Metric Geometry and the Determination of the Bohmian Quantum Potential

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Metric Geometry and the Determination of the Bohmian Quantum Potential J. Phys. Commun. 3 (2019) 065006 https://doi.org/10.1088/2399-6528/ab2820 PAPER Metric geometry and the determination of the Bohmian quantum OPEN ACCESS potential RECEIVED 6 February 2019 Paul Bracken REVISED 26 April 2019 Department of Mathematics, University of Texas, Edinburg, TX 78540, United States of America ACCEPTED FOR PUBLICATION E-mail: [email protected] 10 June 2019 Keywords: quantum theory, Finsler geometry, potential, curvature PUBLISHED 18 June 2019 Original content from this Abstract work may be used under A geometric approach to quantum mechanics which is formulated in terms of Finsler geometry is the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 3.0 developed. It is shown that quantum mechanics can be formulated in terms of Finsler configuration licence. space trajectories which obey Newton-like evolution but in the presence of an additional kind of Any further distribution of this work must maintain potential. This additional quantum potential which was obtained first by Bohm has the consequence attribution to the author(s) and the title of of contributing to the forces driving the system. This geometric picture accounts for many aspects of the work, journal citation quantum dynamics and leads to a more natural interpretation. It is found for example that dynamics and DOI. can be accounted for by incorporating quantum effects into the geometry of space-time. 1. Introduction It is still a task to understand and interpret quantum mechanics. It has become clear that quantum mechanics can be looked at from a geometric point of view. In fact, geometry can be applied to the study of the structure and interpretation of quantum mechanics. This is due largely to the fact that geometrical considerations have resulted in advances in various other areas of physics, most notably, general relativity. Quantum mechanics is not so easy to formulate in terms of a dynamical, geometric description in terms of trajectories in some configuration space for a number of reasons. It will be seen here that a particular framework for such a task can be developed. A first reason for this is the important fact of quantum correlation and another is the complicated phenomenon of quantum entanglement. Both quantum coherence and decoherence effects, the state superposition principle and so forth have a natural description based on the Schrödinger equation. It has long been known that determinism is hard to reconcile with such a description of quantum dynamics. This problem has been discussed by both de Broglie and Bohm [1–3]. This view of things consists of material point trajectories carried along by a pilot wave that evolves according to the Schrödinger equation for the wavefunction of the system. Bohmian trajectories follow the flux lines of probability current which is a function of the position coordinate of the particle involved. This implies that there is a certain nonlocality inherent in the usual picture. Bohm realized that this kind of dynamics can be described by configuration space trajectories which follow a Newton’s law evolution, but under the influence of a quantum potential in addition to the external potential. This quantum potential can be calculated in closed form. This quantum potential is added to the classical potential function and it makes a contribution to the evolution of the system. It will be useful to have a brief description of Bohm’s theory at hand [4], to be able to refer to it further on. Bohm began from a series of basic postulates. An individual system comprises a wave propagating in space and time along with a point particle which moves under the guidance of the wave. The wave is described mathematically by Schrödinger’s equation i ¶=t yy()xx,,tH ( t), where H is the Hamiltonian. The motion of the particle is obtained as the solution to 1 xx˙ =St()∣,1.1xx= ()t () m © 2019 The Author(s). Published by IOP Publishing Ltd J. Phys. Commun. 3 (2019) 065006 P Bracken where S is the phase of y()x, t and m the mass. One initial condition for (1.1) suffices to solve it. These give a theory of motion which is consistent from a physical point of view. To get compatibility of the motion of an ensemble of particles with quantum mechanics, Bohm states that the probability that a particle in the ensemble resides between x and x+dx at time t is R23()x, tdxwhere R = ∣∣y 2. In Bohm’s approach, the wavefunction in polar form y = ReiS is substituted into Schrödinger’s equation. By isolating real and imaginary parts, he found the movement under the guidance of the wave happens in agreement with a law of motion of the form ¶S 1 2 ++S2 +=2 RV0.() 1.2 ¶tm22mR Equation (1.2) is equal to the classical Hamilton-Jacobi equation except for the appearance of the term 2 Q =2R.1.3() 2mR It is referred to as the quantum potential. The equation of motion can be expressed as well in the form, d2x m =-()QV + ,1.4 () dt 2 where x=x (t) is the trajectory of the particle associated with its wavefunction. One approach to obtain a geometric formulation and interpretation of quantum mechanics is to introduce a particular geometric structure on which to base everything. Finsler geometry is a metric geometry which is well suited to this purpose [5]. It is described by a metric tensor which is a function of both the position and momentum variables. The metric in Finsler geometry is in fact a generalization of a Riemannian metric, and the case in which the metric is developed from the quantum potential will be studied. The approach of Chern to Finsler geometry will be followed [6, 7]. The theory that results by proceeding in this way accounts for quantum effects as a consequence of the geometry of space-time [8, 9]. The curvature is self-induced as well as generated by the collection of particles in a nonlocal fashion resulting in a curved configuration space. The metric tensor and as a consequence the curvature of the manifold depends on the coordinates of the particle, as well as all the other particles of the system. The wavelike nature of quantum mechanics is then confined to accounting for how space is described by the particular geometry. The main result of proceeding in this fashion is the conclusion that quantum mechanical properties are a net result of the metric used for the underlying space itself [10–15]. 2. Geometry of the projectivized tangent bundle and the Hilbert form A mathematical presentation of the geometric setting will be given so that later the physical application can be adapted in a straightforward manner. Let M be an m-dimensional manifold. This manifold is said to be a Finsler manifold if the length s of any curve described by t ¼(()ut1 ,, um ()) t in coordinates atb is given by the integral b ⎛ du1 dum ⎞ sFuu=¼¼⎜ 1,,,m ,,⎟ dt .() 2.1 òa ⎝ dt dt ⎠ In (2.1), F is a smooth non-negative function in 2m variables and the function F (x, y) vanishes only when y=0. It is required to be symmetrically homogeneous of degree one in the y variables Fx()∣∣()11,,;¼¼=¼¼ xmmll y ,, y l Fx 11 ,,;,, x mm y y , l Î . () 2.2 A Finsler manifold M has a tangent bundle p: TM M and a cotangent bundle p**: TM M. From TM the projectivized tangent bundle of M is obtained and denoted PTM, by identifying the non-zero vectors differing from each other by a real factor. Geometrically, PTM is the space of line elements on M. Let u i, 1im be local coordinates on M. Then a non-zero tangent vector can be represented in the form ¶ XX= i ,2.3() ¶ui with the X i not all zero. The uXii, are local coordinates on TM. They are also local coordinates on the space PTM with the X i homogeneous coordinates which are determined up to a real factor. A fundamental idea is to regard PTM as the base manifold of the vector bundle pT* M which is pulled back by means of the canonical projection map pPTM: M defined by pu()()ii,. X= u i () 2.4 2 J. Phys. Commun. 3 (2019) 065006 P Bracken Since the function F (uXii, ) is homogeneous of degree one in the X i variables, Euler’s theorem for homogeneous functions implies that ¶F X i = F.2.5() ¶X i Differentiating (2.5) with respect to X j, we obtain ¶F ¶2F ¶F + X i = .2.6() ¶X j ¶¶XXij¶X j Clearly (2.6) simplifies to ¶2 F X i = 0.() 2.7 ¶¶XXij Result (2.7) implies that the first derivatives of F with respect to the X i are homogeneous functions of degree zero in the X i coordinates. Such functions are functions on PTM. Suppose (vYii, ) is another local coordinate system on PTM, then it is the case that ¶vi Y i = X j,2.8() ¶X j hence ¶F ¶F ¶v j = .2.9() ¶X ij¶Y ¶ui Now an important one-form ω can be defined as ¶F ¶F w = dui = dvi.2.10() ¶X i ¶Y i It follows that ω in (2.10) is independent of the choice of local coordinates, hence it is defined intrinsically on PTM. The form (2.10) is usually referred to as the Hilbert form. By Euler’s theorem, the arclength integral (2.1) with respect to M can be formulated as b s = w.2.11() òa The integral (2.11) is called Hilbert’s invariant integral. On exterior differentiation, the Hilbert form yields a connection with some remarkable properties.
Recommended publications
  • Quantum Trajectories: Real Or Surreal?
    entropy Article Quantum Trajectories: Real or Surreal? Basil J. Hiley * and Peter Van Reeth * Department of Physics and Astronomy, University College London, Gower Street, London WC1E 6BT, UK * Correspondence: [email protected] (B.J.H.); [email protected] (P.V.R.) Received: 8 April 2018; Accepted: 2 May 2018; Published: 8 May 2018 Abstract: The claim of Kocsis et al. to have experimentally determined “photon trajectories” calls for a re-examination of the meaning of “quantum trajectories”. We will review the arguments that have been assumed to have established that a trajectory has no meaning in the context of quantum mechanics. We show that the conclusion that the Bohm trajectories should be called “surreal” because they are at “variance with the actual observed track” of a particle is wrong as it is based on a false argument. We also present the results of a numerical investigation of a double Stern-Gerlach experiment which shows clearly the role of the spin within the Bohm formalism and discuss situations where the appearance of the quantum potential is open to direct experimental exploration. Keywords: Stern-Gerlach; trajectories; spin 1. Introduction The recent claims to have observed “photon trajectories” [1–3] calls for a re-examination of what we precisely mean by a “particle trajectory” in the quantum domain. Mahler et al. [2] applied the Bohm approach [4] based on the non-relativistic Schrödinger equation to interpret their results, claiming their empirical evidence supported this approach producing “trajectories” remarkably similar to those presented in Philippidis, Dewdney and Hiley [5]. However, the Schrödinger equation cannot be applied to photons because photons have zero rest mass and are relativistic “particles” which must be treated differently.
    [Show full text]
  • The Stueckelberg Wave Equation and the Anomalous Magnetic Moment of the Electron
    The Stueckelberg wave equation and the anomalous magnetic moment of the electron A. F. Bennett College of Earth, Ocean and Atmospheric Sciences Oregon State University 104 CEOAS Administration Building Corvallis, OR 97331-5503, USA E-mail: [email protected] Abstract. The parametrized relativistic quantum mechanics of Stueckelberg [Helv. Phys. Acta 15, 23 (1942)] represents time as an operator, and has been shown elsewhere to yield the recently observed phenomena of quantum interference in time, quantum diffraction in time and quantum entanglement in time. The Stueckelberg wave equation as extended to a spin–1/2 particle by Horwitz and Arshansky [J. Phys. A: Math. Gen. 15, L659 (1982)] is shown here to yield the electron g–factor g = 2(1+ α/2π), to leading order in the renormalized fine structure constant α, in agreement with the quantum electrodynamics of Schwinger [Phys. Rev., 73, 416L (1948)]. PACS numbers: 03.65.Nk, 03.65.Pm, 03.65.Sq Keywords: relativistic quantum mechanics, quantum coherence in time, anomalous magnetic moment 1. Introduction The relativistic quantum mechanics of Dirac [1, 2] represents position as an operator and time as a parameter. The Dirac wave functions can be normalized over space with respect to a Lorentz–invariant measure of volume [2, Ch 3], but cannot be meaningfully normalized over time. Thus the Dirac formalism offers no precise meaning for the expectation of time [3, 9.5], and offers no representations for the recently– § observed phenomena of quantum interference in time [4, 5], quantum diffraction in time [6, 7] and quantum entanglement in time [8]. Quantum interference patterns and diffraction patterns [9, Chs 1–3] are multi–lobed probability distribution functions for the eigenvalues of an Hermitian operator, which is typically position.
    [Show full text]
  • Bohmian Mechanics Versus Madelung Quantum Hydrodynamics
    Ann. Univ. Sofia, Fac. Phys. Special Edition (2012) 112-119 [arXiv 0904.0723] Bohmian mechanics versus Madelung quantum hydrodynamics Roumen Tsekov Department of Physical Chemistry, University of Sofia, 1164 Sofia, Bulgaria It is shown that the Bohmian mechanics and the Madelung quantum hy- drodynamics are different theories and the latter is a better ontological interpre- tation of quantum mechanics. A new stochastic interpretation of quantum me- chanics is proposed, which is the background of the Madelung quantum hydro- dynamics. Its relation to the complex mechanics is also explored. A new complex hydrodynamics is proposed, which eliminates completely the Bohm quantum po- tential. It describes the quantum evolution of the probability density by a con- vective diffusion with imaginary transport coefficients. The Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics is guilty for the quantum mys- tery and many strange phenomena such as the Schrödinger cat, parallel quantum and classical worlds, wave-particle duality, decoherence, etc. Many scientists have tried, however, to put the quantum mechanics back on ontological foundations. For instance, Bohm [1] proposed an al- ternative interpretation of quantum mechanics, which is able to overcome some puzzles of the Copenhagen interpretation. He developed further the de Broglie pilot-wave theory and, for this reason, the Bohmian mechanics is also known as the de Broglie-Bohm theory. At the time of inception of quantum mechanics Madelung [2] has demonstrated that the Schrödinger equa- tion can be transformed in hydrodynamic form. This so-called Madelung quantum hydrodynam- ics is a less elaborated theory and usually considered as a precursor of the Bohmian mechanics. The scope of the present paper is to show that these two theories are different and the Made- lung hydrodynamics is a better interpretation of quantum mechanics than the Bohmian me- chanics.
    [Show full text]
  • The Quantum Potential And''causal''trajectories For
    REFERENCE IC/88/161 \ ^' I 6 AUG INTERNATIONAL CENTRE FOR / Co THEORETICAL PHYSICS THE QUANTUM POTENTIAL AND "CAUSAL" TRAJECTORIES FOR STATIONARY STATES AND FOR COHERENT STATES A.O. Barut and M. Bo2ic INTERNATIONAL ATOMIC ENERGY AGENCY UNITED NATIONS EDUCATIONAL, SCIENTIFIC AND CULTURAL ORGANIZATION IC/88/161 I. Introduction International Atomic Energy Agency During the last decade Bohm's causal trajectories based on the and concept of the so called "quantum potential" /I/ have been evaluated United Nations Educational Scientific and Cultural Organization in a number of cases, the double slit /2,3/, tunnelling through the INTERNATIONAL CENTRE FOR THEORETICAL PHYSICS barrier /4,5/, the Stern-Gerlach magnet /6/, neutron interferometer /8,9/, EPRB experiment /10/. In all these works the trajectories have been evaluated numerically for the time dependent wave packet of the Schrodinger equation. THE QUANTUM POTENTIAL AND "CAUSAL" TRAJECTORIES FOR STATIONARY STATES AND FOR COHERENT STATES * In the present paper we study explicitly the quantum potential and the associated trajectories for stationary states and for coherent states. We show how the quantum potential arises from the classical A.O. Barut ** and M. totii *** action. The classical action is a sum of two parts S ,= S^ + Sz> one International Centre for Theoretical Physics, Trieste, Italy. part Sj becomes the quantum action, the other part S2 is shifted to the quantum potential. We also show that the two definitions of causal ABSTRACT trajectories do not coincide for stationary states. We show for stationary states in a central potential that the quantum The content of our paper is as follows. Section II is devoted to action S is only a part of the classical action W and derive an expression for the "quantum potential" IL in terms of the other part.
    [Show full text]
  • Photon Wave Mechanics: a De Broglie - Bohm Approach
    PHOTON WAVE MECHANICS: A DE BROGLIE - BOHM APPROACH S. ESPOSITO Dipartimento di Scienze Fisiche, Universit`adi Napoli “Federico II” and Istituto Nazionale di Fisica Nucleare, Sezione di Napoli Mostra d’Oltremare Pad. 20, I-80125 Napoli Italy e-mail: [email protected] Abstract. We compare the de Broglie - Bohm theory for non-relativistic, scalar matter particles with the Majorana-R¨omer theory of electrodynamics, pointing out the impressive common pecu- liarities and the role of the spin in both theories. A novel insight into photon wave mechanics is envisaged. 1. Introduction Modern Quantum Mechanics was born with the observation of Heisenberg [1] that in atomic (and subatomic) systems there are directly observable quantities, such as emission frequencies, intensities and so on, as well as non directly observable quantities such as, for example, the position coordinates of an electron in an atom at a given time instant. The later fruitful developments of the quantum formalism was then devoted to connect observable quantities between them without the use of a model, differently to what happened in the framework of old quantum mechanics where specific geometrical and mechanical models were investigated to deduce the values of the observable quantities from a substantially non observable underlying structure. We now know that quantum phenomena are completely described by a complex- valued state function ψ satisfying the Schr¨odinger equation. The probabilistic in- terpretation of it was first suggested by Born [2] and, in the light of Heisenberg uncertainty principle, is a pillar of quantum mechanics itself. All the known experiments show that the probabilistic interpretation of the wave function is indeed the correct one (see any textbook on quantum mechanics, for 2 S.
    [Show full text]
  • Relativistic Quantum Field Theory - Implications for Gestalt Therapy (Brian O’Neil)
    Relativistic Quantum Field Theory - Implications for Gestalt Therapy (Brian O’Neil) It is timely to address how the terms ‘field’ and ‘field theory’ have developed in physics and Gestalt therapy and the inter-relation between the two. Gestalt therapy writers such as Parlett have noted advances in physics which have moved beyond the initial formulation of Maxwell’s electromagnetic field. This includes the quantum field, the relativitistic quantum field, and now post relativistic quantum fields through the work of Bohm and others. These advanced notions of field are beyond the original field theory taken up by Smuts, Lewin, Wertheimer and Gestalt therapy. The possible implication of this expanded field perception in physics for Gestalt therapy is outlined theoretically and clinically. Arjuna Said What are Nature and Self? What are the field and its Knower, knowledge and the object of knowledge? Teach me about them Krishna. Krisna: I am the Knower of the field in everybody Arjuna. genuine knowledge means knowing both the field and the Knower The Bhagavad Gita This paper is offered as a heuristic device to better understand the impact and application of field theory in Gestalt therapy and to refresh and enrich the dialogue between Gestalt therapy and other domains, specifically physics and biology. In particular, to what extent are the terms ‘field’ and field theory’ used as an epistemology (ie as a method of obtaining and validating knowledge) and as an ontology (ie expressing the nature of being), with the understanding that each term is not exclusive of the other. In the present state of physics there is an acceptance of ‘field’ as an ontological reality, while many Gestalt therapy writers relate to ‘field’ epistemologically as a metaphor or method.
    [Show full text]
  • Multi-Field and Bohm's Theory
    Multi-field and Bohm’s theory Davide Romano∗ June 02, 2020 forthcoming in Synthese Abstract In the recent literature, it has been shown that the wave function in the de Broglie–Bohm theory can be regarded as a new kind of field, i.e., a “multi-field”, in three-dimensional space. In this paper, I argue that the natural framework for the multi-field is the original second- order Bohm’s theory. In this context, it is possible: i) to construe the multi-field as a real scalar field; ii) to explain the physical interaction between the multi-field and the Bohmian particles; and iii) to clarify the status of the energy-momentum conservation and the dynamics of the theory. Contents 1 Introduction2 2 Is the wave function nomological?5 2.1 The nomological view: a brief introduction...........5 2.2 The analogy between the wave function and the Hamiltonian function..............................6 2.3 Top-down ( ) versus bottom-up (H) functions.........6 2.4 Time-dependence of the wave function.............9 2.5 Interaction between V and ................... 10 3 Bohm’s theory and Bohmian mechanics 12 3.1 Bohmian mechanics........................ 12 3.2 Bohm’s theory........................... 13 ∗University of Salzburg, philosophy department. E-mail: [email protected] 1 4 Why Bohm’s theory 15 5 Multi-field(s) from Bohm’s theory 17 6 Further considerations 19 6.1 Why not first order?....................... 19 6.2 Energy and momentum conservation.............. 22 6.3 A possible objection: the no-back reaction problem...... 23 7 Conclusions 27 1 Introduction Quantum mechanics describes the behavior of microscopic systems via a mathematical function defined on the system’s configuration space: the wave function.
    [Show full text]
  • Quantum Mechanics of the Electron Particle-Clock
    Quantum Mechanics of the electron particle-clock David Hestenes Department of Physics, Arizona State University, Tempe, Arizona 85287-1504∗ Understanding the electron clock and the role of complex numbers in quantum mechanics is grounded in the geometry of spacetime, and best expressed with Spacetime Algebra (STA). The efficiency of STA is demonstrated with coordinate-free applications to both relativistic and non- relativistic QM. Insight into the structure of Dirac theory is provided by a new comprehensive analysis of local observables and conservation laws. This provides the foundation for a comparative analysis of wave and particle models for the hydrogen atom, the workshop where Quantum Mechanics was designed, built and tested. PACS numbers: 10,03.65.-w Keywords: pilot waves, zitterbewegung, spacetime algebra I. INTRODUCTION The final Section argues for a realist interpretation of the Dirac wave function describing possible particle De Broglie always insisted that Quantum Mechanics is paths. a relativistic theory. Indeed, it began with de Broglie`s relativistic model for an electron clock. Ironically, when Schr¨odingerintroduced de Broglie`s idea into his wave II. SPACETIME ALGEBRA equation, he dispensed with both the clock and the rela- tivity! Spacetime Algebra (STA) plays an essential role in the This paper aims to revitalize de Broglie's idea of an formulation and analysis of electron theory in this paper. electron clock by giving it a central role in physical inter- Since thorough expositions of STA are available in many pretation of the Dirac wave function. In particular, we places [2{4], a brief description will suffice here, mainly aim for insight into structure of the wave function and to establish notations and define terms.
    [Show full text]
  • The Quantum Theory of Motion Firstly Introduced by Louis De Broglie, and Later and Independently by David Bohm, Has Several Attractive Features
    INERTIAL TRAJECTORIES IN DE BROGLIE-BOHM QUANTUM THEORY: AN UNEXPECTED PROBLEM1 PABLO ACUÑA INSTITUTO DE FILOSOFÍA PONTIFICIA UNIVERSIDAD CATÓLICA DE VALPARAÍSO AVENIDA EL BOSQUE 1290, 2530388, VIÑA DEL MAR, CHILE [email protected] A salient feature of de Broglie-Bohm quantum theory is that particles have de- terminate positions at all times and in all physical contexts. Hence, the trajec- tory of a particle is a well-defined concept. One then may expect that the closely related notion of inertial trajectory is also unproblematically defined. I show that this expectation is not met. I provide a framework that deploys six different ways in which de Broglie-Bohm theory can be interpreted, and I state that only in the canonical interpretation the concept of inertial trajectory is the customary one. However, in this interpretation the description of the dynamical interac- tion between the pilot-wave and the particles, which is crucial to distinguish inertial from non-inertial trajectories, is affected by serious difficulties, so other readings of the theory intend to avoid them. I show that in the alternative in- terpretations the concept at issue gets either drastically altered, or plainly un- defined. I also spell out further conceptual difficulties that are associated to the redefinitions of inertial trajectories, or to the absence of the concept. 1. INTRODUCTION The quantum theory of motion firstly introduced by Louis de Broglie, and later and independently by David Bohm, has several attractive features. Most notably: it is not affected by the measurement problem, it provides an intuitive and visualisable explanation of quantum phenomena, it offers a clear account of the classical limit, particles are always distinguishable, and they have definite positions at all times and in all contexts.
    [Show full text]
  • Hydrodynamics of the Dark Superfluid: I. Genesis of Fundamental Particles Marco Fedi
    Hydrodynamics of the dark superfluid: I. genesis of fundamental particles Marco Fedi To cite this version: Marco Fedi. Hydrodynamics of the dark superfluid: I. genesis of fundamental particles. 2017. hal- 01549082v1 HAL Id: hal-01549082 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01549082v1 Preprint submitted on 28 Jun 2017 (v1), last revised 19 Jul 2017 (v2) HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) Hydrodynamics of the dark superfluid: I. genesis of fundamental particles. Marco Fedi Received: date / Accepted: date Abstract Here we consider the existence of an ubiquitous 1 Introduction: a superfluid universe? dark superfluid which fills the universe corresponding to dark energy (∼ 70% of the universe mass-energy, also expressed K.Huang has dedicated a book [9] to the possibility that our in the cosmological constant) and dark matter. As in oth- universe possess superfluid features. Here we want to con- er superfluids, quantum vortices would originate, whose ge- tinue the theoretical investigation, also taking into account ometry can describe the spin of fundamental particles, sug- recent experiments and observations and in this first paper gesting the validity of a quantum hydrodynamic approach concerning the hydrodynamics of the dark superfluid we fo- to particle physics.
    [Show full text]
  • Quantum Mathematics
    Quantum Mathematics by Peter J. Olver University of Minnesota Table of Contents 1. Introduction .................... 3 2. Hamiltonian Mechanics ............... 3 Hamiltonian Systems ................ 3 Poisson Brackets ................. 7 Symmetries and First Integrals ........... 9 Hamilton-Jacobi Theory .............. 11 3. Geometric Optics and Wave Mechanics ....... 25 The Wave Equation ................ 25 Maxwell’s Equations ................ 27 High Frequency Limit and Quantization ........ 29 4. Basics of Quantum Mechanics ........... 36 Phase space ....................36 Observables ....................37 Schr¨odinger’s Equation ............... 38 Spectrum .....................39 The Uncertainty Principle ............. 43 5. Linear Operators and Their Spectrum ....... 44 Hilbert Space and Linear Operators ......... 44 The Spectral Theorem ............... 46 Spectrum of Operators ............... 48 Dispersion and Stationary Phase ........... 55 6. One–Dimensional Problems ............. 59 The Harmonic Oscillator .............. 63 Scattering and Inverse Scattering .......... 65 Isopectral Flows ..................75 9/9/21 1 c 2021 Peter J. Olver 7. Symmetry in Quantum Mechanics ......... 77 Why is Symmetry Important? ............ 77 Group Representations ............... 79 Lie Algebra Representations ............. 81 Representations of the Orthogonal Group ....... 83 The Hydrogen Atom ................ 91 The Zeeman Effect ................. 96 Addition of Angular Momenta ............ 97 Intensities and Selection Rules ............104
    [Show full text]
  • Reality of the Wave Function and Quantum Entanglement Mani Bhaumik1 Department of Physics and Astronomy, University of California, Los Angeles, USA.90095
    Reality of the wave function and quantum entanglement Mani Bhaumik1 Department of Physics and Astronomy, University of California, Los Angeles, USA.90095 Abstract The intrinsic fluctuations of the underlying, immutable quantum fields that fill all space and time can support the element of reality of a wave function in quantum mechanics. The mysterious non-locality of quantum entanglement may also be understood in terms of these inherent quantum fluctuations, ever-present at the most fundamental level of the universe. 1. Introduction The reality of the wave function in quantum mechanics has been controversial ever since Schrödinger introduced it in his equation of motion. Nevertheless, it would be reasonable to embrace at least a tentative conception of the quantum reality since quantum formalism invariably underpins the reality of our entire objective universe. 1 e-mail: [email protected] 1 In a recent article [1], it was pointed out that the wave function plausibly represents a structural reality of the very foundation of our universe. In brief, contemporary experimental observations supported by the quantum field theory demonstrate the universal presence and immutability of the abiding quantum fields at the ultimate level of reality as well as some definitive confirmation of the existence of inherent ceaseless fluctuations of these fields. Let us now explore how an elementary particle like electron can have its inescapable associated wave as a result of the incessant fluctuations of the primary quantum field. According to QFT, an electron represents a propagating discrete quantum of the underlying electron field. In other words, an electron is a quantized wave (or a ripple) of the electron quantum field, which acts as a particle because of its well-defined energy, momentum, and mass, which are conserved fundamentals of the electron.
    [Show full text]