Commentary on Galen Strawson

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Commentary on Galen Strawson Catherine Wilson Commentary on Galen Strawson I The ancient philosopher Anaxagoras (500–428 BCE) wondered how hair could be made from what was not hair, and flesh from what was not flesh. He concluded that the ‘seeds’ of everything were in every- thing, and his defiantly nonreductionistic theory of mind was ridi- culed by the atomist Lucretius as follows: If we cannot explain the ability of each animate being to experience sen- sation without attributing sensation to its constituent elements, what are we to say of the special atoms that compose the human race? Doubtless they shake and tremble with uncontrollable laughter and sprinkle their faces with dewy tears; doubtless they are qualified to discourse at length on the structure of compounds, and even investigate the nature of their own constituent atoms. (Lucretius, 2001, p. 59) Lucretius in turn found emergentism unproblematic: [S]ince we perceive that the eggs of birds change into live chicks, and that worms come seething out of the earth when untimely rains have caused putrefaction, it is evident that the sensible can be produced from the insensible. (Lucretius, 2001, p. 58) Galen Strawson sides with Lucretius on the question of hair and flesh, but with Anaxagoras on the question of mind. He asserts that the real physicalism to which he subscribes entails that the basic constitu- ents of the physical world, though not entities like tables and chairs, have experiences. According to Strawson, it is not necessary to have a brain to have experiences; some physical things that exist outside of and are not identical with living creatures, must have experiences too. I take his argument to comprise a thesis and two conditionals. The the- sis is that explanans and explanandum need to share properties and characteristics for there to be explanation at all. The first conditional Journal of Consciousness Studies, 13, No. 10–11, 2006, pp. 177–83 Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2010 For personal use only -- not for reproduction 178 C. WILSON is that if there are experiences, they must be explicable. The second conditional is that if we can’t in principle explain how the brain gener- ates experiences, the brain can’t be a necessary condition of experi- ence. It follows, according to Strawson, that there are sub-brain experiencing entities that permit or necessitate the emergence of experiences. I am not sure why the sub-brain experiencing entities are identified with ultimate particles; there is no separate argument for this that I found in Strawson’s text, but I leave this objection aside. In this comment, I will attempt to bring some historical perspective to this issue to show that Strawson’s Anaxagorean micropsychism, while not impossible, is unlikely and is not entailed by real physical- ism. It conflicts with some of the most exotic, as well as some of the most popular views about consciousness on record, including the views of Descartes, Kant and also Spinoza and Leibniz. Historically, defenders of ‘thinking matter’have been concerned to show that, even if atoms could not think, suitably organized congeries of them could do so. The possibility of thinking matter was much discussed after the publication of Descartes’s Meditations, with its claim to have demon- strated the existence of incorporeal thinking substance. Long before Locke ventured the seemingly timid, but actually rather inflammatory suggestion in the second edition of the Fourth Book of his Essay that we could not know that matter could not think, critics of Descartes urged an open-minded stance, for example, the authors of Objections VI. ‘[S]ince we do not know,’ they said, ‘what can be done by bodies and their motions, and since you confess that without a divine revela- tion no one can know everything which God has imparted ...howcan you possibly have known that God has not implanted in certain bodies a power or property enabling them to doubt, think, etc.?’ (Descartes, 1985–1993, VII, p. 421). The author of a notorious anti-Cartesian broadsheet circulating in Holland proposed that thought and exten- sion were modes of a single substance. This single-substance position was explicitly developed by Spinoza. Other critics thought Descartes’s restriction of experiences to humans was arbitrary and implausible. Leibniz in turn developed that line of thought. Spinoza and Leibniz might at first appear to be natural allies for Strawson. However, nei- ther Spinoza nor Leibniz sanctions the view that physical particles are or even might be conscious. Spinoza insisted against Descartes that we cannot conceive of dis- embodied minds: ‘An idea that excludes the existence of our Body can- not be in our Mind, but is contrary to it.’ (Spinoza, 1985, I, p. 500) He did not treat the question of the distribution of consciousness in the Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2010 For personal use only -- not for reproduction COMMENTARY ON GALEN STRAWSON 179 universe directly, but he seems to have ascribed thoughts of an intellec- tual, conceptual type only to God (identical with the totality of extended substance) and to humans, and to have ascribed experiences and feelings only to humans and animals. He took a definite anti-Car- tesian stand in referring to the lusts and appetites of insects, fish and birds (Spinoza, 1985, I, p. 528). Though Spinoza failed to say why one had to be a certain kind of ‘finite mode’ to possess consciousness, or even what kind of finite mode one had to be, he implied that one had to be a fairly complex entity of a certain degree of maturity. Some human bodies, he thought, possess very little by way of consciousness: He who, like an infant or child, has a Body capable of very few things, and very heavily dependent on external causes, has a Mind which con- sidered solely in itself is conscious of almost nothing of itself, or of God, or of things. On the other hand, he who has a Body capable of a great many things, has a Mind which considered only in itself is very much conscious of itself, and of God, and of things. (Spinoza, 1985, I, p. 614) Spinoza is accordingly best read as an ordinary physicalist who thinks that human and animal minds depend on their brains, and as an unusual ‘macropsychist’who considers the entire corporeal world as a divine thinking subject. It is hard to see him as an Anaxagorean micropsychist. With Leibniz, the case is more difficult. Leibniz’s famous ‘mill’ argument, though not identical to Strawson’s, appeals similarly to the inexplicability of experience by reference to the combined effects of non-experiencing entities in interaction: We must confess that the perception, and what depends on it, is inexpli- cable in terms of mechanical reasons, that is, through shapes and motions. If we imagine that there is a machine whose structure makes it think, sense, and have perceptions, we could conceive it enlarged, keep- ing the same proportions, so that we could enter into it, as one enters into a mill. Assuming that, when inspecting its interior, we will only find parts that push one another, and we will never find anything to explain a perception. And so, we should seek perception in the simple substance and not in the composite or in the machine. (Leibniz, 1989, p. 215) So Leibniz claimed that, because there are experiences and because experiences cannot be generated by complex machines, perception must pertain to the simple. There must be monads, unextended, simple, indivisible entities, with perception and appetition. Leibniz was a panpsychist in the sense of believing that everything that is a real, individual thing, and not an entity by convention, has experiences. Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2010 For personal use only -- not for reproduction 180 C. WILSON (For Leibniz, a table or chair is no more a single, real, individual thing than a salt-and-pepper set, or, for that matter, a knife and a fork.) Monads are not, however, like Strawson’s ultimate physical constit- uents. First, they are not physical — everything the natural scientist encounters in the physical world, said Leibniz, is complex and divisible. Second, they are supposed to give rise to the phenomenal world of extended bodies, and Strawson says that the emergence of extension from nonextension is incoherent. The monads are metaphysical and are the basis of an incoherently articulated emergentist account. Therefore, in insisting on them, Leibniz disqualified himself as a Strawsonian real physicalist. II Leibniz however held another version of panpsychism that has given commentators headaches because it does not seem to fit with the monadological theory. This version is well worth considering, because it suggests that the ultimate physical particles do not as a matter of fact have experiences, though, for all we know, they could. Leibniz’ other version of panpsychism adopts Spinoza’s anti- Cartesian dictum that there are no experiences that do not belong to living, organic bodies. Additionally, there is no lower limit to the size of organisms. Everything that exists is either an animated organism, and itself a federation of smaller animated organisms, or an entity by convention composed of such organisms. Though Leibniz’s theory has been judged unacceptable for centuries, it is in some ways less problematic than Strawson’s, insofar as Leibniz supposed that a power of autonomous change — ‘appetition’ always accompanied the power of ‘perception’. Here is another passage from the Monadology that has special relevance to that point: I...takeforgrantedthateverycreatedbeing,andconsequentlythe created monad as well, is subject to change, and even that this change is continual in each thing ...Itfollowsfromwhatwehavejustsaidthatthe monad’s natural changes come from an internal principle, since no externalcausecaninfluenceitinternally...Onecancallallsimplesub- stances or created monads entelechies, for they have in themselves a certainperfection...;theyhaveasufficiency...thatmakesthemthe sources of their internal actions, and, so to speak, incorporeal automata.
Recommended publications
  • Galen Strawson, Selves. an Essay in Revisionary Metaphysics
    Review: Galen Strawson, Selves. An Essay in Revisionary Metaphysics Ludwig Gierstl & Ludwig J. Jaskolla In 1929, Alfred North Whitehead wrote that philosophy never reverts to its old position after the shock of a great philosopher1. It might be the case that Galen Strawson's Selves2 causes such a shock. Selves is a brilliant piece of philosophy synthesizing deep insights into nature of human experience with speculative force3. Although, the book can- not be said to be easily accessible, studying it is rewarding and can be recommended to almost any philosopher interested in Metaphysics or Philosophy of Mind. In the following paragraphs, we are going to give a systematic sketch of Strawson's main line of thought and his central arguments. Basically, Selves can be divided into two main parts: The rst part addresses the phenomenology of the self as understood in our everyday approach to the world, while the second part discusses the phenomenological ndings of the rst part in terms of metaphysics. Despite this two-fold structure, we emphasize that due to our understanding both parts are interrelated systematically and methodologically forming a coherent whole. 1 The Phenomenology of the Self As everybody familiar with the debate concerning personal identity knows, there is abundant literature discussing the typical phenomenolog- ical features of the self or in particular: the human self. This ordinary account of the varieties of experiences tied to the self is merely deriva- tively Strawson's target. He is mainly interested in the discussion of one particular phenomenon which he calls SELF-experience. This phe- nomenon is best characterized in contrast to other experiences: While I may have a stinging pain in my left arm which is so strong that it eects my whole experiential pattern, the fact that my self is in some way part of this experience is not SELF-experience.
    [Show full text]
  • The Consciousness Deniers | by Galen Strawson | NYR Daily | the New York Review of Books 4/4/18, 12(56 PM
    The Consciousness Deniers | by Galen Strawson | NYR Daily | The New York Review of Books 4/4/18, 12(56 PM The Consciousness Deniers Galen Strawson What is the silliest claim ever made? The competition is fierce, but I think the answer is easy. Some people have denied the existence of consciousness: conscious experience, the subjective character of experience, the “what-it-is-like” of experience. Next to this denial—I’ll call it “the Denial”—every known religious belief is only a little less sensible than the belief that grass is green. The Denial began in the twentieth century and continues today in a few pockets of philosophy and psychology and, now, information technology. It had two main causes: the rise of the behaviorist approach in psychology, and the naturalistic approach in philosophy. These were good things in their way, but they spiraled out of control and gave birth to the Great Silliness. I want to consider these Courtesy the artist and Galerie Buchholz/The Museum of Modern Art/Licensed by SCALA / Art Resource, NY main causes first, and then say something rather gloomy Lucy McKenzie: Untitled, 2002 about a third, deeper, darker cause. But before that, I need to comment on what is being denied—consciousness, conscious experience, experience for short. What is it? Anyone who has ever seen or heard or smelled anything knows what it is; anyone who has ever been in pain, or felt hungry or hot or cold or remorseful, dismayed, uncertain, or sleepy, or has suddenly remembered a missed appointment. All these things involve what are sometimes called “qualia”—that is to say, different types or qualities of conscious experience.
    [Show full text]
  • The Elusive Origins of Consciousness: a Philosophical Argument for Panpsychism Over Competing Metaphysical Theories of Mind
    Trinity College Trinity College Digital Repository Trinity Publications (Newspapers, Yearbooks, The Trinity Papers (2011 - present) Catalogs, etc.) 2019 The Elusive Origins of Consciousness: A Philosophical Argument for Panpsychism over Competing Metaphysical Theories of Mind Tommy Tobias Aahlberg Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalrepository.trincoll.edu/trinitypapers Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Aahlberg, Tommy Tobias, "The Elusive Origins of Consciousness: A Philosophical Argument for Panpsychism over Competing Metaphysical Theories of Mind". The Trinity Papers (2011 - present) (2019). Trinity College Digital Repository, Hartford, CT. https://digitalrepository.trincoll.edu/trinitypapers/79 The Elusive Origins of Consciousness: A Philosophical Argument for Panpsychism over Competing Metaphysical Theories of Mind Tommy Tobias Aahlberg Introduction Underpinning everything that constitutes our perceived reality is consciousness. The fact that there is something that it is like to be us is at the foundation of everything we consequently come to care about in our lives. Every observation, sensation, thought, and emotion is predicated on the phenomenon that there is something that it is like to observe, sense, think, and feel. The awareness and experience of a world is the essential factor that separates our universe from any conceivable zombie universe where nothing is observed, sensed, thought, or felt. Necessarily, we filter every single moment through our consciousness. If consciousness did not exist there would be no groundwork for meaning as it would hold no basis in any conceivable creature’s awareness, and therefore such a universe would be meaningless. Despite, or perhaps due to, its fundamental nature and important implications – consciousness is poorly understood by contemporary science and philosophy alike, at least in the theoretical sense of understanding.
    [Show full text]
  • Naturalism Nagel and Theism.Docx
    Nagel, Naturalism and Theism Todd Moody (Saint Joseph’s University, Philadelphia) In his recent controversial book, Mind and Cosmos, Thomas Nagel writes: Many materialist naturalists would not describe their view as reductionist. But to those who doubt the adequacy of such a world view, the different attempts to accommodate within it mind and related phenomena all appear as attempts to reduce the true extent of reality to a common basis that is not rich enough for the purpose. Hence the resistance can be brought together as antireductionism.1 I want to discuss the italicized phrases and their implications. First, the term “materialist naturalist” calls for comment. Materialism is understood to be the ontological thesis that material things, or perhaps physical things and physical properties, are the only things there are. What does “naturalist” add to this? Nagel explains: I will use the terms “materialism” or “materialist naturalism” to refer to one side of this conflict and “antireductionism” to refer to the other side, even though the terms are rather rough.2 Elsewhere he adds, [T]here is ultimately one way that the natural order is intelligible, namely, through physical law—law—everything that exists and everything that happens can in principle be explained by the laws that govern the physical universe.3 What “naturalism” adds to materialism is the thesis that all that happens in the physical realm is “explained”, i.e., described by “mathematically stateable” laws.4 So much for “materialist naturalist.” Turning to the second italicized passage, we see that Nagel believes that this project has failed and must fail.
    [Show full text]
  • Consciousness As a Biological Phenomenon : an Alternative to Panpsychism
    This is a repository copy of Consciousness as a Biological Phenomenon : An Alternative to Panpsychism. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/132202/ Version: Accepted Version Article: Wilson, Catherine orcid.org/0000-0002-0760-4072 (Accepted: 2018) Consciousness as a Biological Phenomenon : An Alternative to Panpsychism. Harvard Review of Philosophy. (In Press) Reuse Items deposited in White Rose Research Online are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved unless indicated otherwise. They may be downloaded and/or printed for private study, or other acts as permitted by national copyright laws. The publisher or other rights holders may allow further reproduction and re-use of the full text version. This is indicated by the licence information on the White Rose Research Online record for the item. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ Consciousness as a Biological Phenomenon: An Alternative to Panpsychism 1 Catherine Wilson University of York (UK) The Graduate Center, CUNY Forthcoming in Harvard Review of Philosophy. Abstract: Following centuries of Cartesianism, which ascribed conscious awareness to humans alone, philosophers have begun to explore the possibility that experience in some form is widely distributed in the universe. It has been proposed that consciousness may pertain to machines, rocks, elementary particles, and perhaps the universe itself. This paper shows why philosophers have good reason to suppose that experiences are widely distributed in living nature, including worms and insects, but why panpsychism extending to non-living nature is an implausible doctrine.
    [Show full text]
  • FREE WILL Galen Strawson
    FREE WILL Galen Strawson Abstract ‘Free will’ is the conventional name of a topic that is best discussed without reference to the will. It is a topic in metaphysics and ethics as much as in the philosophy of mind. Its central questions are ‘What is it to act (or choose) freely?’, and ‘What is it to be morally responsible for one’s actions (or choices)?’ These two questions are closely connected, for it seems clear that freedom of action is a necessary condition of moral responsibility, even if it is not sufficient. Philosophers give very different answers to these questions. Consequently they give very different answers to two more specific questions, which are questions about ourselves: (1) Are we free agents? and (2) Can we be morally responsible for what we do? Answers to (1) and (2) range from ‘Yes, Yes’, to ‘No, No’-via ‘Yes, No’ and various degrees of ‘Perhaps’, ‘Possibly’, and ‘In a sense’. (The fourth pair of outright answers, ‘No, Yes’, is rare, but it has a kind of existentialist panache, and appears to be embraced by Wintergreen in Joseph Heller’s novel Closing Time, as well as by some Protestants). Prominent among the ‘Yes, Yes’ sayers are the compatibilists. They have this name because they hold that free will is compatible with determinism. Briefly, determinism is the view that the history of the universe is fixed: every- thing that happens is necessitated by what has already gone before, in such a way that nothing can happen otherwise than it does. According to compatibilists, freedom is compatible with determinism because freedom is essentially just a matter of not being constrained or hindered in certain ways when one acts or chooses.
    [Show full text]
  • Comments on Galen Strawson ‘Realistic Monism: Why Physicalism Entails Panpsychism’1
    Daniel Stoljar Comments on Galen Strawson ‘Realistic Monism: Why Physicalism Entails Panpsychism’1 There is at least one element in Strawson’s extremely rich paper that seems to me to be correct and important, and Strawson is absolutely right to bring it out. This is the point that people in philosophy of mind go around assuming that they know what the physical facts are, if not in detail then in outline: ‘… they think they know a lot about the nature of the physical’ (Strawson, 2006, p. 4). This assumption is false, or at any rate implausible, or at any rate un-argued for. To make the assumption, Strawson says, is a ‘very large mistake. It is perhaps Des- cartes’s, or perhaps rather “Descartes’s”, greatest mistake, and it is funny that in the past fifty years it has been the most fervent revilers of the great Descartes, the true father of modern materialism, who have made the mistake with most intensity’ (p. 5; footnote omitted). Strawson says that the mistake is not only large: it is fatal. Here too I agree, though I think I would express the fatality somewhat differently from him. In my view, the mistake is fatal because, on the assumption that we are ignorant of some of the crucial facts, the central pieces of reasoning in philosophy of mind collapse. For example, consider the zombie argument against materialism, or, as Strawson would say for reasons slightly opaque to me, the Australian (p. 22, fn. 37) zombie argument. Its first premise is that it is conceivable that I have a zombie duplicate; that is, there is someone identical to me in respect of every physical fact, but different from me in respect of some experiential fact.
    [Show full text]
  • Panpsychism, Priority Cosmopsychism and Information
    Fundamental Consciousness: Panpsychism, Priority Cosmopsychism and Information By Nino Kadić Submitted to Central European University Department of Philosophy In partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree Master of Philosophy Supervisor: Philip A. Goff Budapest, Hungary CEU eTD Collection 2016 Abstract In this thesis, I argue that consciousness cannot be explained solely in terms of the facts revealed to us by empirical science. This is explained through a discussion of the explanatory gap between our knowledge of physical facts and those regarding consciousness. Specifically, I argue against the Phenomenal Concept Strategy, a fairly recent approach to answering anti-physicalist arguments. I then claim that if we take consciousness as something that cannot be explained in purely physical terms, we must also say that it is a fundamental and ubiquitous feature of reality. I explain the motivation for accepting this claim by considering what it means for something to be an intrinsic nature and by addressing the problem of strong emergence. The result of these considerations is panpsychism, the theory that consciousness truly is fundamental and ubiquitous. After that, I introduce the combination problem, the issue of how small subjects combine into bigger subjects. Priority cosmopsychism is then offered as a possible way of avoiding the combination problem. I then argue against priority cosmopsychism, claiming instead that we should remain panpsychists. I then move on to suggest a solution to the combination problem based on a discussion of syntactic and semantic information. I argue that information can be used to explain how small subjects bond to form bigger subjects. The final result is an informational form of panpsychism.
    [Show full text]
  • A Novel Reading of Thomas Nagel's
    Organon F 2021: 1–17 ISSN 2585-7150 (online) DOI (to be assigned) ISSN 1335-0668 (print) RESEARCH ARTICLE A Novel Reading of Thomas Nagel’s “Challenge” to Physicalism Serdal Tümkaya* Received: 12 June 2020 / Accepted: 18 November 2020 Abstract: In passing remarks, some commentators have noted that for Nagel, physicalism is true. It has even been argued that Nagel seeks to find the best path to follow to achieve future physicalism. I advance these observations by adding that for Nagel, we should dis- cuss the consciousness problem not in terms of physical and mental issues but in terms of our desire to include consciousness in an objec- tive/scientific account, and we can achieve this only by revising our self-conception, i.e., folk psychology, to develop a more detached view of experience. Through the project of objective phenomenology, Nagel aims to achieve some sort of objective, detached, and scientific ex- planation of the subjective nature of experience. This project seeks to make the truth of physicalism intelligible and consciousness more amenable to scientific study, potentially raising an even broader con- cept than the one physicalism originally proposes. Keywords: Folk psychology; Nagel; objective phenomenology; physi- calism; science of consciousness. * Middle East Technical University and Ardahan University https://orcid.org/0000-0002-2453-4184 Ardahan University Yenisey Kampüsü, Çamlıçatak, Ardahan Department of Phi- losophy, 75002 Ardahan, Turkey. [email protected] © The Author. Journal compilation © The Editorial Board, Organon F. This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attri- bution-NonCommercial 4.0 International Public License (CC BY-NC 4.0).
    [Show full text]
  • Nietzsche on Mind and Nature
    OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 8/6/2015, SPi Nietzsche on Mind and Nature edited by Manuel Dries and P. J. E. Kail Preview - Copyrighted Material 1 OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 8/6/2015, SPi 3 Great Clarendon Street, Oxford, OX2 6DP, United Kingdom Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries # the several contributors 2015 The moral rights of the authors have been asserted First Edition published in 2015 Impression: 1 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, by licence or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above You must not circulate this work in any other form and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press 198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016, United States of America British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Control Number: 2014954288 ISBN 978–0–19–872223–6 Printed and bound by CPI Group (UK) Ltd, Croydon, CR0 4YY Links to third party websites are provided by Oxford in good faith and for information only.
    [Show full text]
  • Determinism and the Role of Moral Responsibility Justin Edward Edens University of Arkansas, Fayetteville
    University of Arkansas, Fayetteville ScholarWorks@UARK Theses and Dissertations 5-2017 Determinism and the Role of Moral Responsibility Justin Edward Edens University of Arkansas, Fayetteville Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarworks.uark.edu/etd Part of the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Edens, Justin Edward, "Determinism and the Role of Moral Responsibility" (2017). Theses and Dissertations. 1987. http://scholarworks.uark.edu/etd/1987 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by ScholarWorks@UARK. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks@UARK. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. Determinism and the Role of Moral Responsibility A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in Philosophy by Justin Edens University of Central Arkansas Bachelor of Arts in Philosophy, 2012 May 2017 University of Arkansas _____________________________ Dr. Warren Herold Thesis Director _____________________________ _____________________________ Dr. Eric Funkhouser Dr. Richard Lee Committee Member Committee Member Abstract In order to solve the apparent incompatibility between moral responsibility and determinism, it is necessary to understand moral responsibility in terms of the function it plays within moral systems, which is highly similar to the role played by laws within judicial systems. By showing that a conception of moral responsibility based upon desert is metaphysically untenable, a function-based conception will be showed to be much more likely. Furthermore, by considering why the desert-based conception has proven so resilient, insight into the moral responsibility/determinism debate may be possible.
    [Show full text]
  • ~Mind and Being Primacy of Panpsychism Strawson March2016
    Mind and Being: The Primacy of Panpsychism Galen Strawson to appear in Panpsychism: Philosophical Essays ed Brüntrup and Jaskolla (OUP). Updated February 2016 ——————————————————————————————————— 0. Introduction I’ll start with a metaphysical creed—four propositions. I’m confident that the first three are true, and I suspect that the fourth is true, but I don't think one has to accept any of them to agree with my principal thesis—the thesis of the primacy of panpsychism, the highly unoriginal thesis that there are compelling reasons for favouring panpsychism above all other positive substantive proposals about the fundamental nature of concrete reality. I’ll state the four propositions first in German because I like the way they sound in German. [1] Stoff ist Kraft, [2] Wesen ist Werden, [3] Sein ist Sosein, [4] Ansichsein ist Fürsichsein. These are identity claims—fully reversible. I’m not going to argue for them but I’ll provide a few glosses.1 1. Stoff ist Kraft [1] Stoff ist Kraft. Matter is force or as I will say energy: [1] matter is energy. Strictly speaking matter is only one form of concrete being, but I’ll use the word loosely to mean all concrete stuff: all concrete being is energy—energy-activity, energy-stuff. I’m using the word ‘energy’ as Heisenberg does when he writes that “energy is a substance”, “all particles are made of the same substance: energy” (Heisenberg 1958, 63; 71), and putting aside the common use according to which ‘energy’ denotes the power of ‘doing work’ contained in or possessed by a body or system of bodies.
    [Show full text]