Nihilism and Revaluation

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Nihilism and Revaluation Nihilism and Revaluation. An essay on the role of perspectivism in the overcoming of nihilism. Leonardo Sias Student Number: 3699846 Research Master Philosophy Graduate School of Humanities Utrecht University August 2014 Supervisor: Prof. Dr. Bert van den Brink Second Reader: Prof. Dr. Rosi Braidotti Third Reader: Dr. Joel Anderson “Humans first placed values into things, in order to preserve themselves — they first created meaning for things, a human meaning!” On a Thousand and One Goals Thus Spoke Zarathustra Contents Introduction 2 1st Chapter: The concept of nihilism 13 1.1 The theoretical roots of nihilism and its historical necessity. 14 1.2 The theoretical necessity of overcoming nihilism. 30 2nd Chapter: The meaning of the earth 40 2.1 Bodies and meaning. 41 2.2 Perspectives and objectivity. 51 3rd Chapter: Our new infinite 62 3.1 Truth and interpretation. 63 3.2 The transcendental principle of revaluation. 74 Conclusion 83 Bibliography 86 Introduction This work deals with the problem of nihilism, mainly as we find it articulated in Nietzsche’s work, and some of the innumerable interpretations that followed. Jacobi first introduced this term in his Spinoza Letters (1785), where he meant with it the tendency philosophers had, particularly during the Enlightenment, to interpret reality according to conditions of explanation that are too abstract to account for our personal experience, where the meaning of reality itself is revealed. The improper use of rationality as an instrument to determine existence led in his opinion to an ethical void, because truly free subjects could not be affirmed as existing anymore; they were instead reduced to phenomena that had to answer the rational rules required for their explanation.1 As we will see, Nietzsche’s conception of nihilism, however different, mainly because he employs it to characterize Christianity instead of defending it, presents similarities with this intuition. The term was then appropriated by Russian writers and political activists during the 19th Century,2 and finally became widely famous through the work of Nietzsche and his huge influence in contemporary thought. Given this complex history of the concept, it should not come as a surprise that no agreement exists as to what the definition of nihilism should be. Nevertheless, even if conflicting in various ways, mostly because of the accentuation of only one of its many possible forms, all interpretations share a common denominator, which the famous Nietzschean formulation ‘God is dead’ aptly synthetizes. This is taken to be here the ‘nihilistic thesis’, which consists in affirming that meaning and value cannot be grounded metaphysically. In other words, the possibility of meaning on all levels, from our words to our lives considered in their wholeness (as a sum of connected events), and the purpose of life in its most general character (abstracted from any particular life), cannot be grounded, made possible, and guaranteed through the affirmation of anything beyond the world in which life itself takes place: our world. One of the most employed alternatives to this conception of nihilism is that, following from the nihilistic thesis, meaning and universal values cannot be grounded at all. This is often expressed in sentences such as “Existence is meaningless”, “Everything that happens is meaningless”, and “Everything is permitted.” Here, this problem will be called the ‘nihilistic 1 On Jacobi’s concept of nihilism, see, for instance: G. Di Giovanni, 2010. 2 Nihilism Now!: 22-31. 2 crisis’. This is considered to be the case because, in this world, a universal, necessary, and univocal meaning associated with what is presented to us in experience is never to be found. The alternative to a transcendental ground of meaning and value, then, would be only mere relativism. Meanings and values are only expressions of the contingent experiences each of us encounter in our own, limited, and particular life. There is not one meaning, and there is not one value, to which the presence of life in the universe can be led back and justified. Life is unjustified, meaningless, and consequently not worth living. In this work, I will argue that Nietzsche hopes to overcome nihilism by going through and fully accepting it. This is to be understood in one, precise sense: that the overcoming of the nihilistic crisis is possible for Nietzsche only by accepting the nihilistic thesis, and by bringing it to its extreme consequences. This means that, in order to find an alternative to the mere relativism to which the rejection of any transcendent foundation seems to conduct, metaphysics must not only be rejected, but also understood as valuable in a certain context, and explained within a broader framework. The nihilistic thesis denies in fact all metaphysical grounding whatsoever, so the value of metaphysics in the history of Western thought must be conceived as dependent on the contingent need to which it was an answer. To deny this value from our current perspective represents in Nietzsche’s account an implicit reassertion of metaphysics through the criteria we use to evaluate metaphysics itself. Even though this evaluation is negative with regard to metaphysics, since it explicitly denies it, it remains nonetheless metaphysical in character, as it will hopefully be shown during the course of the first chapter. From this point of view, then, the nihilistic crisis is the result of an incomplete, partially naïve understanding of nihilism. Its problematic character springs from its incompleteness, which constitutes a deadlock for reason when left implicit, unaddressed, and neglected. By contrast, Nietzsche – who called himself the perfect nihilist – hoped to offer a means of overcoming the nihilistic crisis that he saw coming from a cultural, incomplete awareness of the nihilistic thesis. This reading has the advantage of coherently interpreting Nietzsche as both the nihilistic philosopher par excellence and the philosopher who first undertook the heavy task of overcoming nihilism. This task brought him to elaborate a possible alternative to our metaphysical need, a theory that could offer a different ground for meaning and value. The question around which this thesis revolves is precisely whether Nietzsche managed to offer a coherent solution to this problem: how to ground meaning and value in a non-metaphysical, non-dogmatic interpretation of the world, without falling in a relativistic philosophy that would only nourish a solipsistic individualism. The theory he 3 comes up with is widely acknowledged, and bears the name of perspectivism. Yet, the question of whether this theory withstands the twofold challenge mentioned above is left unanswered. The challenge is thus to show whether Nietzsche, the perfect nihilist, succeeded in offering a viable path to overcome nihilism. Before approaching a detailed explanation of what perspectivism is, and why Nietzsche saw in this theory a solution to the nihilistic crisis, a preliminary exposition of nihilism is necessary, which will also be useful to understand the research question lying behind this work. After this part, I will be in a suitable position to explain how the entire work has been organized in order to reach its aim. Nihilism, conceived as the impossibility of a metaphysical foundation of meaning, concerns primarily human reason. For practical reasons, in Nietzsche’s opinion, prehistoric humanity started to conceive of objects and events as being identical to the concepts with which we refer to them. Through this practice, we have eventually come to consider the possibility of this use of concepts as guaranteed by the existence of things in themselves, to which our concepts are supposed to correspond. Even if the world is a constant flux of becoming, where nothing is really the same as it was before, we learned how to master it – foreseeing what it would become and adapting our behavior accordingly – by taking different things to be expressions, however imperfect, of the same thing. Even if this operation was justified insofar as it could help us surviving and overcoming the fear of an always-unknown world, we then forgot its arbitrary character. We reconstructed the world through concepts, and then we posited that world as prior, antecedent, and truer than the world of impressions that we experience in our everyday life. This is, for Nietzsche, the origin and character of metaphysics. The abstraction of identity from differences responds directly to what is called our ‘metaphysical need’: the need to conceive of the world as something already determined, which can be known in advanced and predicted. Something is true, from this point of view, when it corresponds precisely to the concept we use to refer to it. This correspondence is thought to be possible because there are transcendent entities to which we implicitly refer when applying particular concepts to the imperfect, accidental, and contingent phenomena constituting our existences. From the basic, pragmatic abstractions of different events and objects concerning our survival – like, for instance, two different tigers behaving in more or less the same way, that is, like ‘a tiger’ – we have slowly come to abstract from those operations underlying abstraction itself. This is clearly visible, from Nietzsche’s point of view 4 – that of a learned and renowned philologist – in the pragmatic origin of our abstract concepts. A few examples should clarify this position: first, the concept of ‘concept’ is, etymologically – and, from a Nietzschean perspective, genealogically – related to the Latin word concipere, which literally means ‘to give existence to another being’, notably a child. Second, the concept of ‘abstraction’ itself: this concept directly comes from the Latin abstràhere (abs + tràhere), literally ‘to take something from something else’ or ‘to pull something from something else’. It means to consider, in things or ideas, one or more of their parts separately from the others. The concept ‘consideration’ comes from Latin consideràre, formed by con (with) and sidus (star).
Recommended publications
  • Full Dissertation
    UC Santa Cruz UC Santa Cruz Electronic Theses and Dissertations Title Suffering & The Value of Life Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/00f6w6mk Author Coronado, Amena Publication Date 2016 License https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/ 4.0 Peer reviewed|Thesis/dissertation eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA SANTA CRUZ SUFFERING & THE VALUE OF LIFE A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY in PHILOSOPHY by Amena Coronado June 2016 The Dissertation of Amena Coronado is approved: ____________________________________ Professor Daniel Guevara, chair ____________________________________ Professor Jocelyn Hoy ____________________________________ Professor John Bowin _____________________________ Tyrus Miller Vice Provost and Dean of Graduate Studies Copyright © by Amena Coronado 2016 CONTENTS ABSTRACT vi PREFACE 1 Chapter 1 | The Limits of Life Affirmation 5 I Structure of Nietzsche’s Project 9 Crisis 9 Response 14 Critical Tools of Revaluation 16 Who Undertakes Revaluation 21 II Affirmation and Suffering 25 Formulations of Life Affirmation 27 Treatments of Affirmation 30 The Good of Suffering 30 Affirmation of the Whole 35 Inward Affirmation 40 III Conclusion 45 Shortcomings of Affirmation 45 Role of Affirmation 48 Chapter 2 | Sounding Out Idols 52 I Brief Exposition of Revaluation 55 Origin of the Concept 56 Translating Umwerthung 59 Revaluation as Experiment 64 II Critique of the
    [Show full text]
  • Robert B. Pippin
    CURRICULUM VITAE ROBERT B. PIPPIN Evelyn Stefansson Nef Distinguished Service Professor in the John U. Nef Committee on Social Thought, the Department of Philosophy, and the College The University of Chicago The John U. Nef Committee on Social Thought 1130 East 59th Street Chicago, Illinois 60637 The Department of Philosophy 1115 E. 58th St. Chicago, IL 60637 (773) 702-5453 FAX: (773) 834-1968 email: [email protected] website: http://home.uchicago.edu/~rbp1/ Education B.A. with Honors in English, Trinity College, Hartford, Conn. 1970 M.A. Philosophy (Minor: Greek), Pennsylvania State University 1972 Ph.D. Philosophy, Pennsylvania State University, August 31, 1974 Honors, Awards, Endowed Lectures, Prizes 2019 - Guggenheim Fellowship 2019 - Penn State Alumni Association Lifetime Achievement Award 2018 - Penn State Graduate School Distiunguished Alumnus Award 2018 (winter) – Steiner Lecture, St. John’s College, Santa Fe, New Mexico 2018 (spring) – Kneller Lecture, Philosophy of Education Society, Chicago, Illinois 2019 (winter) – Penn State Alumni Fellow Award 2017 (fall) – Alumni Association of Penn State Lifetime Achievement Award 2017 (fall) – Thomas Scholl Lecture, Purdue University Philosophy Department 2017 (fall) – Friedrich Nietzsche Lecture (Inaugural), University of Basel, Switzerland 2017 (spring) – elected to the German National Academy of Sciences Leopoldina 2016 (fall) – Townsend Visitor (three lectures), University of California, Berkeley 2015 (fall) – Suarez Lecture, Fordham University 2015 (fall) - Larwill Lecture, Kenyon
    [Show full text]
  • Scott Jenkins April 2015
    Scott Jenkins April 2015 Department of Philosophy (785) 864-2324 1445 Jayhawk Blvd. Rm. 3090 [email protected] Wescoe Hall The University of Kansas Lawrence, KS 66045 Employment: University of Kansas (2007-present) Associate Professor of Philosopy (2012-present) Assistant Professor of Philosophy (2007-2012) Reed College (2002-2007) Visiting Assistant Professor of Philosophy and Humanities (2002-2007) Education: Princeton University (1996-2002) Ph.D. in Philosophy 2003 Dissertation: “Self-Consciousness and Agency in Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit” Advisor: Béatrice Longuenesse M.A. in Philosophy 1999 Ludwig Maximilians Universität, Munich (1999-2000) Visiting Fulbright Scholar Stanford University (1992-1996) B.A. in Philosophy 1996, conferred with distinction and departmental honors. Areas of Specialization: Kant, German Idealism, Nietzsche Areas of Competence: Early Modern Philosophy, 20th Century European Philosophy, Ancient Philosophy, Ethics, Aesthetics, Wittgenstein Articles: • “Self-Consciousness in the Phenomenology”, in preparation for The Oxford Handbook of Hegel, ed. Dean Moyar. • “Truthfulness as Nietzsche’s Highest Virtue”, forthcoming in The Journal of Value Inquiry, 2015. • “Life, Injustice, and Recurrence”, forthcoming in Nietzsche and the Becoming of Life, Vanessa Lemm (ed.), Fordham University Press, 2015. • “Nietzsche’s Use of Monumental History”, The Journal of Nietzsche Studies, 45.2 (Summer 2014): 169- 181. • “Nietzsche’s Revaluation of Cruelty: The Case of Cesare Borgia”, in The Revival of the Renaissance in the Nineteenth and Twentieth Centuries, Frank Baron and Helmut Koopmann (eds.), Mentis Verlag, 2013. 55-68. • “Time and Personal Identity in Nietzsche’s Theory of Eternal Recurrence”, Philosophy Compass, 7/3 (2012): 208-217. Scott Jenkins • Curriculum Vitae • 2 • “Nietzsche’s Questions Concerning the Will to Truth”, Journal of the History of Philosophy, Vol.
    [Show full text]
  • “Aesthetic Judgment” the Fourth NYU Conference on Issues in Modern Philosophy New York University, November 9-10, 2007
    “Aesthetic Judgment” The Fourth NYU Conference on Issues in Modern Philosophy New York University, November 9-10, 2007 914 NYU Kimmel Center, 61 Washington Square South The New York University Department of Philosophy will host the fourth in its series of conferences on issues in the history of modern philosophy on November 9 and 10, 2007. Each conference in the series examines the development of a central philosophical problem from early modern philosophy to the present, exploring the evolution of formulations of the problem and of approaches to resolving it. By examining the work of philosophers of the past both in historical context and in relation to contemporary philosophical thinking, the conferences allow philosophy’s past and present to illuminate one another. The topic of the 2007 conference is: the nature and significance of aesthetic judgments. There will be four sessions on historical figures—Hume, Kant, Hegel, and Nietzsche—and a fifth session on contemporary treatments of the issue. The schedule of sessions and speakers is as follows: Friday, November 9 2:30: Welcoming words by Stephen Schiffer, Chair of the NYU Philosophy Department 2:35-4:30: “Sensibility and Sense: Hutcheson, Hume, and the Rationalist Critique” Speaker: Peter Kivy (Rutgers University) Commentator: Paul Guyer (University of Pennsylvania) Chair: Alison Simmons (Harvard University) 5:00-7:00: “Kant, Proust, and the Appeal of Beauty” Speaker: Richard Moran (Harvard University) Commentator: Rebecca Kukla (University of South Florida) Chair: Jerry Schneewind
    [Show full text]
  • Nietzsche's Subjectivism About Life's Meaning Nicholas Halford
    Nietzsche's Subjectivism about Life's Meaning by Nicholas Halford A thesis submitted to the Faculty of Graduate and Postdoctoral Affairs in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in Philosophy Carleton University Ottawa, Ontario © 2019 Nicholas Halford Abstract: The purpose of this thesis is to demonstrate the subjective nature of Friedrich Nietzsche's account of existential meaning. I aim to emphasize that Nietzsche's account can only be properly understood by considering his subjective account of value and the limitations of knowledge and sensory perception imposed by perspectivism. I seek to illustrate that this is only possible by considering many of his works and the concepts contained therein. I first consider Nietzsche's strongly negative reaction to Arthur Schopenhauer's pessimism; next, I adopt Gilles Deleuze's interpretation of the will to power while arguing that the will to power is not as central as might be thought; and, finally, I argue that the death of God is the foundation of Nietzsche's account, as it is this concept that enables and/or necessitates the will to power, the revaluation of values, eternal return, and perspectivism. ii Table of Contents Abstract: …………………………………………………………………………………ii Table of Contents: ……………………………………………………………………...iii Acknowledgements: …………………………………………………………………….iv List of Abbreviations: ……………………………………………………………….....vi Introduction: …………………………………………………………………………..vii Chapter 1: Existential Meaning……………………………………………………….1 1.1 Schopenhauer………………………………………………………………1
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae
    JESSICA N. BERRY Curriculum Vitae Georgia State University Mailing Address: P.O. Box 3994 Department of Philosophy Atlanta, GA 30302-3994 25 Park Place NE, #1621 Office: (404) 413-6100 Atlanta, GA 30303 [email protected] EDUCATION Ph.D., University of Texas at Austin (Philosophy), August 2003 B.A. cum laude, University of Puget Sound (Philosophy), May 1994 EXPERIENCE Associate Professor of Philosophy, Georgia State University (2011 – present) Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Georgia State University (2006 – 2011) Assistant Professor of Philosophy, The University of North Carolina at Wilmington (2004 – 2006) Visiting Assistant Professor of Philosophy, The College of William & Mary (2003 – 2004) AREAS OF SPECIALIZATION German Philosophy (late 18th – early 20th century) History of Ancient Philosophy AREAS OF INTEREST Aesthetics; Epistemology; Metaphilosophy PUBLICATIONS: MONOGRAPHS Marx, Nietzsche, Freud: The School of Suspicion (London: Routledge, under contract). Nietzsche and the Ancient Skeptical Tradition (New York: Oxford University Press, 2011). REVIEWS: Notre Dame Philosophical Review (07.31.2011); Philosophy in Review 31.6 (2011): 400-1; Ethics 122.2 (2012): 398-402; The Journal of Nietzsche Studies 43.1 (2012); International Journal for the Study of Skepticism 2 (2012): 79-82; The Review of Metaphysics 66.1 (2012): 134-36; The Journal of the History of Philosophy 51.1 (2013): 138-40. PUBLICATIONS: BOOK CHAPTERS & JOURNAL ARTICLES “Nietzsche on Philosophy as Psychopathology,” in Nietzsche (Routledge Philosophy Minds Series), ed. Paul Katsafanas (New York: Routledge, forthcoming). “The Burden of Antiquity” in The Oxford Handbook of Nineteenth Century German Philosophy, ed. Michael Forster & Kristin Gjeldsal (New York: Oxford University Press, 2015); pp. 751–78. “Is Nietzsche a Virtue Theorist?,” Journal of Value Inquiry 49.3 (2015), pp.
    [Show full text]
  • Metaethics and Nihilism in Reginster's the Affirmation of Life
    Metaethics and Nihilism in Reginster's The Affirmation of Life Nadeem J. Z. Hussain The Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Volume 43, Number 1, Spring 2012, pp. 99-117 (Article) Published by Penn State University Press DOI: 10.1353/nie.2012.0024 For additional information about this article http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/nie/summary/v043/43.1.hussain.html Access Provided by Stanford University at 01/05/13 12:51AM GMT Metaethics and nihilism in reginster’s The Affirmation of Life Nadeem J. Z. HussaiN abstract: Bernard reginster, in his book The Affirmation of Life: Nietzsche on Overcoming Nihilism, takes up the challenge of figuring out what nietzsche might mean by nihilism and the revaluation of values. he argues that there is an alternative, normative subjectivist interpretation of nietzsche’s views on nihilism and revaluation that makes as much sense as—indeed, he often clearly leans toward thinking that it makes more sense than—a fictionalist reading of nietzsche. i argue that his arguments do not succeed. once we have looked care- fully at the details of the positions and the arguments ascribed to nietzsche, the fictionalist option is the more charitable interpretation of the texts. i focus on the metaethical issues that play a central role for reginster in his articulation of nietzsche’s nihilism and nietzsche’s strategy for overcoming nihilism. t is not a simple matter to determine either what nietzsche means by “nihil- iism” or what he thinks we should do about it. to start with, there seem to be many different nihilisms discussed in different places in nietzsche’s writings.1 furthermore, though he seems at times to accept positions we might be inclined to think of as nihilistic, he also presents himself as showing us, or at least some of us, a path beyond nihilism.2 the following famous passage from a draft pref- ace, part of one of the many plans for works to be entitled The Will to Power, dramatically captures both of these facets: he that speaks here .
    [Show full text]
  • APA NEWSLETTER on Asian and Asian American Philosophers and Philosophies
    NEWSLETTER | The American Philosophical Association Asian and Asian American Philosophers and Philosophies FALL 2020 VOLUME 20 | NUMBER 1 WHAT IS IT LIKE TO BE A PHILOSOPHER OF ASIAN DESCENT? Dedicated to the memory of Dr. Jaegwon Kim FROM THE EDITORS A. Minh Nguyen and Yarran Hominh Editors’ Introduction: What Is It Like to Be a Philosopher of Asian Descent? ARTICLES M. Ashraf Adeel The Rock on My Chest Kenneth Aizawa The Not-So-Lonely Journey of a Japanese American Philosopher Yubraj Aryal Fashioning Oneself as a Philosopher of Asian Descent Prasanta S. Bandyopadhyay The Unbearable Lightness of Being an Asian American Philosopher Celia T. Bardwell-Jones What Does It Mean to Be a Philosopher of Filipina American Descent? Julianne Chung What Am I? Kenny Easwaran One Life in Philosophy Saba Fatima Philosophy, Liberation, and Other Roads Less Travelled: Being Asian in Philosophy VOLUME 20 | NUMBER 1 FALL 2020 © 2020 BY THE AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL ASSOCIATION ISSN 2155-9708 TABLE OF CONTENTS, CONT. Dien Ho Anthony Nguyen Thinking While Asian Ambiguity, Alienation, and Authenticity Masato Ishida Ann A. Pang-White Does He Get Paid? My Philosophy Journey to the West Yoichi Ishida Jin Y. Park In Praise of Teachers Doing Philosophy at the Margin Justin Khoo Yuriko Saito Mixed, but not Diluted My Journey Across the Pacific David H. Kim Falguni A. Sheth Frenemy Philosophy The Fluidity of Identity: Moving Toward a Philosophy of Race Halla Kim Criss-Crossing the Philosophical Saam Trivedi Borderlines: What Is It Like to Be a “Wogs” and Philosophers Philosopher of Asian Descent? Anand Jayprakash Vaidya Monika Kirloskar-Steinbach The Story of One Male Asian American Making Meaning of Practices in Academic Philosopher Philosophy Audrey Yap Emily S.
    [Show full text]
  • The Man and His Work Bart Vandenabeele (Ghent University)
    A Companion to Schopenhauer Edited by Bart Vandenabeele 1 Arthur Schopenhauer: The Man and his Work Bart Vandenabeele (Ghent University) Part I Nature, Knowledge, and Perception 2 Schopenhauer on Scientific Knowledge Vojislav Bozickovic (University of Belgrade) 3 Perception and Understanding: Schopenhauer, Reid, and Kant Paul Guyer (University of Pennsylvania) 4 Schopenhauer’s Philosophy of Logic and Mathematics Dale Jacquette (University of Bern) 5 Schopenhauer’s Colour Theory Paul F.H. Lauxtermann (University of Twente) 6 Schopenhauer and Transcendental Idealism Douglas McDermid (Trent University) Part II World, Will, and Life 7 Schopenhauer’s Philosophy of the Dark Origin William Desmond (University of Leuven) 8 The Consistency of Schopenhauer’s Metaphysics G. Steven Neeley (Saint Francis University) 9 Schopenhauer on Sex, Love and Emotions Gudrun von Tevenar (Birkbeck College, London) 10 Schopenhauer and Platonic Ideas Frank C. White (University of Tasmania) 11 Schopenhauer’s On the Will in Nature: The Reciprocal Containment of Idealism and Realism Robert Wicks (University of Auckland) Part III Art, Beauty, and the Sublime 12 Schopenhauer’s Philosophy of Music Robert W. Hall (University of Vermont) 13 Schopenhauer’s Theory of Architecture W. Julian Korab-Karpowicz (Bilkent University) 14 The Artist as Subject of Pure Cognition Matthias Kossler (Mainz University) 15 Schopenhauer on Tragedy and the Sublime Alex Neill (University of Southampton) 16 Schopenhauer and the Objectivity of Art Bart Vandenabeele (Ghent University) Part IV Compassion, Resignation, and Sainthood 17 Schopenhauer on the Metaphysics of Art and Morality Daniel Came (University of Oxford) 18 Schopenhauer on the Value of Compassion David E. Cartwright (University of Wisconsin-Whitewater) 19 Schopenhauer and Indian Philosophy David E.
    [Show full text]