Expansions of the Exponential and the Logarithm of Power Series and Applications

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Expansions of the Exponential and the Logarithm of Power Series and Applications Arab. J. Math. (2017) 6:95–108 DOI 10.1007/s40065-017-0166-4 Arabian Journal of Mathematics Feng Qi · Xiao-Ting Shi · Fang-Fang Liu Expansions of the exponential and the logarithm of power series and applications Received: 12 June 2016 / Accepted: 2 April 2017 / Published online: 17 April 2017 © The Author(s) 2017. This article is an open access publication Abstract In the paper, the authors establish explicit formulas for asymptotic and power series expansions of the exponential and the logarithm of asymptotic and power series expansions. The explicit formulas for the power series expansions of the exponential and the logarithm of a power series expansion are applied to find explicit formulas for the Bell numbers and logarithmic polynomials in combinatorics and number theory. Mathematics Subject Classification 34E05 · 11B73 · 11B75 · 11B83 · 30B10 ﺍﻟﻤﻠﺨﺺ ﻓﻲ ﻫﺬﻩ ﺍﻟﻮﺭﻗﺔ ﻳﻜﺮﺱ ﺍﻟﻤﺆﻟﻔﻮﻥ ﺻﻴﻐﺎ ﺻﺮﻳﺤﺔ ﻟﺘﻤﺪﻳﺪﺍﺕ ّﻣﻘﺎﺭﺑﻴ ﺔ ﻭﻣﺘﺴﻠﺴﻼﺕ ﻗﻮﻯ ﻷﺱ ﻭﻟﻮﻏﺎﺭﻳﺘﻢ ﺗﻤﺪﻳﺪﺍﺕ ﻣﻘﺎﺭﺑﻴﺔ ﻭﻣﺘﺴﻠﺴﻼﺕ ﻗﻮﻯ. ﺗﻢ ﺗﻄﺒﻴﻖ ﺍﻟﺼﻴﻎ ﺍﻟﺼﺮﻳﺤﺔ ﻟﺘﻤﺪﻳﺪﺍﺕ ﻣﺘﺴﻠﺴﻼﺕ ﺍﻟﻘﻮﻯ ﻷﺱ ﻭﻟﻮﻏﺎﺭﻳﺘﻢ ﺗﻤﺪﻳﺪ ﻣﺘﺴﻠﺴﻼﺕ ﻗﻮﻯ ﻹﻳﺠﺎﺩ ﺻﻴﻎ ﺻﺮﻳﺤﺔ ﻷﻋﺪﺍﺩ ﺑﻞ ﻭﻛﺜﻴﺮﺍﺕ ﺍﻟﺤﺪﻭﺩ ﺍﻟﻠﻮﻏﺎﺭﻳﺘﻤﻴﺔ ﻓﻲ ﻧﻈﺮﻳﺔ ﺍﻟﺘﺮﻛﻴﺒﺎﺕ ﻭﻧﻈﺮﻳﺔ ﺍﻷﻋﺪﺍﺩ. 1 Introduction Throughout this paper, we understand an empty sum to be 0 and regard an empty product as 1. Let us recall definitions for an asymptotic expansion. ∞ an Definition 1.1 [11, p. 31, Definition 2.1] Let F be a function of a real or complex variable z;let n=0 zn denote a convergent or divergent formal power series, of which the sum of the first n terms is denoted by Sn(z); and let Rn(z) = F(z) − Sn(z). F. Qi (B) Institute of Mathematics, Henan Polytechnic University, Jiaozuo 454010, Henan, China E-mail: [email protected]; [email protected]; [email protected] URL: https://qifeng618.wordpress.com F. Qi College of Mathematics, Inner Mongolia University for Nationalities, Tongliao 028043, Inner Mongolia Autonomous Region, China X.-T. Shi · F.-F. Liu Department of Mathematics, College of Science, Tianjin Polytechnic University, Tianjin 300387, China E-mail: [email protected]; [email protected] F.-F. Liu E-mail: [email protected] 123 96 Arab. J. Math. (2017) 6:95–108 In other words, − n 1 a F(z) = k + R (z) = S (z) + R (z), n ≥ 0, zk n n n k=0 where we assume that when n = 0wehaveF(z) = R0(z). Next, assume that for each n ≥ 0 the relation 1 R (z) = O , z →∞ n zn ∞ an ( ) holds in some unbounded domain . Then, n=0 zn is called an asymptotic expansion of the function F z and we denote this by ∞ a F(z) ∼ n , z →∞, z ∈ . zn n=0 Definition 1.2 [12, p. 151] A divergent series ∞ An , zn n=0 in which the sum of the first n + 1termsisSn(z), is said to be an asymptotic expansion of a function f (z) for a given range of values of arg z, if the expression n Rn(z) = z [ f (z) − Sn(z)] satisfies the condition lim Rn(z) = 0 (n fixed), |z|→∞ even though lim |Rn(z)|=∞ (z fixed). n→∞ We denote the fact that the series is the asymptotic expansion of f (z) by writing ∞ A f (z) ∼ n . zn n=0 On the asymptotic expansion of the composite of a function and an asymptotic expansion, we recite the following four results. ( ) = ∞ α n , ( ) Theorem 1.3 [6, p. 540, Theorem 2] If g z n=0 n z is a power series with positive radius r if F x possesses the asymptotic representation ∞ a F(x) ∼ k , xk k=0 and if |a0| < r, then the function (x) = g(F(x)) ∞ , an also possesses an asymptotic representation and this is again calculated exactly as if n=0 xn were convergent, where, since F(x) → a0 as x →∞, and since |a0| < r, the function (x) is obviously defined for every sufficiently large x. 123 Arab. J. Math. (2017) 6:95–108 97 In [6, p. 541], it was stated that, when taking g(z) = ez in Theorem 1.3, we obtain, without any restrictions, 2 ( ) a1 a /2 + a2 eF x ∼ ea0 1 + + 1 +··· . x x2 Theorem 1.4 [9, Remark 3.2] If ∞ a f (x) ∼ k , x →∞, xk k=0 then ∞ ( ) α e f x ∼ k , x →∞, xk k=0 a where α0 = e 0 and k j 1 a0 αk = e ai (1.1) j! j=1 j = , =1 =1 i k 0≤i≤k,1≤≤ j, i∈{0}∪N Theorem 1.5 [1, Lemma 4] Let ∞ a A(x) = n (1.2) xn n=1 be a given asymptotic expansion. Then, the composition B(x) = eA(x) has the asymptotic expansion ∞ b B(x) = n , xn n=0 where b0 = 1 and n 1 b = ka b − , n ∈ N. (1.3) n n k n k k=1 Theorem 1.6 [1, Lemma 5] Let c0 = 0 and ∞ c C(x) = n xn n=0 be a given asymptotic expansion. Then, the composition A(x) = ln C(x) has the expansion ∞ a A(x) = n , xn n=1 where n− 1 1 1 a = c − ka c − , n ∈ N. (1.4) n c n n k n k 0 k=1 123 98 Arab. J. Math. (2017) 6:95–108 In [3], many useful conclusions on asymptotic expansions were obtained. We note that no accurate and explicit references were given in [9] to cite the formula (1.1) in Theorem 1.4. We observe that the constant term did not appear in (1.2) in Theorem 1.5 and that the formulas (1.3)and (1.4) are recurrences. In Sect. 2 of this paper, we will add a constant term into (1.2) and acquire a modified version of Theorem 1.5. In Sect. 3, we will derive from the recurrences (1.3)and(1.4) explicit formulas for the above an and bn.In Sect. 4, we will simply confirm explicit formulas for power series expansions of the exponential and the logarithm of a power series expansion. In Sect. 5, we will apply the explicit formulas for the power series expansions of the exponential and the logarithm of a power series expansion to find explicit formulas for the Bell numbers and logarithmic polynomials extensively studied in combinatorics and number theory. 2 A slightly modified version of Theorem 1.5 Now we are in a position to give a slightly modified version of Theorem 1.5. Theorem 2.1 Let ∞ d D(x) = k xk k=0 be an asymptotic expansion. Then, the function E(x) = eD(x) has the asymptotic expansion ∞ e E(x) = k , xk k=0 where d0 e0 = e (2.1) and k k− 1 1 1 e = de − = (k − )d −e, k ∈ N. (2.2) k k k k k =1 =0 First proof Differentiation yields ( ) E (x) = eD x D (x) = E(x)D (x) which can be written as: ∞ ∞ ∞ e e d (−k) k = k (−k) k xk+1 xk xk+1 k=1 k=0 k=1 ∞ ∞ ∞ k 1 ek dk+1 1 1 = (−k − 1) = (− − 1)d+ e − , x2 xk xk x2 1 k xk k=0 k=0 k=0 =0 that is, ∞ ∞ k−1 ∞ k ek 1 1 k = ( + 1)d+ e −− = de − . xk+1 1 k 1 xk+1 k xk+1 k=1 k=1 =0 k=1 =1 1 Equating coefficients of xk+1 results in (2.2). Taking the limit x →∞on both sides of E(x) = eD(x), we arrive at (2.1). The proof of Theorem 2.1 is complete. 123 Arab. J. Math. (2017) 6:95–108 99 ∞ dk Second proof Set D(x) = d + D (x),whereD (x) = = . Then, by virtue of Theorem 1.5,wehave 0 1 1 k 1 xk ∞ ( ) ( ) βk E(x) = eD x = ed0 eD1 x = ed0 , xk k=0 where β0 = 1and k 1 β = dβ −, k ∈ N. k k k =1 d This means that the Eq. (2.1) is valid and that ek = e 0 βk for k ∈ N. Hence, the sequence ek for k ∈ N satisfies k ek 1 ek− = d , k ∈ N. ed0 k ed0 =1 Consequently, the recurrence relation (2.2) follows. The proof of Theorem 2.1 is complete. 3 Explicit formulas for an and en In this section, we derive explicit formulas for an and en from recurrence relations (1.4)and(2.2). Theorem 3.1 Under the conditions of Theorem 1.6, we have n−1 j cn 1 j cmi an = + (−1) m j , n ∈ N. (3.1) c0 n c0 j=1 j = , i=0 i=0 mi n mi ≥1,0≤i≤ j Proof From the recurrence relation (1.4) and by induction, it follows that n−1 cn 1 1 an = − akkcn−k c0 c0 n k=1 ⎛ ⎞ n−1 k−1 cn 1 1 ⎝ck 1 1 ⎠ = − − a pc − kc − c c n c c k p k p n k 0 0 k=1 0 0 p=1 n−1 n−1 k−1 cn 1 1 1 1 = − c kc − + a pc − c − 2 k n k 2 p k p n k c0 c0 n = c0 n = = k 1 k 1 p ⎛1 ⎞ n−1 n−1 k−1 p−1 cn 1 1 1 1 ⎝cp 1 1 ⎠ = − c kc − + − a qc − pc − c − c c 2 n k n k c 2 n c c p q p q k p n k 0 0 k=1 0 k=1 p=1 0 0 q=1 n−1 n−1 k−1 cn 1 1 1 1 = − c kc − + c pc − c − c c 2 n k n k c 3 n p k p n k 0 0 k=1 0 k=1 p=1 n− k− p−1 1 1 1 1 − a qc − c − c − c 3 n q p q k p n k 0 k=1 p=1 q=1 n−1 n−1 k−1 cn 1 1 1 1 = − c kc − + c pc − c − c c 2 n k n k c 3 n p k p n k 0 0 k=1 0 k=1 p=1 123 100 Arab.
Recommended publications
  • Finite Sum – Product Logic
    Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 8, No. 5, pp. 63–99. FINITE SUM – PRODUCT LOGIC J.R.B. COCKETT1 AND R.A.G. SEELY2 ABSTRACT. In this paper we describe a deductive system for categories with finite products and coproducts, prove decidability of equality of morphisms via cut elimina- tion, and prove a “Whitman theorem” for the free such categories over arbitrary base categories. This result provides a nice illustration of some basic techniques in categorical proof theory, and also seems to have slipped past unproved in previous work in this field. Furthermore, it suggests a type-theoretic approach to 2–player input–output games. Introduction In the late 1960’s Lambekintroduced the notion of a “deductive system”, by which he meant the presentation of a sequent calculus for a logic as a category, whose objects were formulas of the logic, and whose arrows were (equivalence classes of) sequent deriva- tions. He noticed that “doctrines” of categories corresponded under this construction to certain logics. The classic example of this was cartesian closed categories, which could then be regarded as the “proof theory” for the ∧ – ⇒ fragment of intuitionistic propo- sitional logic. (An excellent account of this may be found in the classic monograph [Lambek–Scott 1986].) Since his original work, many categorical doctrines have been given similar analyses, but it seems one simple case has been overlooked, viz. the doctrine of categories with finite products and coproducts (without any closed structure and with- out any extra assumptions concerning distributivity of the one over the other). We began looking at this case with the thought that it would provide a nice simple introduction to some techniques in categorical proof theory, particularly the idea of rewriting systems modulo equations, which we have found useful in investigating categorical structures with two tensor products (“linearly distributive categories” [Blute et al.
    [Show full text]
  • Topic 7 Notes 7 Taylor and Laurent Series
    Topic 7 Notes Jeremy Orloff 7 Taylor and Laurent series 7.1 Introduction We originally defined an analytic function as one where the derivative, defined as a limit of ratios, existed. We went on to prove Cauchy's theorem and Cauchy's integral formula. These revealed some deep properties of analytic functions, e.g. the existence of derivatives of all orders. Our goal in this topic is to express analytic functions as infinite power series. This will lead us to Taylor series. When a complex function has an isolated singularity at a point we will replace Taylor series by Laurent series. Not surprisingly we will derive these series from Cauchy's integral formula. Although we come to power series representations after exploring other properties of analytic functions, they will be one of our main tools in understanding and computing with analytic functions. 7.2 Geometric series Having a detailed understanding of geometric series will enable us to use Cauchy's integral formula to understand power series representations of analytic functions. We start with the definition: Definition. A finite geometric series has one of the following (all equivalent) forms. 2 3 n Sn = a(1 + r + r + r + ::: + r ) = a + ar + ar2 + ar3 + ::: + arn n X = arj j=0 n X = a rj j=0 The number r is called the ratio of the geometric series because it is the ratio of consecutive terms of the series. Theorem. The sum of a finite geometric series is given by a(1 − rn+1) S = a(1 + r + r2 + r3 + ::: + rn) = : (1) n 1 − r Proof.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 2 of Concrete Abstractions: an Introduction to Computer
    Out of print; full text available for free at http://www.gustavus.edu/+max/concrete-abstractions.html CHAPTER TWO Recursion and Induction 2.1 Recursion We have used Scheme to write procedures that describe how certain computational processes can be carried out. All the procedures we've discussed so far generate processes of a ®xed size. For example, the process generated by the procedure square always does exactly one multiplication no matter how big or how small the number we're squaring is. Similarly, the procedure pinwheel generates a process that will do exactly the same number of stack and turn operations when we use it on a basic block as it will when we use it on a huge quilt that's 128 basic blocks long and 128 basic blocks wide. Furthermore, the size of the procedure (that is, the size of the procedure's text) is a good indicator of the size of the processes it generates: Small procedures generate small processes and large procedures generate large processes. On the other hand, there are procedures of a ®xed size that generate computa- tional processes of varying sizes, depending on the values of their parameters, using a technique called recursion. To illustrate this, the following is a small, ®xed-size procedure for making paper chains that can still make chains of arbitrary lengthÐ it has a parameter n for the desired length. You'll need a bunch of long, thin strips of paper and some way of joining the ends of a strip to make a loop. You can use tape, a stapler, or if you use slitted strips of cardstock that look like this , you can just slip the slits together.
    [Show full text]
  • Formal Power Series - Wikipedia, the Free Encyclopedia
    Formal power series - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Formal_power_series Formal power series From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia In mathematics, formal power series are a generalization of polynomials as formal objects, where the number of terms is allowed to be infinite; this implies giving up the possibility to substitute arbitrary values for indeterminates. This perspective contrasts with that of power series, whose variables designate numerical values, and which series therefore only have a definite value if convergence can be established. Formal power series are often used merely to represent the whole collection of their coefficients. In combinatorics, they provide representations of numerical sequences and of multisets, and for instance allow giving concise expressions for recursively defined sequences regardless of whether the recursion can be explicitly solved; this is known as the method of generating functions. Contents 1 Introduction 2 The ring of formal power series 2.1 Definition of the formal power series ring 2.1.1 Ring structure 2.1.2 Topological structure 2.1.3 Alternative topologies 2.2 Universal property 3 Operations on formal power series 3.1 Multiplying series 3.2 Power series raised to powers 3.3 Inverting series 3.4 Dividing series 3.5 Extracting coefficients 3.6 Composition of series 3.6.1 Example 3.7 Composition inverse 3.8 Formal differentiation of series 4 Properties 4.1 Algebraic properties of the formal power series ring 4.2 Topological properties of the formal power series
    [Show full text]
  • The Discovery of the Series Formula for Π by Leibniz, Gregory and Nilakantha Author(S): Ranjan Roy Source: Mathematics Magazine, Vol
    The Discovery of the Series Formula for π by Leibniz, Gregory and Nilakantha Author(s): Ranjan Roy Source: Mathematics Magazine, Vol. 63, No. 5 (Dec., 1990), pp. 291-306 Published by: Mathematical Association of America Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2690896 Accessed: 27-02-2017 22:02 UTC JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://about.jstor.org/terms Mathematical Association of America is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mathematics Magazine This content downloaded from 195.251.161.31 on Mon, 27 Feb 2017 22:02:42 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms ARTICLES The Discovery of the Series Formula for 7r by Leibniz, Gregory and Nilakantha RANJAN ROY Beloit College Beloit, WI 53511 1. Introduction The formula for -r mentioned in the title of this article is 4 3 57 . (1) One simple and well-known moderm proof goes as follows: x I arctan x = | 1 +2 dt x3 +5 - +2n + 1 x t2n+2 + -w3 - +(-I)rl2n+1 +(-I)l?lf dt. The last integral tends to zero if Ix < 1, for 'o t+2dt < jt dt - iX2n+3 20 as n oo.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1811.04966V3 [Math.NT]
    Descartes’ rule of signs, Newton polygons, and polynomials over hyperfields Matthew Baker and Oliver Lorscheid Abstract. In this note, we develop a theory of multiplicities of roots for polynomials over hyperfields and use this to provide a unified and conceptual proof of both Descartes’ rule of signs and Newton’s “polygon rule”. Introduction Given a real polynomial p ∈ R[T ], Descartes’ rule of signs provides an upper bound for the number of positive (resp. negative) real roots of p in terms of the signs of the coeffi- cients of p. Specifically, the number of positive real roots of p (counting multiplicities) is bounded above by the number of sign changes in the coefficients of p(T ), and the number of negative roots is bounded above by the number of sign changes in the coefficients of p(−T ). Another classical “rule”, which is less well known to mathematicians in general but is used quite often in number theory, is Newton’s polygon rule. This rule concerns polynomi- als over fields equipped with a valuation, which is a function v : K → R ∪{∞} satisfying • v(a) = ∞ if and only if a = 0 • v(ab) = v(a) + v(b) • v(a + b) > min{v(a),v(b)}, with equality if v(a) 6= v(b) for all a,b ∈ K. An example is the p-adic valuation vp on Q, where p is a prime number, given by the formula vp(s/t) = ordp(s) − ordp(t), where ordp(n) is the maximum power of p dividing a nonzero integer n. Another example is the T -adic valuation v on k(T), for any field k, given by v ( f /g) = arXiv:1811.04966v3 [math.NT] 26 May 2020 T T ordT ( f )−ordT (g), where ordT ( f ) is the maximum power of T dividing a nonzero polyno- mial f ∈ k[T].
    [Show full text]
  • AN INTRODUCTION to POWER SERIES a Finite Sum of the Form A0
    AN INTRODUCTION TO POWER SERIES PO-LAM YUNG A finite sum of the form n a0 + a1x + ··· + anx (where a0; : : : ; an are constants) is called a polynomial of degree n in x. One may wonder what happens if we allow an infinite number of terms instead. This leads to the study of what is called a power series, as follows. Definition 1. Given a point c 2 R, and a sequence of (real or complex) numbers a0; a1;:::; one can form a power series centered at c: 2 a0 + a1(x − c) + a2(x − c) + :::; which is also written as 1 X k ak(x − c) : k=0 For example, the following are all power series centered at 0: 1 x x2 x3 X xk (1) 1 + + + + ::: = ; 1! 2! 3! k! k=0 1 X (2) 1 + x + x2 + x3 + ::: = xk: k=0 We want to think of a power series as a function of x. Thus we are led to study carefully the convergence of such a series. Recall that an infinite series of numbers is said to converge, if the sequence given by the sum of the first N terms converges as N tends to infinity. In particular, given a real number x, the series 1 X k ak(x − c) k=0 converges, if and only if N X k lim ak(x − c) N!1 k=0 exists. A power series centered at c will surely converge at x = c (because one is just summing a bunch of zeroes then), but there is no guarantee that the series will converge for any other values x.
    [Show full text]
  • Diagrammatics in Categorification and Compositionality
    Diagrammatics in Categorification and Compositionality by Dmitry Vagner Department of Mathematics Duke University Date: Approved: Ezra Miller, Supervisor Lenhard Ng Sayan Mukherjee Paul Bendich Dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of Mathematics in the Graduate School of Duke University 2019 ABSTRACT Diagrammatics in Categorification and Compositionality by Dmitry Vagner Department of Mathematics Duke University Date: Approved: Ezra Miller, Supervisor Lenhard Ng Sayan Mukherjee Paul Bendich An abstract of a dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of Mathematics in the Graduate School of Duke University 2019 Copyright c 2019 by Dmitry Vagner All rights reserved Abstract In the present work, I explore the theme of diagrammatics and their capacity to shed insight on two trends|categorification and compositionality|in and around contemporary category theory. The work begins with an introduction of these meta- phenomena in the context of elementary sets and maps. Towards generalizing their study to more complicated domains, we provide a self-contained treatment|from a pedagogically novel perspective that introduces almost all concepts via diagrammatic language|of the categorical machinery with which we may express the broader no- tions found in the sequel. The work then branches into two seemingly unrelated disciplines: dynamical systems and knot theory. In particular, the former research defines what it means to compose dynamical systems in a manner analogous to how one composes simple maps. The latter work concerns the categorification of the slN link invariant. In particular, we use a virtual filtration to give a more diagrammatic reconstruction of Khovanov-Rozansky homology via a smooth TQFT.
    [Show full text]
  • Discussion Problems 2
    CS103 Handout 11 Fall 2014 October 6, 2014 Discussion Problems 2 Problem One: Product Parities Suppose that you have n integers x₁, x₂, …, xₙ. Prove that the product x₁ · x₂ · … · xₙ is odd if and only if each number xᵢ is odd. You might want to use the following facts: the product of zero numbers is called the empty product and is, by definition, equal to 1, and any two true state- ments imply one another. Problem Two: Prime Numbers A natural number p ≥ 2 is called prime if it has no positive divisors except 1 and itself. A natural number is called composite if it is the product of two natural numbers m and n, where both m and n are greater than one. Every natural number greater than or equal to two is either prime or composite. Prove, by strong induction, that every natural number greater than or equal to two can be written as a product of prime numbers. Problem Three: Factorials! Multiplied together! The number n! is defined as 1 × 2 × … × n. We choose to define 0! = 1. Prove by induction that for any m, n ∈ ℕ, we have m!n! ≤ (m + n)!. Can you explain intuitively why this is true? Problem Four: Picking Coins Consider the following game for two players. Begin with a pile of n coins for some n ≥ 0. The first player then takes between one and ten coins out of the pile, then the second player takes between one and ten coins out of the pile. This process repeats until some player has no coins to take; at this point, that player loses the game.
    [Show full text]
  • Logic and Categories As Tools for Building Theories
    Logic and Categories As Tools For Building Theories Samson Abramsky Oxford University Computing Laboratory 1 Introduction My aim in this short article is to provide an impression of some of the ideas emerging at the interface of logic and computer science, in a form which I hope will be accessible to philosophers. Why is this even a good idea? Because there has been a huge interaction of logic and computer science over the past half-century which has not only played an important r^olein shaping Computer Science, but has also greatly broadened the scope and enriched the content of logic itself.1 This huge effect of Computer Science on Logic over the past five decades has several aspects: new ways of using logic, new attitudes to logic, new questions and methods. These lead to new perspectives on the question: What logic is | and should be! Our main concern is with method and attitude rather than matter; nevertheless, we shall base the general points we wish to make on a case study: Category theory. Many other examples could have been used to illustrate our theme, but this will serve to illustrate some of the points we wish to make. 2 Category Theory Category theory is a vast subject. It has enormous potential for any serious version of `formal philosophy' | and yet this has hardly been realized. We shall begin with introduction to some basic elements of category theory, focussing on the fascinating conceptual issues which arise even at the most elementary level of the subject, and then discuss some its consequences and philosophical ramifications.
    [Show full text]
  • Fun Power Series Problems
    FUN POWER SERIES PROBLEMS Joseph Breen Solutions will be periodically added at the bottom. Problems 1. Evaluate each of the following infinite series. Don’t just show they converge, actually evaluate them! (a) 1 X n 2n n=1 (b) 1 X n2 2n n=1 (c) 1 X n + 1 n! n=0 (d) 1 X 1 (2n)! n=0 2. Let f(x) = x sin(x2). What is f (147)(0)? What about f (148)(0)? Hint: you probably don’t want to take 147 derivatives of f. 3. Evaluate the following integral as an infinite series: Z 1 1 x dx: 0 x 4. Determine whether the following series converge or diverge. (The point of these exercises is that thinking about Maclaurin series can help you!) (a) 1 X 1 arctan : n2 n=1 (b) 1 X − 1 1 − 3 n : n=1 (c) 1 X 1 sin3 p : n n=1 (d) 1 1 ! X Z n sin(x2) dx : x n=1 0 1 (e) 1 ! X 1 ln 2 1 : n=1 1 − sin n (f) 1 1 X arcsin n : (ln n)2 n=1 (g) 1 X − 1 −1 tan n 2 sin n : n=1 (h) 1 1 1 1 1 X ln 1 + 1 + + + ··· + n 2 3 n : n n=1 5. Determine the interval of convergence for each of the following power series. (a) 1 X n!(x − 2)2n : nn n=1 (b) 1 X x3n : (2n)! n=1 (c) 1 X 3n n!(x − 1)n : nn n=1 6.
    [Show full text]
  • Formal Power Series License: CC BY-NC-SA
    Formal Power Series License: CC BY-NC-SA Emma Franz April 28, 2015 1 Introduction The set S[[x]] of formal power series in x over a set S is the set of functions from the nonnegative integers to S. However, the way that we represent elements of S[[x]] will be as an infinite series, and operations in S[[x]] will be closely linked to the addition and multiplication of finite-degree polynomials. This paper will introduce a bit of the structure of sets of formal power series and then transfer over to a discussion of generating functions in combinatorics. The most familiar conceptualization of formal power series will come from taking coefficients of a power series from some sequence. Let fang = a0; a1; a2;::: be a sequence of numbers. Then 2 the formal power series associated with fang is the series A(s) = a0 + a1s + a2s + :::, where s is a formal variable. That is, we are not treating A as a function that can be evaluated for some s0. In general, A(s0) is not defined, but we will define A(0) to be a0. 2 Algebraic Structure Let R be a ring. We define R[[s]] to be the set of formal power series in s over R. Then R[[s]] is itself a ring, with the definitions of multiplication and addition following closely from how we define these operations for polynomials. 2 2 Let A(s) = a0 + a1s + a2s + ::: and B(s) = b0 + b1s + b1s + ::: be elements of R[[s]]. Then 2 the sum A(s) + B(s) is defined to be C(s) = c0 + c1s + c2s + :::, where ci = ai + bi for all i ≥ 0.
    [Show full text]