The Adjoint Functor Theorem Oliver Kullmann

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Adjoint Functor Theorem Oliver Kullmann The adjoint functor theorem Oliver Kullmann Review Special morphisms Comma categories Universal arrows The adjoint functor theorem Natural transformations Adjoint functors Limits and colimits Transfers via functors 1 Finding initial and Oliver Kullmann terminal objects The adjoint functor 1Computer Science, University of Wales Swansea, UK theorem http://cs.swan.ac.uk/~csoliver Reflections and coreflections The fundamental PhD Theory Seminar (Hauptseminar) examples Swansea, March 14, 2007 Topological examples Reminders Compact spaces The Cech-Stoneˇ compactification Concrete: Ultrafilters The adjoint functor Introduction theorem Oliver Kullmann Review Special morphisms Comma categories The main topic is: Universal arrows Natural transformations after a review of notions and theorems relevant to Adjoint functors Limits and colimits adjunctions Transfers via functors Finding initial and we prove the “adjoint functor theorem”, a necessary terminal objects and sufficient criterion for the existence of (left- or The adjoint functor right-) adjoints of a given functor. theorem Reflections and With this criterion the construction of adjoint functors is coreflections often considerably facilitated. The fundamental examples We will also outline main corollaries and main Topological examples applications / examples. Reminders Compact spaces The Cech-Stoneˇ compactification Concrete: Ultrafilters The adjoint functor The adjoint functor theorem theorem Oliver Kullmann Review Theorem Consider a complete category C with small Special morphisms Comma categories morphism-sets, and a functor V : C S. Universal arrows → Natural transformations Then V has a left adjoint if and only if V respects all limits Adjoint functors Limits and colimits (is “continuous”), and for every every X Obj(S) we Transfers via functors ∈ have a “solution set”, that is, a family A of objects in Finding initial and ( i )i∈I terminal objects C together with a family (fi )i∈I of morphisms The adjoint functor theorem fi : X V (Ai ) in S such that → Reflections and coreflections for all A Obj(C) and all f : X V (A) there is some i I ∈ → ∈ The fundamental together with some morphism g : A A in C with examples i → f = V (g) fi . Topological ◦ examples Reminders (Remark: For I = 1 we nearly get the condition, that A is Compact spaces The Cech-Stoneˇ | | compactification universal for X to V (uniqueness is missing).) Concrete: Ultrafilters The adjoint functor Overview theorem Oliver Kullmann Review Special morphisms 1 Review Comma categories Universal arrows Natural transformations Adjoint functors 2 Finding initial and terminal objects Limits and colimits Transfers via functors Finding initial and 3 The adjoint functor theorem terminal objects The adjoint functor theorem 4 Reflections and Reflections and coreflections coreflections The fundamental examples 5 The fundamental examples Topological examples Reminders 6 Topological examples Compact spaces The Cech-Stoneˇ compactification Concrete: Ultrafilters The adjoint functor Cancellation and inversion theorem Oliver Kullmann Consider a category C and a morphism f in C: Review Regarding cancellation: Special morphisms Comma categories f is a monomorphism if f is left-cancellable. Universal arrows f is an epimorphism if f is right-cancellable. Natural transformations Adjoint functors Regarding invertibility: Limits and colimits Transfers via functors f is a coretraction if f is left-invertible. Finding initial and f is a retraction if f is right-invertible. terminal objects The adjoint functor It follows, that f is an isomorphism iff f is a theorem retraction and a coretraction. Reflections and coreflections Necessary conditions for cancellability: The fundamental Every coretraction is a monomorphism examples Topological Every retraction is an epimorphism. examples The following conditions are equivalent: Reminders Compact spaces The Cech-Stoneˇ f is an isomorphism. compactification f is a monomorphism and a retraction. Concrete: Ultrafilters f is an epimorphism and a coretraction. The adjoint functor Bimorphisms theorem Oliver Kullmann A morphism is called a bimorphism if it is a Review Special morphisms monomorphism and an epimorphism. Comma categories Universal arrows Every isomorphism is a bimorphism. Natural transformations Adjoint functors Limits and colimits A category is called balanced if every bimorphism is an Transfers via functors isomorphism. Finding initial and terminal objects In a balanced concrete category, the isomorphisms The adjoint functor are exactly the bijections. theorem Reflections and A concrete category, where every bijection is an coreflections isomorphism, does not need to be balanced, as The fundamental examples MON shows (the canonical injection Topological j :(Z, , 1) (Q, , 1) is a bimorphism). examples · → · Reminders (The category of groups, on the other hand, is balanced.) Compact spaces The Cech-Stoneˇ compactification If V : C S is faithful, and C is balanced, then V is discrete Concrete: Ultrafilters → (i.e., the fibres of V are discrete orders). The adjoint functor Equalisers and coequalisers theorem Oliver Kullmann Consider two morphisms f , g : X Y . → Review Special morphisms α : E X is an equaliser for f , g if f α = g α, and Comma categories → ◦ ◦ Universal arrows for every α′ : E′ X with f α′ = g β′ there is a → ◦ ◦ Natural transformations unique β : E′ E with α′ = α β. Adjoint functors → ◦ Limits and colimits α : Y C is an coequaliser for f , g if α f = α g, Transfers via functors → ′ ′ ′ ◦ ◦ Finding initial and and for every α : Y C with α f = α g there is terminal objects ′→ ′ ◦ ◦ a unique β : E E with α = β α. The adjoint functor → ◦ theorem We have Reflections and coreflections 1 Every equaliser is a monomorphism. The fundamental examples 2 Every coequaliser is an epimorphism. Topological To see this, let α be an equaliser of f , g, and consider examples Reminders ϕ,ψ with α ϕ = α ψ. Trivially f (αϕ)= g(αϕ), and the Compact spaces ◦ ◦ The Cech-Stoneˇ (unique(!)) β with αβ = αϕ is β = ϕ. Now αψ = αϕ, and compactification Concrete: Ultrafilters thus ψ = β = ϕ. √ The adjoint functor Upon an object theorem Let V : C S be a functor, and X Obj(S). The Oliver Kullmann → ∈ comma-category (X ↓ V ) has Review Special morphisms objects (C,α) where C Obj(C) and α : X V (C); Comma categories ∈ → Universal arrows morphisms from (C,α) to (D,β) are f : C D with Natural transformations → Adjoint functors commuting Limits and colimits V (f ) Transfers via functors V (C) / V (D) bDD z< Finding initial and DDα β zz terminal objects DD zz DD zz The adjoint functor z theorem X Reflections and identities and composition as in C; check the coreflections commutativity of The fundamental examples V (idC ) V (f ) V (g) Topological V (C) / V (C) , V (C) / V (D) / V (E) aCC {= bFF O x< examples CCα α {{ FFα γ xx Reminders C { F β x Compact spaces CC {{ F x C { FF xx The Cech-Stoneˇ { x compactification X X Concrete: Ultrafilters So (X V ) is a concrete category over C via the ↓ projection P :(X V ) C, P((C,α)) := C. ↓ → The adjoint functor The other side (into an object) theorem The comma-category (V ↓ X) has Oliver Kullmann Review objects (C,α) where C Obj(C) and α : V (C) X; Special morphisms ∈ → Comma categories morphisms from (C,α) to (D,β) are f : C D with Universal arrows → Natural transformations commuting Adjoint functors V (f ) Limits and colimits V (C) / V (D) Transfers via functors DD z DD zz Finding initial and α DD zz terminal objects DD zz β " |z The adjoint functor X theorem Reflections and identities and composition as in C; check the coreflections commutativity of The fundamental examples V (idC ) V (f ) V (g) V (C) / V (C) , V (C) / V (D) / V (E) Topological CC { FF x examples CC { F x C {{ F β x Reminders α C { α α FF xxγ CC {{ FF xx Compact spaces ! }{ " |x The Cech-Stoneˇ X X compactification Concrete: Ultrafilters So (V X) is a concrete category over C via the ↓ projection P :(X V ) C, P((C,α)) := C. ↓ → The adjoint functor Universality via commas theorem Let V : C S be a functor, and X Obj(S). Oliver Kullmann → ∈ Review A universal arrow from X to V is an initial object of Special morphisms Comma categories (X V ). Universal arrows ↓ Natural transformations A universal arrow from V to X is a terminal object of Adjoint functors Limits and colimits (V X). Transfers via functors ↓ In [Borceux] the terminology “(co)reflection of X along V ” is used; universal Finding initial and terminal objects constructions were (under the above name) made well-known in the 1950s, The adjoint functor and since then they carried this name. theorem Reflections and The definitions carried out: coreflections The fundamental A universal arrow from X to V is a pair (C,α) with examples C Obj(C) and α : X V (C) such that for every Topological ∈ → examples (D,β) there is a unique f : C D with β = V (f ) α. Reminders → ◦ Compact spaces The Cech-Stoneˇ A universal arrow from V to X is a pair (C,β) with compactification C Obj(C) and β : V (C) X such that for every Concrete: Ultrafilters ∈ → (D,α) there is a unique f : C D with α = β V (f ). → ◦ The adjoint functor Functorial morphisms theorem Given functors F, G : C D,a natural transformation Oliver Kullmann → η : F G is a family η =(ηX )X∈Obj(C) with Review → Special morphisms ηX : F(X) G(X) such that for all objects A, B in C and Comma categories → Universal arrows morphisms f : A B the following diagram commutes: Natural transformations → Adjoint functors Limits and colimits G(f ) G(A) / G(B) Transfers via functors O O Finding initial and terminal objects ηA ηB The adjoint functor F(f ) theorem F(A) / F(B) Reflections and coreflections Natural transformations η : F G are morphisms The fundamental → examples between functors; the “vertical composition” of Topological natural transformations yields the category examples Reminders FUN(C, D) of functors from C to D.
Recommended publications
  • Types Are Internal Infinity-Groupoids Antoine Allioux, Eric Finster, Matthieu Sozeau
    Types are internal infinity-groupoids Antoine Allioux, Eric Finster, Matthieu Sozeau To cite this version: Antoine Allioux, Eric Finster, Matthieu Sozeau. Types are internal infinity-groupoids. 2021. hal- 03133144 HAL Id: hal-03133144 https://hal.inria.fr/hal-03133144 Preprint submitted on 5 Feb 2021 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Types are Internal 1-groupoids Antoine Allioux∗, Eric Finstery, Matthieu Sozeauz ∗Inria & University of Paris, France [email protected] yUniversity of Birmingham, United Kingdom ericfi[email protected] zInria, France [email protected] Abstract—By extending type theory with a universe of defini- attempts to import these ideas into plain homotopy type theory tionally associative and unital polynomial monads, we show how have, so far, failed. This appears to be a result of a kind of to arrive at a definition of opetopic type which is able to encode circularity: all of the known classical techniques at some point a number of fully coherent algebraic structures. In particular, our approach leads to a definition of 1-groupoid internal to rely on set-level algebraic structures themselves (presheaves, type theory and we prove that the type of such 1-groupoids is operads, or something similar) as a means of presenting or equivalent to the universe of types.
    [Show full text]
  • Category Theory for Autonomous and Networked Dynamical Systems
    Discussion Category Theory for Autonomous and Networked Dynamical Systems Jean-Charles Delvenne Institute of Information and Communication Technologies, Electronics and Applied Mathematics (ICTEAM) and Center for Operations Research and Econometrics (CORE), Université catholique de Louvain, 1348 Louvain-la-Neuve, Belgium; [email protected] Received: 7 February 2019; Accepted: 18 March 2019; Published: 20 March 2019 Abstract: In this discussion paper we argue that category theory may play a useful role in formulating, and perhaps proving, results in ergodic theory, topogical dynamics and open systems theory (control theory). As examples, we show how to characterize Kolmogorov–Sinai, Shannon entropy and topological entropy as the unique functors to the nonnegative reals satisfying some natural conditions. We also provide a purely categorical proof of the existence of the maximal equicontinuous factor in topological dynamics. We then show how to define open systems (that can interact with their environment), interconnect them, and define control problems for them in a unified way. Keywords: ergodic theory; topological dynamics; control theory 1. Introduction The theory of autonomous dynamical systems has developed in different flavours according to which structure is assumed on the state space—with topological dynamics (studying continuous maps on topological spaces) and ergodic theory (studying probability measures invariant under the map) as two prominent examples. These theories have followed parallel tracks and built multiple bridges. For example, both have grown successful tools from the interaction with information theory soon after its emergence, around the key invariants, namely the topological entropy and metric entropy, which are themselves linked by a variational theorem. The situation is more complex and heterogeneous in the field of what we here call open dynamical systems, or controlled dynamical systems.
    [Show full text]
  • A Category-Theoretic Approach to Representation and Analysis of Inconsistency in Graph-Based Viewpoints
    A Category-Theoretic Approach to Representation and Analysis of Inconsistency in Graph-Based Viewpoints by Mehrdad Sabetzadeh A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Master of Science Graduate Department of Computer Science University of Toronto Copyright c 2003 by Mehrdad Sabetzadeh Abstract A Category-Theoretic Approach to Representation and Analysis of Inconsistency in Graph-Based Viewpoints Mehrdad Sabetzadeh Master of Science Graduate Department of Computer Science University of Toronto 2003 Eliciting the requirements for a proposed system typically involves different stakeholders with different expertise, responsibilities, and perspectives. This may result in inconsis- tencies between the descriptions provided by stakeholders. Viewpoints-based approaches have been proposed as a way to manage incomplete and inconsistent models gathered from multiple sources. In this thesis, we propose a category-theoretic framework for the analysis of fuzzy viewpoints. Informally, a fuzzy viewpoint is a graph in which the elements of a lattice are used to specify the amount of knowledge available about the details of nodes and edges. By defining an appropriate notion of morphism between fuzzy viewpoints, we construct categories of fuzzy viewpoints and prove that these categories are (finitely) cocomplete. We then show how colimits can be employed to merge the viewpoints and detect the inconsistencies that arise independent of any particular choice of viewpoint semantics. Taking advantage of the same category-theoretic techniques used in defining fuzzy viewpoints, we will also introduce a more general graph-based formalism that may find applications in other contexts. ii To my mother and father with love and gratitude. Acknowledgements First of all, I wish to thank my supervisor Steve Easterbrook for his guidance, support, and patience.
    [Show full text]
  • Derived Functors and Homological Dimension (Pdf)
    DERIVED FUNCTORS AND HOMOLOGICAL DIMENSION George Torres Math 221 Abstract. This paper overviews the basic notions of abelian categories, exact functors, and chain complexes. It will use these concepts to define derived functors, prove their existence, and demon- strate their relationship to homological dimension. I affirm my awareness of the standards of the Harvard College Honor Code. Date: December 15, 2015. 1 2 DERIVED FUNCTORS AND HOMOLOGICAL DIMENSION 1. Abelian Categories and Homology The concept of an abelian category will be necessary for discussing ideas on homological algebra. Loosely speaking, an abelian cagetory is a type of category that behaves like modules (R-mod) or abelian groups (Ab). We must first define a few types of morphisms that such a category must have. Definition 1.1. A morphism f : X ! Y in a category C is a zero morphism if: • for any A 2 C and any g; h : A ! X, fg = fh • for any B 2 C and any g; h : Y ! B, gf = hf We denote a zero morphism as 0XY (or sometimes just 0 if the context is sufficient). Definition 1.2. A morphism f : X ! Y is a monomorphism if it is left cancellative. That is, for all g; h : Z ! X, we have fg = fh ) g = h. An epimorphism is a morphism if it is right cancellative. The zero morphism is a generalization of the zero map on rings, or the identity homomorphism on groups. Monomorphisms and epimorphisms are generalizations of injective and surjective homomorphisms (though these definitions don't always coincide). It can be shown that a morphism is an isomorphism iff it is epic and monic.
    [Show full text]
  • N-Quasi-Abelian Categories Vs N-Tilting Torsion Pairs 3
    N-QUASI-ABELIAN CATEGORIES VS N-TILTING TORSION PAIRS WITH AN APPLICATION TO FLOPS OF HIGHER RELATIVE DIMENSION LUISA FIOROT Abstract. It is a well established fact that the notions of quasi-abelian cate- gories and tilting torsion pairs are equivalent. This equivalence fits in a wider picture including tilting pairs of t-structures. Firstly, we extend this picture into a hierarchy of n-quasi-abelian categories and n-tilting torsion classes. We prove that any n-quasi-abelian category E admits a “derived” category D(E) endowed with a n-tilting pair of t-structures such that the respective hearts are derived equivalent. Secondly, we describe the hearts of these t-structures as quotient categories of coherent functors, generalizing Auslander’s Formula. Thirdly, we apply our results to Bridgeland’s theory of perverse coherent sheaves for flop contractions. In Bridgeland’s work, the relative dimension 1 assumption guaranteed that f∗-acyclic coherent sheaves form a 1-tilting torsion class, whose associated heart is derived equivalent to D(Y ). We generalize this theorem to relative dimension 2. Contents Introduction 1 1. 1-tilting torsion classes 3 2. n-Tilting Theorem 7 3. 2-tilting torsion classes 9 4. Effaceable functors 14 5. n-coherent categories 17 6. n-tilting torsion classes for n> 2 18 7. Perverse coherent sheaves 28 8. Comparison between n-abelian and n + 1-quasi-abelian categories 32 Appendix A. Maximal Quillen exact structure 33 Appendix B. Freyd categories and coherent functors 34 Appendix C. t-structures 37 References 39 arXiv:1602.08253v3 [math.RT] 28 Dec 2019 Introduction In [6, 3.3.1] Beilinson, Bernstein and Deligne introduced the notion of a t- structure obtained by tilting the natural one on D(A) (derived category of an abelian category A) with respect to a torsion pair (X , Y).
    [Show full text]
  • Limits Commutative Algebra May 11 2020 1. Direct Limits Definition 1
    Limits Commutative Algebra May 11 2020 1. Direct Limits Definition 1: A directed set I is a set with a partial order ≤ such that for every i; j 2 I there is k 2 I such that i ≤ k and j ≤ k. Let R be a ring. A directed system of R-modules indexed by I is a collection of R modules fMi j i 2 Ig with a R module homomorphisms µi;j : Mi ! Mj for each pair i; j 2 I where i ≤ j, such that (i) for any i 2 I, µi;i = IdMi and (ii) for any i ≤ j ≤ k in I, µi;j ◦ µj;k = µi;k. We shall denote a directed system by a tuple (Mi; µi;j). The direct limit of a directed system is defined using a universal property. It exists and is unique up to a unique isomorphism. Theorem 2 (Direct limits). Let fMi j i 2 Ig be a directed system of R modules then there exists an R module M with the following properties: (i) There are R module homomorphisms µi : Mi ! M for each i 2 I, satisfying µi = µj ◦ µi;j whenever i < j. (ii) If there is an R module N such that there are R module homomorphisms νi : Mi ! N for each i and νi = νj ◦µi;j whenever i < j; then there exists a unique R module homomorphism ν : M ! N, such that νi = ν ◦ µi. The module M is unique in the sense that if there is any other R module M 0 satisfying properties (i) and (ii) then there is a unique R module isomorphism µ0 : M ! M 0.
    [Show full text]
  • Comparison of Waldhausen Constructions
    COMPARISON OF WALDHAUSEN CONSTRUCTIONS JULIA E. BERGNER, ANGELICA´ M. OSORNO, VIKTORIYA OZORNOVA, MARTINA ROVELLI, AND CLAUDIA I. SCHEIMBAUER Dedicated to the memory of Thomas Poguntke Abstract. In previous work, we develop a generalized Waldhausen S•- construction whose input is an augmented stable double Segal space and whose output is a 2-Segal space. Here, we prove that this construc- tion recovers the previously known S•-constructions for exact categories and for stable and exact (∞, 1)-categories, as well as the relative S•- construction for exact functors. Contents Introduction 2 1. Augmented stable double Segal objects 3 2. The S•-construction for exact categories 7 3. The S•-construction for stable (∞, 1)-categories 17 4. The S•-construction for proto-exact (∞, 1)-categories 23 5. The relative S•-construction 26 Appendix: Some results on quasi-categories 33 References 38 Date: May 29, 2020. 2010 Mathematics Subject Classification. 55U10, 55U35, 55U40, 18D05, 18G55, 18G30, arXiv:1901.03606v2 [math.AT] 28 May 2020 19D10. Key words and phrases. 2-Segal spaces, Waldhausen S•-construction, double Segal spaces, model categories. The first-named author was partially supported by NSF CAREER award DMS- 1659931. The second-named author was partially supported by a grant from the Simons Foundation (#359449, Ang´elica Osorno), the Woodrow Wilson Career Enhancement Fel- lowship and NSF grant DMS-1709302. The fourth-named and fifth-named authors were partially funded by the Swiss National Science Foundation, grants P2ELP2 172086 and P300P2 164652. The fifth-named author was partially funded by the Bergen Research Foundation and would like to thank the University of Oxford for its hospitality.
    [Show full text]
  • A Few Points in Topos Theory
    A few points in topos theory Sam Zoghaib∗ Abstract This paper deals with two problems in topos theory; the construction of finite pseudo-limits and pseudo-colimits in appropriate sub-2-categories of the 2-category of toposes, and the definition and construction of the fundamental groupoid of a topos, in the context of the Galois theory of coverings; we will take results on the fundamental group of étale coverings in [1] as a starting example for the latter. We work in the more general context of bounded toposes over Set (instead of starting with an effec- tive descent morphism of schemes). Questions regarding the existence of limits and colimits of diagram of toposes arise while studying this prob- lem, but their general relevance makes it worth to study them separately. We expose mainly known constructions, but give some new insight on the assumptions and work out an explicit description of a functor in a coequalizer diagram which was as far as the author is aware unknown, which we believe can be generalised. This is essentially an overview of study and research conducted at dpmms, University of Cambridge, Great Britain, between March and Au- gust 2006, under the supervision of Martin Hyland. Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 General knowledge 3 3 On (co)limits of toposes 6 3.1 The construction of finite limits in BTop/S ............ 7 3.2 The construction of finite colimits in BTop/S ........... 9 4 The fundamental groupoid of a topos 12 4.1 The fundamental group of an atomic topos with a point . 13 4.2 The fundamental groupoid of an unpointed locally connected topos 15 5 Conclusion and future work 17 References 17 ∗e-mail: [email protected] 1 1 Introduction Toposes were first conceived ([2]) as kinds of “generalised spaces” which could serve as frameworks for cohomology theories; that is, mapping topological or geometrical invariants with an algebraic structure to topological spaces.
    [Show full text]
  • A Small Complete Category
    Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 40 (1988) 135-165 135 North-Holland A SMALL COMPLETE CATEGORY J.M.E. HYLAND Department of Pure Mathematics and Mathematical Statktics, 16 Mill Lane, Cambridge CB2 ISB, England Communicated by D. van Dalen Received 14 October 1987 0. Introduction This paper is concerned with a remarkable fact. The effective topos contains a small complete subcategory, essentially the familiar category of partial equiv- alence realtions. This is in contrast to the category of sets (indeed to all Grothendieck toposes) where any small complete category is equivalent to a (complete) poset. Note at once that the phrase ‘a small complete subcategory of a topos’ is misleading. It is not the subcategory but the internal (small) category which matters. Indeed for any ordinary subcategory of a topos there may be a number of internal categories with global sections equivalent to the given subcategory. The appropriate notion of subcategory is an indexed (or better fibred) one, see 0.1. Another point that needs attention is the definition of completeness (see 0.2). In my talk at the Church’s Thesis meeting, and in the first draft of this paper, I claimed too strong a form of completeness for the internal category. (The elementary oversight is described in 2.7.) Fortunately during the writing of [13] my collaborators Edmund Robinson and Giuseppe Rosolini noticed the mistake. Again one needs to pay careful attention to the ideas of indexed (or fibred) categories. The idea that small (sufficiently) complete categories in toposes might exist, and would provide the right setting in which to discuss models for strong polymorphism (quantification over types), was suggested to me by Eugenio Moggi.
    [Show full text]
  • Homotopical Categories: from Model Categories to ( ,)-Categories ∞
    HOMOTOPICAL CATEGORIES: FROM MODEL CATEGORIES TO ( ;1)-CATEGORIES 1 EMILY RIEHL Abstract. This chapter, written for Stable categories and structured ring spectra, edited by Andrew J. Blumberg, Teena Gerhardt, and Michael A. Hill, surveys the history of homotopical categories, from Gabriel and Zisman’s categories of frac- tions to Quillen’s model categories, through Dwyer and Kan’s simplicial localiza- tions and culminating in ( ;1)-categories, first introduced through concrete mod- 1 els and later re-conceptualized in a model-independent framework. This reader is not presumed to have prior acquaintance with any of these concepts. Suggested exercises are included to fertilize intuitions and copious references point to exter- nal sources with more details. A running theme of homotopy limits and colimits is included to explain the kinds of problems homotopical categories are designed to solve as well as technical approaches to these problems. Contents 1. The history of homotopical categories 2 2. Categories of fractions and localization 5 2.1. The Gabriel–Zisman category of fractions 5 3. Model category presentations of homotopical categories 7 3.1. Model category structures via weak factorization systems 8 3.2. On functoriality of factorizations 12 3.3. The homotopy relation on arrows 13 3.4. The homotopy category of a model category 17 3.5. Quillen’s model structure on simplicial sets 19 4. Derived functors between model categories 20 4.1. Derived functors and equivalence of homotopy theories 21 4.2. Quillen functors 24 4.3. Derived composites and derived adjunctions 25 4.4. Monoidal and enriched model categories 27 4.5.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Category Theory (Notes for Course Taught at HUJI, Fall 2020-2021) (UNPOLISHED DRAFT)
    Introduction to category theory (notes for course taught at HUJI, Fall 2020-2021) (UNPOLISHED DRAFT) Alexander Yom Din February 10, 2021 It is never true that two substances are entirely alike, differing only in being two rather than one1. G. W. Leibniz, Discourse on metaphysics 1This can be imagined to be related to at least two of our themes: the imperative of considering a contractible groupoid of objects as an one single object, and also the ideology around Yoneda's lemma ("no two different things have all their properties being exactly the same"). 1 Contents 1 The basic language 3 1.1 Categories . .3 1.2 Functors . .7 1.3 Natural transformations . .9 2 Equivalence of categories 11 2.1 Contractible groupoids . 11 2.2 Fibers . 12 2.3 Fibers and fully faithfulness . 12 2.4 A lemma on fully faithfulness in families . 13 2.5 Definition of equivalence of categories . 14 2.6 Simple examples of equivalence of categories . 17 2.7 Theory of the fundamental groupoid and covering spaces . 18 2.8 Affine algebraic varieties . 23 2.9 The Gelfand transform . 26 2.10 Galois theory . 27 3 Yoneda's lemma, representing objects, limits 27 3.1 Yoneda's lemma . 27 3.2 Representing objects . 29 3.3 The definition of a limit . 33 3.4 Examples of limits . 34 3.5 Dualizing everything . 39 3.6 Examples of colimits . 39 3.7 General colimits in terms of special ones . 41 4 Adjoint functors 42 4.1 Bifunctors . 42 4.2 The definition of adjoint functors . 43 4.3 Some examples of adjoint functors .
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1005.0156V3
    FOUR PROBLEMS REGARDING REPRESENTABLE FUNCTORS G. MILITARU C Abstract. Let R, S be two rings, C an R-coring and RM the category of left C- C C comodules. The category Rep (RM, SM) of all representable functors RM→ S M is C shown to be equivalent to the opposite of the category RMS . For U an (S, R)-bimodule C we give necessary and sufficient conditions for the induction functor U ⊗R − : RM→ SM to be: a representable functor, an equivalence of categories, a separable or a Frobenius functor. The latter results generalize and unify the classical theorems of Morita for categories of modules over rings and the more recent theorems obtained by Brezinski, Caenepeel et al. for categories of comodules over corings. Introduction Let C be a category and V a variety of algebras in the sense of universal algebras. A functor F : C →V is called representable [1] if γ ◦ F : C → Set is representable in the classical sense, where γ : V → Set is the forgetful functor. Four general problems concerning representable functors have been identified: Problem A: Describe the category Rep (C, V) of all representable functors F : C→V. Problem B: Give a necessary and sufficient condition for a given functor F : C→V to be representable (possibly predefining the object of representability). Problem C: When is a composition of two representable functors a representable functor? Problem D: Give a necessary and sufficient condition for a representable functor F : C → V and for its left adjoint to be separable or Frobenius. The pioneer of studying problem A was Kan [10] who described all representable functors from semigroups to semigroups.
    [Show full text]