Compositionality Without Word Boundaries
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Acknowledgments We would like to express our gratitude to the following colleagues for their valuable assistance in reviewing abstracts for Semantics and Linguistic Theory 22: Barbara Abbott Ted Fernald Andrew Koontz-Garboden Mats Rooth Dorit Abusch Tim Fernando Marcus Kracht Daniel Rothschild Maria Aloni Marcelo Ferreira Angelika Kratzer Susan Rothstein Luis Alonso-Ovalle Hana Filip Manfred Krifka Hotze Rullmann Peter Alrenaga Kai von Fintel Kiyomi Kusumoto Jerry Sadock Pranav Anand Danny Fox Bill Ladusaw Uli Sauerland Ana Arregui Itamar Francez Utpal Lahiri Philippe Schlenker Ron Artstein Lyn Frazier Fred Landman Bernhard Schwarz Nicholas Asher Jon Gajewski Peter Lasersohn Florian Schwarz Rebekah Baglini Mark Gawron Daniel Lassiter Roger Schwarzschild Alan Bale Anastasia Giannakidou Chungmin Lee Yael Sharvit Chris Barker Brendan Gillon Beth Levin Junko Shimoyama David Beaver Delia Graff Fara Jeff Lidz Mandy Simons John Beavers Aidan Gray Jo-Wang Lin Benjamin Spector Sigrid Beck Jeroen Groenendijk Sophia Malamud Jason Stanley Rajesh Bhatt Patrick Grosz Luisa Marti Penka Stateva Maria Bittner Elena Guerzoni Lisa Matthewson Markus Steinbach M. Ryan Bochnak Christine Gunlogson Ora Matushansky Tamina Stephenson Andrea Bonomi Martin Hackl William Mcclure Isidora Stojanovic Adrian Brasoveanu Valentine Hacquard Eric Mccready Anna Szabolcsi Seth Cable Chung-Hye Han Louise Mcnally Shoichi Takahashi Ivano Caponigro Nancy Hedberg Paula Menendez-Benito Yukinori Takubo Greg Carlson Irene Heim Jason Merchant Christopher Tancredi Elena Castroviejo-Miro Daphna Heller Friederike Moltmann Alice Ter Meulen Emmanuel Chemla Elena Herburger Marcin Morzycki Satoshi Tomioka Anna Chernilovskaya Klaus von Heusinger Sarah Murray Judith Tonhauser Gennaro Chierchia James Higginbotham Kimiko Nakanishi Galit W. Sassoon Ariel Cohen Jack Hoeksema Rick Nouwen Arnim von Stechow Cleo Condoravdi Angeliek van Hout Toshiyuki Ogihara Michael Wagner Bridget Copley Sabine Iatridou Roumyana Pancheva Gregory Ward Stephen Crain Tania Ionin Barbara Partee Tom Werner Henriette De Swart Michela Ippolito Jeffrey Pelletier Malte Willer Amy Rose Deal Pauline Jacobson Doris Penka Yoad Winter Paul Dekker Gerhard Jaeger Orin Percus Ming Xiang Ashwini Deo Hans Kamp Christopher Pinon Masahiro Yamada Jenny Doetjes Stefan Kaufmann Paul Portner Suwon Yoon Edit Doron Magdalena Kaufmann Chris Potts Ede Zimmermann Veena Dwivedi Edward Keenan Josep Quer Malte Zimmermann Regine Eckardt Chris Kennedy Jessica Rett Alessandro Zucchi Paul Elbourne Ezra Keshet Craige Roberts Martina Faller Peter Klecha Maribel Romero Donka Farkas Nathan Klinedinst Robert van Rooij Finally, we wish to express our sincere appreciation to the following units at the University of Chicago for providing financial and organizational support for the conference: The Division of Humanities The Department of Linguistics The Office of the Provost The Department of Philosophy The Franke Institute for the Humanities The Chicago Linguistic Society Chris Barker How to sprout Sluicing without deletion? Case matching provides a well-known argument that sluicing may involve deletion of silent syntactic structure (e.g., Merchant 2001): (1) a. Someonenom spoke to John, but I don’t know whonom/*whomacc spoke to John. b. John spoke to someoneacc, but I don’t know whomacc John spoke to . If the sluice gap contains a copy of the antecedent clause, the case of the wh-word is determined just as in any non-sluiced embedded question. Jager¨ (2001, 2005) explains how to guarantee case matching without resorting to silent syntactic structure. However, Jager’s¨ (2005:228) analysis does not generalize to sprouting (Chung, Ladusaw & McCloskey 1995): (2) John left at some time, but I don’t know when he left . Jager’s¨ analysis requires the antecedent clause to contain an indefinite, but the essence of sprouting is that there is no overt indefinite or any other overt sluicing trigger. I will provide a primarily semantic, anaphoric analysis that generalizes smoothly to sprouting cases. Although I will share Jager’s¨ starting point (type logical grammar), my solution will di⇤er from his not only in its empirical coverage, but conceptually and technically as well. Fragment. Let us reason about syntactic and semantic composition. If two constituents, A and Γ, can combine to form a complex expression in category B (i.e., if A Γ B, where ‘ ’ · ⇤ · indicates normal syntactic composition) and if we remove A, then what remains is an expression that clearly can combine with an A to its left to form a B: we conclude that Γ A B. This is simple ⇤ \ categorial grammar. Likewise (but less familiarly), if Γ[A] is a syntactic structure containing a specific occurrence of A inside of it, and this composite structure is in category B (i.e., if Γ[A] B), ⇤ then removing A from Γ produces an expression containing an A gap: ⇥xΓ[x] A B, where ‘A B’ ⇤ is the category of a B missing an A somewhere inside of it. I will write A ⇥xΓ[x] B, where ‘ ’ ◦ ⇤ ◦ is the syntactic operation of plugging A into the gap left in Γ, and where “⇥x...x)...” keeps track) of the syntactic position from which A has been removed. For instance, if the syntactic structure John ((spoke (to someone)) yesterday) has category · · · · S, and someone has category DPacc, then by the reasoning given above we are able to infer that ⇥x(John ((spoke (to x)) yesterday)) DPacc S. Since this is the expression that the sluice gap · · · · ⇤ is anaphoric to (and that supplies its semantic content), we correctly predict that the sluice gap will combine only with an accusative wh-word, and) not with a nominative one. We can implement the reasoning developed above in the form of a practical (i.e., decidable) fragment using Genzen sequent inference rules. Although the talk will not presuppose any previous familiarity with type logical grammar, the notation is as in Moortgat 1997: Γ A ⇥[B] Z A Γ B ⇥[B] Z Γ A Γ A B ⇤ ⇤ L · ⇤ R ⇤ ⇤ /L · ⇤ /R ⇥[Γ A B] Z \ Γ A B \ ⇥[B/A Γ] Z Γ B/A · \ ⇤ ⇤ \ · ⇤ ⇤ Γ A ⇥[B] Z A Γ B ⇥[B] Z Γ A Γ A B ⇤ ⇤ L ◦ ⇤ R ⇤ ⇤ L ◦ ⇤ R ⇥[Γ A B] Z Γ A B ⇥[B A Γ] Z Γ B A ◦ ⇤ ⇤ ◦ ⇤ ⇤ The R and R rules have already been discussed; the other inferences can easily be justified. \ ) ) ( ( We need one) additional rule to allow) for in-situ scope-taking:( ( ) Γ[A] A ⇥xΓ[x] ⇥ ◦ This rule says that A ⇥xΓ[x] is an equivalent way of writing the result of plugging A into the gap ◦ in ⇥xΓ[x], and that the two forms can be freely intersubstituted. Chris Barker Example. Then we have the following derivation for a simple sluicing example, Someone left, but I don’t know who (bidk is an amalgam representing but-I-don’t-know): (someone dp s) (bidk (who dp s)) s ◦ · · · ⇤ dp s ⇥y((someone y) (bidk (who dp s))) s ⇥ dp dp s s ◦ ) ◦ · · ·) ⇤ R · \ ⇤ ⇥y((someone y) (bidk (who dp s))) (dp s) s dp ⇥x(x left) s ⇥ ) ◦ · · · ⇤ ) ◦ · ⇤ R dp s ⇥z⇥y((someone y) (but (who z))) (dp s) )s ⇥ ⇥x(x left) dp sss ◦ ◦ · · ) · ⇤ ) ) R · ⇤ ⇤ L ⇥z⇥y((someone y) (bidk (who z))) (dp s) ((dp s) s) ⇥x(x left) (dp s)) s s ) ◦ · · · ⇤ ) ) · ◦ ) ⇤ L ⇥x(x left) (((dp s) s) ((dp s) ((dp s) s)) ⇥z⇥y((someone) y) (bidk (who z)))) s ) · ◦ ) )◦ ) ) ◦ · · )· ) ⇤ ⇥x(x left) ⇥y((someone y) (bidk (who sluicegap))) s ⇥( ) ·) ( ◦ ) ) ) ◦) · · · ⇤ (someone ⇥x(x left)) (bidk (who sluicegap)) s ⇥ ◦ · · · · ⇤ (someone left) (bidk (who sluicegap)) s ⇥ · · · · ⇤ Starting from the bottom: someone “raises” to take scope over the antecedent clause; the remnant of someone, i.e., ⇥x(x left) raises to take scope over the entire sluice; then the sluice gap raises · and tucks in beneath the raised remnant. The final ingredient is to assign to the sluice gap the duplicator meaning ⇥x.κxx. Then the standard (Curry-Howard) semantics for multi-modal type logical grammars (for now, see, e.g., Moortgat 1997 for details) delivers the denotation of the remnant as the content of the sluice gap. Sprouting. The fragment already generates sprouting examples. In the derivation above, the wh-word who needs an S containing a DP gap in order to form an embedded question, and so has category q/(dp s). The wh-word when in (2), then, requires a clause with an adverbial gap, i.e., q/(adv s), where adv = (dp s) (dp s). But assuming that the empty structure is a right identity for \ \ \ ) dp s dp s ‘ ’, i.e., that Γ () Γ, we have this simple proof: \ ⇤ \ R . In other words, starting · ) · ⇥ (dp s) (dp s) \ ⇤ \ \ \ with the tautology dp s dp s, if we remove the leftmost constituent from the structure on the left \ ⇤ \ of the turnstyle, the remaining (empty) structure must have category adv (with the identity function as its Curry-Howard semantic value). This means that we can freely add a silent, identity-function denoting adverb to the antecedent clause. There is no need to posit silent lexical content such as at some time, since