Sex, Laws, and Inequality: What India Can Teach the United States

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Sex, Laws, and Inequality: What India Can Teach the United States Comment by Ira Katznelson Evil & politics In the immediate aftermath of the innocents. Behavior is evil when it events of September 11, 2001, it was hard attacks valued goods proffered by West- to know what to say. We seemed bereft ern modernity. of “a terminology,” as Madame de Staël Disputing the integrity and worth of observed after the Jacobin Terror, in a these goods, critics in other intellectual situation “beyond the common meas- circles have focused instead on the evils ure.” In the days that followed, my own of postcolonialism and the exploitative thoughts turned to Hannah Arendt, and relationships characteristic of global the works she had written in an effort to capitalism. It is these iniquities that grapple with another situation beyond should command our attention, not the the common measure. “The problem of acts of terror they consider in a cooler, evil,” Arendt forecast in 1945, “will be sometimes icy, register. the fundamental question of postwar I ½nd the impulses at play in both intellectual life in Europe–as death responses unsettling. Each group is bet- became the fundamental problem after ter at assuming a posture than develop- the last war.” ing ways of acting and living decently in ‘Evil’ is a word one heard with some a world riven by heterogeneous, inter- frequency in the aftermath of the attacks connected, and sometimes conflicting on the World Trade Center and the Pen- cultures. A rote defense of Western lib- tagon, though rarely deployed with eralism could very well authorize a new Arendt’s precision. Within some intel- brand of colonialism, once again making lectual circles, a denunciation of these many non-Western peoples ineligible for acts as evil has been accompanied by a its core values of rights, toleration, par- far too simple justi½cation of liberalism ticipation, and consent. A wholesale and the Enlightenment as decency incar- rejection of enlightened liberalism as a nate. Evil, in this view, implies more mere ½gment of Western imperialism than doing harm or inflicting pain on could very well license an irresponsible and foundationless antimodernism, reinforcing a mirror-image view of ‘us’ Ira Katznelson, Ruggles Professor of Political Sci- against ‘them.’ Intransigently advanced, ence and History at Columbia University, is the each perspective evades asking how we author of numerous books and articles on Ameri- can shade the sensibilities, deepen the can politics, political theory, and social history, capacities, and address the limitations of including “Liberalism’s Crooked Circle: Letters to the liberal tradition in full awareness Adam Michnik” (1996). A Fellow of the Ameri- that credulous notions of human per- can Academy since 2000, he is completing a new fectibility have been mocked by the book on the New Deal, the South, and the origins global diffusion of human superfluous- of postwar American liberalism. ness, the central hallmark of modern Dædalus Winter 2002 7 Comment “radical evil,” as Hannah Arendt argued Any meaningful effort to re½ne the by Ira in The Origins of Totalitarianism. language and institutions that a robust Katznelson Writing in the aftermath of total war liberalism requires must move beyond a and the Shoah, Arendt sought both to thin and often misleading claim to uni- apprehend the appearance of “radical versality; it also can gain con½dence evil, previously unknown to us,” and to from a fresh appreciation for the En- transform the eschatology of evil into a lightenment’s rich, though often neg- systematic tool with which to name and lected, lineage of realism and a recogni- explain the terrible cost Nazism and tion of liberalism’s history of invention Stalinism had exacted. By ‘radical evil,’ and transformation. Kant, for example, she understood the project of erasing the worried about the demagogic uses of moral and the juridical person as a prel- reason and the possibility that a new set ude to physical annihilation. Justi½ed by of ostensibly enlightened “prejudices millenarian ideologies and advanced by [can] serve, like the old, as the leading what Arendt called manufactured unre- strings of the thoughtless masses.” He alities, radical evil literally erased human also well knew that demonic violence plurality by stripping large populations has long characterized human affairs. of their rights as citizens, including the Such realism is quite distinct from the right to a name, as a prelude to mass rosy optimism of those eighteenth-cen- killing. Turning innocents into nonpeo- tury philosophes who supposed that sys- ple, both the Nazis and the Soviets thus tematic understanding would trump tor- elided the liberal tradition’s central puz- ture and barbarism, as if to realize the zle of how to make it possible for incom- title of Pierre-Paul Prud’hon’s painting mensurable values and identities to of 1798: Darkness Dissipates as Wisdom and coexist, perhaps even flourish, in a cli- Truth Descend to Earth. Rather than mate of toleration. Prud’hon’s canvas, it is Goya’s etchings Although today’s constellation of of Los desastres de la guerra after the Span- Muslim fervency, fascist-style mobiliza- ish insurrection of 1808 and the Peninsu- tion, and Internet-friendly coordination lar War with Napoleon that might better may be new in some respects, it is mani- be adopted as chastening emblems of a festly as capable of producing radical evil humane realism. as the barbarous offshoots of Western Today’s terror forces, or should force, civilization Arendt addressed, even if an engagement not just with this year’s thankfully it has yet to equal them. Fa- instance of evil but with a proper role for miliar, too, are the challenges that Islam- realistic reason and institutional innova- ic zealotry can pose to the tradition of tion in the face of a persistent human Enlightenment and to the possibilities of capacity for desolation, now enhanced a decent liberal politics. by the legacy and diffusion of twentieth- Given these hazards, we need to century models of radical evil. Times of explore whether the Western liberal tra- turmoil and fear urgently pose two ques- dition can effectively contest radical evil tions: whether liberalism can thrive in without sacri½cing its own best features. the face of determined adversaries and I think it can, though not on its own and what kind of liberalism we should wish only if liberals can ½nd a terminology to have. Answers to ‘what kind’ affect and institutional practices to engage the possibilities for ‘whether’ by offering with nonliberal beliefs and cultures choices not only about doctrines but also without dismissing them too hastily as about institutions and public policies. irremediably antiliberal. The ideals of the liberal tradition, 8 Dædalus Winter 2002 properly appreciated, represent an open nance of an idea may affect its status but Evil & sensibility rather than a ½xed set of not its value or capacity. Even if liberal politics arrangements or ideas. The most impor- political thought is inescapably Western tant moments of innovation and change in origin, it no longer belongs only to the in the modern West’s liberal political West. “Concepts such as citizenship, the tradition have come in circumstances state, civil society, public sphere, human governed by anxiety and alarm. Consider rights, equality before the law, the indi- not only Locke’s institutional formula vidual, distinctions between public and for toleration in conditions of religious private, the idea of the subject, democra- warfare between Catholics and Protes- cy, popular sovereignty, social justice, tants, but his speci½cations for political scienti½c rationality, and so on,” he consent and representation in the con- observes, “all bear the burden of Euro- text of a century of civil war in England. pean thought and history.” These secular Consider, too, the constitutional innova- and universal categories and concepts tions of Benjamin Constant in France were preached “at the colonized and at when faced with a global war and the the same time denied . in practice. But collapse of legitimate kingship. Consid- the vision,” writes Chakrabarty, “has er, ½nally, the development of the twen- been powerful in its effects. It has histor- tieth-century liberal welfare state in ically provided a strong foundation on response to depression, class conflict, which to erect–both in Europe and out- and the rise of Bolshevism, Fascism, and side–critiques of socially unjust prac- Nazism. tices. This heritage is now global.” Especially at moments of danger and Even when contradicted by such deep innovation, the liberal tradition has been injustices as slavery and Jim Crow, Euro- neither self-contained nor homoge- pean imperialism, and today’s spectacu- neous. There have been liberal demo- lar global inequalities, struggles based on crats, liberal socialists, liberal republi- these orientations ensue “because there cans, liberal monarchists–and also lib- is no easy way of dispensing with these eral Christians, liberal Jews, liberal Mus- universals in the condition of political lims. In each instance, the absence of a modernity.” Or at least, one might say, partnership with political liberalism has no attractive struggles are possible whol- proved an invitation to oppression. ly outside their frame. Without a commitment to such a cardi- Both liberalism and the Enlightenment nal liberal value as toleration, even a within which it nestles advance a philo- declared democrat may be tempted by sophical anthropology of rational actors despotism. The liberal tradition is thus and rational action, insisting that human necessary to an effectively decent poli- agents develop the capacity to deliberate, tics. But it is not suf½cient. An abstract choose, and achieve sensible goals. In commitment to universal human rights their effort to cultivate such rational citi- by itself, without depth, passion, and zens, liberal regimes in the past have all historical particularity, cannot possibly too often imposed various limits, draw- contend with radical evil.
Recommended publications
  • The Existentialism of Martin Buber and Implications for Education
    This dissertation has been microfilmed exactly as received 69-4919 KINER, Edward David, 1939- THE EXISTENTIALISM OF MARTIN BUBER AND IMPLICATIONS FOR EDUCATION. The Ohio State University, Ph.D., 1968 Education, general University Microfilms, Inc., Ann Arbor, Michigan THE EXISTENTIALISM OF MARTIN BUBER AND IMPLICATIONS FOR EDUCATION DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Edward David Kiner, B.A., M.A. ####*### The Ohio State University 1968 Approved by Adviser College of Education This thesis is dedicated to significant others, to warm, vital, concerned people Who have meant much to me and have helped me achieve my self, To people whose lives and beings have manifested "glimpses" of the Eternal Thou, To my wife, Sharyn, and my children, Seth and Debra. VITA February 14* 1939 Born - Cleveland, Ohio 1961......... B.A. Western Reserve University April, 1965..... M.A. Hebrew Union College Jewish Institute of Religion June, 1965...... Ordained a Rabbi 1965-1968........ Assistant Rabbi, Temple Israel, Columbus, Ohio 1967-1968...... Director of Religious Education, Columbus, Ohio FIELDS OF STUDY Major Field: Philosophy of Education Studies in Philosophy of Education, Dr. Everett J. Kircher Studies in Curriculum, Dr. Alexander Frazier Studies in Philosophy, Dr. Marvin Fox ill TABLE OF CONTENTS Page DEDICATION............................................. ii VITA ................................................... iii INTRODUCTION............................ 1 Chapter I. AN INTRODUCTION TO MARTIN BUBER'S THOUGHT....... 6 Philosophical Anthropology I And Thou Martin Buber and Hasidism Buber and Existentialism Conclusion II. EPISTEMOLOGY . 30 Truth Past and Present I-It Knowledge Thinking Philosophy I-Thou Knowledge Complemented by I-It Living Truth Buber as an Ebdstentialist-Intuitionist Implications for Education A Major Problem Education, Inclusion, and the Problem of Criterion Conclusion III.
    [Show full text]
  • Altruism, Morality & Social Solidarity Forum
    Altruism, Morality & Social Solidarity Forum A Forum for Scholarship and Newsletter of the AMSS Section of ASA Volume 3, Issue 2 May 2012 What’s so Darned Special about Church Friends? Robert D. Putnam Harvard University One purpose of my recent research (with David E. Campbell) on religion in America1 was to con- firm and, if possible, extend previous research on the correlation of religiosity and altruistic behavior, such as giving, volunteering, and community involvement. It proved straight-forward to show that each of sev- eral dozen measures of good neighborliness was strongly correlated with religious involvement. Continued on page 19... Our Future is Just Beginning Vincent Jeffries, Acting Chairperson California State University, Northridge The beginning of our endeavors has ended. The study of altruism, morality, and social solidarity is now an established section in the American Sociological Association. We will have our first Section Sessions at the 2012 American Sociological Association Meetings in Denver, Colorado, this August. There is a full slate of candidates for the ASA elections this spring, and those chosen will take office at the Meetings. Continued on page 4... The Revival of Russian Sociology and Studies of This Issue: Social Solidarity From the Editor 2 Dmitry Efremenko and Yaroslava Evseeva AMSS Awards 3 Institute of Scientific Information for Social Sciences, Russian Academy of Sciences Scholarly Updates 12 The article was executed in the framework of the research project Social solidarity as a condition of society transformations: Theoretical foundations, Bezila 16 Russian specificity, socio-biological and socio-psychological aspects, supported Dissertation by the Russian foundation for basic research (Project 11-06-00347а).
    [Show full text]
  • Banality of Evil Or Radical Evil?
    Filosofia Unisinos Unisinos Journal of Philosophy 21(3):240-250, sep/dec 2020 Unisinos – doi: 10.4013/fsu.2020.213.01 Torture: banality of evil or radical evil? Tortura: banalidade do mal ou mal radical? Delamar José Volpato Dutra1 ABSTRACT The text aims to explore legal and moral aspects of torture. Under the legal aspect the text compares three definitions of torture: UN definition, Brazilian definition, and Spanish defi- nition. In this regard, neither the UN formulation nor the Brazilian formulation are ideal, be- cause the Brazilian legal definition restricts the element of action by the part of the perpe- trator of torture, and the UN convention restricts the effect on the victim, given that pain or suffering should be severe. The hypothesis is that a better proposal could be linked to the Spanish Penal Code, which in its art. 174 defines torture as the submission of someone “to conditions or procedures that, due to their nature, duration or other circumstances, involve physical or mental suffering, the suppression or decrease of their faculties of knowledge, discernment or decision, or that otherwise undermine their moral integrity”. The Spanish definition seems more encompassing in both aspects, on the act of the perpetrator of torture, and on the effect on the victim, since the suffering involved is not characterized as severe. Concerning the moral meaning of the repulse to torture it is intended to defend the paradigmatic character of the human right to not be tortured in at least two respects. The first aspect refers to its universalizing vocation in the full sense, since it can be extended to all sentient beings.
    [Show full text]
  • 547 Joël Madore Joël Madore Persuasively Argues That Kant's
    Book Reviews 547 Joël Madore Difficult Freedom and Radical Evil in Kant (New York: Continuum, 2011), 184 pp. isbn 978-1-4411-9319-3 (hardcover). Joël Madore persuasively argues that Kant’s moral theory cannot be deeply understood without a careful examination of his account of “radical evil,” developed in the late work Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone. In that work, Kant argues – to the surprise of many readers – that every human being is evil by nature. And he didn’t mean by this that we are all contaminated by embodiment. Rather, the infamous doctrine of radical evil maintains that we each freely acquire an evil character. That is: there is no sin in the flesh, and we are all sinners. Madore rightly resists the temptation to dismiss radical evil as an aberration in the Kantian corpus. That reason’s great Enlightenment champion also held reason responsible for the universal guilt of our species is just too interesting to ignore. For Madore, evil constitutes a deep philosophical problem for Kant as the philosopher of autonomy, and Kant’s engagement with this problem both enriches and complicates his theory. He argues that the Kantian distinc- tion between ‘ought’ and ‘is’ amounts to a “moral gap” – Madore’s term for the space made by the free will between the good and the actual (p. 25). The “prob- lem of evil”, for Madore, is that we fall short of what we have ourselves legis- lated for ourselves as binding. This “falling short” emerges in our weakness in resisting temptation, in our failure to justify morality in the face of challenges, and in our inability to motivate virtue without marshaling an obscure rhetoric of sublimity and divinity.
    [Show full text]
  • Radical Evil and the Invisibility of Moral Worth in Kant's Die Religion
    Radical EvIl and thE invIsibilIty oF MoRal woRth in KaNt’s Die Religion El mal radical y la invisibilidad del valor moral en Die Religion de Kant CaRlos ManriquE* University of Chicago · Chicago, USA AbstrAct There is an aporia in Kant’s analysis of evil: he defines radical evil as an invisible disposition of the will, but he also demands an inferential connection between vis- ible evil actions and this invisible disposition. This inference, however, undermines the radical invisibility of radical evil according to Kant’s own definition of the lat- ter. Noting how this invisibility of moral worth is a distinctive feature of Kant’s approach to the moral problem, the paper then asks why, in the Groundwork, he nonetheless forecloses a question about evil that seems to be consistent with this approach. It is argued that to account for this aporia and this foreclosure, one has to interrogate the way in which the category of religion orients Kant’s incipient philosophy of history in Die Religion. Keywords: Kant, radical evil, philosophy of religion. resumen Hay una aporía en el análisis kantiano del mal: Kant define el mal radical como una disposición de la voluntad invisible, pero también exige que esta disposición invi- sible se pueda inferir a partir de aquellas acciones visiblemente malas. Sin embargo, esta inferencia socava el carácter radicalmente invisible del mal radical según la definición que de éste da el propio Kant. Enfatizando la manera en que este carácter invisible del valor moral es una característica distintiva de la aproximación kantia- na al problema moral, se plantea la pregunta de por qué Kant, no obstante, rechaza en la Fundamentación una pregunta sobre el mal que parece ser consistente con esta aproximación.
    [Show full text]
  • Trauma and the Nature of Evil
    Trauma and the Nature of Evil TRAUMA AND THE NATURE OF EVIL Sandra L. Bloom, M.D. CommunityWorks There are a thousand hacking at the branches of evil to one who is striking at the root. HENRY DAVID THOREAU If only there were evil people somewhere, insidiously committing evil deeds, and it were necessary only to separate them from the rest of us and destroy them. But the line dividing good and evil cuts through the heart of every human being. And who is willing to destroy a piece of his own heart? ALEKSANDR SOLZHENITSYN We met - Katarina, August and I - and from then on it became impossible ever again to give up completely. I have given some thought to why this should be. I believe it was love. When once you have encountered it, you will never sink again. Then you will always yearn for the light and the surface. PETER HØEG BORDERLINERS It may legitimately be asked, “What is a psychiatrist doing delving into the long- standing philosophical question about the nature of evil?” As we know, finding meaning and redefining reality to incorporate the experience of trauma is a fundamental task for the survivor of overwhelming life experiences (Herman, 1992; McCann and Pearlman, 1990; Janoff-Bulman, 1992). So too, is it one of the fundamental tasks for those of us who listen to the stories of trauma, those who attempt to provide the support needed for victims to turn their nonverbal, inexorable pain into a healing narrative. The effects of trauma are contagious and the witness is always in danger of becoming a secondary victim (Figley, 1995; McCann and Pearlman, 1990; Pearlman and Saakvitne, 1995).
    [Show full text]
  • Is Kantian Ethics Left Defenseless in the Face of Evil?
    IS KANTIAN ETHICS LEFT DEFENSELESS IN THE FACE OF EVIL? Matthew Stapleton (Marshall University) [email protected] Abstract: Within this essay the question of whether Kantian ethics is left defenseless in the face of evil is unfolded. Some thinkers claim that it is not advisable to rigorously adhere to the categorical imperative. That is to say, it is prudent only to follow the categorical imperative, acting in such a way that you may will that the maxim of your actions becomes a universal law, when one is dealing with other ethical beings. However, when dealing with evil, it is claimed that we should develop other special principles that allow for consequences favorable to the ethical party. This essay takes exception with this claim, demonstrating that for Kant such a problem would not have even appeared. Furthermore, this essay argues that to deviate from the moral principle does damage to the truth and humanity as a whole. According to Kant to act ethically is to act not only in conformity with but also from the motive of duty. This motive, the motive of duty, is “the necessity to act out of reverence for the law”, a law that I give myself “to never act except in such a way that I can also will that my maxim should become a universal law”1. Under the ideal condition that every rational being acts in accordance with the categorical imperative I think hardly anyone would disagree that Kantian ethics is thoroughly well thought out and provides for the possibility of determining in every scenario what is the right course of action.
    [Show full text]
  • Reflections on Radical Evil: Arendt and Kant1
    Vorträge und Schwerpunkte 239 Richard J. Bernstein Reflections on Radical Evil: Arendt and Kant1 In the final pages of The Origins of Totalitarianism, Hannah Arendt sums up her horrendous narrative of the eruption of twentieth-cen- tury totalitarianism. She declares: It is inherent in our entire philosophic tradition that we cannot conceive of a “radical evil”, and this is true both for Christian the- ology, which conceded even to the Devil himself a celestial origin, as well as for Kant, the only philosopher who, in the word he coined for it, at least must have suspected the existence of this evil even though he immediately rationalized it in the concept of a “perverted ill will” that could be explained by comprehensible motives. Therefore, we actually have nothing to fall back on in order to understand a phenomenon that nevertheless confronts us with its overpowering reality and breaks down all standards we know. There is only one thing that seems to be discernable: we may say that radical evil has emerged in connection with a system in which all men have become equally superfluous. The manipu- lators of this system believe in their own superfluousness as much as in that of all others, and the totalitarian murderers are all the more dangerous because they do not care if they themselves are alive or dead, if they ever lived or never were born. The danger of the corpse factories and holes of oblivion is that today, with pop- ulations and homelessness everywhere on the increase, masses of people are continuously rendered superfluous if we continue to think of our world in utilitarian terms.
    [Show full text]
  • Can We Choose Evil? a Discussion of the Problem of Radical Evil As a Modern and Ancient Problem of Freedom
    Can We Choose Evil? A Discussion of the Problem of Radical Evil as a Modern and Ancient Problem of Freedom Mark Coeckelbergh University of Liège, Belgium ***** 1. Introduction The problem discussed in this paper emerges from work I’ve done on the modern ideal of autonomy.1 I found that autonomy is often seen as a morally neutral term. Put in terms of good and evil, this means that it is held consistent to say that a person is autonomous and chooses evil. Autonomy, by itself, so it is argued, is neutral with regard to good or evil. On this view, whether or not I choose evil, if I make this choice in the capacity of being my own master, of governing and ruling myself, then there is nothing in the way of autonomy that I lack. For example, Feinberg argues that autonomy is consistent with ruthlessness, cruelty, and other (moral) failings, and that it is therefore at best only a partial ideal “insufficient for full moral excellence.”2 Is this a tenable position? In this paper I discuss whether it makes sense to say that a person has a (real) choice between good and evil, regardless of his state in terms of autonomy. First, I clarify the problem by using aspects from the work of Plato and Augustine. Second, I show how Kant attempts to deal with this problem by discussing key aspects of his moral theory, in particular his concept of radical evil. For the sake of my argument, I assume in this paper that it is meaningful to speak of ‘good’ and ‘evil’.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant on Radical Evil Kyoung Min Cho University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee
    University of Wisconsin Milwaukee UWM Digital Commons Theses and Dissertations December 2015 Kant on Radical Evil Kyoung Min Cho University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee Follow this and additional works at: https://dc.uwm.edu/etd Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Cho, Kyoung Min, "Kant on Radical Evil" (2015). Theses and Dissertations. 1043. https://dc.uwm.edu/etd/1043 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by UWM Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of UWM Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. KANT ON RADICAL EVIL by Kyoung Min Cho A Thesis Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts in Philosophy at The University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee December 2015 ABSTRACT KANT ON RADICAL EVIL by Kyoung Min Cho The University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee, 2015 Under the Supervision of Professor Julius O. Sensat The purpose of this thesis is to propose an interpretation of Kant’s claim that the human being’s evil nature is the effect of the free power of choice. I suggest that if his concept of free choice is properly understood, Kant’s claim should be interpreted as follows: the human being’s radical evil is the effect of a failure to use freely the power of choice that determines its fundamental disposi- tion, a failure that is to be presupposed as universal for all human agents. According to this reading, we are evil by nature since evil lies in our fundamental disposition.
    [Show full text]
  • Radical Evil
    Radical Evil. Artigos / Articles RADICAL EVIL (RADIKAL BÖSE). The doctrine of radical evil is the backbone of Kant’s Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason (1793). After introducing it in Part I, Kant uses it to organize his argument throughout the rest of the book: his Christology (Part II), escathology (Part III), and critique of ecclesiastical organizations (Part IV), all owe their distinctive character to the claim that “the human being is evil by nature” (6:32). By “evil,” Kant does not mean to designate any set of particularly pernicious acts, but the type of volition that underlies and makes possible immorality in all its forms. Such a volitional structure is present in “the multitude of woeful examples that the experience of human deeds parade before us” (R 6:33), no less than in the subterfuges of self-deception with which we excuse our misconduct and delude ourselves about our moral worth (R 6:38). In all cases, Kant believes, the evil person “makes self-love and their inclinations the condition of compliance with the moral law –whereas it is the latter that, as the supreme condition of the satisfaction of the former, should have been incorporated into the universal maxim of the power of choice as the sole incentive” (R 6:36). Kant’s view rests on two important assumptions. First, it presupposes a distinctive an- thropological picture, according to which a finite rationality like ours, torn by the presence of two inextricable and yet incommensurably different types of incentives (self-love and duty), experiences morality as “necessitation” and “command” (Gr 4:413).
    [Show full text]
  • Is Radical Evil Banal? Is Banal Evil Radical? Paul Formosa
    Is Radical Evil Banal? Is Banal Evil Radical? Paul Formosa Is Radical Evil Banal? Is Banal Evil Radical? 1. Introduction There has been much recent debate concerning how Hannah Arendt’s concepts of radical evil and the banality of evil ‘fit together’, if at all. There are two general positions in regard to this question. The first, forwarded most notably by Richard Bernstein,1 sees the two concepts as broadly compatible. However, within this position, there are those who see some localised incompatibility with regard to the account of motivation (such as Bernstein and Henry Allison),2 and those who see the two concepts as intimately related and not at all in contradiction with each other (such as Peg Birmingham).3 Others, such as Wayne Allen, seem to fall somewhere in between.4 The second, forwarded initially by Gershom Scholem (and arguably by Arendt herself) and recently updated by Dana Villa,5 sees the two concepts as inherently incompatible. In this paper I shall argue for a position of the first type, by showing that the two concepts are broadly compatible. However, I shall also argue against the various other positions of this type, listed above, which all see the two concepts as fundamentally interdependent. Instead, I contend that radical evil and the banality of evil are independent but nonetheless highly complementary concepts. 2. Radical Evil For Arendt, as for many others, the Nazi regime and the Holocaust were seen as utterly unprecedented events which dictated the need to re-think the possible extremes of evil. Arendt initially attempted to do this through her concept of radical evil, which she also refers to as the ‘greatest’ or ‘absolute’ evil.
    [Show full text]