Carnap and Twentieth-Century Thought: Explication As Enlightenment A

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Carnap and Twentieth-Century Thought: Explication As Enlightenment A Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-86227-1 - Carnap and Twentieth-Century Thought: Explication as Enlightenment A. W. Carus Index More information Index Abbe, Ernst 45 Boltzmann, Ludwig 68, 144 Adickes, Erich 70, 90 Bolzano, Bernard 130 Adorno, Theodor W., see Horkheimer, Max Bourbaki 226 Akademische Freischar 51–2, 57, 59 Brouwer, L. E. J. 163, 208, 223, 236, 256 d’Alembert, Jean Le Rond ix, 1, 8, 75, Buffon, Georges-Louis LeClerc, Comte de 75 85, 93 Buhler,¨ Karl 240, 243 analytic philosophy 5–6 Burge, Tyler 7 Anaximander 141 Aristotle 8, 74, 75, 93, 94, 101, 174, 272 Carnap, Agnes 43, 46 artificial languages, see constructed languages Carnap, Anna Dorpfeld¨ 41, 43–9 Aufbau, see Carnap, published works (1928a) Carnap, Ina 39, 44 Aufbau project 39, 106–8, 123, 126, 130, 139–41, Carnap, Johann Sebulon 43, 46–8 144, 148–9, 155, 160, 161, 166–77, 181–4, Carnap, Rudolf 199–202, 209–18 autobiography, see published works (1963), Austin, John L. 28, 291 unpublished documents (1957a) Avenarius, Richard 73, 74 convention, attitude towards 42, 44–5, 55 Awodey, Steve xii, 102, 188, 192, 195, 196, 222, ethical values 49–50, 123 230, 235, 251, 271 father’s family (Carnap) 47–8 Ayer, A. J. 7, 8, 34, 35 Metalogik (first draft of Syntax) 250–1, 253, 259 Bachelard, Gaston 274 mother’s family (Dorpfeld)¨ 41–3, 46, 48–9 Bacon, Francis 8, 93 political views, development of 57–63, 156 Bain, Alexander 125 published works Bar-Hillel, Yehoshua 248, 250 1922 (Der Raum) 63, 104, 110, 112, 115, Bauch, Bruno 106, 108, 109, 113 127–31, 138, 145, 152, 154, 162, 171, 185 Bauer, Helene 241 1923 (Aufgabe der Physik) 105, 120–1, 134–5, Bauhaus 32, 123, 204, 206, 218–20 136, 162 Bayesianism 39 1924 (‘Dreidimensionalitat¨ und Kausalitat’)¨ Behmann, Heinrich 157 126, 148–52, 153, 162, 170–1 Bergisches Land (region of Rhineland) 47–8 1926 (Physikalische Begriffsbildung) 165, 172, Bergson, Henri 107 177–81, 212–13, 219, 220 Berkeley, George 71, 77 1927 (‘Eigentliche und Uneigentliche Berlin, Isaiah 34 Begriffe’) 192–5 Beth, Evert 250, 267, 291 1928a(Aufbau) 4, 13–15, 34, 39, 63, 97, Bildung 41, 45, 49, 50, 65, 158 106–8, 126, 129, 144–5, 156, 157–8, Bildungsideal 41–2, 64 167–73, 177, 178, 184, 186, 194, 195, 198, Bird, Graham 70, 90 199, 202, 205, 206, 212, 213, 221, 240, Bittel, Karl 59, 61 243–5, 287–9 Bloor, David 30 1928b(Scheinprobleme) 15, 158, 201, 204, Bluher,¨ Hans 53–5, 59 216, 221, 285 Bohnert, Herbert 38 1929 (Abriß) 156 340 © Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-86227-1 - Carnap and Twentieth-Century Thought: Explication as Enlightenment A. W. Carus Index More information Index 341 1930a (‘Alteund neueLogik’) 189 ASP 1922b (Letter to Scholz) 157, 158–9, 1932b (‘DiephysikalischeSprache’) 35, 245, 161–2 252, 253, 255 ASP 1922c, 1922d, 1923b (Erlangen papers) 1932c (‘Psychologie’) 240, 252 130, 156, 162–3, 165 1932e(‘ Uber¨ Protokollsatze’)¨ 168, 244, 253, ASP 1923a (‘Die Quasizerlegung’) 162 254–5 ASP 1923d (Letter to Scholz) 159 1934a(Syntax) xi, 18–19, 34–7, 63, 64, ASP 1925a, 1925b (‘Gedanken zum 202, 207, 225, 238, 246, 247, 249, 250–1, Kategorienproblem’) 168–9, 174 254, 255–6, 258, 261–3, 266, 274, 276, ASP 1927a(Allgemeine Axiomatik) 193, 285 194–5, 196, 222–3, 226–7, 229 1934b (‘Character of Philosophical ASP 1928b (Letter to Russell) 4 Problems’) 249, 261 ASP 1928c (Letter to Neurath) 240 1934c(Aufgabe der Wissenschaftslogik) 248, ASP 1929a (‘Neue Grundlegung der Logik’) 249 196, 197, 198, 200, 202–3, 205–7, 218, 1935a(Philosophy and Logical Syntax) 158, 225, 227, 230, 231, 236 263 ASP 1929c (‘Von Gott und Seele’) 181–2, 1935b (Popper review) 254 183, 219, 240, 287 1936–7 (‘Testability and Meaning’) ix, 35, ASP 1929b (Feigl’s ideas for Prague) 220–1 172, 202, 205–6, 249–50 ASP 1929d–g (Bauhaus lectures) 204, 1942 (Introduction to Semantics) 36, 247–8, 218–20 263 ASP 1930c (‘Materielle Basis’) 241 1945 (‘Two Concepts of Probability’) 256 ASP 1930e (‘Einheitswissenschaft’) 241 1947 (Meaning and Necessity) 63, 267 ASP 1930f(Buhler¨ talk) 240, 241 1950a (‘Empiricism, Semantics, and ASP 1930h (Warsaw lecture) 198, 204 Ontology’) 263, 288 ASP 1930i, 1931d, g, h, k, l, n (Vienna 1950b(Logical Foundations of Probability) Circleminutes) 190, 209, 227–8, 236–40, 21, 38, 63, 256 244, 246–7 1956 (‘Theoretical Concepts’) 172 ASP 1931a, b (Munich lecture) 244, 245 1961 (Introduction to reprint of Aufbau) ASP 1931e(‘Diskussion zum 169, 172, 199, 287 Physikalismus’) 244 1963 (Schilpp volume) 36, 123, 186–7, 188, ASP 1931j (‘Zur phanomenalen¨ Sprache’) 220, 230, 232–3, 241–2, 248, 250, 253, ASP 1931m (Diary) 233–4 264–6, 291 ASP 1932b (Copenhagen lecture) 261 1966 (Gardner book) 94, 95, 180 ASP 1932d(Metalogik Tableof Contents) religious views, development of 46–9 206, 250–1 unpublished documents ASP 1933a (German original of 1934b) 261 ASP 1908a (Diary) 16 ASP 1933b (Composition of Syntax) 263 ASP 1918c (‘Deutschlands Niederlage’) ASP 1934a (‘Philosophie’) 242 59–63, 155, 156 ASP 1934b (Class lecture notes) 120 ASP 1920b (‘Axiomatik der ASP 1936a (‘Unity of Science’) 278 Raum-Zeit-Welt’) 194 ASP 1938a (‘Testability and Meaning’) ASP 1920c (‘Skelett der Erkenntnistheorie’) 250 139 ASP 1954a (Sellars discussion) 124 ASP 1920d (Letter to Sera friends) 91–2, 104 ASP 1956a (Notes on Bar-Hillel’s Schilpp ASP 1921a (‘Analyse des Weltbildes’) 126, paper) 276 139–40, 141 ASP/HD 1920a (Letter to Dingler) 122, ASP 1921c (First draft of 1923) 120–1, 124, 123 136 ASP/HD 1921a (Dingler Review) 119 ASP 1921d(‘UberdieAnalysevon¨ ASP/RR 1930a(Buhler¨ talk) 240, 253 Erlebnissen’) 140, 146 ASP/WF 1916b (Letter to Flitner) 94–5 ASP 1921e (Letter to Russell) 131 ASP/WF 1916c (Letter to Flitner) 91 ASP 1921f (Letter to Flitner) 91 CK 1929a, 1930a (Letters to Kaila) 199–201, ASP 1922a (‘Vom Chaos zur Wirklichkeit’) 214 108, 146, 148–51, 153, 156, 157, 162, 166, UCLA 1919a (Fachwissenschaftliche 168–74, 176, 177, 185, 203, 210 Hausarbeit) 104–5 © Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-86227-1 - Carnap and Twentieth-Century Thought: Explication as Enlightenment A. W. Carus Index More information 342 Index Carnap, Rudolf (cont.) ‘dialectic of enlightenment’, see Horkheimer, UCLA 1920a (Dissertation on Geometry) Max 97–8, 101–2, 104, 109–15, 118–19, 121, 127, Diderot, Denis ix, 1, 75 128, 129, 133, 134, 135, 137–8, 140, 154 Diederichs, Eugen 54–5 UCLA 1928a, 1929c-f, 1930b (Kaila papers) Dilthey, Wilhelm 13, 123 196, 197, 204–5, 209–18 Dingler, Hugo 119–23, 221 UCLA 1929a (Berlin lecture) 197–8, 201, DiSalle, Robert 78, 271 206 Dorpfeld,¨ Friedrich Wilhelm 41, 42–3, 47–9 UCLA 1930a (Notes on Feigl conversation) Dorpfeld,¨ Wilhelm 46 166–7, 168 Driesch, Hans 107, 129–30, 131, 146, 174 UCLA 1931b (‘Versuch einer Metalogik’) Dubois-Reymond, Emil 66, 67, 89, 175 229–34, 237, 238 Duhring,¨ Eugen 92 UCLA 1931d–j (‘Sprache der Wissenschaft’) Duhem, Pierre 220 230, 231, 234–6, 239, 249 Dummett, Michael 26, 101, 102, 188 UCLA 1931k–q (‘Grundlegung der Duncker, Karl 252 Mathematik’) 236–9 Durkheim, Emile´ 27 UCLA 1957a, b (Original autobiography) 43–50, 55–6, 58, 109, 119, 141, 144 Earman, John 283, 287–9 wartime experience (1914–18) xi, 56–61, 91, Einstein, Albert 26, 64, 94, 109, 120 94 Elias, Norbert 41 Carnap Thost, Hanna 37, 50 Encyclop´edie x, 1, 9, 10–11, 16, 27, 68, 69, 73–5, Cassirer, Ernst 13, 70, 76, 77, 82–3, 84, 86, 88, 93, 161 90, 92, 98–100, 105–7, 116, 144, 146, 159, energeticism 67–8 196, 211, 243 Enlightenment ix, x, 1–5, 8–13, 14, 16–19, 23, 24, Chomsky, Noam 248, 268 27, 29, 31, 37, 40, 43, 63, 68–9, 73–5, 81, Christiansen, Broder 173 275, 292–309 clarification, see explication Erdmann, Benno 73 classicism, German 3, 4, 48–50, 106 Erlangen conference (March 1923) 156–60, 162, Cohen, Hermann 65, 76, 77, 81–3, 85, 89, 99, 164 100, 106, 108, 120, 122 Esperanto 16 communicativereason, see reason evolved languages x–xi, 14–15, 16, 21, 24, 28–9, Comte, Auguste 4, 8, 12–15, 42, 63, 68, 93, 161 189, 236–41, 248, 250, 258, 259, 263–6, Condorcet, Marie-Jean-Antoine-Nicolas Caritat, 273–7, 284, 285–7, 290–2 Marquis de 14, 42 explication xi, 20–1, 32, 37–9, 105, 115, 247, 248, conceptual engineering 17, 20, 21–2, 29, 31, 256, 263–6, 267, 272, 273, 276–84, 241–4, 249, 265–71 290–2 convention 44–5, 115–18, 119, 121, 125–7 clarification 20, 164–5, 166, 178–9, 260, 278 constructed languages x–xi, 14–15, 21, 116–17, explicandum 20, 165, 259, 266, 269, 278, 279, 236–41, 263–6, 273–84, 290–2 281, 285–7 Couturat, Louis 64, 92, 97, 135 explicatum 20–1, 165, 266, 279, 281, 285–7 Creath, Richard xi, 25, 39 external concepts, see internal and external Czapski, Siegfried 45 concepts Dahms, Hans-Joachim 18 FBI, spying on Carnap 36 Darwin, Charles 125 Fechner, Gustav Theodor 49 Davos (EuropaischeHochschultage,¨ Feigl, Herbert 34, 39, 166, 169, 201, 220, 221, February–March 1929) 159, 196 253–4, 289–90 Dedekind, Richard 66, 70, 89, 90, 195 Feynman, Richard 270 Descartes, Rene´ 17, 74, 75, 84 Fichte, Johann Gottlieb 42, 53, 72, 75 Dewey, John 267 ‘first philosophy’ 74–5, 76 dialectic Fischer, Karl 51 in the sense of Hegel 19 Flitner, Wilhelm 45, 56, 95–7, 123, 126, 141 in thesenseofPlato 19 Foucault, Michel 18 in thesenseofStein 19, 20, 23, 278, 279–80, Frank, Philipp 34, 67, 176–7 284 Franklin, Allan 283 © Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-86227-1 - Carnap and Twentieth-Century Thought: Explication as Enlightenment A.
Recommended publications
  • Philosophy of Science -----Paulk
    PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE -----PAULK. FEYERABEND----- However, it has also a quite decisive role in building the new science and in defending new theories against their well-entrenched predecessors. For example, this philosophy plays a most important part in the arguments about the Copernican system, in the development of optics, and in the Philosophy ofScience: A Subject with construction of a new and non-Aristotelian dynamics. Almost every work of Galileo is a mixture of philosophical, mathematical, and physical prin~ a Great Past ciples which collaborate intimately without giving the impression of in­ coherence. This is the heroic time of the scientific philosophy. The new philosophy is not content just to mirror a science that develops independ­ ently of it; nor is it so distant as to deal just with alternative philosophies. It plays an essential role in building up the new science that was to replace 1. While it should be possible, in a free society, to introduce, to ex­ the earlier doctrines.1 pound, to make propaganda for any subject, however absurd and however 3. Now it is interesting to see how this active and critical philosophy is immoral, to publish books and articles, to give lectures on any topic, it gradually replaced by a more conservative creed, how the new creed gener­ must also be possible to examine what is being expounded by reference, ates technical problems of its own which are in no way related to specific not to the internal standards of the subject (which may be but the method scientific problems (Hurne), and how there arises a special subject that according to which a particular madness is being pursued), but to stan­ codifies science without acting back on it (Kant).
    [Show full text]
  • Mach, Einstein, and the Search for Reality
    Mach, Einstein, and the Search for Reality The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Holton, Gerald. 1968. Mach, Einstein, and the Search for Reality. Daedalus 97 (2), Historical Population Studies (Spring, 1968): 636-673 Published Version https://www.jstor.org/stable/20023833 Citable link http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:37902464 Terms of Use This article was downloaded from Harvard University’s DASH repository, and is made available under the terms and conditions applicable to Other Posted Material, as set forth at http:// nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of- use#LAA ANTICIPATIONS GERALD HOLTON Mach, Einstein, and the Search for Reality In the history of ideas of our century, there is a chapter that might be entitled "The Philosophical Pilgrimage of Albert Einstein," a pilgrimage from a philosophy of science in which sensationism and empiricism were at the center, to one in which the basis was a rational realism. This essay, a portion of a more extensive study,1 is concerned with Einstein's gradual philosophical reorientation, particularly as it has become discernible during the work on his largely unpublished scientific correspondence.2 The earliest known letter by Einstein takes us right into the middle of the case. It is dated 19 March 1901 and addressed to Wilhelm Ostwald.3 The immediate cause for Einstein's letter was his failure to receive an assistantship at the school where he had recently finished his formal studies, the Polytechnic Institute in Z?rich; he now turned to Ostwald to ask for a position at his laboratory, partly in the hope of receiving "the opportunity for further education." Einstein included a copy of his first publica tion, "Folgerungen aus den Capillarit?tserscheinungen" (Annalen d.
    [Show full text]
  • ST, Phd Masterdoc, 14.02.2016
    Bilderverbot: Adorno & the Ban on Images Sebastian Truskolaski Goldsmiths College, University of London PhD in Visual Cultures February 2016 1 Declaration: I, Sebastian Truskolaski, hereby confirm that the content of this thesis is entirely my own. Signature:_______________________________________ Date:_______________ 2 Acknowledgments: I’d like to thank my family, my supervisors and my friends who generously commented on sections of this thesis. Vielen Dank. 3 Abstract: My thesis examines the significance of Theodor W. Adorno’s recurrent reference to the Old Testament ban on making images of God: the ‘Bilderverbot’. In particular I focus on three facets of this figure that occur at prominent junctures of Adorno’s work: his ‘imageless materialism’ (Chapter One), his ‘inverse theology’ (Chapter Two) and his ‘negative aesthetics’ (Chapter Three). In each case I argue that Adorno strips the image ban of its religious associations and enlists it in the service of a broadly Marxian critique of capitalist modernity. The ban on picturing the absolute is rendered as a ban on pre-determining a future in which all historical antagonisms are reconciled. As Adorno argues, only an unflinching criticism of the present can throw into relief the contours of an ‘imageless’ Utopia. I approach Adorno’s writings with a view to his sources, many of which contain notable references to the image ban that span the history of modern German thought. They include: Marx and Lukács, Benjamin and Bloch, Kant and Hegel, as well as Hölderlin, Kafka and Schoenberg. By emphasising these elective affinities, I aim to shed light on Adorno’s singular application of the figure of the image ban to his critical project.
    [Show full text]
  • Passmore, J. (1967). Logical Positivism. in P. Edwards (Ed.). the Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Vol. 5, 52- 57). New York: Macmillan
    Passmore, J. (1967). Logical Positivism. In P. Edwards (Ed.). The Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Vol. 5, 52- 57). New York: Macmillan. LOGICAL POSITIVISM is the name given in 1931 by A. E. Blumberg and Herbert Feigl to a set of philosophical ideas put forward by the Vienna circle. Synonymous expressions include "consistent empiricism," "logical empiricism," "scientific empiricism," and "logical neo-positivism." The name logical positivism is often, but misleadingly, used more broadly to include the "analytical" or "ordinary language philosophies developed at Cambridge and Oxford. HISTORICAL BACKGROUND The logical positivists thought of themselves as continuing a nineteenth-century Viennese empirical tradition, closely linked with British empiricism and culminating in the antimetaphysical, scientifically oriented teaching of Ernst Mach. In 1907 the mathematician Hans Hahn, the economist Otto Neurath, and the physicist Philipp Frank, all of whom were later to be prominent members of the Vienna circle, came together as an informal group to discuss the philosophy of science. They hoped to give an account of science which would do justice -as, they thought, Mach did not- to the central importance of mathematics, logic, and theoretical physics, without abandoning Mach's general doctrine that science is, fundamentally, the description of experience. As a solution to their problems, they looked to the "new positivism" of Poincare; in attempting to reconcile Mach and Poincare; they anticipated the main themes of logical positivism. In 1922, at the instigation of members of the "Vienna group," Moritz Schlick was invited to Vienna as professor, like Mach before him (1895-1901), in the philosophy of the inductive sciences. Schlick had been trained as a scientist under Max Planck and had won a name for himself as an interpreter of Einstein's theory of relativity.
    [Show full text]
  • Continental Philosophy of Science: Mach, Duhem, and Bachelard Babette Babich Fordham University, [email protected]
    Fordham University Masthead Logo DigitalResearch@Fordham Articles and Chapters in Academic Book Philosophy Collections 2003 Continental Philosophy of Science: Mach, Duhem, and Bachelard Babette Babich Fordham University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://fordham.bepress.com/phil_babich Part of the Continental Philosophy Commons, and the Philosophy of Science Commons Recommended Citation Babich, Babette, "Continental Philosophy of Science: Mach, Duhem, and Bachelard" (2003). Articles and Chapters in Academic Book Collections. 5. https://fordham.bepress.com/phil_babich/5 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy at DigitalResearch@Fordham. It has been accepted for inclusion in Articles and Chapters in Academic Book Collections by an authorized administrator of DigitalResearch@Fordham. For more information, please contact [email protected]. CHAPTER 6 Philosophies of science Mach, Duhem, Bachelard Babette E.Babich THE TRADITION OF CONTINENTAL PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE If the philosophy of science is not typically represented as a ‘continental’ discipline it is nevertheless historically rooted in the tradition of continental thought. The different approaches to the philosophy of science apparent in the writings of Ernst Mach, Pierre Duhem and Gaston Bachelard suggest the range of these roots. But for a discussion of the tradition of continental philosophy of science—as the term ‘continental’ characterizes a contemporary style of philosophic thinking—it is important to emphasize that while Mach, Duhem and Bachelard may be said to be historically continental, a properly continental-style philosophy of science should not be ascribed to any one of them. Contemporary philosophy of science is pursued in what is largely an analytic or Anglo- American-style philosophic tradition.
    [Show full text]
  • Mach's Philosophical Use of the History of Science
    MACH'S USE OF THE HISTORY OF SCIENCE based upon new principles, his work invariably exhibited "extraordinary ------ERWIN N. HIEBERT------ experimental talent."2 Mach was a physicist by training. He never wanted to be known profes­ sionally as anything but a physicist. Of course, his conception of what con­ stitutes physics was broad from the start. In his teaching and research and Mach's Philosophical Use of the in his professorial role he was not bound by conventional academic guide­ History ofScience lines. His doctoral work at the University of Vienna was completed in 1860 with a study on electrical discharge and induction. As a privatdocent at the university he engaged in studies on the change of musical pitch and color resulting from motion, viz., the Doppler effect.3 During the winter semester of 1861-62 he lectured on "Physics for Medical Students."4 Dur­ Ernst Mach devoted a major part of his life to historicocritical investiga­ ing the summer semester his course was entitled "The Principles of Me­ tions that are focused upon philosophical problems in science. The object chanics." He was able to supplement his meager income at this time by of this paper is to consider how he made use of the history of science to delivering popular lectures on psychophysics, Helmholtz's theory of the 5 illuminate problems in the philosophy of science that he encountered in sensation of tone, and optics. his work as a physicist.1 From 1864 to 1867 Mach was, in turn, professor of mathematics and professor of physics at the University of Graz.
    [Show full text]
  • A Parting Shot at Misunderstanding: Fuller Vs. Kuhn Review Essay Of
    1 A Parting Shot at Misunderstanding: Fuller vs. Kuhn The definitive version of this paper has been published in Metascience 14: 12-19. by Springer Netherlands, all rights reserved. It is available at http://www.springerlink.com/content/pu6748rq94p2j2v8/fulltext.pdf Review essay of Steve Fuller, Kuhn vs. Popper: The Struggle for the Soul of Science. Cambridge: Icon Books; Crows Nest, NSW: Allen & Unwin, 2003. Pp. 227. UK £9.99, Australia $29.95 HC. By Stephen P. Turner The question of the political character of science, and of what side one ought to take about science, celebratory or critical, is a complex and confusing domain which Fuller tries to simplify and package in a novel way in this interesting, footnote- free, reflection by identifying, in the history of twentieth century discussions of science, a “Left rationalism” that can say something critical and novel about science. In his book on Thomas Kuhn, Fuller contrasted Kuhn’s politics of science to Ernst Mach’s. Mach was the good guy, who was for democratizing science, and Kuhn was the bad guy, a proponent of a “Cold War” authoritarian conception of science which treated science education as a form of indoctrination, who regarded external influences on science negatively and characterized science in a way that made democratic scrutiny impossible, since it elevated the scientific community to a kind of sacred cow which could only be accommodated and not held to external standards. This book follows up on this general approach by bringing in the Popper-Kuhn debate of the 1960s, which was concerned with criticism and the growth of knowledge, as the title of Lakatos and Musgrave’s famous book put it (Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge 1970).
    [Show full text]
  • The Reception of Ernst Mach in the School of Brentano
    DENIS FISETTE The Reception of Ernst Mach in the School of Brentano Franz Brentano is one of the most infl uential fi gures in the philosophy of the late nineteenth century. Brentano and his successors have established a philosophical program which had a decisive impact on the history of philosophy in Austria. This program stands out clearly in several lectures delivered by Brentano during his stay in Vienna, particularly in his inaugural address at the University of Vienna (Brentano 1929) in which Brentano outlines the program that he systematically develops in his Psychology from an empirical Standpoint (2009). This program was the result of Brentano’s research in Würzburg (1866–1873) which has been partly inspired by Auguste Comte’s positive philosophy and John Stuart Mill’s empiricism (Münch 1989; Fisette 2018). During his stay in Vienna, Brentano’s interest in pos- itivism remained intact as evidenced by his 1893–1894 lectures “Contemporary philosophical questions” in which he examines several versions of positivism, in- cluding Mach’s version. This paper is about the reception of Mach by Brentano and his students in Austria1. I shall outline the main elements of this reception, starting with Bren- tano’s evaluation, in his lectures on positivism, of Mach’s theory of sensations. Secondly, I shall comment the early reception of Mach by Brentano’s pupils in Prague. The third part bears on the close relationship that Husserl established between his phenomenology and Mach’s descriptivism. I will then briefly ex- amine Mach’s contribution to the controversy on gestalt qualities. The fifth part bears on Stumpf’s debate with Mach on psychophysical relations and I shall conclude this study with some remarks on Husserl’s criticism of Mach’s alleged logical psychologism in his Logical Investigations.
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosophy of Karl Popper
    P1: JZX 0521839467Agg.xml CY443/Keuth 0521839467 August 25, 2004 16:38 The Philosophy of Karl Popper HERBERT KEUTH Eberhard Karls Universitat,¨ Tubingen¨ iii P1: JZX 0521839467Agg.xml CY443/Keuth 0521839467 August 25, 2004 16:38 published by the press syndicate of the university of cambridge The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge, United Kingdom cambridge university press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge cb2 2ru, uk 40 West 20th Street, New York, ny 10011-4211, usa 477 Williamstown Road, Port Melbourne, vic 3207, Australia Ruiz de Alarcon´ 13, 28014 Madrid, Spain Dock House, The Waterfront, Cape Town 8001, South Africa http://www.cambridge.org Die Philosophie Karl Poppers C J.C.B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck) 2000 English translation C Herbert Keuth 2005 This book is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published in German in 2000 English edition first published 2005 Printed in the United States of America Typeface itc New Baskerville 10/13 pt. System LATEX 2ε [tb] A catalog record for this book is available from the British Library. Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication data Keuth, Herbert, 1940– [Philosophie Karl Poppers. English] The philosophy of Karl Popper / Herbert Keuth. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and indexes. isbn 0-521-83946-7 – isbn 0-521-54830-6 (pbk.) 1. Popper, Karl Raimund, Sir, 1902–1994 I. Title. b1649.p64k4813 2004 192 – dc22 2004045179 isbn 0 521 83946 7 hardback isbn 0 521 54830 6 paperback iv P1: JZX 0521839467Agg.xml CY443/Keuth 0521839467 August 25, 2004 16:38 Contents List of Abbreviations page xiii Preface xv Introduction 1 part i.
    [Show full text]
  • Mach and the Principle of Verification
    University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Transactions of the Nebraska Academy of Sciences and Affiliated Societies Nebraska Academy of Sciences 1976 Mach and the Principle of Verification Thomas Manig University of Nebraska-Lincoln Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/tnas Manig, Thomas, "Mach and the Principle of Verification" (1976). Transactions of the Nebraska Academy of Sciences and Affiliated Societies. 408. https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/tnas/408 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Nebraska Academy of Sciences at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in Transactions of the Nebraska Academy of Sciences and Affiliated Societiesy b an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE MACH AND THE PRINCIPLE OF VERIFICA nON THOMAS MANIG Department of Philosophy University of Nebraska-Lincoln 68588 Scholars of the history of the philosophy of science take it pretty much for iSranted that the scientist Ernst Mach had created much of the initial thrust if not many of the central principles of logical positivism. And for the most part they are quite right in thinking so. Although, as Toulmin aptly put it, 'Mach himself was never a "logical" positivist,' Mach's radically empiricis­ tic and anti-metaphysical orientation was sufficient to justify the feelings of indebtedness most early logical positivists had for him. Indeed, the first manifesto of the so-called "Vienna Circle" oflogical positivists was published by the Viennese Ernst Mach Society, a group headed by Moritz Schlick, the acknowledged founder of logical positivism.
    [Show full text]
  • Relational Mechanics Relational Principle and Implementation of Mach’S Force Gravitational with Weber’S
    A s s i s Relational Mechanics R Relational Mechanics ¨ A new mechanics intended to replace newtonian e mechanics and also Einstein’s theories of relativity. l a and Implementation of Mach’s Principle ¨ It implements Mach’s principle quantitatively based on t i Weber’s force for gravitation and the principle of o n with Weber’s Gravitational Force dynamical equilibrium. a l ¨ It explains Newton’s bucket experiment with the concave M figure of the water being due to a gravitational e c interaction between the water and the distant galaxies h when in relative rotation. a n i ¨ It is intended for physicists, engineers, mathematicians, c historians, philosophers of science and students. s a n d About the Author I m Andre Koch Torres Assis was born in Brazil (1962) and educated at the Uni- p l versity of Campinas – UNICAMP, BS (1983), PhD (1987). He spent the aca- e m demic year of 1988 in England with a post-doctoral position at the Culham e Laboratory (Oxfordshire, United Kingdom Atomic Energy Authority). He n spent one year in 1991-92 as a Visiting Scholar at the Center for Electro- t a magnetics Research of Northeastern University (Boston, USA). From August t i 2001 to November 2002, and from February to May 2009, he worked at the o Institute for the History of Natural Sciences, Hamburg University (Hamburg, n Germany) with research fellowships awarded by the Alexander von Hum- o f boldt Foundation of Germany. He is the author of Weber’s Electrodynamics M (1994), Relational Mechanics (1999), Inductance and Force Calculations in a Electrical Circuits (with M.
    [Show full text]
  • INTRODUCTION to SOCIOLOGY Theodor W. Adorno
    INTRODUCTION TO SOCIOLOGY Theodor W. Adorno Edited by Christoph Godde Translated by Edmund Jephcott Stanford University Press Stanford, California The posthumous works Beethoven: The Philosophy of Music Introduction to Sociology Problems of Moral Philosophy Metaphysics: Concept and Problems Kant's Critique of Pure Reason Stanford University Press Stanford, California Translation copyright© 2000 Polity Press. First published in the U.K. by Polity Press. First published in the U.S.A. by Stanford University Press, 2000. First published in Germany as Einleitung in die Soziologie © 199 3 Suhrkamp Verlag. ISBN 0-8047- 4683-4 Library of Congress Catalog Card Number: 99 075607 This book is printed on acid-free paper. Last figure below indicates year of this printing: 10 CONTENTS LECTURE ONE 1 Professional prospects and intentions of sociologists • Sociology as educational study and as socially useful work • Difficulties in planning a course of study • The university as school and academic freedom • Gaps and leaps when studying • Discontinuity of knowledge • Introduction e contrario • Sociology as agglomerate • The inhomogeneity of sociology in Comte: the scientific and the philosophical ideal LECTURE TWO 10 Antagonism within sociology • Sociology's stance towards politics • Negation of truth, methodological dispute and technocracy • Affirmative character of sociology in Comte: static and dynamic; theory of productive forces in Marx • Pareto: circulation of elites and cycle of history • Sociology is insight into the essential in society; against
    [Show full text]