(D. 1037), Logical Theory, and the Aristotelian Tradition

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

(D. 1037), Logical Theory, and the Aristotelian Tradition AVICENNA (D. 1037), LOGICAL THEORY, AND THE ARISTOTELIAN TRADITION The Institute of Islamic Studies at McGill University, Montreal January 2014 A Thesis submitted to McGill University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy ©Kamran I. Karimullah 2014 1 ABSTRACT In this study I examine Avicenna’s (d. 1037) theory of conditional propositions, (or “if, then” sentences, qaḍāyā šarṭiyya muttaṣila), and his system of repetitive and conjunctive syllogisms (qiyāsāt istiṯnāʾiyya, qiyāsāt iqtirāniyya). I show that Avicenna’s theory of conditional propositions is conceived as a rejection of Alfarabi’s “context theory”–based system of conditional propositions and conditional syllogisms (qaḍāyā šarṭiyya). I also show that Avicenna’s “if, then” connectors operate as propositional connectives in the modern, technical sense of that term. However, the theoretical bases of Avicenna’s conjunctive syllogistic belong to the Prior Analytics. The system of conjunctive syllogisms and quantified conditionals, which is one of Avicenna’s most important contributions to the history of formal logic, is explicable in terms of Aristotle’s syllogistic theory. Stoic logic, on the other hand, plays a minor role. 2 RÉSUMÉ Dans cette étude, j’examine la théorie des propositions conditionnelles (qaḍāyā šarṭiyya muttaṣila) d’Avicenne (m. 1037) ainsi que son système des syllogismes répétitifs et conjonctifs (qiyāsāt istiṯnāʾiyya et qiyāsāt iqtirāniyya). J’établie que Avicenne a formulé sa théorie des propositions conditionnelles afin de rejeter le système des propositions conditionnelles et syllogismes hypothétiques (qiyāsāt šarṭiyya) d’Alfarabi (m. 950), qui s’est fondé sur une théorie de langue dans laquelle le contexte dialectique demeure au centre de l’analyse des propositions et des syllogismes (appelée “context theory”). Ainsi je démontre que le connecteur conditionnel “si, alors” dans la logique hypothétique d’Avicenne fonctionne comme l’opérateur logique au sens technique du terme. Pourtant, les bases théorétiques du syllogisme conjonctif sont tirées des Premiers Analytiques d’Aristote. Le système du syllogisme conjonctif et la théorie des conditionnelles quantifiées, que je considère ici parmi les apports les plus importants á l’histoire de la logique formelle, sont explicables à la lumière de la théorie syllogistique d’Aristote. Cependant, la logique stoïcienne ne joue pas un rôle essentiel. 3 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS My debt to my thesis supervisor Robert Wisnovsky cannot be expressed adequately in words. His kindness, generosity, wisdom, attention to detail, and encouragement at every instance has been more than could be expected. He will serve as a model for me in the future. This thesis could not have been written without the support of my beloved wife Sirad. It has been a long road, though with much joy: Mustafa and Nusayba were born during this journey. I thank her for help, support, good-humor, and, above all, patience. And to my parents, for—everything. 4 CONTENTS ABSTRACT RÉSUMÉ ACKNOWLEDGMENTS INTRODUCTION CHAPTER 1: THE STUDY OF AVICENNA’S THEORY OF CONDITIONAL PROPOSITIONS AND REPETITIVE AND CONJUNCTIVE SYLLOGISMS §1.0: CHAPTER OVERVIEW §1.1: VIRTUES OF RESCHER’S INTERPRETATION OF AVICENNA’S THEORY OF HYPOTHETICAL (“IF…THEN…” AND “EITHER…OR…”) PROPOSITIONS §1.2.0: INADEQUACIES OF RESCHER’S INTERPRETATION OF AVICENNA’S THEORY OF HYPOTHETICAL (“IF…THEN…” AND “EITHER…OR…”) SYLLOGISMS §1.2.1: HISTORIOLOGICAL CRITICISMS OF RESCHER’S INTERPRETATION §1.2.2: CONCEPTUAL CRITICISMS OF RESCHER’S INTERPRETATION §1.3: AFTER RESCHER 1: SHEHABY, GÄTJE AND MARÓTH ON ALFARABI AND AVICENNA’S THEORY OF HYPOTHETICAL (“IF…THEN…” AND “EITHER…OR…”) SYLLOGISMS §1.4: AFTER RESCHER 2: SHEHABY AND MARÓTH ON AVICENNA’S “PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC” §1.5: AFTER RESCHER 3: AVICENNA AND ARISTOTLE’S LOGICAL THEORY CHAPTER 2: ALFARABI ON CONDITIONALS §1 INTRODUCTION §2 THE ‘CONTEXT THEORY’ OF LOGIC: TRUTH, ASSENT, AND CONDITIONALS §3 CONDITIONALS IN ARGUMENTATIVE CONTEXTS §4 CLASSIFICATION OF IMPLICATION (LUZŪM) IN APCA: CONDITIONS OF ASSENT, CONTRADICTION §5 CONDITIONAL PROPOSITIONS AND INFERENTIAL VALIDITY §6 CONCLUSION CHAPTER 3: AVICENNA AND ALFARABI ON THE SUBJECT MATTER OF LOGIC, AND AVICENNA’S REJECTION OF COMPLETE (TĀMM) AND INCOMPLETE (ĠAYR TĀMM) CONNECTION §3.0 INTRODUCTION §3.1.1 ALFARABI ON THE SUBJECT MATTER OF LOGIC §3.1.2 AVICENNA ON THE AIMS, UTILITY AND SUBJECT MATTER OF LOGIC §3.2.0 COMPLETE/INCOMPLETE VS. COINCIDENTAL/RESTRICTED FOLLOWING: INTRODUCTION 5 §3.2.1 THE NATURE OF CONNECTIVE CONDITIONAL PROPOSITIONS AND THE COMPLETE/INCOMPLETE DIVISION OF CONNECTION (ITTIṢĀL) §3.3.0 AVICENNA ON REPETITIVE SYLLOGISMS IN ŠQ VIII: INTRODUCTION §3.3.1 AVICENNA’S SIMPLICITER AND RESTRICTED CONDITIONALS IN REPETITIVE SYLLOGISMS IN ŠQ VIII CHAPTER 4: INTERPRETING AVICENNA’S CONDITIONAL SYLLOGISTIC AS A PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC §4.0 INTRODUCTION §4.1 PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC IN ISLAMIC LATE ANTIQUITY? ENGAGING IN ANACHRONISM §4.2 CONDITION FP: AVICENNA ON DOUBT AND CONDITIONALITY §4.3 CONDITION WFF: AVICENNA ON NESTED CONDITIONALS AND REPETITIVE SYLLOGISMS (QIYĀSĀT ISTIṮNĀʾIYYA) CHAPTER 5: AVICENNA ON PRIOR ANALYTICS A23: CONJUNCTIVE SYLLOGISMS, REPETITIVE SYLLOGISMS, AND REDUCTION §5.1 INTRODUCTION §5.2.1 INTRODUCTORY REMARKS ON AVICENNA’S CONJUNCTIVE SYLLOGISMS (QIYĀSĀT IQTIRĀNIYYA): §5.2.2 AVICENNA’S CONJUNCTIVE SYLLOGISMS: ON THE “MIDDLE PART”, SYLLOGISTIC FIGURES, AND “STRONG RELEVANCE” §5.2.3 AVICENNA’S CONJUNCTIVE SYLLOGISMS: A-, I, E, O-CONDITIONALS §5.2.4 AVICENNA’S CONJUNCTIVE SYLLOGISMS: DIRECT AND INDIRECT REDUCTION IN AVICENNA AND ARISTOTLE §5.3.1 INTRODUCTORY REMARKS ON THE PROBLEM OF REPETITIVE SYLLOGISMS, AND THEIR REDUCTION TO CONJUNCTIVE SYLLOGISMS §5.3.2 ARISTOTLE ON DIRECT AND INDIRECT REDUCTION, AND THE REDUCTION OF PER IMPOSSIBILE SYLLOGISMS AND “SYLLOGISMS FROM A HYPOTHESIS” §5.3.3 AVICENNA ON THE REDUCTION OF CONDITIONAL SYLLOGISMS CONCLUSION BIBLIOGRAPHY 6 INTRODUCTION This study has two main objectives. The first is to examine Avicenna’s theory of conditionals. According to the convention Avicenna inherited from earlier logicians— especially Alfarabi—what I call conditionals, or “if, then” sentences, Avicenna calls “connective conditional propositions (qaḍāyā šarṭiyya muttaṣila)”.1 The second objective is to examine how Avicenna deploys conditionals in syllogistic forms of reasoning. These objectives are closely related, but if there is any deeper philosophical conclusion to be drawn from this study, it is that for Avicenna the second project is prior to the first project. In Avicenna’s systematic development of his theory of conditionals and conditional syllogisms in ŠQ V-IX, Avicenna presents his theory of restricted (ʿalā t-taḥqīq) and simpliciter (muṭlaq) conditionals,2 and his theory of quantified conditionals, before his presentation of the conjunctive syllogistic (qiyāsāt iqtirāniyya) in ŠQ VI,3 and before his exposition of repetitive syllogisms (qiyāsāt istiṯnāʾiyya) in ŠQ VIII.4 Nevertheless, despite the appearance that Avicenna develops his theory of conditionals prior to his theory of the syllogism, in fact, the converse is closer to the mark. It is Avicenna’s intuitions about what makes an argument with conditionals good that dictate the final form of his theory of conditional propositions, not the reverse. 1 These stand in contrast with “disjunctive conditional propositions (qaḍāyā šarṭiyya munfaṣila)”, which will not be dealt with in this study. 2 See N. Rescher, “Avicenna on the Logic of the ‘Conditional’ Proposition,” in Studies in the History of Arabic Logic (Pittsburgh: Pittsburgh University Press, 1963), 76-86. 3 Other manuscripts of this portion of the Šifāʾ make what is called Book VII in the edition follow Book V in the edition. The order in the printed edition is: V (conditional propositions) VI (conjunctive syllogisms) VII (conditional proposition equipollence). Other manuscripts (e.g. Ayasofia 2442 and Nuruosmaniye 2710) have the following order: (conditional propositions) (conditional proposition equipollence) (conjunctive syllogisms). This latter must be the correct one, since Avicenna uses the equipollence relations from ŠQ VII in the reduction of imperfect conjunctive syllogisms to perfect ones in ŠQ VI. 4 On the translation of istiṯnāʾī as “repetitive”, see K. Gyekye, “The Term ‘istithnāʾ’ in Arabic Logic”, Journal of the American Oriental Society 92 (1972): 88-92). 7 The truth that intuitions about what makes an argument good dictate the account of what makes a conditional true is evidently on display in Avicenna. Without a doubt, the theoretical work in ŠQ V and VII is undertaken in order to make possible an account of valid inferences with conditional premises and conclusions that closely parallels Aristotle’s syllogistic theory set out in An. Pr. A1-7. In other words, it is because Avicenna feels that Aristotle’s account of logical validity is the correct account that he feels the need to develop a theory of quantified conditionals, and a doctrine of genuine versus absolute following (luzūm) and concomitance (muwāfaqa, maʿiyya). Yet, this belief also impels him to reject earlier theories of the conditional such as those found in Alfarabi (and likely originating in the work of Galen5) that are based on complete (tāmm) and incomplete (ġayr tāmm, nāqiṣ) connection (ittiṣāl, ittibāʿ) and incompatibility (ʿinād, taʿānud) because they are incompatible with Aristotle’s views of syllogistic validity. To varying degrees, secondary literature has not appreciated
Recommended publications
  • Immediate Inference
    Immediate Inference Dr Desh Raj Sirswal, Assistant Professor (Philosophy) P.G. Govt. College for Girls, Sector-11, Chandigarh http://drsirswal.webs.com . Inference Inference is the act or process of deriving a conclusion based solely on what one already knows. Inference has two types: Deductive Inference and Inductive Inference. They are deductive, when we move from the general to the particular and inductive where the conclusion is wider in extent than the premises. Immediate Inference Deductive inference may be further classified as (i) Immediate Inference (ii) Mediate Inference. In immediate inference there is one and only one premise and from this sole premise conclusion is drawn. Immediate inference has two types mentioned below: Square of Opposition Eduction Here we will know about Eduction in details. Eduction The second form of Immediate Inference is Eduction. It has three types – Conversion, Obversion and Contraposition. These are not part of the square of opposition. They involve certain changes in their subject and predicate terms. The main concern is to converse logical equivalence. Details are given below: Conversion An inference formed by interchanging the subject and predicate terms of a categorical proposition. Not all conversions are valid. Conversion grounds an immediate inference for both E and I propositions That is, the converse of any E or I proposition is true if and only if the original proposition was true. Thus, in each of the pairs noted as examples either both propositions are true or both are false. Steps for Conversion Reversing the subject and the predicate terms in the premise. Valid Conversions Convertend Converse A: All S is P.
    [Show full text]
  • MGF1121 Course Outline
    MGF1121 Course Outline Introduction to Logic............................................................................................................. (3) (P) Description: This course is a study of both the formal and informal nature of human thought. It includes an examination of informal fallacies, sentential symbolic logic and deductive proofs, categorical propositions, syllogistic arguments and sorites. General Education Learning Outcome: The primary General Education Learning Outcome (GELO) for this course is Quantitative Reasoning, which is to understand and apply mathematical concepts and reasoning, and analyze and interpret various types of data. The GELO will be assessed through targeted questions on either the comprehensive final or an outside assignment. Prerequisite: MFG1100, MAT1033, or MAT1034 with a grade of “C” or better, OR the equivalent. Rationale: In order to function effectively and productively in an increasingly complex democratic society, students must be able to think for themselves to make the best possible decisions in the many and varied situations that will confront them. Knowledge of the basic concepts of logical reasoning, as offered in this course, will give students a firm foundation on which to base their decision-making processes. Students wishing to major in computer science, philosophy, mathematics, engineering and most natural sciences are required to have a working knowledge of symbolic logic and its applications. Impact Assessment: Introduction to Logic provides students with critical insight
    [Show full text]
  • Prof. C. Byrne Dept. of Philosophy SYLLOGISTIC LOGIC Syllogistic
    Prof. C. Byrne Dept. of Philosophy SYLLOGISTIC LOGIC Syllogistic logic is the original form in which formal logic was developed; hence it is sometimes also referred to as Aristotelian logic after Aristotle, one of the founders of this branch of formal logic. Before we can examine the logical structure of any argument to see whether it is valid or invalid, we must first examine the logical structure of the propositions out of which it is com- posed. In the case of syllogistic logic, this requires an examination of categorical propositions because all syllogistic arguments, or syllogisms, are composed of categorical propositions. CATEGORICAL PROPOSITIONS A categorical proposition claims that a certain relation holds between two classes, groups, or general kinds of things (a.k.a. categories). In particular, every categorical proposition claims that one class of things either includes or excludes, either in whole or in part, another class of things. As a result, every categorical proposition has a quality, either affirmative or negative, and a quantity, either universal or particular. Taken together, this means that there are four different types of categorical propositions, which appear below. Note as well that every categorical proposition is made out of exactly four components, which must appear in the following order if the proposition is to be in standard categorical form: 1) the quantifier; 2) the subject term (S); 3) the copula; and 4) the predicate term (P). 1. Universal affirmative (A) All S’s are P’s. 2. Universal negative (E) No S’s are P’s. 3. Particular affirmative (I) Some S’s are P’s.
    [Show full text]
  • Unit 2 Deductive Reasoning
    UNIT 2 DEDUCTIVE REASONING Contents 2.0 Objectives 2.1 Introduction 2.2 Deductive Arguments: Truth-Conditions of Relations 2.3 Opposition of Relations 2.4 Categorical Proposition and Distribution of Terms 2.5 Diagrammatic Presentation of Distribution 2.6 Equivalence Relation 2.7 Criticisms 2.8 Let Us Sum Up 2.9 Key Words 2.10 Further Readings and References 2.11 Answers to Check Your Progress 2.0 OBJECTIVES This unit will help you to study: • one type of deductive argument known as immediate inference • the truth-conditions, which define the relations • which terms are distributed or undistributed • the subsequent units • the limitations of immediate inference which have been briefly touched upon 2.1 INTRODUCTION Since any reasoning involves argument, we shall begin with the type of relations between statements, which constitute an argument. A study of relation between propositions is also known as ‘Eduction’ in classical logic and eduction is one of the types of inference called immediate inference because we infer from one premise only. 2.2 DEDUCTIVE ARGUMENTS: TRUTH CONDITIONS OF RELATIONS 1 For the sake of convenience, let p and q denote premise and conclusion respectively. Any relation between p and q is defined by the truth-value, which they take. Let us first, define these relations. ‘True’ and ‘False’ are denoted respectively by 1 and 0. 1. p – 1, q – 1 Relation p – 0, q – 1 or Independence p – 0, q – 0 p – 1, q – 0 2. p – 1, q – 1 Equivalence p – 0, q - 0 3. p – 1; q – 0 Contradiction p – 0; q - 1 4.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Logic: from Everyday Life to Formal Systems Albert Mosley Smith College, [email protected]
    Smith ScholarWorks Open Educational Resources: Textbooks Open Educational Resources 2019 An Introduction to Logic: From Everyday Life to Formal Systems Albert Mosley Smith College, [email protected] Eulalio Baltazar Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.smith.edu/textbooks Part of the Logic and Foundations of Mathematics Commons Recommended Citation Mosley, Albert and Baltazar, Eulalio, "An Introduction to Logic: From Everyday Life to Formal Systems" (2019). Open Educational Resources: Textbooks, Smith College, Northampton, MA. https://scholarworks.smith.edu/textbooks/1 This Book has been accepted for inclusion in Open Educational Resources: Textbooks by an authorized administrator of Smith ScholarWorks. For more information, please contact [email protected] AN INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC FROM EVERYDAY LIFE TO FORMAL SYSTEMS Dr. Albert Mosley Dr. Eulalio Baltazar 2019 Northampton, Massachusetts AN INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC FROM EVERYDAY LIFE TO FORMAL SYSTEMS Dr. Albert Mosley Dr. Eulalio Baltazar © Copyright 2019 Dr. Albert Mosley This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-ShareAlike 4.0 International License. For more information, visit https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc- sa/4.0/ TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION: LANGUAGE AND RATIONALITY i-v CHAPTER 1: THE STRUCTURE OF ARGUMENTS A. Distinguishing Arguments from Non-arguments 1 B. Logic in Everyday Life 13 C. Classical Logic: Categorical …………………………………… ……… ……….....17 D. Refutations 23 E. Validity and Soundness……………………………………………………………… 29 F. Modern Logic: Truth-Functional…… ……………………………………………… 32 G. Refutations 38 H. Validity and Soundness……………………………………….……………………... 44 CHAPTER 2: CLASSICAL LOGIC A. Categorical Propositions…………………………………………………… 47 B. Definitions…………………………………………………………… ………………….53 C. Definition by Genus and Difference…………………………………. ……………..63 D. Translation From Ordinary Language to Formal Logic………………………………… 67 CHAPTER 3: CATEGORICAL INFERENCES A.
    [Show full text]
  • Part 3. the Logic of Arguments
    Logic for Liberal Arts Students Part 3. The Logic of Arguments nto the assembly of the gods came Dialectic, a woman whose weapons are Icomplex and knotty utterances....In her left hand she held a snake twined in immense coils; in her right hand a set of formulas, carefully inscribed on wax tablets, which were adorned with the beauty of contrasting colors, was held on the inside by a hidden hook; but since her left hand kept the crafty device of the snake hidden under her cloak, her right was offered to one and all. Then if anyone took one of those formulas, he was soon caught on the hook and dragged toward the poisonous coils of the hidden snake, which presently emerged and after first biting the man relentlessly with the venomous points of its sharp teeth then gripped him in its many coils and compelled him to the intended position. If no one wanted to take any of the formulas, Dialectic confronted them with some other questions; or secretly stirred the snake to creep up on them until its tight embrace strangled those who were caught and compelled them to accept the will of their interrogator. Martianus Capella, The Seven Liberal Arts, 327-329 (310-339 A.D.) Dialectica with Serpent resting on Aristotle with the Organon. Chartres Cathedral West Façade, Right Portal, ca. 1145-1155. Version2/10/2008 Table of Contents Part 3. The Logic of Arguments .........................................................................................1 Introduction......................................................................................................................1
    [Show full text]
  • LOGIC and SCIENTIFIC METHOD PHL2B02 II SEMESTER CORE COURSE BA PHILOSOPHY PROGRAMME (2019 Admission) Book Code - 19502
    School of Distance Education LOGIC AND SCIENTIFIC METHOD PHL2B02 II SEMESTER CORE COURSE BA PHILOSOPHY PROGRAMME (2019 Admission) Book Code - 19502 UNIVERSITY OF CALICUT SCHOOL OF DISTANCE EDUCATION Calicut university P.O, Malappuram Kerala, India 673 635. Logic and Scientific Method Page 1 School of Distance Education UNIVERSITY OF CALICUT SCHOOL OF DISTANCE EDUCATION STUDY MATERIAL Core Course BA PHILOSOPHY PROGRAMME II Semester Logic & scientific method Module I Module II Dr. K. Syamala Prof. V. M. Siddharthan Head of the Dept. of Philosophy Former Head of the Dept. of Philosophy Sree Sankaracharya University of Sanskrit, Maharaja’s College, Ernakulu Regional Center Edat, Payyannur, Kannur (Dt.) Module III Module IV Dr. Smitha T. M. Ms. Priya. O Assistant Professor of Philosophy Assistant Professor of Philosophy Maharaja’s College Govt. Brennen College Ernakulum, Cochin - 682 011 Thalassery - 670 106 Module V Scrutinized by: Dr. M. Ramakrishnan Dr. Lenin C. C. Former Head of the Dept. of Philosophy Assistant Professor of Philosophy Govt. Brennen College Govt. Brennen College Thalassery - 670 106 Thalassery (Chairperson, Board of Studies in Philosophy, University of Calicut) Layout: Computer Section, SDE © Reserved Logic and Scientific Method Page 2 School of Distance Education MODULE -1 08 MODULE-II 18 MODULE-III 29 MODULE-IV 43 MODULE-V 66 Logic and Scientific Method Page 3 School of Distance Education PREFACE The progression of human knowledge is motivated and guided by the incessant search for truth. The innate faculty of reasoning is the most reliable means to distinguish between the true and false in knowledge. Logic is the branch of philosophy that analyses and prescribes the norms, principles and rules that govern our reasoning process.
    [Show full text]
  • 5.6 Further Immediate Inferences
    M05_COPI1396_13_SE_C05.QXD 10/12/07 9:00 PM Page 198 198 CHAPTER 5 Categorical Propositions EXERCISES A. If we assume that the first proposition in each of the following sets is true, what can we affirm about the truth or falsehood of the remaining proposi- tions in each set? B. If we assume that the first proposition in each set is false, what can we affirm? *1. a. All successful executives are intelligent people. b. No successful executives are intelligent people. c. Some successful executives are intelligent people. d. Some successful executives are not intelligent people. 2. a. No animals with horns are carnivores. b. Some animals with horns are carnivores. c. Some animals with horns are not carnivores. d. All animals with horns are carnivores. 3. a. Some uranium isotopes are highly unstable substances. b. Some uranium isotopes are not highly unstable substances. c. All uranium isotopes are highly unstable substances. d. No uranium isotopes are highly unstable substances. 4. a. Some college professors are not entertaining lecturers. b. All college professors are entertaining lecturers. c. No college professors are entertaining lecturers. d. Some college professors are entertaining lecturers. 5.6 Further Immediate Inferences Three other important kinds of immediate inference are not associated directly with the square of opposition: Conversion, Obversion, and Contraposition. These we now explain: A. CONVERSION Conversion is an inference that proceeds by interchanging the subject and predicate terms of the proposition. “No men are angels” converts to “No an- gels are men,” and these propositions may be validly inferred from one another. Similarly, “Some women are writers” and “Some writers are women” are log- ically equivalent, and by conversion either can be validly inferred from the other.
    [Show full text]
  • 5.5 the Traditional Square of Opposition 193
    M05_COPI1396_13_SE_C05.QXD 10/12/07 9:00 PM Page 193 5.5 The Traditional Square of Opposition 193 EXERCISES Name the quality and quantity of each of the following propositions, and state whether their subject and predicate terms are distributed or undistributed. *1. Some presidential candidates will be sadly disappointed people. 2. All those who died in Nazi concentration camps were victims of a cruel and irrational tyranny. 3. Some recently identified unstable elements were not entirely acciden- tal discoveries. 4. Some members of the military-industrial complex are mild-mannered people to whom violence is abhorrent. *5. No leader of the feminist movement is a major business executive. 6. All hard-line advocates of law and order at any cost are people who will be remembered, if at all, only for having failed to understand the major social pressures of the twenty-first century. 7. Some recent rulings of the Supreme Court were politically motivated decisions that flouted the entire history of U.S. legal practice. 8. No harmful pesticides or chemical defoliants were genuine contribu- tions to the long-range agricultural goals of the nation. 9. Some advocates of major political, social, and economic reforms are not responsible people who have a stake in maintaining the status quo. *10. All new labor-saving devices are major threats to the trade union movement. 5.5 The Traditional Square of Opposition The preceeding analysis of categorical propositions enables us to exhibit the relations among those propositions, which in turn provide solid grounds for a great deal of the reasoning we do in everyday life.
    [Show full text]
  • Definitional Dictionary of Logic
    DEFINITIONAL DICTIONARY OF LOGIC 2009 Complied by Dr Desh Raj Sirswal http://drsirswal.webs.com A Accident, Fallacy of: A fallacy committed when a general rule is applied to a specific case, but because of extenuating circumstances, the case is an exception to the general rule and the general rule should not be applied to the case. Amphiboly, Fallacy of: A fallacy containing a statement that is ambiguous because of its grammatical construction. One interpretation makes the statement true, the other makes it false. If the ambiguous statement is interpreted one way, the premise is true but the conclusion is false; but if the ambiguous statement is interpreted the other way, the premise is false. The meaning must shift if the argument is going to go from a true premise to a true conclusion. If the meaning is not allowed to shift during the argument, either the argument has false a premise or it is invalid. Appeal to Questionable Authority Fallacy (argumentum ad verecundiam):When someone attempts to support a claim by appealing to an authority that is untrustworthy, or when the authority is unqualified, or prejudiced, or has a motive to lie. Argument: An argument is a connected series of statements or propositions, some of which are intended to provide support, justification or evidence for the truth of another statement or proposition. Arguments consist of one or more premises and a conclusion. Argument Against the Person (argumentum ad hominem): This fallacy is committed when you attack a person s character or personal circumstances in order to oppose or discredit their argument or viewpoint.
    [Show full text]