The Logic of Boolean Connectives

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Logic of Boolean Connectives Introduction & Review Truth Tables Logical Truths & Tautologies Equivalence Consequence Introduction & Review Truth Tables Logical Truths & Tautologies Equivalence Consequence Announcements For 09.15.11 1 HW1 was due on Tuesday The Logic of Boolean Connectives • If you didn't turn it in, it's late 2 HW2 & HW3 are due next Tuesday (09.20) Truth Tables, Tautologies & Logical Truths • Electronic HW must be submitted before class • Written HW must be handed in at beginning of class William Starr • Otherwise, it's late 3 Optional sections have been scheduled • Wednesday 1:25-2:10, Uris 307 09.15.11 • Thursday 1:25-2:10, Uris G22 William Starr j Phil 2621: Minds & Machines j Cornell University 1/45 William Starr j Phil 2621: Minds & Machines j Cornell University 2/45 Introduction & Review Truth Tables Logical Truths & Tautologies Equivalence Consequence Introduction & Review Truth Tables Logical Truths & Tautologies Equivalence Consequence Outline Introduction Truth Functions • Last class, we learned the meaning of ^; _; : in terms 1 Introduction & Review of truth functions • We also saw that truth functions allowed us to do 2 Truth Tables something useful: • Figure out the truth value of a complex sentence from 3 Logical Truths & Tautologies the truth values of its atomic parts, and vice versa • For example, we know that :(Cube(a) _ Cube(b)) is true in a world where neither a nor b are cubes, since: 4 Equivalence • If :(Cube(a) _ Cube(b)) is true, then Cube(a) _ Cube(b) is false 5 Consequence • If Cube(a) _ Cube(b) is false, then Cube(a) and Cube(b) are false William Starr j Phil 2621: Minds & Machines j Cornell University 3/45 William Starr j Phil 2621: Minds & Machines j Cornell University 5/45 Introduction & Review Truth Tables Logical Truths & Tautologies Equivalence Consequence Introduction & Review Truth Tables Logical Truths & Tautologies Equivalence Consequence Introduction Review Truth Tables The Boolean Connectives Truth Table for : Truth Table for _ • These calculations | ones like the one we just went P :P through | are a bit clunky P Q P _ Q true false • There's a more elegant method: Truth tables false true true true true • As it turns out, truth tables will also provide us with a true false true helpful way to understand 3 core logical concepts: false true true false false false 1 Logical Consequence Truth Table for ^ 2 Logical Truth P Q P ^ Q 3 Logical Equivalence • : flips the value true true true • Today, we'll learn all about truth tables & these true false false • ^ takes the applications! false true false `worst' value false false false • _ takes the `best' value William Starr j Phil 2621: Minds & Machines j Cornell University 6/45 William Starr j Phil 2621: Minds & Machines j Cornell University 7/45 Introduction & Review Truth Tables Logical Truths & Tautologies Equivalence Consequence Introduction & Review Truth Tables Logical Truths & Tautologies Equivalence Consequence The Basics The Basics Step 1: The Reference Columns Step 2: Inside Out • We are going to construct a truth table for Truth Table for (1) (1) Cube(a) _:Cube(a) Cube(a) Cube(a) _: Cube(a) First, some columns: Truth Table for (1) t f 1 Reference Columns: f t Cube(a) Cube(a) _: Cube(a) columns for each atomic sub-sentence of (1) t f • Third, fill column beneath innermost connective :: 2 A column for (1) itself • In the first row, Cube(a) is t so :Cube(a) is f Second, fill the reference columns w/truth values. • In the second row, Cube(a) is f so :Cube(a) is t • One row for each unique logical possibility William Starr j Phil 2621: Minds & Machines j Cornell University 10/45 William Starr j Phil 2621: Minds & Machines j Cornell University 11/45 Introduction & Review Truth Tables Logical Truths & Tautologies Equivalence Consequence Introduction & Review Truth Tables Logical Truths & Tautologies Equivalence Consequence The Basics The Basics Step 3: The Main Connective Summary: In General Truth Table for (1) How to Construct a Truth Table for Any Sentence P Cube(a) Cube(a) _: Cube(a) 1 Reference Columns: Draw a column for each atomic t t f sub-sentence of P, these columns are called the f t t reference columns and are filled with every possible combination of truth-values for the sub-sentences • Last, fill columns beneath outermost connective _: 2 Inside Out: Draw a column for P itself. Then fill in • In the first row, Cube(a) is t and :Cube(a) is f, so the column below P's innermost connective. Repeat their disjunction is t for the next innermost connective, until you get to the • In the first row, Cube(a) is f and :Cube(a) is t, so main connective. their disjunction is t 3 Main Connective: Fill in the column under the main • This column lists every logically possible truth value connective. This row lists the possible truth values of P for (1) William Starr j Phil 2621: Minds & Machines j Cornell University 12/45 William Starr j Phil 2621: Minds & Machines j Cornell University 13/45 Introduction & Review Truth Tables Logical Truths & Tautologies Equivalence Consequence Introduction & Review Truth Tables Logical Truths & Tautologies Equivalence Consequence Reference Columns Reference Columns There is More to It... How Many Rows? Let's figure it out: • We have 2 atomic sub-sentences • When you have more than one atomic sub-sentence, • Each can have 2 different truth values (t,f) filling in the reference columns requires more thought • So there 22 = 4 possible combinations of truth values • Remember that each row of the reference columns lists and atomic sub-sentences a unique logical possibility • Therefore, a table for a formula with 2 atomic • Also remember that there is supposed to be a row for sub-sentences needs 4 rows every unique possibility You Always Need 2n Rows • Okay, well how many rows would we need for a formula with 2 atomic sub-sentences? In general, if there are n atomic sub-sentences of P then there will be 2n possible assignments of truth values to those atomic sub-sentences, in which case the truth table for P should have 2n rows. William Starr j Phil 2621: Minds & Machines j Cornell University 15/45 William Starr j Phil 2621: Minds & Machines j Cornell University 16/45 Introduction & Review Truth Tables Logical Truths & Tautologies Equivalence Consequence Introduction & Review Truth Tables Logical Truths & Tautologies Equivalence Consequence Another Example Another Example Step 1 Steps 2 & 3 • Let's construct a truth table for: Truth Table for (2) (2) :(Cube(a) ^ Cube(b)) • We need 2 reference columns: Cube(a) Cube(b) :(Cube(a) ^: Cube(b)) • In them, we need a row for each of the 4 logical t t t f f possibilities t f f t t • Cube(a) can be t and Cube(b) t; Cube(a) t and f t t f f Cube(b) f, and so on. f f t f t Truth Table for (2) • Next, the innermost connective :: • Cube(a) Cube(b) :(Cube(a) ^ :Cube(b)) It will flip each value of Cube(b) t t • Now, the next innermost ^: t f • ^ takes worst value of the pair f t • Finally, the main connective :: f f • : flips the value of the conjunction we just computed William Starr j Phil 2621: Minds & Machines j Cornell University 17/45 William Starr j Phil 2621: Minds & Machines j Cornell University 18/45 Introduction & Review Truth Tables Logical Truths & Tautologies Equivalence Consequence Introduction & Review Truth Tables Logical Truths & Tautologies Equivalence Consequence Building Reference Columns Yet Another Example A Helpful Routine Step 1 • You need to list each possibility exactly once when We'll construct a table for: filling in reference columns (3)( Cube(a) ^ :Cube(b)) _:Cube(c) • Here's a helpful routine for this: Let A = Cube(a); B = Cube(b); C = Cube(c) 1 In the innermost ref. column, you alternate t's and f's Table for (3) 2 In the next innermost column, you double that A B C (A ^ :B) _:C • First, the 8 rows of the alternation, and so on for any more rows t t t reference columns: Truth Table for (2) t t f 1 Alternate on innermost Cube(a) Cube(b) :(Cube(a) ^ :Cube(a)) t f t column t t t f f f t t 2 Double this alternation t f on the next f t f t f 3 Double again f f f f t f f f Let's put this routine to work William Starr j Phil 2621: Minds & Machines j Cornell University 19/45 William Starr j Phil 2621: Minds & Machines j Cornell University 20/45 Introduction & Review Truth Tables Logical Truths & Tautologies Equivalence Consequence Introduction & Review Truth Tables Logical Truths & Tautologies Equivalence Consequence Yet Another Example You Try It Steps 2 & 3 In Class Exercise Table for (3) • Next, rows for innermost connectives (:) A B C (A ^ :B) _:C t t t f f f f • :B: flips value of B Break into groups of 4-6 and construct a truth table for: t t f f f t t • :C: flips value of C t f t t t t f • Now, the row for the next t f f t t t t innermost connective (^) f t t f f f f f t f f f t t • ^ takes lowest value (4)( B _:C) ^ :A f f t f t f f f f f f t t t • Finally, the row for the main connective (_): • _ takes highest value William Starr j Phil 2621: Minds & Machines j Cornell University 21/45 William Starr j Phil 2621: Minds & Machines j Cornell University 22/45 Introduction & Review Truth Tables Logical Truths & Tautologies Equivalence Consequence Introduction & Review Truth Tables Logical Truths & Tautologies Equivalence Consequence Boole Truth Tables An Introduction Summary • LPL contains a program called Boole, which is for • Okay, we've learned how to draw these pretty tables, but how do they help us do logic? constructing truth tables 1 Truth tables probe logical possibility • Now that you've done a one by hand, you can 2 This underlies several important concepts: appreciate how nice of a tool this is! • Logical truth • Let's run through the basics of Boole by using it to • Logical consequence construct a table for (3) • Logical equivalence • Let's see how William Starr j Phil 2621: Minds & Machines j Cornell University 24/45 William Starr j Phil 2621: Minds & Machines j Cornell University 25/45 Introduction & Review Truth Tables Logical Truths & Tautologies Equivalence Consequence Introduction & Review Truth Tables Logical Truths & Tautologies Equivalence Consequence Logical Truth Tautologies The Basics Logical Truth Tautology Truth Table for (1) P is a logical truth if and only if it is logically necessary.
Recommended publications
  • Logical Truth, Contradictions, Inconsistency, and Logical Equivalence
    Logical Truth, Contradictions, Inconsistency, and Logical Equivalence Logical Truth • The semantical concepts of logical truth, contradiction, inconsistency, and logi- cal equivalence in Predicate Logic are straightforward adaptations of the corre- sponding concepts in Sentence Logic. • A closed sentence X of Predicate Logic is logically true, X, if and only if X is true in all interpretations. • The logical truth of a sentence is proved directly using general reasoning in se- mantics. • Given soundness, one can also prove the logical truth of a sentence X by provid- ing a derivation with no premises. • The result of the derivation is that X is theorem, ` X. An Example • (∀x)Fx ⊃ (∃x)Fx. – Suppose d satisfies ‘(∀x)Fx’. – Then all x-variants of d satisfy ‘Fx’. – Since the domain D is non-empty, some x-variant of d satisfies ‘Fx’. – So d satisfies ‘(∃x)Fx’ – Therefore d satisfies ‘(∀x)Fx ⊃ (∃x)Fx’, QED. • ` (∀x)Fx ⊃ (∃x)Fx. 1 (∀x)Fx P 2 Fa 1 ∀ E 3 (∃x)Fx 1 ∃ I Contradictions • A closed sentence X of Predicate Logic is a contradiction if and only if X is false in all interpretations. • A sentence X is false in all interpretations if and only if its negation ∼X is true on all interpretations. • Therefore, one may directly demonstrate that a sentence is a contradiction by proving that its negation is a logical truth. • If the ∼X of a sentence is a logical truth, then given completeness, it is a theorem, and hence ∼X can be derived from no premises. 1 • If a sentence X is such that if it is true in any interpretation, both Y and ∼Y are true in that interpretation, then X cannot be true on any interpretation.
    [Show full text]
  • Pluralisms About Truth and Logic Nathan Kellen University of Connecticut - Storrs, [email protected]
    University of Connecticut OpenCommons@UConn Doctoral Dissertations University of Connecticut Graduate School 8-9-2019 Pluralisms about Truth and Logic Nathan Kellen University of Connecticut - Storrs, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://opencommons.uconn.edu/dissertations Recommended Citation Kellen, Nathan, "Pluralisms about Truth and Logic" (2019). Doctoral Dissertations. 2263. https://opencommons.uconn.edu/dissertations/2263 Pluralisms about Truth and Logic Nathan Kellen, PhD University of Connecticut, 2019 Abstract: In this dissertation I analyze two theories, truth pluralism and logical pluralism, as well as the theoretical connections between them, including whether they can be combined into a single, coherent framework. I begin by arguing that truth pluralism is a combination of realist and anti-realist intuitions, and that we should recognize these motivations when categorizing and formulating truth pluralist views. I then introduce logical functionalism, which analyzes logical consequence as a functional concept. I show how one can both build theories from the ground up and analyze existing views within the functionalist framework. One upshot of logical functionalism is a unified account of logical monism, pluralism and nihilism. I conclude with two negative arguments. First, I argue that the most prominent form of logical pluralism faces a serious dilemma: it either must give up on one of the core principles of logical consequence, and thus fail to be a theory of logic at all, or it must give up on pluralism itself. I call this \The Normative Problem for Logical Pluralism", and argue that it is unsolvable for the most prominent form of logical pluralism. Second, I examine an argument given by multiple truth pluralists that purports to show that truth pluralists must also be logical pluralists.
    [Show full text]
  • Boolean Satisfiability Solvers: Techniques and Extensions
    Boolean Satisfiability Solvers: Techniques and Extensions Georg WEISSENBACHER a and Sharad MALIK a a Princeton University Abstract. Contemporary satisfiability solvers are the corner-stone of many suc- cessful applications in domains such as automated verification and artificial intelli- gence. The impressive advances of SAT solvers, achieved by clever engineering and sophisticated algorithms, enable us to tackle Boolean Satisfiability (SAT) problem instances with millions of variables – which was previously conceived as a hope- less problem. We provide an introduction to contemporary SAT-solving algorithms, covering the fundamental techniques that made this revolution possible. Further, we present a number of extensions of the SAT problem, such as the enumeration of all satisfying assignments (ALL-SAT) and determining the maximum number of clauses that can be satisfied by an assignment (MAX-SAT). We demonstrate how SAT solvers can be leveraged to solve these problems. We conclude the chapter with an overview of applications of SAT solvers and their extensions in automated verification. Keywords. Satisfiability solving, Propositional logic, Automated decision procedures 1. Introduction Boolean Satisfibility (SAT) is the problem of checking if a propositional logic formula can ever evaluate to true. This problem has long enjoyed a special status in computer science. On the theoretical side, it was the first problem to be classified as being NP- complete. NP-complete problems are notorious for being hard to solve; in particular, in the worst case, the computation time of any known solution for a problem in this class increases exponentially with the size of the problem instance. On the practical side, SAT manifests itself in several important application domains such as the design and verification of hardware and software systems, as well as applications in artificial intelligence.
    [Show full text]
  • The Analytic-Synthetic Distinction and the Classical Model of Science: Kant, Bolzano and Frege
    Synthese (2010) 174:237–261 DOI 10.1007/s11229-008-9420-9 The analytic-synthetic distinction and the classical model of science: Kant, Bolzano and Frege Willem R. de Jong Received: 10 April 2007 / Revised: 24 July 2007 / Accepted: 1 April 2008 / Published online: 8 November 2008 © The Author(s) 2008. This article is published with open access at Springerlink.com Abstract This paper concentrates on some aspects of the history of the analytic- synthetic distinction from Kant to Bolzano and Frege. This history evinces con- siderable continuity but also some important discontinuities. The analytic-synthetic distinction has to be seen in the first place in relation to a science, i.e. an ordered system of cognition. Looking especially to the place and role of logic it will be argued that Kant, Bolzano and Frege each developed the analytic-synthetic distinction within the same conception of scientific rationality, that is, within the Classical Model of Science: scientific knowledge as cognitio ex principiis. But as we will see, the way the distinction between analytic and synthetic judgments or propositions functions within this model turns out to differ considerably between them. Keywords Analytic-synthetic · Science · Logic · Kant · Bolzano · Frege 1 Introduction As is well known, the critical Kant is the first to apply the analytic-synthetic distinction to such things as judgments, sentences or propositions. For Kant this distinction is not only important in his repudiation of traditional, so-called dogmatic, metaphysics, but it is also crucial in his inquiry into (the possibility of) metaphysics as a rational science. Namely, this distinction should be “indispensable with regard to the critique of human understanding, and therefore deserves to be classical in it” (Kant 1783, p.
    [Show full text]
  • Deduction (I) Tautologies, Contradictions And
    D (I) T, & L L October , Tautologies, contradictions and contingencies Consider the truth table of the following formula: p (p ∨ p) () If you look at the final column, you will notice that the truth value of the whole formula depends on the way a truth value is assigned to p: the whole formula is true if p is true and false if p is false. Contrast the truth table of (p ∨ p) in () with the truth table of (p ∨ ¬p) below: p ¬p (p ∨ ¬p) () If you look at the final column, you will notice that the truth value of the whole formula does not depend on the way a truth value is assigned to p. The formula is always true because of the meaning of the connectives. Finally, consider the truth table table of (p ∧ ¬p): p ¬p (p ∧ ¬p) () This time the formula is always false no matter what truth value p has. Tautology A statement is called a tautology if the final column in its truth table contains only ’s. Contradiction A statement is called a contradiction if the final column in its truth table contains only ’s. Contingency A statement is called a contingency or contingent if the final column in its truth table contains both ’s and ’s. Let’s consider some examples from the book. Can you figure out which of the following sentences are tautologies, which are contradictions and which contingencies? Hint: the answer is the same for all the formulas with a single row. () a. (p ∨ ¬p), (p → p), (p → (q → p)), ¬(p ∧ ¬p) b.
    [Show full text]
  • Yuji NISHIYAMA in This Article We Shall Focus Our Attention Upon
    The Notion of Presupposition* Yuji NISHIYAMA Keio University In this article we shall focus our attention upon the clarificationof the notion of presupposition;First, we shall be concerned with what kind of notion is best understood as the proper notion of presupposition that grammars of natural languageshould deal with. In this connection,we shall defend "logicalpresupposi tion". Second, we shall consider how to specify the range of X and Y in the presuppositionformula "X presupposes Y". Third, we shall discuss several difficultieswith the standard definition of logical presupposition. In connection with this, we shall propose a clear distinction between "the definition of presupposi tion" and "the rule of presupposition". 1. The logical notion of presupposition What is a presupposition? Or, more particularly, what is the alleged result of a presupposition failure? In spite of the attention given to it, this question can hardly be said to have been settled. Various answers have been suggested by the various authors: inappropriate use of a sentence, failure to perform an illocutionary act, anomaly, ungrammaticality, unintelligibility, infelicity, lack of truth value-each has its advocates. Some of the apparent disagreementmay be only a notational and terminological, but other disagreement raises real, empirically significant, theoretical questions regarding the relationship between logic and language. However, it is not the aim of this article to straighten out the various proposals about the concept of presupposition. Rather, we will be concerned with one notion of presupposition,which stems from Frege (1892)and Strawson (1952),that is: (1) presupposition is a condition under which a sentence expressing an assertive proposition can be used to make a statement (or can bear a truth value)1 We shall call this notion of presupposition "the statementhood condition" or "the conditionfor bivalence".
    [Show full text]
  • Solving the Boolean Satisfiability Problem Using the Parallel Paradigm Jury Composition
    Philosophæ doctor thesis Hoessen Benoît Solving the Boolean Satisfiability problem using the parallel paradigm Jury composition: PhD director Audemard Gilles Professor at Universit´ed'Artois PhD co-director Jabbour Sa¨ıd Assistant Professor at Universit´ed'Artois PhD co-director Piette C´edric Assistant Professor at Universit´ed'Artois Examiner Simon Laurent Professor at University of Bordeaux Examiner Dequen Gilles Professor at University of Picardie Jules Vernes Katsirelos George Charg´ede recherche at Institut national de la recherche agronomique, Toulouse Abstract This thesis presents different technique to solve the Boolean satisfiability problem using parallel and distributed architec- tures. In order to provide a complete explanation, a careful presentation of the CDCL algorithm is made, followed by the state of the art in this domain. Once presented, two proposi- tions are made. The first one is an improvement on a portfo- lio algorithm, allowing to exchange more data without loosing efficiency. The second is a complete library with its API al- lowing to easily create distributed SAT solver. Keywords: SAT, parallelism, distributed, solver, logic R´esum´e Cette th`ese pr´esente diff´erentes techniques permettant de r´esoudre le probl`eme de satisfaction de formule bool´eenes utilisant le parall´elismeet du calcul distribu´e. Dans le but de fournir une explication la plus compl`ete possible, une pr´esentation d´etaill´ee de l'algorithme CDCL est effectu´ee, suivi d'un ´etatde l'art. De ce point de d´epart,deux pistes sont explor´ees. La premi`ereest une am´eliorationd'un algorithme de type portfolio, permettant d'´echanger plus d'informations sans perte d’efficacit´e.
    [Show full text]
  • The Development of Mathematical Logic from Russell to Tarski: 1900–1935
    The Development of Mathematical Logic from Russell to Tarski: 1900–1935 Paolo Mancosu Richard Zach Calixto Badesa The Development of Mathematical Logic from Russell to Tarski: 1900–1935 Paolo Mancosu (University of California, Berkeley) Richard Zach (University of Calgary) Calixto Badesa (Universitat de Barcelona) Final Draft—May 2004 To appear in: Leila Haaparanta, ed., The Development of Modern Logic. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004 Contents Contents i Introduction 1 1 Itinerary I: Metatheoretical Properties of Axiomatic Systems 3 1.1 Introduction . 3 1.2 Peano’s school on the logical structure of theories . 4 1.3 Hilbert on axiomatization . 8 1.4 Completeness and categoricity in the work of Veblen and Huntington . 10 1.5 Truth in a structure . 12 2 Itinerary II: Bertrand Russell’s Mathematical Logic 15 2.1 From the Paris congress to the Principles of Mathematics 1900–1903 . 15 2.2 Russell and Poincar´e on predicativity . 19 2.3 On Denoting . 21 2.4 Russell’s ramified type theory . 22 2.5 The logic of Principia ......................... 25 2.6 Further developments . 26 3 Itinerary III: Zermelo’s Axiomatization of Set Theory and Re- lated Foundational Issues 29 3.1 The debate on the axiom of choice . 29 3.2 Zermelo’s axiomatization of set theory . 32 3.3 The discussion on the notion of “definit” . 35 3.4 Metatheoretical studies of Zermelo’s axiomatization . 38 4 Itinerary IV: The Theory of Relatives and Lowenheim’s¨ Theorem 41 4.1 Theory of relatives and model theory . 41 4.2 The logic of relatives .
    [Show full text]
  • 12 Propositional Logic
    CHAPTER 12 ✦ ✦ ✦ ✦ Propositional Logic In this chapter, we introduce propositional logic, an algebra whose original purpose, dating back to Aristotle, was to model reasoning. In more recent times, this algebra, like many algebras, has proved useful as a design tool. For example, Chapter 13 shows how propositional logic can be used in computer circuit design. A third use of logic is as a data model for programming languages and systems, such as the language Prolog. Many systems for reasoning by computer, including theorem provers, program verifiers, and applications in the field of artificial intelligence, have been implemented in logic-based programming languages. These languages generally use “predicate logic,” a more powerful form of logic that extends the capabilities of propositional logic. We shall meet predicate logic in Chapter 14. ✦ ✦ ✦ ✦ 12.1 What This Chapter Is About Section 12.2 gives an intuitive explanation of what propositional logic is, and why it is useful. The next section, 12,3, introduces an algebra for logical expressions with Boolean-valued operands and with logical operators such as AND, OR, and NOT that Boolean algebra operate on Boolean (true/false) values. This algebra is often called Boolean algebra after George Boole, the logician who first framed logic as an algebra. We then learn the following ideas. ✦ Truth tables are a useful way to represent the meaning of an expression in logic (Section 12.4). ✦ We can convert a truth table to a logical expression for the same logical function (Section 12.5). ✦ The Karnaugh map is a useful tabular technique for simplifying logical expres- sions (Section 12.6).
    [Show full text]
  • Logical Consequence: a Defense of Tarski*
    GREG RAY LOGICAL CONSEQUENCE: A DEFENSE OF TARSKI* ABSTRACT. In his classic 1936 essay “On the Concept of Logical Consequence”, Alfred Tarski used the notion of XU~@~ZC~~NIto give a semantic characterization of the logical properties. Tarski is generally credited with introducing the model-theoretic chamcteriza- tion of the logical properties familiar to us today. However, in his hook, The &ncel>f of Lugid Consequence, Etchemendy argues that Tarski’s account is inadequate for quite a number of reasons, and is actually incompatible with the standard mod&theoretic account. Many of his criticisms are meant to apply to the model-theoretic account as well. In this paper, I discuss the following four critical charges that Etchemendy makes against Tarski and his account of the logical properties: (1) (a) Tarski’s account of logical consequence diverges from the standard model-theoretic account at points where the latter account gets it right. (b) Tarski’s account cannot be brought into line with the model-thcorctic account, because the two are fundamentally incompatible. (2) There are simple countcrcxamples (enumerated by Etchemcndy) which show that Tarski’s account is wrong. (3) Tarski committed a modal faIlacy when arguing that his account captures our pre-theoretical concept of logical consequence, and so obscured an essential weakness of the account. (4) Tarski’s account depends on there being a distinction between the “log- ical terms” and the “non-logical terms” of a language, but (according to Etchemendy) there are very simple (even first-order) languages for which no such distinction can be made. Etchemcndy’s critique raises historica and philosophical questions about important foun- dational work.
    [Show full text]
  • Logic, Proofs
    CHAPTER 1 Logic, Proofs 1.1. Propositions A proposition is a declarative sentence that is either true or false (but not both). For instance, the following are propositions: “Paris is in France” (true), “London is in Denmark” (false), “2 < 4” (true), “4 = 7 (false)”. However the following are not propositions: “what is your name?” (this is a question), “do your homework” (this is a command), “this sentence is false” (neither true nor false), “x is an even number” (it depends on what x represents), “Socrates” (it is not even a sentence). The truth or falsehood of a proposition is called its truth value. 1.1.1. Connectives, Truth Tables. Connectives are used for making compound propositions. The main ones are the following (p and q represent given propositions): Name Represented Meaning Negation p “not p” Conjunction p¬ q “p and q” Disjunction p ∧ q “p or q (or both)” Exclusive Or p ∨ q “either p or q, but not both” Implication p ⊕ q “if p then q” Biconditional p → q “p if and only if q” ↔ The truth value of a compound proposition depends only on the value of its components. Writing F for “false” and T for “true”, we can summarize the meaning of the connectives in the following way: 6 1.1. PROPOSITIONS 7 p q p p q p q p q p q p q T T ¬F T∧ T∨ ⊕F →T ↔T T F F F T T F F F T T F T T T F F F T F F F T T Note that represents a non-exclusive or, i.e., p q is true when any of p, q is true∨ and also when both are true.
    [Show full text]
  • Logic, Sets, and Proofs David A
    Logic, Sets, and Proofs David A. Cox and Catherine C. McGeoch Amherst College 1 Logic Logical Statements. A logical statement is a mathematical statement that is either true or false. Here we denote logical statements with capital letters A; B. Logical statements be combined to form new logical statements as follows: Name Notation Conjunction A and B Disjunction A or B Negation not A :A Implication A implies B if A, then B A ) B Equivalence A if and only if B A , B Here are some examples of conjunction, disjunction and negation: x > 1 and x < 3: This is true when x is in the open interval (1; 3). x > 1 or x < 3: This is true for all real numbers x. :(x > 1): This is the same as x ≤ 1. Here are two logical statements that are true: x > 4 ) x > 2. x2 = 1 , (x = 1 or x = −1). Note that \x = 1 or x = −1" is usually written x = ±1. Converses, Contrapositives, and Tautologies. We begin with converses and contrapositives: • The converse of \A implies B" is \B implies A". • The contrapositive of \A implies B" is \:B implies :A" Thus the statement \x > 4 ) x > 2" has: • Converse: x > 2 ) x > 4. • Contrapositive: x ≤ 2 ) x ≤ 4. 1 Some logical statements are guaranteed to always be true. These are tautologies. Here are two tautologies that involve converses and contrapositives: • (A if and only if B) , ((A implies B) and (B implies A)). In other words, A and B are equivalent exactly when both A ) B and its converse are true.
    [Show full text]