Clark & Chalmers Ask Where Does the Mind Stop

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Clark & Chalmers Ask Where Does the Mind Stop The reactive brain and the extended mind: A fourth position1 Francisco Calvo Garzón Department of Philosophy University of Murcia Campus de Espinardo Murcia 30100 - Spain Phone: 968-36-34-60 Fax: 968-36-39-67 Email: [email protected] Abstract: Clark and Chalmers (1998) exploit a “parity” argument to argue in favour of the extended mind thesis. In their view, any worldly dimension which does contribute to the achievement of a cognitive task and which would count as cognitive, had that contribution come from endogenous processes, should count as a cognitive input. The conclusion they draw is that the mind spreads out into the world. They contrast their position, coined “active externalism”, with internalism and externalism à la Putnam. Internalism and externalism reject the parity argument, and argue, on different grounds, that the mind doesn’t extend into the world. More recently, Clark (2005) replies to a number of criticisms. In this paper I argue for a fourth position (“reactive primagenesis”) that is left unexplored by Clark in his latest treatment. According to reactive primagenesis, although the parity argument is to be accepted (contra internalism and externalism à la Putnam), the extended mind thesis can still be resisted (contra active externalism). 1 I would like to thank Ken Aizawa, Richard Campbell and Terry Dartnall for their helpful comments and suggestions. 2 The reactive brain and the extended mind: A fourth position 1. Introduction Clark and Chalmers (hereafter, C&C; 1998) ask “Where does the mind stop and the rest of the world begin?” (p. 7). To pave the way for their particular response, they call into question the intuitive appeal to the boundaries of skin and skull, and the more technical approach according to which mind stuff is on a par with meaning externalism à la Putnam (“externalism about meaning carries over into externalism about mind”, ibid., p. 7). In C&C’s view, however, a third (still externalist) position opens up in logical space. To wit, a sort of active externalism where the environment is part and parcel of cognition. In their view, cognition spreads out into the world in a non-trivial way. As C&C argue, any worldly dimension which does contribute to the achievement of a cognitive task and which would count as cognitive, had that contribution come from endogenous processes, should count as a cognitive input. Put bluntly, skin and skull are irrelevant to the identification of a cognitive process. Externalist approaches appear as somehow trivialized or at least, as far less radical than active externalism. In particular, whereas (orthodox) externalism exploits issues that belong to the theory of reference and the narrow/wide content debate, “active externalism” focuses on how narrow content itself effectively widens up via causally- efficacious exogenous vehicles. Factually, according to active externalism, the mind spreads out there. There is, however, a philosophically tenable stance left unexplored in C&C’s study; a position that is not biased, not even minimally, by skin-and-skull 3 preconceptions, but that nevertheless eschews active externalism. The purpose of this paper is to vindicate such a stance.2 2. Opening up the landscape To make their case, C&C put to work an “intuition pump” embedded in their parity argument. According to the parity argument, If, as we confront some task, a part of the world functions as a process which, were it done in the head, we would have no hesitation in recognizing as part of the cognitive process, then that part of the world is (so we claim) part of the cognitive process. (C&C, 1998, p. 8; emphasis in original). The parity argument considers a competency that almost no one would hesitate to count as cognitive, and asks the reader to deem what would happen in case a feature of the world was rather the critical part that allows the individual to perform the task in question. Recalling very briefly C&C’ well-known example, Inga is a subject who can exploit her “biological” memory to get to a museum somewhere downtown. On the other hand, Otto, an agent who suffers from Alzheimer, exploits the information he has patiently “stored” in a notebook he always carries around with him. Thanks to this notebook, Otto can also successfully navigate through his complex surroundings and find the museum. According to C&C, Otto executes cognitive (information-processing) manipulations as much as Inga does, or as any other person who achieves the same 2 C&C spell out in great detail the differences between Putnam-like externalism, and the sort of “active” externalism they endorse. The reader not familiar with their arguments is encouraged to visit their paper. The position I’m about to defend arises independently of the (historical) externalist considerations that readers familiar with the philosophy of language and mind will surely be aware of. 4 competency by exploiting her “biological” memories does. Manipulation of external objects (notebooks or what may) is tantamount to endogenously generated operations. Both are genuinely cognitive insofar as both are seen as part of a broader system that comprehends all brain, body and environment. Their conclusion is that the mind extends into the world (see also Clark, 1997; Dennett, 1996; and Hutchins, 1995).3 C&C frame the parity argument conditionally, and so framed, the argument is clearly valid. The antecedent, however, may be false. That is, we may actually hesitate to recognize a process done in the head as cognitive. In this case, we would be confronted with a valid, although harmless type of argument. C&C may have very good reasons to treat endogenous and exogenous activity on a par, but if the antecedent is false, we may end up concluding that a process that is performed out there doesn’t count as cognitive either.4 In short, C&C’s three-fold picture, I contend, doesn’t exhaust the landscape. Both endogenous and exogenous factors may be equally (non-trivially) causally efficacious in the generation of the agent’s behaviour. However, granting that says nothing as to whether the behaviour in question is cognitive or not. My thesis is that coupled 3 C&C carefully flesh the Alzheimer patient example up so as to draw the analogy. Thus, for example, Otto can retrieve the information in the notebook effortlessly whenever required, automatically endorsing it. C&C also go over a number of more or less obvious rejoinders. Reviewing all this would take us far afield. The reader may care to consult C&C (1998) for a detailed elaboration of their example. To see the main lines of attack launched so far, the reader may care to consult Adams & Aizawa (2001); Dartnall (2005); Gertler (manuscript); O’Brien (1998); Rupert (2004); Sterelny (in press); and Weiskopf (submitted). See also Clark (2005; forthcoming) for replies. In what follows, rather than reviewing the structure of their arguments, I shall concentrate on a fourth alternative, which in my understanding emerges naturally as a result of turning C&C’ position upside-down (see below). 4 Note that this possibility should at least be granted for the sake of the argument. C&C’s position is also usually appraised as highly counterintuitive, and that doesn’t prevent it from being argued for or against. 5 processes of the type C&C mull over are on a par with endogenously generated processes, but, crucially, because they both count as reactive processes. This way, my position grants the parity argument. We may agree that inner and outer factors are to be treated on a par; but they are to be treated on a par for good and for bad! There is thus still some room left for a fourth answer to C&C’ initial question; an option that remains faithful to the dynamicist spirit (see below) that underlies their “extended mind” thesis.5 This position differs substantially from other strategies found in the literature. A common line of response would consist in the identification of divergences in the explanation of Inga’s and Otto’s behaviour. The strategy of the defender of the extended mind thesis is then to resist and show how parity still remains under enemy fire (see Clark, 2005). Adams and Aizawa (2001), for instance, make the non-modal claim that Otto’s notebook only delivers derived content. And they further argue that there are cognitive processes going on in Otto that are unlike those going on in Inga. This way, although they wouldn’t call into question the parity principle per se, they question C&C’s parity argument. Although, in principle, it may be wise not to treat derived and intrinsic content on a par, my position is to grant the parity argument. Reconciliation may be achieved by arguing that neither endogenous nor exogenous states can be ascribed intrinsic content.6 My reasons then for questioning the extended mind thesis are pretty different from the 5 Notice, however, that nothing hinges on endorsing an anti-representationalist perspective tout court. All I’m saying is that these states may count as a genuine non-cognitive natural kind and that nothing in C&C’ thesis cancels that option out. It is thus an alternative that cannnot be discarded beforehand. 6 It might be good to find a reason to disallow intrinsic content. Dennett gives it a shot in “The Myth of Original Intentionality,” but see Adams and Aizawa (forthcoming) for a response. 6 ones typically adduced from the internalist/externalist corners.7 What are then the reasons to argue that the piece of behaviour C&C consider is not cognitive? 3. A way to offload the cognitive cargo We are now in a position to assess the extended mind thesis.
Recommended publications
  • The Extended Mind Thesis and Mechanistic Explanations
    The Extended Mind Thesis and Mechanistic Explanations Peter Fazekas Institute of Philosophy, Research Centre for the Humanities Hungarian Academy of Sciences email: [email protected] Abstract The Extended Mind Thesis (EMT) is traditionally formulated against the bedrock of functionalism, and ongoing debates are typically bogged down with questions concerning the exact relationship between EMT and different versions of functionalism. In this paper, I offer a novel ally for EMT: the new mechanistic approach to explanation. I argue that the mechanistic framework provides useful resources not just to disambiguate EMT, and to show which objections fail to pose a serious challenge, but also to answer some of the deeper problems that stem from the functionalist roots of EMT. ! 1. Introduction The Extended Mind Thesis (EMT), first proposed by Clark and Chalmers (1998), claims that the vehicles of our cognitive processes and mental states can and sometimes do extend beyond the boundaries of our brain and even body (cf. Clark, 2008, p. 76). If a physical object plays a part in the machinery realising a cognitive process, then that physical object is part of the cognitive process, no matter whether it is inside or outside the head. This is the so-called parity principle (Clark & Chalmers, 1998, p. 8), the heart and soul of EMT. The most well-known illustration is the case of Otto and Inga. When Inga hears about a new exhibition at the Museum of Modern Art (MoMA) she retrieves from her biological memory that it is on 53rd Street and goes to the museum. Her counterpart, Otto, who suffers from a mild form of Alzheimer’s disease, uses a notebook to jot down and retrieve information.
    [Show full text]
  • Extended Cognition and Extended Consciousness∗
    Extended Cognition and Extended Consciousness∗ David J. Chalmers It’s a pleasure to contribute to this volume honoring Andy Clark. Andy has been an influential figure for me ever since I read his first book Microcognition while I was in graduate school. A few years later I took up my first job as a post-doctoral fellow working with him in the newly initiated Philosophy-Neuroscience-Psychology program at Washington University in St Louis. We had a lot of adventures, but the one that seems to have left the most traces is our joint paper on “The Extended Mind”, which argued that cognitive processes can extend outside the brain and the body to include objects that we interact with in our environment. I recently came across hard copies of two early drafts of “The Extended Mind” in my files. The first draft was by Andy on his own, and is covered in handwritten comments by me. The second draft is a co-authored version with revisions by me, and is covered in handwritten comments by Andy. (I have put these two online at consc.net/papers/e-drafts.html.) There were many further iterations after that. The whole thing is a wonderful record of distributed and extended cognition, involving a complex cognitive process spread between Andy, me, various notes on paper, and computer files. I’m proud to have played a role in constituting this process. That said, I have to acknowledge that as with many cases of distributed cognition, there was an individual at the core who set the whole process into motion and who bears primary responsbility, and that individual was Andy.
    [Show full text]
  • Extended Emotion
    Forthcoming in Philosophical Psychology EXTENDED EMOTION J. Adam Carter, Emma C. Gordon & S. Orestis Palermos Abstract: Recent thinking within philosophy of mind about the ways cognition can extend (e.g. Clark 2011; Clark & Chalmers 1998; Wilson 2000, 2004; Menary 2006) has yet to be integrated with philosophical theories of emotion, which give cognition a central role. We carve out new ground at the intersection of these areas, and in doing so, defend what we call the extended emotion thesis: i.e., the claim that some emotions can extend beyond skin and skull to parts of the external world. 0. INTRODUCTION Under certain descriptions, the claim that emotions ‘extend’ can be used to express ideas that are natural and familiar. Marshall McLuhan, for instance, famously advocated a very broad and intuitive idea of ‘human extension’ according to which individuals’ intellectual and emotional lives could be thought of as ‘extending’ into the world, through the resources of mass media and technology1. Within academic philosophy, at least one familiar expression of the idea of emotions ‘extending’ can be traced to David Hume’s account of motivational psychology; on this view, sentiment is necessary to motivate action, and thus as the thought would go, we might think of emotions as ‘extending’ through the causal vehicle of the actions they motivate. A much more provocative way, however, to think about emotions extending is along the following lines: that emotions themselves can extend beyond biological agents, and include parts of the physical world, external to the agent. On this proposal, the notion of emotions extending is not a metaphysically innocent metaphor: rather, some emotions themselves are claimed to supervene partly on extraorganismic elements in the 1 McLuhan (1964) world.
    [Show full text]
  • The Emergence of Distributed Cognition: a Conceptual Framework
    submitted for Proceedings of Collective Intentionality IV, Siena (Italy), to be published as a special issue of Cognitive Systems Research The Emergence of Distributed Cognition: a conceptual framework Francis HEYLIGHEN, Margeret HEATH and Frank VAN OVERWALLE Vrije Universiteit Brussel, Pleinlaan 2, B-1050 Brussels, Belgium {fheyligh, mheath, fjvoverw}@vub.ac.be ABSTRACT: We propose a first step in the development of an integrated theory of the emergence of distributed cognition/extended mind. Distributed cognition is seen as the confluence of collective intelligence and “situatedness”, or the extension of cognitive processes into the physical environment. The framework is based on five fundamental assumptions: 1) groups of agents self-organize to form a differentiated, coordinated system, adapted to its environment, 2) the system co-opts external media for internal propagation of information, 3) the resulting distributed cognitive system can be modelled as a learning, connectionist network, 4) information in the network is transmitted selectively, 5) novel knowledge emerges through non-linear, recurrent interactions. The implication for collective intentionality is that such a self-organizing agent collective can develop “mental content” that is not reducible to individual cognitions. Extended Mind: collective intelligence and distributed cognition From a cybernetic perspective [Heylighen & Joslyn, 2001], a cognitive system cannot be understood as a discrete collection of beliefs, procedures, and/or modules. Cognition is a continuously evolving process which relates present perceptions via internal states to potential further perceptions and actions. It thus allows an agent to anticipate what may happen, adapt to changes in its environment, and moreover effect changes upon its environment [Kirsch & Maglio, 1994].
    [Show full text]
  • Active Externalism and Epistemic Internalism
    Forthcoming in Erkenntnis ACTIVE EXTERNALISM AND EPISTEMIC INTERNALISM J. Adam Carter & S. Orestis Palermos University of Edinburgh Abstract. Internalist approaches to epistemic justification are, though controversial, considered a live option in contemporary epistemology. Accordingly, if ‘active’ externalist approaches in the philosophy of mind—e.g. the extended cognition and extended mind theses—are in principle incompatible with internalist approaches to justification in epistemology, then this will be an epistemological strike against, at least the prima facie appeal of, active externalism. It is shown here however that, contrary to pretheoretical intuitions, neither the extended cognition nor the extended mind theses are in principle incompatible with two prominent versions of epistemic internalism—viz., accessibilism and mentalism. In fact, one possible diagnosis is that pretheoretical intuitions regarding the incompatibility of active externalism with epistemic internalism are symptomatic of a tacit yet incorrect identification of epistemic internalism with epistemic individualism. Thus, active externalism is not in principle incompatible with epistemic internalism per se and does not (despite initial appearances to the contrary) significantly restrict one’s options in epistemology. Keywords: extended cognition, extended mind, epistemic internalism 1 Two Questions of Incompatibility Ever since the Putnam/Burge-style thought experiments led to the institution of content externalism—viz., the thesis that mental contents are widely
    [Show full text]
  • Extended Mind-Wandering Bruineberg
    Habitual smartphone use as extended mind-wandering Preprint before review, June 7, 2021 Jelle Bruineberg [email protected] ORCID: 0000-0001-5675-3376 Department of Philosophy, Macquarie University Regina E. Fabry [email protected] ORCID: 0000-0003-1078-1499 Department of Philosophy II, Ruhr University Bochum Habitual smartphone use as extended mind-wandering Jelle Bruineberg & Regina E. Fabry1 Abstract Smartphone use plays an increasingly important role in our daily lives. Philosophical research that has used first-wave or second-wave theories of extended cognition in order to understand our engagement with digital technologies has focused on the contribution of these technologies to the completion of specific cognitive tasks (e.g., remembering, reasoning, problem-solving, navigation). However, in a considerable number of cases, everyday smartphone use is either task-unrelated or task-free. In psychological research, these cases have been captured by notions such as absent-minded smartphone use (Marty- Dugas et al., 2018) or smartphone-related inattentiveness (Liebherr et al., 2020). Given the prevalence of these cases, we develop a conceptual framework that can accommodate the functional and phenomenological characteristics of task-unrelated or task-free smartphone use. To this end, we will integrate research on second-wave extended cognition with mind- wandering research and introduce the concept of ‘extended mind-wandering’. Elaborating the family resemblances approach to mind-wandering (Seli, Kane, Smallwood, et al., 2018), we will argue that task-unrelated or task-free smartphone use shares many characteristics with mind-wandering. We will suggest that an empirically informed conceptual analysis of cases of extended mind-wandering can enrich current work on digitally extended cognition by specifying the influence of the attention economy on our cognitive dynamics.
    [Show full text]
  • Extended Mind” Thesis Helps to Solve a Fundamental Dilemma of Literacy Theory
    AVANT Volume IV, Number 2/2013 www.avant.edu.pl/en AVANT, Vol. IV, No. 2/2013 ISSN: 2082-6710 avant.edu.pl/en DOI: 10.12849/40202013.0709.0005 How the “Extended Mind” Thesis Helps to Solve a Fundamental Dilemma of Literacy Theory Marcin Trybulec Maria Curie-Sklodowska University in Lublin marcin.trybulec[]umcs.pl Received 25 June 2013; accepted 7 September 2013; published Autumn 2013. Abstract The aim of the paper is to outline the basic theoretical reasons for applying the concept of extended mind to literacy theory. In order to explicate theoreti- cal difficulties faced by literacy theory, one needs to take into account the de- bate regarding technological determinism. Using this debate as an example, one can observe two basic strategies applied to defining the concept of a me- dium. On the one hand, there exists a strategy to formulate a narrow defini- tion of a medium in terms of material artifacts. On the other hand, one can observe a strategy which relies on creating a wide definition of a medium. According to this definition, a medium is understood as a social institution which denotes a particular way of behaving and thinking. The paper aims at justifying the hypothesis that both interpretational strategies employed in defining a medium and the related concept of technology are inaccurate in certain important respects. If the argumentation presented here proves cor- rect, literacy theory will be faced with a serious dilemma: a choice between two equally unsuitable definitions of technology/media. However, the theoret- ical dilemma pertaining to the question of media can be elucidated by appeal- ing to the conceptual framework of the extended mind hypothesis.
    [Show full text]
  • Foreword to Andy Clark's Supersizing the Mind
    Foreword to Andy Clark’s Supersizing the Mind David J. Chalmers A month ago, I bought an iPhone. The iPhone has already taken over some of the central functions of my brain. It has replaced part of my memory, storing phone numbers and addresses that I once would have taxed my brain with. It harbors my desires: I call up a memo with the names of my favorite dishes when I need to order at a local restaurant. I use it to calculate, when I need to figure out bills and tips. It is a tremendous resource in an argument, with Google ever present to help settle disputes. I make plans with it, using its calendar to help determine what I can and can’t do in the coming months. I even daydream on the iPhone, idly calling up words and images when my concentration slips. Friends joke that I should get the iPhone implanted into my brain. But if Andy Clark is right, all this would do is speed up the processing, and free up my hands. The iPhone is part of my mind already. Clark is a connoisseur of the myriad ways in which the mind relies on the world to get its work done. The first part of this marvelous book explores some of these ways: the extension of our bodies, the extension of our senses, and crucially, the use of language as a tool to extend our thought. The second part of the book defends the thesis that in at least some of these cases, the world is not serving as a mere instrument for the mind.
    [Show full text]
  • Predictive Processing and Extended Consciousness: Why the Machinery of Consciousness
    DEUTS FAILURE 1 Predictive processing and extended consciousness: why the machinery of consciousness is (probably) still in the head and the DEUTS argument won’t let it leak outside Abstract Consciousness vehicle externalism (CVE) is the claim that the material machinery of a subject’s phenomenology partially leaks outside a subject’s brain, encompassing bodily and environmental structures. The DEUTS argument is the most prominent argument for CVE in the sensorimotor enactivists’ arsenal. In a recent series of publications, Kirchhoff and Kiverstein have deployed such an argument to claim that a prominent view of neural processing, namely predictive processing, is fully compatible with CVE. Indeed, in Kirchhoff and Kiverstein’s view, a proper understanding of predictive processing mandates CVE. In this essay, we critically examine Kirchhoff and Kiverstein’s argument. Our aim is to argue in favor of the following three points. First, that Kirchhoff and Kiverstein’s emphasis on cultural practices lends no support to CVE: at best, it vindicates some form of content externalism about phenomenal content. Secondly, the criteria Kirchhoff and Kiverstein propose to identify a subject’s phenomenal machinery greatly overgeneralize, leaving them open to a “consciousness bloat” objection, which is an analog of the cognitive bloat objection against the extended mind. Lastly, we will argue that the “consciousness bloat” problem is inbuilt in the very argumentative structure of the DEUTS argument. We will thus conclude that, contrary to the philosophical mainstream, DEUTS is not the best argument for CVE in the sensorimotor enactivists’ argumentative arsenal. Keywords: Predictive​ Processing, Free Energy Principle, Markov Blankets, Extended Consciousness, Sensorimotor Enactivism.
    [Show full text]
  • Artificial Intelligence Beyond the Philosophy of Mind
    RETHINKING MACHINES: ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE BEYOND THE PHILOSOPHY OF MIND BY DANIEL JOSE ESTRADA DISSERTATION Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy in the Graduate College of the University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign, 2014 Urbana, Illinois Doctoral Committee: Associate Professor Jonathan Waskan, Chair Associate Professor Daniel Korman Emeritus Professor Steven Wagner Associate Professor Andrew Arana Abstract Recent philosophy of mind has increasingly focused on the role of technology in shaping, influencing, and extending our mental faculties. Technology extends the mind in two basic ways: through the creative design of artifacts and the purposive use of instruments. If the meaningful activity of technological artifacts were exhaustively described in these mind-dependent terms, then a philosophy of technology would depend entirely on our theory of mind. In this dissertation, I argue that a mind-dependent approach to technology is mistaken. Instead, some machines are best understood as independent participants in their own right, contributing to and augmenting a variety of social practices as active, though often unrecognized, community members. Beginning with Turing’s call for “fair play for machines”, I trace an argument concerning the social autonomy of nonhuman agents through the artificial intelligence debates of the 20th century. I’ll argue that undue focus on the mind has obscured the force of Turing’s proposal, leaving the debates in an unfortunate stalemate. I will then examine a network theoretic alternative to the study of multi- agent complex systems that can avoid anthropocentric, mind-dependent ways of framing human- machine interactions. I argue that this approach allows for both scientific and philosophical treatment of large and complicated sociotechnical systems, and suggests novel methods for designing, managing, and maintaining such systems.
    [Show full text]
  • Extending the Extended Mind from Cognition to Consciousness
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Helsingin yliopiston digitaalinen arkisto Department of Philosophy, History and Art Studies Faculty of Arts University of Helsinki Finland Extending the Extended Mind From Cognition to Consciousness Pii Telakivi DOCTORAL DISSERTATION to be presented for public discussion with the permission of the Faculty of Arts of the University of Helsinki, in lecture room 107, Athena (Siltavuorenpenger 3 A), on the 5th of September, 2020 at 12 o’clock. Filosofisia tutkimuksia Helsingin yliopistosta Filosofiska Studier från Helsingfors universitet Philosophical Studies from the University of Helsinki Publishers: Theoretical Philosophy Philosophy (in Swedish) Social and Moral Philosophy P.O. Box 24 (Unioninkatu 40A) 00014 University of Helsinki Finland Editors: Samuli Reijula Michiru Nagatsu Thomas Wallgren ISBN 978-951-51-6436-0 (pbk.) ISBN 978-951-51-6437-7 (PDF) ISSN 1458-8331 (series) http://ethesis.helsinki.fi Unigrafia, Helsinki 2020 Cover: Mirko Varano Abstract Where does conscious experience stop and the rest of the world begin? Is the material basis of consciousness confined to the brain, or can it be extended to include other parts of the body and environmental elements? This study proposes an extended account: when all the requirements are fulfilled, an external tool may become part of the realising basis for certain experiential processes. Andy Clark and David Chalmers argued famously that the material basis of cognitive states sometimes extends out of the barriers of skin and skull to external objects such as notebooks and other everyday tools. However, they draw the line there: only cognition, but not consciousness can have an extended base.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction: Memory, Embodied Cognition, and the Extended Mind
    Philosophical Psychology Vol. 19, No. 3, June 2006, pp. 281–289 Introduction: Memory, Embodied Cognition, and the Extended Mind John Sutton I introduce the seven papers in this special issue, by Andy Clark, Je´roˆme Dokic, Richard Menary, Jenann Ismael, Sue Campbell, Doris McIlwain, and Mark Rowlands. This paper explains the motivation for an alliance between the sciences of memory and the extended mind hypothesis. It examines in turn the role of worldly, social, and internalized forms of scaffolding to memory and cognition, and also highlights themes relating to affect, agency, and individual differences. Keywords: Memory; Embodied Cognition; Extended Mind; Autobiography; Affect; Agency Whatever one’s overall assessment of the current state of the sciences of memory, which span a daunting range of disciplines across the neurosciences, the cognitive sciences, and the social sciences, an integrative spirit can be identified in recent research trends. By this I refer not only to the development of frameworks—whether broadly reductive or not—for making sense of interfield or interlevel relations in memory studies (Bickle, 2003; Craver, 2002; Craver & Darden, 2001; Hardcastle, 1996; Sutton, 2004); but also to insistent attempts to integrate methods and results from the core laboratory disciplines of cognitive psychology and neuropsychology with memory research in ecological or ‘‘real-life’’ contexts. In 1978 Ulric Neisser could fairly lament that ‘‘If X is an interesting or socially significant aspect of memory, then psychologists have hardly ever studied X’’ (1978/2000, p. 4). But the situation changed swiftly, partly as a result of brave conceptual innovations and institutional initiatives taken by Neisser and other leading figures in the field, and partly because of complex and independent shifts both within psychology and in the wider cultural significance attributed to memory.
    [Show full text]