕ(x, b ) : i < µ} is consistent. Since p (x) is inconsistent with p 0 (x) for ν νi ν ν 0 µ <µ ν 6= ν , it follows that there are 2 > λ complete ϕ-types over the set A = {bν : ν ∈ 2 } but |A| ≤ λ. This shows that ϕ(x, y) is not λ-stable. 2. ⇒ 3. Let p(x) ∈ Sϕ(A) and assume Γϕ(ω) is inconsistent. Then also Γϕ(ω) ∪ S ν∈2ω p(xν ) is inconsistent and by compactness there is a least natural number n for which [ Γϕ(n) ∪ p(xν ) ν∈2n is inconsistent. Again by compactness, there is a finite subset p0(x) ⊆ p(x) such that S Γϕ(n) ∪ ν∈2n p0(xν ) is inconsistent. Then n > 0 and one can check that for any a ∈ A, [ ϕ(x, a) ∈ p ⇔ Γϕ(n − 1) ∪ p0(xν ) ∪ {ϕ(xν , a)} is consistent ν∈2n−1 that is n−1 <n−1 ^ ^ ϕ(x, a) ∈ p ⇔ ∃(xν : ν ∈ 2 )∃(yη : η ∈ 2 )( Γϕ(n − 1) ∧ p0(xν ) ∧ ϕ(xν , a)) ν∈2n−1 which is a definition of p of the form indicated above. 3. ⇒ 4. Since there are at most λ many definitions of the described form over a set A with |A| ≤ λ, there are also λ many complete ϕ-types over A. This shows that ϕ(x, y) is λ-stable for any λ but uses the hypothesis 3. with the added information on the form of the definition. Without this information we can only guarantee that it is stable in any λ ≥ |T |. But this is enough since after all we have established that 1. implies 4. 2 Remark 2.6 If ϕ is stable any global ϕ-type p ∈ Sϕ(C) is definable. Proof: The proof of 2 ⇒ 3 given for Proposition 2.5 works also for p ∈ Sϕ(C). 2 Definition 2.7 ϕ = ϕ(x, y) ∈ L has the order property if for some ai, bi (i < ω) the following holds: |= ϕ(ai, bj) ⇔ i < j Remark 2.8 1. ϕ(x, y) has the order property if and only if for some ai, bi (i < ω), |= ϕ(ai, bj) ⇔ i ≤ j. 2. ϕ(x, y) has the order property if and only if ¬ϕ(x, y) has the order property. 11 3. In the definition of the order property one can change the index set ω and its order by any infinite linear ordering. Lemma 2.9 Assume ϕ = ϕ(x, y) does not have the order property. If p ∈ Sϕ(A) is finitely satisfiable in A (which is always true if A is a model), then p is definable by a positive boolean combination of formulas of the form ϕ(a, y) with a ∈ A. Proof: Let X1,...,Xn be a family of subsets of a set A.
Recommended publications
  • [Math.LO] 2 Mar 2011 39,18B40
    GROUPOIDS, IMAGINARIES AND INTERNAL COVERS EHUD HRUSHOVSKI Abstract. Let T be a first-order theory. A correspondence is established between internal covers of models of T and definable groupoids within T . We also consider amalgamations of independent diagrams of algebraically closed substructures, and find strong relation between: covers, uniqueness for 3-amalgamation, existence of 4-amalgamation, imaginaries of T σ, and definable groupoids. As a corollary, we describe the imaginary elements of families of finite- dimensional vector spaces over pseudo-finite fields. The questions this manuscript addresses arose in the course of an investigation of the imag- inary sorts in ultraproducts of p-adic fields. These were shown to be understandable given the imaginary sorts of certain finite-dimensional vector spaces over the residue field. The residue field is pseudo-finite, and the imaginary elements there were previously studied, and shown in fact to be eliminable over an appropriate base. It remains therefore to describe the imaginaries of finite-dimensional vector spaces over a field F , given those of F . I expected this step to be rather easy; but it turned out to become easy only after a number of issues, of interest in themselves, are made clear. Let T be a first-order theory. A correspondence is established between internal covers of models of T and definable groupoids within T . Internal covers were recognized as central in the study of totally categorical structures, but nevertheless remained mysterious; it was not clear how to describe the possible T ′ from the point of view of T . We give an account of this here, in terms of groupoids in place of equivalence relations.
    [Show full text]
  • Oort Conjecture for the Moduli Space of Abelian Surfaces
    COMPOSITIO MATHEMATICA The Andr´e{Oortconjecture for the moduli space of abelian surfaces Jonathan Pila and Jacob Tsimerman Compositio Math. 149 (2013), 204{216. doi:10.1112/S0010437X12000589 FOUNDATION COMPOSITIO MATHEMATICA Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 170.106.35.234, on 28 Sep 2021 at 16:32:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1112/S0010437X12000589 Compositio Math. 149 (2013) 204{216 doi:10.1112/S0010437X12000589 The Andr´e{Oortconjecture for the moduli space of abelian surfaces Jonathan Pila and Jacob Tsimerman Abstract We provide an unconditional proof of the Andr´e{Oortconjecture for the coarse moduli space A2;1 of principally polarized abelian surfaces, following the strategy outlined by Pila{Zannier. 1. Introduction and notation Let Ag;1 denote the coarse moduli space of principally polarized abelian varieties of dimension g. Our main theorem is the following, proving the Andr´e{Oortconjecture for A2;1. Theorem 1.1. Let V ⊂ A2;1 be an algebraic subvariety, which is equal to the Zariski closure of its CM points. Then V is a special subvariety. Here, a subvariety means a relatively closed irreducible subvariety. Varieties will be identified with their sets of complex-valued points. We follow the general strategy of Pila{Zannier. Set Hg to be the Siegel upper half space t Hg = fZ 2 Mg×g(C) j Z = Z ; Im(Z) > 0g: We denote by π : Hg !Ag;1 t g(g+1)=2 the natural projection map. The set fZ 2 Mg×g(C)jZ = Z g is naturally identified with C , g(g+1)=2 g(g+1) identifying Hg with an open domain.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 1. Stability Stability Is Fundamentally a Local Hypothesis, Indeed A
    1 1 1. Stability Stability is fundamentally a local hypothesis, indeed a combinatorial hy- pothesis on a bipartite graph. A bi-partite graph is just a triple of sets G = (G1;G2; I) with I G1 G2; one thinks of I as relating elements of ⊂ × G1 to elements of G2. An example is Ln, where G1 and G2 are two copies of 1; : : : ; n , and I is the graph of the order relation i < j. f g Definition 1.1. A bi-partite graph is stable if for some n, G does not embed the graph Ln Definition 1.2. A Γ-formula a formula equivalent to a quantifier-free formula, possibly with additional parameters. A set C is Γ-algebraically-closed if for every Γ-formula E over C defining an equivalence relation with finitely many classes, each class of E is coded by an element of C.A Γ-type over C is a maximal consistent collection of Γ-formulas over C.A Γ-type p over Γ is clearly determined by its restriction to atomic formulas; we will say p is definable if there exists a formula α(y) such that xIy p iff α(y) (or dually; we will write 2 xIy or yIx interchangeably.) If p is definable, the defining formula is unique up to logical equivalence, and will be denoted (dpx)(xIy). Atomic types over Γ are assumed consistent with Th(Γ) (equivalently, with the universal theory of Γ.) Lemma 1.3. The following are equivalent: i) Γ is stable ii) For every countable Γ0 satisfying the universal theory T of Γ, there are 8 countably many atomic types over Γ0 consistent with the universal theory of Γ0.
    [Show full text]
  • Stability Theory
    Department of Mathematics Master's thesis Stability Theory Author: Supervisor: Sven Bosman Dr. Jaap van Oosten Second reader: Prof. Dr. Gunther Cornelissen May 15, 2018 Acknowledgements First and foremost, I would like to thank my supervisor, Dr. Jaap van Oosten, for guiding me. He gave me a chance to pursue my own interests for this project, rather then picking a topic which would have been much easier to supervise. He has shown great patience when we were trying to determine how to get a grip on this material, and has made many helpful suggestions and remarks during the process. I would like to thank Prof. Dr. Gunther Cornelissen for being the second reader of this thesis. I would like to thank Dr. Alex Kruckman for his excellent answer to my question on math.stackexchange.com. He helped me with a problem I had been stuck with for quite some time. I have really enjoyed the master's thesis logic seminar the past year, and would like to thank the participants Tom, Menno, Jetze, Mark, Tim, Bart, Feike, Anton and Mireia for listening to my talks, no matter how boring they might have been at times. Special thanks go to Jetze Zoethout for reading my entire thesis and providing me with an extraordinary number of helpful tips, comments, suggestions, corrections and improvements. Most of my thesis was written in the beautiful library of the Utrecht University math- ematics department, which has been my home away from home for the last three years. I would like to thank all my friends there for the many enjoyable lunchbreaks, the interesting political discussions, and the many, many jokes.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1801.06566V1 [Math.LO] 19 Jan 2018
    MODEL THEORY AND MACHINE LEARNING HUNTER CHASE AND JAMES FREITAG ABSTRACT. About 25 years ago, it came to light that a single combinatorial property deter- mines both an important dividing line in model theory (NIP) and machine learning (PAC- learnability). The following years saw a fruitful exchange of ideas between PAC learning and the model theory of NIP structures. In this article, we point out a new and similar connection between model theory and machine learning, this time developing a correspon- dence between stability and learnability in various settings of online learning. In particular, this gives many new examples of mathematically interesting classes which are learnable in the online setting. 1. INTRODUCTION The purpose of this note is to describe the connections between several notions of com- putational learning theory and model theory. The connection between probably approxi- mately correct (PAC) learning and the non-independence property (NIP) is well-known and was originally noticed by Laskowski [8]. In the ensuing years, there have been numerous interactions between the combinatorics associated with PAC learning and model theory in the NIP setting. Below, we provide a quick introduction to the PAC-learning setting as well as learning in general. Our main purpose, however, is to explain a new connection between the model theory and machine learning. Roughly speaking, our manuscript is similar to [8], but develops the connection between stability and online learning. That the combinatorial quantity of VC-dimension plays an essential role in isolating the main dividing line in both PAC-learning and perhaps the second most prominent dividing line in model-theoretic classification theory (NIP/IP) is a remarkable fact.
    [Show full text]
  • 3 Fundamental Class 20 3.1 Bottom Fundamental Class
    JAIST Repository https://dspace.jaist.ac.jp/ Title A Categorical Description of Relativization Author(s) 吉村, 和人 Citation Issue Date 2013-03 Type Thesis or Dissertation Text version author URL http://hdl.handle.net/10119/11296 Rights Description Supervisor:石原 哉, 情報科学研究科, 修士 Japan Advanced Institute of Science and Technology A Categorical Description of Relativization By Kazuto Yoshimura A thesis submitted to School of Information Science, Japan Advanced Institute of Science and Technology, in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Information Science Graduate Program in Information Science Written under the direction of Hajime Ishihara March 2013 A Categorical Description of Relativization By Kazuto Yoshimura (1110069) A thesis submitted to School of Information Science, Japan Advanced Institute of Science and Technology, in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Information Science Graduate Program in Information Science Written under the direction of Hajime Ishihara and approved by Hajime Ishihara Kazuhiro Ogata Mizuhito Ogawa February 2013 (Submitted) Copyright c 2013 by Kazuto Yoshimura Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 Preliminairies 5 2.1 Set Theoretic Notations . 5 2.2 Category . 9 2.3 Functor . 18 3 Fundamental Class 20 3.1 Bottom Fundamental Class . 20 3.1.1 Classes of Morphisms . 20 3.1.2 Factorization System . 22 3.1.3 Pre-Effectiveness . 27 3.2 Imaginary Fundamental Class . 29 3.2.1 Extending Fundamental classes . 29 3.2.2 Imaginary Operator . 32 3.2.3 The Strongest Extension Ability . 34 3.2.4 Dense morphisms . 37 3.3 Limit Fundamental Class . 38 3.3.1 Effectiveness .
    [Show full text]
  • The André-Oort Conjecture for the Moduli Space Of
    THE ANDRE-OORT´ CONJECTURE FOR THE MODULI SPACE OF ABELIAN SURFACES JONATHAN PILA AND JACOB TSIMERMAN Abstract. We provide an unconditional proof of the Andr´e-Oortcon- jecture for the coarse moduli space A2;1 of principally polarized Abelian surfaces, following the strategy outlined by Pila-Zannier. 1. introduction and notation Set Hg to be the Siegel upper half space t Hg = fZ 2 Mg(C) j Z = Z ; Im(Z) > 0g: Let Ag;1 denote the coarse moduli space of principally polarized Abelian varieties of dimension g. Our main theorem is the following, proving the Andr´e-Oortconjecture for A2;1 : Theorem 1.1. Let V ⊂ A2;1 be an algebraic subvariety, which is equal to the Zariski closure of its CM points. Then V is a special subvariety. We follow the general strategy of Pila-Zannier. One ingredient we need is the following Ax-Lindemann-Weierstrass theorem: We denote by π : H2 !A2;1 6 the natural projection map. We consider H2 ⊂ R with coordinates provided 3 by real and imaginary part of the complex coordinates in C , and call a set 6 semialgebraic if it is a semialgebraic set in R . Let V ⊂ A2;1 be an algebraic variety, Z = π−1(V ), and Y ⊂ Z an irreducible semialgebraic subvariety 0 of H2. We say that Y is maximal if for all semialgebraic subvarieties Y containing Y with Y 0 ⊂ Z, Y is a component of Y 0. Theorem 1.2. Let Y ⊂ Z be a maximal semialgebraic variety. Then Y is a weakly special subvariety. Fix Fg ⊂ Hg to be the standard fundamental domain [8].
    [Show full text]
  • View of first-Order Logic and O-Minimality
    TAMENESS RESULTS FOR EXPANSIONS OF THE REAL FIELD BY GROUPS DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of the Ohio State University By Michael A. Tychonievich, B.S., M.S. Graduate Program in Mathematics The Ohio State University 2013 Dissertation Committee: Prof. Christopher Miller, Advisor Prof. Timothy Carlson Prof. Ovidiu Costin Prof. Daniel Verdier c Copyright by Michael A. Tychonievich 2013 ABSTRACT Expanding on the ideas of o-minimality, we study three kinds of expansions of the real field and discuss certain tameness properties that they possess or lack. In Chapter 1, we introduce some basic logical concepts and theorems of o-minimality. In Chapter 2, we prove that the ring of integers is definable in the expansion of the real field by an infinite convex subset of a finite-rank additive subgroup of the reals. We give a few applications of this result. The main theorem of Chapter 3 is a struc- ture theorem for expansions of the real field by families of restricted complex power functions. We apply it to classify expansions of the real field by families of locally closed trajectories of linear vector fields. Chapter 4 deals with polynomially bounded o-minimal structures over the real field expanded by multiplicative subgroups of the reals. The main result is that any nonempty, bounded, definable d-dimensional sub- manifold has finite d-dimensional Hausdorff measure if and only if the dimension of its frontier is less than d. ii To my father, who has fallen asleep. iii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS As a graduate student, I owe thanks to many people, but I will only list a few here.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1609.03252V6 [Math.LO] 21 May 2018 M 00Sbetcasfiain Rmr 34.Secondary: 03C48
    TOWARD A STABILITY THEORY OF TAME ABSTRACT ELEMENTARY CLASSES SEBASTIEN VASEY Abstract. We initiate a systematic investigation of the abstract elementary classes that have amalgamation, satisfy tameness (a locality property for or- bital types), and are stable (in terms of the number of orbital types) in some cardinal. Assuming the singular cardinal hypothesis (SCH), we prove a full characterization of the (high-enough) stability cardinals, and connect the sta- bility spectrum with the behavior of saturated models. We deduce (in ZFC) that if a class is stable on a tail of cardinals, then it has no long splitting chains (the converse is known). This indicates that there is a clear notion of superstability in this framework. We also present an application to homogeneous model theory: for D a homogeneous diagram in a first-order theory T , if D is both stable in |T | and categorical in |T | then D is stable in all λ ≥|T |. Contents 1. Introduction 2 2. Preliminaries 4 3. Continuity of forking 8 4. ThestabilityspectrumoftameAECs 10 5. The saturation spectrum 15 6. Characterizations of stability 18 7. Indiscernibles and bounded equivalence relations 20 arXiv:1609.03252v6 [math.LO] 21 May 2018 8. Strong splitting 22 9. Dividing 23 10. Strong splitting in stable tame AECs 25 11. Stability theory assuming continuity of splitting 27 12. Applications to existence and homogeneous model theory 31 References 32 Date: September 7, 2018 AMS 2010 Subject Classification: Primary 03C48. Secondary: 03C45, 03C52, 03C55, 03C75, 03E55. Key words and phrases. Abstract elementary classes; Tameness; Stability spectrum; Saturation spectrum; Limit models. 1 2 SEBASTIEN VASEY 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Measures in Model Theory
    Measures in model theory Anand Pillay University of Leeds Logic and Set Theory, Chennai, August 2010 IntroductionI I I will discuss the growing use and role of measures in \pure" model theory, with an emphasis on extensions of stability theory outside the realm of stable theories. I The talk is related to current work with Ehud Hrushovski and Pierre Simon (building on earlier work with Hrushovski and Peterzil). I I will be concerned mainly, but not exclusively, with \tame" rather than \foundational" first order theories. I T will denote a complete first order theory, 1-sorted for convenience, in language L. I There are canonical objects attached to T such as Bn(T ), the Boolean algebra of formulas in free variables x1; ::; xn up to equivalence modulo T , and the type spaces Sn(T ) of complete n-types (ultrafilters on Bn(T )). IntroductionII I Everything I say could be expressed in terms of the category of type spaces (including SI (T ) for I an infinite index set). I However it has become standard to work in a fixed saturated model M¯ of T , and to study the category Def(M¯ ) of sets X ⊆ M¯ n definable, possibly with parameters, in M¯ , as well as solution sets X of types p 2 Sn(A) over small sets A of parameters. I Let us remark that the structure (C; +; ·) is a saturated model of ACF0, but (R; +; ·) is not a saturated model of RCF . I The subtext is the attempt to find a meaningful classification of first order theories. Stable theoriesI I The stable theories are the \logically perfect" theories (to coin a phrase of Zilber).
    [Show full text]
  • Real and Imaginary Parts of Decidability-Making Gilbert Giacomoni
    On the Origin of Abstraction : Real and Imaginary Parts of Decidability-Making Gilbert Giacomoni To cite this version: Gilbert Giacomoni. On the Origin of Abstraction : Real and Imaginary Parts of Decidability-Making. 11th World Congress of the International Federation of Scholarly Associations of Management (IF- SAM), Jun 2012, Limerick, Ireland. pp.145. hal-00750628 HAL Id: hal-00750628 https://hal-mines-paristech.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-00750628 Submitted on 11 Nov 2012 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. On the Origin of Abstraction: Real and Imaginary Parts of Decidability-Making Gilbert Giacomoni Institut de Recherche en Gestion - Université Paris 12 (UPEC) 61 Avenue de Général de Gaulle 94010 Créteil [email protected] Centre de Gestion Scientifique – Chaire TMCI (FIMMM) - Mines ParisTech 60 Boulevard Saint-Michel 75006 Paris [email protected] Abstract: Firms seeking an original standpoint, in strategy or design, need to break with imitation and uniformity. They specifically attempt to understand the cognitive processes by which decision-makers manage to work, individually or collectively, through undecidable situations generated by equivalent possible choices and design innovatively. The behavioral tradition has largely anchored on Simon's early conception of bounded rationality, it is important to engage more explicitly cognitive approaches particularly ones that might link to the issue of identifying novel competitive positions.
    [Show full text]
  • Notes on Totally Categorical Theories
    Notes on totally categorical theories Martin Ziegler 1991 0 Introduction Cherlin, Harrington and Lachlan’s paper on ω0-categorical, ω0-stable theories ([CHL]) was the starting point of geometrical stability theory. The progress made since then allows us better to understand what they did in modern terms (see [PI]) and also to push the description of totally categorical theories further, (see [HR1, AZ1, AZ2]). The first two sections of what follows give an exposition of the results of [CHL]. Then I explain how a totally categorical theory can be decomposed by a sequence of covers and in the last section I discuss the problem how covers can look like. I thank the parisian stabilists for their invation to lecture on these matters, and also for their help during the talks. 1 Fundamental Properties Let T be a totally categorical theory (i.e. T is a complete countable theory, without finite models which is categorical in all infinite cardinalities). Since T is ω1-categorical we know that a) T has finite Morley-rank, which coincides with the Lascar rank U. b) T is unidimensional : All non-algebraic types are non-orthogonal. The main result of [CHL] is that c) T is locally modular. A pregeometry X (i.e. a matroid) is modular if two subspaces are always independent over their intersection. X is called locally modular if two subspaces are independent over their intersection provided this intersection has positive dimension. A pregeometry is a geometry if the closure of the empty set is empty and the one-dimensional subspaces are singletons.
    [Show full text]