How Does Consciousness Exist? a Comparative Inquiry on Classical Empiricism and William James

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

How Does Consciousness Exist? a Comparative Inquiry on Classical Empiricism and William James HOW DOES CONSCIOUSNESS EXIST? A COMPARATIVE INQUIRY ON CLASSICAL EMPIRICISM AND WILLIAM JAMES A THESIS SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF SOCIAL SCIENCES OF MIDDLE EAST TECHNICAL UNIVERSITY BY ZELİHA BURCU YILMAZ IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS IN THE DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY SEPTEMBER 2006 Approval of the Graduate School of Social Sciences Prof. Dr. Sencer Ayata Director I certify that this thesis satisfies all the requirements as a thesis for the degree of Master of Arts. Prof. Dr. Ahmet İnam Head of Department This is to certify that we have read this thesis and that in our opinion it is fully adequate, in scope and quality, as a thesis for the degree of Master of Arts of Philosophy. Assist. Prof. Dr. Elif Çırakman Supervisor Examining Committee Members Assist. Prof. Dr. Elif Çırakman (METU, PHIL) Assoc. Prof. Dr. Halil Ş. Turan (METU, PHIL) Assoc. Prof. Dr. Murat Baç (Boğaziçi U., PHIL) I hereby declare that all information in this document has been obtained and presented in accordance with academic rules and ethical conduct. I also declare that, as required by these rules and conduct, I have fully cited and referenced all material and results that are not original to this work. Name, Last name : Signature : iii ABSTRACT HOW DOES CONSCIOUSNESS EXIST? A COMPARATIVE INQUIRY ON CLASSICAL EMPIRICISM AND WILLIAM JAMES Yılmaz, Zeliha Burcu Master of Arts in Department of Philosophy Supervisor : Assist. Prof. Dr. Elif Çırakman September 2006, 170 pages William James denies consciousness as an entity and this rejection lies in the background of my thesis. I searched the main reasons for this rejection in his philosophy. Throughout this search, I perceived two modes of existence of consciousness, that active and passive. As James improves his thoughts on consciousness over the main arguments of classical empiricists, I explained his radical empiricism and pragmatism in relation to them. It is difficult to answer whether we are completely active or passive in the ways of our thinking and behaving. However, although it includes some problems and inconsistencies, James’s philosophy presents a more plausible explanation of our thinking than rationalism and empiricism, since it can appreciate the changes of our life in an unfinished world of pure experience. Therefore, my inquiry into the existence of consciousness in James depends on this plausibility of the main characteristics of radical empiricism in connection with the classical empiricists. Key words: Consciousness, radical empiricism, pragmatism, classical empiricism, experience, reasoning, sensation, reflection, perception, knowledge, truth, solipsism, realism, existence, reality. iv ÖZ BİLİNÇ NASIL VAR OLUR? KLASİK EMPİRİSİZM VE WILLIAM JAMES ÜZERİNE KARŞILAŞTIRMALI BİR İNCELEME Yılmaz, Zeliha Burcu Yüksek Lisans, Felsefe Bölümü Tez Yöneticisi : Yrd. Doç. Dr. Elif Çırakman Eylül 2006, 170 sayfa William James bilinci bir varlık olarak reddeder ve bu tezin arkaplanında bu reddediş vardır. James felsefesinde bu reddedişin temel nedenlerini araştırdım. Bu inceleme süresince, onun düşüncesinde bilincin etkin ve edilgin olarak iki varoluş biçimi olduğunu gözlemledim. James bilinç üzerine düşüncelerini klasik deneycilerin temel iddiaları üzerine geliştirdiği için, onun radikal deneyciliğini ve pragmatizmini klasik deneycilikle ilişkisi içerisinde açıkladım. Düşüncelerimizde ve hareketlerimizde tamamen etkin ya da edilgin olup olmadığımıza yanıt vermek güçtür. Ama bazı sorunlar ve tutarsızlıklar içerse de, James’in felsefesi düşüncemize dair usçuluk ve deneycilikten daha akla yatkın bir açıklama sunmaktadır, çünkü James’in yaklaşımı henüz tamamlanmamış bir saf deneyim dünyasında hayatımızdaki değişiklikleri daha iyi karşılayabilir. Sonuç olarak James’teki bilince dair olan tezim bu akla yatkınlığa ve klasik deneycilikle ilişkisi içinde radikal deneyciliğin temel ilkelerinin ikna edici gücüne dayanmaktadır. Anahtar Kelimeler: Bilinç, radikal deneycilik, pragmatizm, klasik deneycilik, deneyim, uslamlama, duyum, düşünüm, bilgi, doğru, tekbencilik, gerçekçilik, varolmak, gerçeklik. v To My Mother vi ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I had a chance of scrutinizing the basic notions of radical empiricism when I took a course during 2002-2003 Academic Year. The main frame of this thesis was formed in this course. In this respect, I wish to express my gratitude to my instructor Tahir Kocayiğit whom I vastly benefited in my graduate education. My background pertaining to classical empiricism is due to my teacher Assoc. Prof. Halil Ş. Turan. I would also like to thank him for his suggestions and comments. My particular chance has been to meet on the way Assoc. Prof. Murat Baç who provides my true acquaintance with thinking and writing analytically. He showed genuine care about my thesis. His valuable criticisms and suggestions made this thesis possible. To study with my advisor Assist. Prof. Elif Çırakman is a great chance also. Beside her excellent instruction, her help was quite vital in figuring out both the technical details and the academic clarification of this study. I would like to thank for her invaluable comments, criticisms, and contributions leading this dissertation to a better level of quality. I learned how to write with her constant watch and she gave me all the resources, help and attention that I need for this thesis. Enjoyable discussions with my friend Eylem Yenisoy and her comments and contributions have an important role in this thesis. For that reason, let me express my sincere appreciation and gratitude to her also. To my parents, I offer sincere for their unshakable faith in me. vii TABLEOF CONTENTS 1. PLAGIARISM…………………………………………………………………..iii 2. ABSTRACT……………………………………………………………………..iv 3. ÖZ………………………………………………………………………………..v 4. ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS……………………………………………………..vi 5. TABLE F CONTENTS……………………………………………………… viii CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION………………………………………………………1 2. THE PROBLEMS OF CLASSICAL EMPIRICISM………………… 12 2.1 Historical Background of Empiricism………………………. 15 2.2 Framing the Difference between Empiricism and Rationalism 20 2.3 The Mode of Existence of Consciousness in Locke………… 25 2.3.1 The Conception of Idea in Locke……………………29 2.3.2 The Existence of Our Mind and the Outer World…..34 2.4 The Problem of Existence in Berkeley………………………. 36 2.4.1 Perception: God’s or ours?..........................................38 2.4.2 Consciousness: Active or Passive?............................. 42 2.5 The Challenge of Hume………………………………………. 43 2.5.1 Association of Ideas………………………………….44 2.5.2 Hume’s Skepticism…………………………………..47 2.5.3 The Conception of Consciousness in Hume…………47 viii 3. THE CONCEPTION OF CONSCIOUSNESS IN WILLIAM JAMES……………………………………………….. 49 3.1 Stream of Thought……………………………………..51 3.1.1 Appropriation……………………………… 59 3.2 Consciousness Does Not Exist!..................................... 62 3.3 The Problem of Solipsism……………………………. 80 3.4 The Dilemma of Realism………………………………88 3.5 The Existence of Consciousness……………………….97 3.6 Pragmatism………………………………………….. 105 3.7 Pragmatism and Radical Empiricism……………….. 108 4. APPROACHING CLASSICAL EMPIRICISM FROM JAMES’S PRAGMATISM AND RADICAL EMPIRICISM…………………….114 4.1 Empiricism of John Locke…………………………..115 4.1.1 Locke as a Pragmatist………………………116 4.1.2 Locke as a Spiritualist…………………….. 120 4.2 Empiricism of George Berkeley…………………….. 130 4.2.1 Berkeley as a Pragmatist……………………131 4.2.2 James’s Difference from Berkeley’ Theory 138 4.3 Empiricism of David Hume………………………… 141 4.3.1 Hume’s Pragmatism……………………… 144 4.3.2 Hume as an Associationist………………… 150 5. CONCLUSION………………………………………………………..157 BIBLIOGRAPHY………………………………………………………..165 ix CHAPTER 1 INTRODUCTION How knowledge is constructed and how we can get true knowledge are the essential problems of philosophy. History of philosophy is the history of comprehensive and original solutions to these questions. Empiricism and rationalism are two conventional theories focusing on this issue. The American pragmatist William James attempted to answer these questions by his radical empiricism. He is against the notion of absolute entity in philosophy and he aims at reducing all our concepts and abstractions to their empirical roots. Pragmatic method supports this aim in the sense that it presents us a means of testing the meanings of our concepts; by asking “what sensible difference to anybody will its truth make?”1 For James, by pursuing this question, we can check all our concepts and define their meanings. This checking process stresses upon that no concept has an absolute meaning. For that reason, if we take philosophical problems from different perspectives and in terms of their “sensible differences”, we can see that their meanings are changeable. Thus, there cannot be any absolute difference between competing theories that exhibit no practical differences. Consciousness is one of the concepts that James tries to explicate by his radical empiricism and pragmatic method. In his explanations, it sometimes has a passive role in knowing, and sometimes it is so active. There lies an important purpose in the setting of James’s accounts of consciousness. He does not think that mind or consciousness is superior in the process of knowing like rationalists. Additionally, he does not hold a strict empiricist position accepting that consciousness is passive in knowing and all our knowing depend on sense experience, either. As an 1 William James, Some Problems of Philosophy, p. 37. 1 alternative to these epistemologies, he improves his radical empiricism. It is closely associated with
Recommended publications
  • The Ten Lenses of Philosophical Inquiry Philosophical Inquiry Research Project1
    The Ten Lenses of Philosophical Inquiry Philosophical Inquiry Research Project1 The real voyage of discovery consists not in seeking new landscapes, but in having new eyes. – Marcel Proust A huge part of Philosophical Inquiry is learning how to see the world with new eyes. To accomplish this goal, you will be introduced to the “ten lenses of philosophical inquiry.” The ten lenses of philosophical inquiry are tools to help us critically engage with, and analyze ourselves, and the world around us. Like a pair of glasses, the ten lenses help to change our perception and give us the power to re-examine our reality. In this philosophical inquiry research project you will get introduced to each of the ten lenses so that you become comfortable using the lenses both inside and out of our class. You will also learn more about a philosopher, their philosophy and the lens of philosophical inquiry that they are most clearly connected to. Focus Question What are the ten lenses of philosophical inquiry, and what are some examples of how they are connected to the philosophies of different philosopher’s throughout history? Philosophical Inquiry Research Process 1) QUESTION - Develop the philosophical questions that you will use to drive your inquiry. 2) PLAN – Determine the types of sources that you will need to answer your questions. 3) GATHER EVIDENCE – Gather the information (textual, visual, quantitative, etc.) you need to explore and answer your questions. 4) ANALYZE – Analyze the answers to your questions, making sure to keep in mind the larger focus question guiding this inquiry. 5) COMMUNICATE CONCLUSIONS – Use evidence and reasons to write an organized (logically sequenced) explanation to the inquiry’s topic/focus question.
    [Show full text]
  • THE THEORY of MATHEMATICAL SUBTRACTION in ARISTOTLE By
    THE THEORY OF MATHEMATICAL SUBTRACTION IN ARISTOTLE by Ksenia Romashova Submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts at Dalhousie University Halifax, Nova Scotia August 2019 © Copyright by Ksenia Romashova, 2019 DEDICATION PAGE To my Mother, Vera Romashova Мама, Спасибо тебе за твою бесконечную поддержку, дорогая! ii TABLE OF CONTENTS LIST OF FIGURES .................................................................................................................. iv ABSTRACT ............................................................................................................................... v LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS USED ....................................................................................... vi ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS ..................................................................................................... vii CHAPTER 1 INTRODUCTION ............................................................................................... 1 CHAPTER 2 THE MEANING OF ABSTRACTION .............................................................. 6 2.1 Etymology and Evolution of the Term ................................................................... 7 2.2 The Standard Phrase τὰ ἐξ ἀφαιρέσεως or ‘Abstract Objects’ ............................ 19 CHAPTER 3 GENERAL APPLICATION OF ABSTRACTION .......................................... 24 3.1 The Instances of Aphairein in Plato’s Dialogues ................................................. 24 3.2 The Use of Aphairein in Aristotle’s Topics
    [Show full text]
  • Continuity and Mathematical Ontology in Aristotle
    Journal of Ancient Philosophy, vol. 14 issue 1, 2020. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v14i1p30-61 Continuity and Mathematical Ontology in Aristotle Keren Wilson Shatalov In this paper I argue that Aristotle’s understanding of mathematical continuity constrains the mathematical ontology he can consistently hold. On my reading, Aristotle can only be a mathematical abstractionist of a certain sort. To show this, I first present an analysis of Aristotle’s notion of continuity by bringing together texts from his Metaphysica and Physica, to show that continuity is, for Aristotle, a certain kind of per se unity, and that upon this rests his distinction between continuity and contiguity. Next I argue briefly that Aristotle intends for his discussion of continuity to apply to pure mathematical objects such as lines and figures, as well as to extended bodies. I show that this leads him to a difficulty, for it does not at first appear that the distinction between continuity and contiguity can be preserved for abstract mathematicals. Finally, I present a solution according to which Aristotle’s understanding of continuity can only be saved if he holds a certain kind of mathematical ontology. My topic in this paper is Aristotle’s understanding of mathematical continuity. While the idea that continua are composed of infinitely many points is the present day orthodoxy, the Aristotelian understanding of continua as non-punctiform and infinitely divisible was the reigning theory for much of the history of western mathematics, and there is renewed interest in it from current mathematicians and philosophers of mathematics.
    [Show full text]
  • A Feminist Epistemological Framework: Preventing Knowledge Distortions in Scientific Inquiry
    Claremont Colleges Scholarship @ Claremont Scripps Senior Theses Scripps Student Scholarship 2019 A Feminist Epistemological Framework: Preventing Knowledge Distortions in Scientific Inquiry Karina Bucciarelli Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.claremont.edu/scripps_theses Part of the Epistemology Commons, Feminist Philosophy Commons, and the Philosophy of Science Commons Recommended Citation Bucciarelli, Karina, "A Feminist Epistemological Framework: Preventing Knowledge Distortions in Scientific Inquiry" (2019). Scripps Senior Theses. 1365. https://scholarship.claremont.edu/scripps_theses/1365 This Open Access Senior Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Scripps Student Scholarship at Scholarship @ Claremont. It has been accepted for inclusion in Scripps Senior Theses by an authorized administrator of Scholarship @ Claremont. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A FEMINIST EPISTEMOLOGICAL FRAMEWORK: PREVENTING KNOWLEDGE DISTORTIONS IN SCIENTIFIC INQUIRY by KARINA MARTINS BUCCIARELLI SUBMITTED TO SCRIPPS COLLEGE IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE DEGREE OF BACHELOR OF ARTS PROFESSOR SUSAN CASTAGNETTO PROFESSOR RIMA BASU APRIL 26, 2019 Bucciarelli 2 Acknowledgements First off, I would like to thank my wonderful family for supporting me every step of the way. Mamãe e Papai, obrigada pelo amor e carinho, mil telefonemas, conversas e risadas. Obrigada por não só proporcionar essa educação incrível, mas também me dar um exemplo de como viver. Rafa, thanks for the jokes, the editing help and the spontaneous phone calls. Bela, thank you for the endless time you give to me, for your patience and for your support (even through WhatsApp audios). To my dear friends, thank you for the late study nights, the wild dance parties, the laughs and the endless support.
    [Show full text]
  • Principles of Scientific Inquiry
    Chapter 2 PRINCIPLES OF SCIENTIFIC INQUIRY Introduction This chapter provides a summary of the principles of scientific inquiry. The purpose is to explain terminology, and introduce concepts, which are explained more completely in later chapters. Much of the content has been based on explanations and examples given by Wilson (1). The Scientific Method Although most of us have heard, at some time in our careers, that research must be carried out according to “the scientific method”, there is no single, scientific method. The term is usually used to mean a systematic approach to solving a problem in science. Three types of investigation, or method, can be recognized: · The Observational Method · The Experimental (and quasi-experimental) Methods, and · The Survey Method. The observational method is most common in the natural sciences, especially in fields such as biology, geology and environmental science. It involves recording observations according to a plan, which prescribes what information to collect, where it should be sought, and how it should be recorded. In the observational method, the researcher does not control any of the variables. In fact, it is important that the research be carried out in such a manner that the investigations do not change the behaviour of what is being observed. Errors introduced as a result of observing a phenomenon are known as systematic errors because they apply to all observations. Once a valid statistical sample (see Chapter Four) of observations has been recorded, the researcher analyzes and interprets the data, and develops a theory or hypothesis, which explains the observations. The experimental method begins with a hypothesis.
    [Show full text]
  • Berkeley's Case Against Realism About Dynamics
    Lisa Downing [Published in Berkeley’s Metaphysics, ed. Muehlmann, Penn State Press 1995, 197-214. Turbayne Essay Prize winner, 1992.] Berkeley's case against realism about dynamics While De Motu, Berkeley's treatise on the philosophical foundations of mechanics, has frequently been cited for the surprisingly modern ring of certain of its passages, it has not often been taken as seriously as Berkeley hoped it would be. Even A.A. Luce, in his editor's introduction to De Motu, describes it as a modest work, of limited scope. Luce writes: The De Motu is written in good, correct Latin, but in construction and balance the workmanship falls below Berkeley's usual standards. The title is ambitious for so brief a tract, and may lead the reader to expect a more sustained argument than he will find. A more modest title, say Motion without Matter, would fitly describe its scope and content. Regarded as a treatise on motion in general, it is a slight and disappointing work; but viewed from a narrower angle, it is of absorbing interest and high importance. It is the application of immaterialism to contemporary problems of motion, and should be read as such. ...apart from the Principles the De Motu would be nonsense.1 1The Works of George Berkeley, Bishop of Cloyne, ed. A.A. Luce and T.E. Jessop (London: Thomas Nelson and Sons, 1948-57), 4: 3-4. In this paper, all references to Berkeley are to the Luce-Jessop edition. Quotations from De Motu are taken from Luce's translation. I use the following abbreviations for Berkeley’s works: PC Philosophical Commentaries PHK-I Introduction to The Principles of Human Knowledge PHK The Principles of Human Knowledge DM De Motu A Alciphron TVV The Theory of Vision Vindicated and Explained S Siris 1 There are good general reasons to think, however, that Berkeley's aims in writing the book were as ambitious as the title he chose.
    [Show full text]
  • Experiential & Inquiry-Based Learning with Youth in Non-Formal Settings
    Working with youth in non-formal settings ensuring rich enrichment Experiential & Inquiry-based Learning with Youth in Non-formal Settings 4-H Science learning for youth can be deepened by building inquiry-based learning methods into programs and curricula. For over two decades of educational reform, science education has focused on inquiry as a method for learning and doing natural science in formal classrooms. When used to make sense of the natural world from within the discipline of science, inquiry-based learning is ‘scientific inquiry. ’ Non-formal program designers and practitioners are faced with decisions about which scientific inquiry methods to transfer from the formal classroom to the non-formal setting, which methods to adapt to better fit the non-formal learning needs of youth, and how to best prepare adults to facilitate scientific inquiry with youth. Why is this thinking important to 4-H staff and volunteers? Evaluation results indicate that inquiry-based methods support youth in Key Concepts their learning. Minner et al (2010) reviewed 138 evaluation studies and found that inquiry-based approaches in the science, engineering, technology ,and math Experiential learning: content areas had the largest effect sizes, or made the greatest positive Constructing learning through hands-on experiences that are difference, when there was an emphasis on active learning and involvement in highly social in nature. the investigative process (asking questions, designing investigations, collecting data, drawing conclusions, communicating findings). Hands-on experiences with Inquiry-based learning: Constructing learning through natural phenomena were also found to be associated with increased conceptual hands-on experiences that provide learning in the science content investigated.
    [Show full text]
  • The Stoics and the Practical: a Roman Reply to Aristotle
    DePaul University Via Sapientiae College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences 8-2013 The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle Robin Weiss DePaul University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd Recommended Citation Weiss, Robin, "The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle" (2013). College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations. 143. https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd/143 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences at Via Sapientiae. It has been accepted for inclusion in College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Via Sapientiae. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE STOICS AND THE PRACTICAL: A ROMAN REPLY TO ARISTOTLE A Thesis Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy August, 2013 BY Robin Weiss Department of Philosophy College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences DePaul University Chicago, IL - TABLE OF CONTENTS - Introduction……………………..............................................................................................................p.i Chapter One: Practical Knowledge and its Others Technê and Natural Philosophy…………………………….....……..……………………………….....p. 1 Virtue and technical expertise conflated – subsequently distinguished in Plato – ethical knowledge contrasted with that of nature in
    [Show full text]
  • Notes on Hume's Problem of Induction 1748 - Inquiry Concerning Human Understanding
    1740 - Treatise of Human Nature Notes on Hume's Problem of Induction 1748 - Inquiry Concerning Human Understanding Recall: Subject of confirmation = How scientific claims are justified. This assumes that they are capable of justification in the first place. Hume asks: Is there a rational basis for inductive inferences? Hume response: No! Consequence: To the extent that scientific claims are based on inductive inferences, they cannot be justified. Example: All observed ravens are black. Hume asks, Can we ever be justified in believing the conclusion? All ravens are black. Two types of objects of knowledge, according to Hume (I) Relations of ideas = Products of deductive (truth-preserving) Ex: 2 + 2 = 4 inferences; negation entails a contradiction. (II) Matters of fact = Products of inductive inferences; negation does Ex: All ravens are black. not entail a contradiction. Outline of Hume's Argument (1) Matters of fact can only be known through experience ("a posteriori"). (2) Therefore matters of fact can only be justified by recourse to experience. (3) But any attempt to do so is circular. ∴ There is no justification for inductive inferences. ASIDE 1. Hume is not just saying that we can never be certain about inductive inferences (i.e., we can never be 100% certain that all ravens are black). This would be uncontentious: Most people would agree that there's always room for error in making an inductive inference. However, most people would at the same time claim that we are justified in making (some) inductive inferences, even though they aren't 100% guaranteed to work (i.e., we think there are standards by which we can judge good inductive inferences from bad ones).
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Philosophy
    An Introduction to Philosophy W. Russ Payne Bellevue College Copyright (cc by nc 4.0) 2015 W. Russ Payne Permission is granted to copy, distribute and/or modify this document with attribution under the terms of Creative Commons: Attribution Noncommercial 4.0 International or any later version of this license. A copy of the license is found at http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0/ 1 Contents Introduction ………………………………………………. 3 Chapter 1: What Philosophy Is ………………………….. 5 Chapter 2: How to do Philosophy ………………….……. 11 Chapter 3: Ancient Philosophy ………………….………. 23 Chapter 4: Rationalism ………….………………….……. 38 Chapter 5: Empiricism …………………………………… 50 Chapter 6: Philosophy of Science ………………….…..… 58 Chapter 7: Philosophy of Mind …………………….……. 72 Chapter 8: Love and Happiness …………………….……. 79 Chapter 9: Meta Ethics …………………………………… 94 Chapter 10: Right Action ……………………...…………. 108 Chapter 11: Social Justice …………………………...…… 120 2 Introduction The goal of this text is to present philosophy to newcomers as a living discipline with historical roots. While a few early chapters are historically organized, my goal in the historical chapters is to trace a developmental progression of thought that introduces basic philosophical methods and frames issues that remain relevant today. Later chapters are topically organized. These include philosophy of science and philosophy of mind, areas where philosophy has shown dramatic recent progress. This text concludes with four chapters on ethics, broadly construed. I cover traditional theories of right action in the third of these. Students are first invited first to think about what is good for themselves and their relationships in a chapter of love and happiness. Next a few meta-ethical issues are considered; namely, whether they are moral truths and if so what makes them so.
    [Show full text]
  • Turns in the Evolution of the Problem of Induction*
    CARL G. HEMPEL TURNS IN THE EVOLUTION OF THE PROBLEM OF INDUCTION* 1. THE STANDARD CONCEPTION: INDUCTIVE "INFERENCE" Since the days of Hume's skeptical doubt, philosophical conceptions of the problem of induction and of ways in which it might be properly solved or dissolved have undergone a series of striking metamor- phoses. In my paper, I propose to examine some of those turnings, which seem to me to raise particularly important questions about the nature of empirical knowledge and especially scientific knowledge. Many, but by no means all, of the statements asserted by empirical science at a given time are accepted on the basis of previously established evidence sentences. Hume's skeptical doubt reflects the realization that most of those indirectly, or inferentially, accepted assertions rest on evidence that gives them no complete, no logically conclusive, support. This is, of course, the point of Hume's obser- vation that even if we have examined many occurrences of A and have found them all to be accompanied by B, it is quite conceivable, or logically possible, that some future occurrence of A might not be accompanied by B. Nor, we might add, does our evidence guarantee that past or present occurrences of A that we have not observed were- or are- accompanied by B, let alone that all occurrences ever of A are, without exception, accompanied by B. Yet, in our everyday pursuits as well as in scientific research we constantly rely on what I will call the method of inductive ac- ceptance, or MIA for short: we adopt beliefs, or expectations, about empirical matters on logically incomplete evidence, and we even base our actions on such beliefs- to the point of staking our lives on some of them.
    [Show full text]
  • The Inquiry Wheel, an Alternative to the Scientific Method. a View of The
    Chemical Education Today Reports from Other Journals The Inquiry Wheel, an Alternative to the Scientific Method A View of the Science Education Research Literature by William R. Robinson For many years I have felt that the scientific method as entific inquiry emerged and led to the description of the presented in many textbooks was not how my colleagues in inquiry wheel illustrated in Figure 1 and discussed below. chemistry did research. Even so, when I wrote a general However, before we look at the inquiry wheel, I think chemistry text I was told to put in a description of the sci- it worth noting that the majority of the scientists interviewed entific method because it was expected. Now, Reiff, (38 of 52) identified the most important aspect of an in- Harwood, and Phillipson have developed a more satisfac- vestigation as being literature based. To them a worthwhile tory model of scientific inquiry, the inquiry wheel, based on investigation was one that crossed the boundary from the information gathered from practicing scientists. This model known to the unknown and a knowledge of the literature is described in their paper “A Scientific Method Based upon is important in identifying that boundary. Research Scientists’ Conceptions of Scientific Inquiry” (1) based on interview data described in “Scientists’ Concep- Stages of Scientific Inquiry tions of Scientific Inquiry: Voices from the Front” (2). As a result of their interviews (2), the investigators de- The informants in this research were 52 science faculty scribe the process used by scientists as they pursue research members in nine science departments (anthropology, biol- as a wheel with questions at the hub and various stages of ogy, chemistry, geography, geology, medical sciences, physics, the inquiry in a circular arrangement around the hub (1).
    [Show full text]