Sets and the Continuum Before 1907

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Sets and the Continuum Before 1907 Chapter 1 Sets and the continuum before 1907 For a fruitful discussion of Brouwer’s early work, a reasonable amount of knowl- edge of the development of set theory, as this took place during the second half of the nineteenth century, is required. We must keep in mind that Brouwer reacted to a new and very current branch of mathematics, which received a lot of attention during the period beginning just a few decades before Brouwer’s active life as a mathematician and philosopher. This first chapter contains background material, needed for a proper under- standing of the discussion about the foundational parts of Brouwer’s disserta- tion. The content will be familiar to many readers, since it consists mainly of basic set theory. For those readers a quick glance will suffice. After 1870 set theory developed rapidly into a separate branch of mathe- matics, despite resistance from mathematicians like Kronecker, but also from philosophers and even from theologians. This new development took place mainly through the work of Georg Cantor, who, for that reason, must be con- sidered as the founder of set theory. Before Cantor, use was made of certain collections possessing certain proper- ties, like the locus in geometry, but collections like that did not seem to have the status of a mathematical object with which and on which certain mathematical operations could be performed. Likewise collections with an infinite number of elements, although their existence had of course to be admitted, seemed to possess strange properties to such an extent (like the possibility of a one-one correspondence between a collection and a part thereof) that they too seemed to lack the status of mathematical object.1 1see [Galileo 1974], page 40, 41 where one of the participants in the discussion concludes, because of the possible one-one relation between natural numbers and their squares, that concepts like ‘equal’, ‘greater’ and ‘smaller’ are not applicable in case of infinite quantities. 1 2 CHAPTER 1. SETS AND THE CONTINUUM BEFORE 1907 To get an insight into the development and in the state of knowledge of set theory at the time of Brouwer’s public defence of his dissertation, the following persons and subjects are of importance, and will be discussed: 1.1 Cantor 1.2 Dedekind 1.3 Poincar´e 1.4 Zermelo 1.5 Schoenflies 1.6 Bernstein 1.7 The paradoxes An important predecessor in the development of set theory was Bolzano (1781–1848), whose main publication on this topic, Paradoxien des Unendlichen, was published posthumously in 1851.2 Bolzano was attracted by the seemingly paradoxical nature of the infinite. Without going into the details of Bolzano’s work, we just mention the fact that he very clearly saw the problems concerning the infinite, that he asked the proper questions, but did not take the steps and did not draw the conclusions, that Cantor did twenty five years later. Because Brouwer made use of Cantor’s results (and disagreed in many re- spects with these results), it is, for a proper understanding of the references that Brouwer made, of importance to give a survey of the content of Cantor’s work in a systematic way. This will be done in the first section of this chapter, despite the fact that it concerns rather basic set theory with which many readers will be familiar. 1.1 Cantor (1845–1918) Cantor started publishing on set theory in 1870, shortly after his Habilitation. From this time onwards the idea that a set can have a one-to-one relation to a proper subset of itself is generally accepted as a typical property of infinite sets (and is certainly no reason to turn away from those sets).3 The word set (German: Menge, French: ensemble) did not appear right from the beginning in the work of Cantor. In his earliest letters to Dedekind during the years 1873 and 18744 and in his paper Uber¨ eine Eigenschaft des Inbegriffes aller reellen algebraischen Zahlen, published in 1874, he employed the mathematically undefined term totality (Inbegriff) e.g. of the natural numbers or of the rational numbers. In the 1877-correspondence to Dedekind and in the 1878-paper Ein Beitrag zur Mannigfaltigkeitslehre, the term Mannigfaltigkeit was used to indicate such totalities, but now also set (Menge) appeared, and in 2[Bolzano 1851]. 3For Dedekind the possibility of a one-to-one mapping of a set onto a proper subset of itself became the definition of the infinity of a set, now known under the term Dedekind infinite. See under section 1.2. 4Cantor communicated his new ideas on sets and cardinalities with Dedekind in a series of letters after 1873; see [Cantor 1937]. 1.1. CANTOR (1845–1918) 3 the eighties of that century this term became the accepted one. We will from now on use only the term set. In the Beitr¨agezur Begr¨undungder transfiniten Mengenlehre5 the following definition of a set is given (§ 1): Unter einer ‘Menge’ verstehen wir jede Zusammenfassung M von bestimmten wohlunterschiedenen Objecten m unsrer Anschauung oder unseres Denkens (welche die ‘Elemente’ von M genannt werden) zu einem Ganzen. To indicate the magnitude of a set M the term power, cardinality or cardinal number (M¨achtigkeit, Cardinalzahl) is used: two sets have the same power or cardinality if a one-to-one mapping of one set onto the other is possible, under abstraction from the order and the nature of their elements. This cardinality with its double abstraction is indicated for a set M by M. Sets satisfying that mapping condition are then said to be equivalent (gleichm¨achtig). Consulted literature for this section about Cantor consists of the following material: – Briefwechsel Cantor-Dedekind, edited by E. Noether and J. Cavaill`es, Paris, 1937. This volume contains the Cantor-Dedekind correspondence between 1872 and 1882; the important 1899-part of this correspondence is contained in Can- tor’s Gesammelte Abhandlungen. – Cantor, Gesammelte Abhandlungen, edited by E. Zermelo, Berlin, 1932. From this volume in particular the following articles: – Uber¨ eine Eigenschaft des Inbegriffes aller reellen algebraischen Zahlen. (Journal f¨urdie reine und angewandte Mathematik6 1874.) – Ein Beitrag zur Mannigfaltigkeitslehre. (idem, 1878.) – Uber¨ einen Satz aus der Theorie der stetigen Mannigfaltigkeiten. (G¨ottinger Nachrichten, 1879.) – Uber¨ unendliche lineare Punktmannigfaltigkeiten. (Mathematische Annalen, 1879, ’80, ’82, ’83, ’84; M.A. Volumes 15, 17, 20, 21 and 23 respectively.) – Uber¨ verschiedene Theoreme aus der Theorie der Punktmengen in einem n-fach ausgedehnten stetigen Raume Gn. (Acta Mathematica, 1885.) – Uber¨ die verschiedenen Standpunkte in bezug auf das aktuelle Un- endliche. (Zeitschrift f¨ur Philosophie und philosophische Kritik bd. 88, 1890.) 5[Cantor 1897], also in [Cantor 1932], page 282 ff. 6Brouwer usually referred to this journal under the name of its editor Crelle, and we will follow this practice henceforth. 4 CHAPTER 1. SETS AND THE CONTINUUM BEFORE 1907 – Mitteilungen zur Lehre vom Transfiniten. (Zschr. f. Philos. u. philos. Kritik, 1887.) – Uber¨ eine elementare Frage der Mannigfaltigkeitslehre. (Jahres- bericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung, Bd.1, 1890–91.) –Beitr¨agezur Begr¨undung der transfiniten Mengenlehre. (Mathema- tische Annalen 1895, ’97, M.A. Volumes 46 and 49 respectively.) As far as possible, the papers mentioned above will be discussed in a chrono- logical order, which results not only in an overview of the state of knowledge on sets in the year 1907, but additionally in a survey of the origin and history of set theory. We must keep in mind that there was only one complete textbook on set theory available during the years of Brouwer’s preparation for his thesis.7 Brouwer drew most of his information directly from Cantor’s papers. In the first sections frequent use will be made of the Cantor-Dedekind cor- respondence; this in particular gives a good insight in the development of his ideas. It will be noticed that in the beginning Cantor often made use of terms and concepts which were only properly defined in a later stage of the develop- ment. 1.1.1 The discovery of non-equivalent infinite sets In a letter to Dedekind of 29 November 1873,8 Cantor considered the possibility of the construction of a one-to-one relation between the natural and the real numbers. He did not know a definite answer to this problem yet, and asked Dedekind to think it over. Intuitively the answer should be no, but there was justified doubt: Auf den ersten Anblick sagt man sich, nein es ist nicht m¨oglich, denn (n) besteht aus discreten Theilen, (x) aber bildet ein Continuum; (...) W¨are man nicht auch auf den ersten Anblick geneigt zu behaupten, p dass sich (n) nicht eindeutig zuordnen lasse dem Inbegriffe ( q ) aller p positiven rationalen Zahlen q ? But this last statement is easy to prove, just as the theorem of the equivalence between the natural numbers and the algebraic numbers. In a following letter to Dedekind of 7 December 1873, Cantor proved in an ingenious way that the assumed equivalence between the natural numbers and 7The first general textbook on set theory was Schoenflies’ Bericht ¨uber die Mengenlehre, [Schoenflies 1900a], published in the Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathmatiker-Vereiniging; see under section 1.5. In fact there was also Young and Young’s The theory of sets of points ([Young and Chisholm Young 1906]), but probably Brouwer was not familiar with this book; he never mentioned the name Young, neither in his thesis, nor in his notebooks, although W.H. Young published in German in the Mathematische Annalen in 1905. 8[Cantor 1937], page 12; all letters between Cantor and Dedekind during the years 1872 – 1882 are published in this volume.
Recommended publications
  • Cantor and Continuity
    Cantor and Continuity Akihiro Kanamori May 1, 2018 Georg Cantor (1845-1919), with his seminal work on sets and number, brought forth a new field of inquiry, set theory, and ushered in a way of proceeding in mathematics, one at base infinitary, topological, and combinatorial. While this was the thrust, his work at the beginning was embedded in issues and concerns of real analysis and contributed fundamentally to its 19th Century rigorization, a development turning on limits and continuity. And a continuing engagement with limits and continuity would be very much part of Cantor's mathematical journey, even as dramatically new conceptualizations emerged. Evolutionary accounts of Cantor's work mostly underscore his progressive ascent through set- theoretic constructs to transfinite number, this as the storied beginnings of set theory. In this article, we consider Cantor's work with a steady focus on con- tinuity, putting it first into the context of rigorization and then pursuing the increasingly set-theoretic constructs leading to its further elucidations. Beyond providing a narrative through the historical record about Cantor's progress, we will bring out three aspectual motifs bearing on the history and na- ture of mathematics. First, with Cantor the first mathematician to be engaged with limits and continuity through progressive activity over many years, one can see how incipiently metaphysical conceptualizations can become systemati- cally transmuted through mathematical formulations and results so that one can chart progress on the understanding of concepts. Second, with counterweight put on Cantor's early career, one can see the drive of mathematical necessity pressing through Cantor's work toward extensional mathematics, the increasing objectification of concepts compelled, and compelled only by, his mathematical investigation of aspects of continuity and culminating in the transfinite numbers and set theory.
    [Show full text]
  • Introductory Topics in the Mathematical Theory of Continuum Mechanics - R J Knops and R
    CONTINUUM MECHANICS - Introductory Topics In The Mathematical Theory Of Continuum Mechanics - R J Knops and R. Quintanilla INTRODUCTORY TOPICS IN THE MATHEMATICAL THEORY OF CONTINUUM MECHANICS R J Knops School of Mathematical and Computer Sciences, Heriot-Watt University, UK R. Quintanilla Department of Applied Mathematics II, UPC Terrassa, Spain Keywords: Classical and non-classical continuum thermomechanics, well- and ill- posedness; non-linear, linear, linearized, initial and boundary value problems, existence, uniqueness, dynamic and spatial stability, continuous data dependence. Contents I. GENERAL PRINCIPLES 1. Introduction 2. The well-posed problem II. BASIC CONTINUUM MECHANICS 3. Introduction 4. Material description 5. Spatial description 6. Constitutive theories III. EXAMPLE: HEAT CONDUCTION 7. Introduction. Existence and uniqueness 8. Continuous dependence. Stability 9. Backward heat equation. Ill-posed problems 10. Non-linear heat conduction 11. Infinite thermal wave speeds IV. CLASSICAL THEORIES 12. Introduction 13. Thermoviscous flow. Navier-Stokes Fluid 14. Linearized and linear elastostatics 15. Linearized Elastodynamics 16. LinearizedUNESCO and linear thermoelastostatics – EOLSS 17. Linearized and linear thermoelastodynamics 18. Viscoelasticity 19. Non-linear Elasticity 20. Non-linearSAMPLE thermoelasticity and thermoviscoelasticity CHAPTERS V. NON-CLASSICAL THEORIES 21. Introduction 22. Isothermal models 23. Thermal Models Glossary Bibliography Biographical sketches ©Encyclopedia of Life Support Systems (EOLSS) CONTINUUM MECHANICS - Introductory Topics In The Mathematical Theory Of Continuum Mechanics - R J Knops and R. Quintanilla Summary Qualitative properties of well-posedness and ill-posedness are examined for problems in the equilibrium and dynamic classical non-linear theories of Navier-Stokes fluid flow and elasticity. These serve as prototypes of more general theories, some of which are also discussed. The article is reasonably self-contained.
    [Show full text]
  • Topology ­ Jon­Paul Cox ­ Connected Spaces May 11, 2016
    Topology ­ Jon­Paul Cox ­ Connected Spaces May 11, 2016 Connected Spaces Jon­Paul Cox 5/11/16 6th Period Topology Parallels Between Calculus and Topology Intermediate Value Theorem If is continuous and if r is a real number between f(a) and f(b), then there exists an element such that f(c) = r. Maximum Value Theorem If is continuous, then there exists an element such that for every . Uniform Continuity Theorem If is continuous, then given > 0, there exists > 0 such that for every pair of numbers , of [a,b] for which . 1 Topology ­ Jon­Paul Cox ­ Connected Spaces May 11, 2016 Parallels Between Calculus and Topology Intermediate Value Theorem If is continuous and if r is a real number between f(a) and f(b), then there exists an element such that f(c) = r. Connected Spaces A space can be "separated" if it can be broken up into two disjoint, open parts. Otherwise it is connected. If the set is not separated, it is connected, and vice versa. 2 Topology ­ Jon­Paul Cox ­ Connected Spaces May 11, 2016 Connected Spaces Let X be a topological space. A separation of X is a pair of disjoint, nonempty open sets of X whose union is X. E.g. Connected Spaces A space is connected if and only if the only subsets of X that are both open and closed in X are and X itself. 3 Topology ­ Jon­Paul Cox ­ Connected Spaces May 11, 2016 Subspace Topology Let X be a topological space with topology . If Y is a subset of X (I.E.
    [Show full text]
  • Big Homotopy Theory
    University of Tennessee, Knoxville TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange Doctoral Dissertations Graduate School 5-2013 Big Homotopy Theory Keith Gordon Penrod [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://trace.tennessee.edu/utk_graddiss Part of the Geometry and Topology Commons Recommended Citation Penrod, Keith Gordon, "Big Homotopy Theory. " PhD diss., University of Tennessee, 2013. https://trace.tennessee.edu/utk_graddiss/1768 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Doctoral Dissertations by an authorized administrator of TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange. For more information, please contact [email protected]. To the Graduate Council: I am submitting herewith a dissertation written by Keith Gordon Penrod entitled "Big Homotopy Theory." I have examined the final electronic copy of this dissertation for form and content and recommend that it be accepted in partial fulfillment of the equirr ements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, with a major in Mathematics. Jurek Dydak, Major Professor We have read this dissertation and recommend its acceptance: Jim Conant, Nikolay Brodskiy, Morwen Thistletwaite, Delton Gerloff Accepted for the Council: Carolyn R. Hodges Vice Provost and Dean of the Graduate School (Original signatures are on file with official studentecor r ds.) Big Homotopy Theory A Dissertation Presented for the Doctor of Philosophy Degree The University of Tennessee, Knoxville Keith Gordon Penrod May 2013 c by Keith Gordon Penrod, 2013 All Rights Reserved. ii This dissertation is dedicated to Archimedes, who was my inspiration for becoming a mathematician.
    [Show full text]
  • UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Electronic Theses and Dissertations
    UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Electronic Theses and Dissertations Title Mechanical Behaviors of Alloys From First Principles Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/1xv2n9dw Author Hanlumyuang, Yuranan Publication Date 2011 Peer reviewed|Thesis/dissertation eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California Mechanical Behaviors of Alloys From First Principles by Yuranan Hanlumyuang A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Materials Sciences and Engineering in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Professor Daryl C. Chrzan, Chair Professor John W. Morris, Jr. Professor Tarek I. Zohdi Fall 2011 Mechanical Behaviors of Alloys From First Principles Copyright 2011 by Yuranan Hanlumyuang 1 Abstract Mechanical Behaviors of Alloys From First Principles by Yuranan Hanlumyuang Doctor of Philosophy in Materials Sciences and Engineering University of California, Berkeley Professor Daryl C. Chrzan, Chair Several mesoscale models have been developed to consider a number of mechanical prop- erties and microstructures of Ti-V approximants to Gum Metal and steels from the atomistic scale. In Gum Metal, the relationships between phonon properties and phase stabilities are studied. Our results show that it is possible to design a BCC (β-phase) alloy that deforms near the ideal strength, while maintaining structural stability with respect to the formation of the ! and α00 phases. Theoretical diffraction patterns reveal the role of the soft N−point phonon and the BCC!HCP transformation path in post-deformation samples. The total energies of the path explain the formation of the giant faults and nano shearbands in Gum Metal.
    [Show full text]
  • Definition in Terms of Order Alone in the Linear
    DEFINITION IN TERMS OF ORDERALONE IN THE LINEAR CONTINUUMAND IN WELL-ORDERED SETS* BY OSWALD VEBLEN First definition of the continuum. A linear continuum is a set of elements { P} which we may call points, sub- ject to a relation -< which we may read precedes, governed by the following conditions, A to E : A. General Postulates of Order. 1. { P} contains at least two elements. 2. If Px and P2 are distinct elements of {P} then either Px -< P2 or P < P . 3. IfP, -< F2 then Px is distinct from P2. f 4. IfPx <. P2 and P2 < P3, then P, < P3. f B. Dedekind Postulate of Closure. J If {P} consists entirely of two infinite subsets, [P] and [P"] such that P' -< P", then there is either a P'0 of [PJ such that P' -< P'0 whenever P + P'0 or a P'J of [P"J such that P'0' < P" whenever P" +- P'¡. C. Pseudo-Archimedean postulate. 1. If { P} is an infinite set then there exists a subset [ P„ ] , such that P„ -< P„+ ,(^==1, 2, 3, ■••) and if P is any element of { P} for which Px "C P, then there exists a v such that P -< Pv. * Presented to the Society December 30, 1904, uuder the title, Non-Metrictd Definition of the Linear Continuum. Received for publication January 26, 1905. |The propositions As and At say that -< is "non-reflexive" and "transitive." It follows immediately that it is "non-symmetric," for if Px -< P2 and P,A. Pi could occur simultaneously, 4 would lead to P¡^P¡, contrary to 3.
    [Show full text]
  • E.1 Normality of Linear Continua Theorem E.1. Every Linear Continuum X Is Normal in the Order Topology. Proof. It Suffices To
    E.1 Normality of Linear Continua Theorem E.1. Every linear continuum X is normal in the order topology. Proof. It suffices to consider the case where X has no largest element and no smallest element. For if X has a smallest x0 but no largest, we can form a new ordered set Y by taking the disjoint union of (,1) and X, and declaring every element of (,1) to be less than every element of X. The ordered set Y is a linear continuum with no largest or smallest. ,Sinc X is a closed subspace of Y, normality of Y implies normality of X. The other cases are similar. So,suppose X hs no largest or smallest. We follow the outline of Exercise 8 of §32. Step 1. Let C h a nonempty closed subset of X. We show that each component of X - C has the form (c,+cm) or (-p,c) or (c,c'), where c ard c' are points of C. Given a point x of X - C, let us take the union U of all open intervals (a~ ,b, ) of X that contain x and lie in X - C. Tlen U is connected. We show that U has one of the given forms, and that U is one of the components of X - C. Let a = inf a or a = -c, according as the set BanJ has a lower bound or not. Let b = sup b or b = +O according as the set fb ) has an upper bound or not. Then U = (a,b). If a - , we show a is a point of C.
    [Show full text]
  • TOPOLOGY NOTES SUMMER, 2006 2. Real Line We Know a Point Is Connected, and We Know an Indiscreet Space Is Connected. but That Ab
    TOPOLOGY NOTES SUMMER, 2006 JOHN C. MAYER 2. Real Line We know a point is connected, and we know an indiscreet space is connected. But that about exhausts our current state of examples. In this section we prove a general theorem about a kind of ordered space from which is follows that the real line and any of its intervals or rays is connected. (See Munkries, Section 24.) The key properties that make this possible are in the following de¯nition. De¯nition 2.1. A nondegenerate simply ordered space L is called a linear continuum i® it satis¯es the following: (1) L has the least upper bound property. (2) If x; y in L, then there exists z 2 L such that x < z < y. A subset C of an ordered set is convex i® whenever a; b 2 C, a · b, then the interval [a; b] ½ C. Theorem 2.2. If L is a linear continuum, then L is connected, and so is any convex set in L. ¤ Corollary 2.3. The real line R is connected, and so are rays and intervals in R. ¤ Corollary 2.4 (Intermediate Value Theorem). Let f : X ! Y be a continuous function of a connected space into an ordered space. If for a; b 2 X, r 2 Y lies between f(a) and f(b) in the order on Y , then there is a point c 2 X such that f(c) = r. ¤ Example 2.5. Let X be a well-ordered set. Then X £[0; 1) in the dictionary order topology is a linear continuum.
    [Show full text]
  • Topology Semester II, 2014–15
    Topology B.Math (Hons.) II Year Semester II, 2014{15 http://www.isibang.ac.in/~statmath/oldqp/QP/Topology%20MS%202014-15.pdf Midterm Solution ! 1 ! Question 1. Let R be the countably infinite product of R with itself, and let R be the subset of R consisting 1 of sequences which are eventually zero, that is, (ai)i=1 such that only finitely many ai's are nonzero. Determine 1 ! ! the closure of R in R with respect to the box topology, the uniform topology, and the product topology on R . Answer. ! (i) The product topology: A basic open set of R is of the form U = U1 × U2 × · · · × Un × R × R × · · · ! where Ui are open sets in R. Now take any x = (x1; x2; : : : ; xn; xn+1; xn+2;:::) 2 R , and any basic open set U as above containing x. Let y = (x1; x2; : : : ; xn; 0; 0; 0;:::). Now, it is easy to see that y 2 U. Also, 1 1 ! y 2 R . Hence R is dense in R in the product topology. (ii) The box topology : Every basic open set is of the form W = W1 × W2 × · · · × Wi × Wi+1 × · · · ! 1 Now take any x = (x1; x2; : : : ; xi; xi+1; xi+2;:::) 2 R nR , then xn 6= 0 for infinitely many n. In particular, if ( R n f0g if xn 6= 0 Wn = (−1; 1) if xn = 0 Q then if W = Wn as above, then x 2 W and 1 W \ R = ; 1 Hence R is closed in the box topology. ! ! (iii) The uniform topology: Consider R with the uniform topology and let d be the uniform metric.
    [Show full text]
  • Cantor's Proof of the Nondenumerability of Perfect Sets
    Rose-Hulman Undergraduate Mathematics Journal Volume 17 Issue 1 Article 8 Cantor’s Proof of the Nondenumerability of Perfect Sets Laila Awadalla University of Missouri — Kansas City Follow this and additional works at: https://scholar.rose-hulman.edu/rhumj Recommended Citation Awadalla, Laila (2016) "Cantor’s Proof of the Nondenumerability of Perfect Sets," Rose-Hulman Undergraduate Mathematics Journal: Vol. 17 : Iss. 1 , Article 8. Available at: https://scholar.rose-hulman.edu/rhumj/vol17/iss1/8 ROSE- H ULMAN UNDERGRADUATE MATHEMATICS JOURNAL CANTOR’S PROOF OF THE NONDENUMERABILITY OF PERFECT SETS Laila Awadallaa VOLUME 17, NO. 1, SPRING 2016 Sponsored by Rose-Hulman Institute of Technology Mathematics Department Terre Haute, IN 47803 Email: [email protected] http://www.rose-hulman.edu/mathjournal a University of Missouri – Kansas City ROSE-HULMAN UNDERGRADUATE MATHEMATICS JOURNAL VOLUME 17, NO. 1, SPRING 2016 CANTOR’S PROOF OF THE NONDENUMERABILITY OF PERFECT SETS Laila Awadalla Abstract. This paper provides an explication of mathematician Georg Cantor’s 1883 proof of the nondenumerability of perfect sets of real numbers. A set of real numbers is denumerable if it has the same (infinite) cardinality as the set of natural numbers {1, 2, 3, …}, and it is perfect if it consists only of so-called limit points (none of its points are isolated from the rest of the set). Directly from this proof, Cantor deduced that every infinite closed set of real numbers has only two choices for cardinality: the cardinality of the set of natural numbers, or the cardinality of the set of real numbers. This result strengthened his belief in his famous continuum hypothesis that every infinite subset of real numbers had one of those two cardinalities and no other.
    [Show full text]
  • The Embedding Structure for Linearly Ordered Topological Spaces ∗ A
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector Topology and its Applications 159 (2012) 3103–3114 Contents lists available at SciVerse ScienceDirect Topology and its Applications www.elsevier.com/locate/topol The embedding structure for linearly ordered topological spaces ∗ A. Primavesi a,1, K. Thompson b, ,2 a School of Mathematics, University of East Anglia, Norwich, NR4 7TJ, UK b Institut für Diskrete Mathematik und Geometrie, Technische Universität Wien, Wiedner Hauptstraße 8-10/104, A-1040 Wien, Austria article info abstract MSC: In this paper, the class of all linearly ordered topological spaces (LOTS) quasi-ordered by primary 54F05 the embeddability relation is investigated. In ZFC it is proved that for countable LOTS this secondary 06F30, 03E75 quasi-order has both a maximal (universal) element and a finite basis. For the class of ℵ uncountable LOTS of cardinality κ where κ 2 0 , it is proved that this quasi-order has no Keywords: maximal element and that in fact the dominating number for such quasi-orders is maximal, Linearly ordered topological space i.e. 2κ . Certain subclasses of LOTS, such as the separable LOTS, are studied with respect to LOTS Universal structure the top and internal structure of their respective embedding quasi-order. The basis problem Basis for uncountable LOTS is also considered; assuming the Proper Forcing Axiom there is an Well-quasi-order eleven element basis for the class of uncountable LOTS and a six element basis for the class of dense uncountable LOTS in which all points have countable cofinality and coinitiality.
    [Show full text]
  • Definable Continuous Induction on Ordered Abelian Groups 3
    DEFINABLE CONTINUOUS INDUCTION ON ORDERED ABELIAN GROUPS JAFAR S. EIVAZLOO1 Abstract. As mathematical induction is applied to prove state- ments on natural numbers, continuous induction (or, real induc- tion) is a tool to prove some statements in real analysis.(Although, this comparison is somehow an overstatement.) Here, we first con- sider it on densely ordered abelian groups to prove Heine-Borel the- orem (every closed and bounded interval is compact with respect to order topology) in those structures. Then, using the recently introduced notion of pseudo finite sets, we introduce a first order definable version of continuous induction in the language of ordered groups and we use it to prove a definable version of Heine-Borel theorem on densely ordered abelian groups. 1. Introduction and Preliminaries As mathematical induction is a good proof technique for statements on natural numbers, some efforts have been made to provide a similar technique in the real field, see [1, 7, 13, 14, 8, 2]. Here, we define con- tinuous induction on densely ordered abelian groups. Our motivation is to give a definable version of continuous induction in ordered struc- tures such as the definable version of mathematical induction in Peano arithmetic. A structure (G, +,<) is an ordered abelian group if (G, +) is an abelian group, (G,<) is a linear ordered set, and for all x, y, z in G, if x<y then x + z<y + z. An ordered abelian group is dense if for all x<y in G there exists z ∈ G such that x<z<y. If G is not dense, then it is discrete, i.e.
    [Show full text]