Incompleteness: the Proof and Paradox of Kurt Gödel

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Incompleteness: the Proof and Paradox of Kurt Gödel Book Review Incompleteness: The Proof and Paradox of Kurt Gödel Reviewed by Juliette Kennedy Incompleteness: The Proof and Paradox of Kurt Incompleteness Theorems. This means that some Gödel of these areas are covered more comprehensively Rebecca Goldstein than others. W. W. Norton & Company In places the author succeeds creditably; for ex- February 2005 ample, her portrayals of behind-the-scenes acade- $22.95, 296 pages, ISBN 0393051692 mic life will likely be of interest to readers who enjoy such material—indeed, such portrayals seem Popular books on mathematics play an impor- to be her forte. tant role in the lay public’s education. But as is As is often the case with books about mathe- known to anyone who has given a popular mathe- matics written by nonmathematicians though, matics lecture or written about a famous theorem for an audience of nonmathematicians, doing jus- shortfalls of precision occurring here and there will tice to the mathematics in question is almost im- leave mathematicians unsatisfied; and the mis- possible in those circumstances. Rebecca Gold- statement of the Fixed Point Theorem on page 180, stein, the MacArthur Foundation fellow and author the heart of the matter technically, makes it, of The Mind-Body Problem (a novel which seems to unfortunately, quite impossible for anyone to be quite popular among mathematicians) attempts reconstruct the proof of the First Incompleteness an even more difficult task in her short new book Theorem from Goldstein’s account. Incompleteness: The Proof and Paradox of Kurt In this review I will comment on the three main Gödel, namely, to place a significant piece of math- aspects of Goldstein’s book, apart from her tech- ematics—Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorems—in nical account of the theorems: first, her portrayal the context of the wider intellectual currents of the of the life and personality of Gödel and the social twentieth century, both within the mathematical surroundings in which he worked; second, her logic and the philosophy of mathematics commu- main claim, which is that Gödel’s work has been nities, as well as within the intellectual culture at misunderstood and misused by postmodernists large. and other intellectuals; and third, her rather sub- The theorems are presented in the context of a stantial discussion of foundational issues, which somewhat detailed personal and intellectual biog- unfortunately is the weakest of these three aspects raphy of Gödel as well as in that of the various schools in foundations of mathematics in exis- of the book. tence at the time. A vast amount of material is The author’s novelistic skills are at their most covered: everything from the history of the Vienna conspicuous in the section of the book devoted to Circle, to Gödel’s philosophical differences with her colorful portrait of Gödel. From p. 59: Wittgenstein, to the Hilbert Program, to Gödel’s I think it is fair to say…that like so views on appointments at the Institute for Ad- many of us Gödel fell in love while an vanced Study, to many aspects of his personal bi- undergraduate. He underwent love’s ec- ography, in addition to the account of the two static transfiguration, its radical re- Juliette Kennedy is university lecturer in the Department ordering of priorities, giving life new of Mathematics and Statistics at the University of Helsinki. focus and meaning. One is not quite Her email address is [email protected]. the same person as before. 448 NOTICES OF THE AMS VOLUME 53, NUMBER 4 Kurt Gödel fell in love with Platonism, Those familiar and he was not quite the same person with Gödel’s life may as he was before. find all this some- what reductive; al- Another example of this theme occurs on p. 110, though it is clear where Gödel is described as “a man whose soul had from the author’s been blasted by the Platonic vision of truth.” portrayal of him that Goldstein includes all of the standard anecdotes she very much sym- about Gödel, as reported by the occasional, usually pathizes with Gödel. confounded, eyewitness. Some of these are quite Some occasional amusing, for example, the story of Gödel’s citi- wrong notes include zenship hearings (pp. 232–233), in which a logical the discussion on pp. inconsistency Gödel discovered in the American 226–227, in which Constitution threatened to upset the proceedings. some key back- The psychological analysis the author sprinkles ground facts are here and there into the biographical material is omitted, as well as nothing if not enterprising. For example, Goldstein the discussion on p. 223, in which the author ven- has a theory about the source of Gödel’s psycho- tures to describe Gödel’s marriage to his wife Adele, logical difficulties (pp. 48–49): a lively and witty woman who seems to have been as I hope will become ever clearer in the somewhat out of place in Princeton, as “weird”, “ac- cording to just about everyone”. One wonders chapters to come, the internal para- about this characterization of their marriage, when doxes in Gödel’s personality were at many of the Gödels’ friends seem to give a differ- least partially provoked by the world’s ent impression in their reports of it. In fact, on the paradoxical responses to his famous whole the portrait of Adele is a bit ungenerous, with work. the author making very heavy weather, for exam- See also p. 57: ple, about such things as Mrs. Gödel’s appalling— to Goldstein—taste in home decoration. …the precocious Gödel grasped the lim- Does the real person come through in this ac- its of parental omniscience at about the count? Gödel was an extremely private person who age of five. It would be comforting, in at the same time suffered, as many creative peo- the presence of such a shattering con- ple do, from disabling episodes of anxiety and de- clusion, especially when it’s reinforced pression. The episodes became worse with age. It by serious illness a few years later, to is not a very pretty story; but his productivity, derive the following additional conclu- given the circumstances, makes it a very moving sion…the grownups around me may be one—albeit one that in the end, at least in this a sorry lot, but luckily I don’t need to book, may remain to be told. depend on them. I can figure out every- That said, interviews the author has conducted thing for myself. The world is thor- with the principals, for example Armand Borel, oughly logical and so is my mind—a have yielded valuable new information about perfect fit. Gödel’s relationship with his colleagues at the In- Quite possibly the young Gödel had stitute for Advanced Study, answering the question why Gödel was so isolated from his colleagues dur- some such thoughts to quell the terror ing his later years there. Goldstein also draws upon of discovering at too young an age that her experience as a graduate student in philosophy he was far more intelligent than his par- at Princeton, which has put her in the position of ents. It would explain much about the being able to speak firsthand about the Princeton man he would become.1 academic culture of the time—even if her per- 1Some of the important memoirs about Gödel include spective is very much that of an awestruck student. those by his brother Rudolf Gödel, his classmate Olga The book is centered around the claim that, in Taussky-Todd [18], the obituary of Gödel for the Royal So- an ironic twist of events, the “intellectual commu- ciety by Georg Kreisel [11], as well as other writings of nity”, as Goldstein refers to it, used Gödel’s own Kreisel on Gödel, Hao Wang’s three books based on his con- incompleteness theorems to discredit his philo- versations with Gödel [14], [15], [16], as well as Stephen sophical Platonism; that the Incompleteness The- Kleene’s memoir [10], to name just a few. The reader is orems became “grist for the postmodern mill”, if also referred to the biography of Gödel by John Dawson not the main weapon in the contemporary “revolt entitled Logical Dilemmas [4], as well as to Palle Yourgrau’s against objectivity”; that consequently Gödel, to portrayal of Gödel in A World without Time [17], which focuses mostly on Gödel’s friendship with Einstein and the whom the notion of mathematical truth was an ab- scientific work which grew out of it. solute and objective one, had to battle to the end APRIL 2006 NOTICES OF THE AMS 449 of his days against postmodern misconceptions and view of Gödel’s time. For example, the Hilbert Pro- misconstruals of his theorems, which were misin- gram aimed to show that all that was required to terpreted to show that there is no such thing as formalize mathematics were finitary axioms stated truth. in a precise syntax together with finitary rules of Platonism in the context of foundations of math- proof (proving consistency was the second desider- ematics is essentially the view that mathematics is atum of it). In showing that mathematics can be con- a descriptive science, although, unlike the empir- strued as a “formal game of symbols”, a slogan ical sciences, the domain described is thought to which came into use at the time, mathematics consist of abstract objects. Another tenet of Pla- would be put on a firm foundation by eliminating tonism is that the concept of mathematical truth reference to infinite objects, as well as the use of is a meaningful one. Gödel held this view from unstated assumptions or proof procedures that about 1925 onwards (though he wavered a bit be- might lead to paradoxes.
Recommended publications
  • “Gödel's Modernism: on Set-Theoretic Incompleteness,” Revisited
    “G¨odel'sModernism: on Set-Theoretic Incompleteness," revisited∗ Mark van Atten and Juliette Kennedy As to problems with the answer Yes or No, the con- viction that they are always decidable remains un- touched by these results. —G¨odel Contents 1 Introduction 1.1 Questions of incompleteness On Friday, November 15, 1940, Kurt G¨odelgave a talk on set theory at Brown University.1 The topic was his recent proof of the consistency of Cantor's Con- tinuum Hypothesis, henceforth CH,2 with the axiomatic system for set theory ZFC.3 His friend from their days in Vienna, Rudolf Carnap, was in the audience, and afterward wrote a note to himself in which he raised a number of questions on incompleteness:4 (Remarks I planned to make, but did not) Discussion on G¨odel'slecture on the Continuum Hypothesis, November 14,5 1940 There seems to be a difference: between the undecidable propo- sitions of the kind of his example [i.e., 1931] and propositions such as the Axiom of Choice, and the Axiom of the Continuum [CH ]. We used to ask: \When these two have been decided, is then everything decided?" (The Poles, Tarski I think, suspected that this would be the case.) Now we know that (on the basis of the usual finitary rules) there will always remain undecided propositions. ∗An earlier version of this paper appeared as ‘G¨odel'smodernism: on set-theoretic incom- pleteness', Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal, 25(2), 2004, pp.289{349. Erratum facing page of contents in 26(1), 2005. 1 1. Can we nevertheless still ask an analogous question? I.e.
    [Show full text]
  • Turing, Gödel and the Bright Abyss
    Turing, Gödel and the “Bright Abyss” Juliet Floyd ! 2/5/2015 9:25 AM Comment [1]: 1. Check phone number okay to use this ong?; Also need 2. ABSTRACT of 1 Introduction 150-200 words and 3. a CONTRIBUTOR bi- ography of up to 100 words! Xxx, J. They have completely forgotten what is a mathematical creation: a vision that decants little by little over months and years, bringing to light the obvious [evident] thing that no one had seen, taking form in an obvious assertion of which no one had dreamed ... and that the first one to come along can then prove in five minutes, using techniques ready to hand [toutes cuites] • A. Grothendiek, Recoltes et Sémailles, 1986 Mathematics: there is that which is taken on faith and that which is proved; there is that which is buried deep inside the heart of the mathematician1 and that which is wholly public; there is intuition and fact and the “bright abyss” in be- tween; there is the raw, one might say, and the cooked. I hold up my hand and I count five fingers. I take it on faith that the mapping from fingers onto numbers is recursive in the sense of the mathematician’s defi- nition of the informal concept, “human calculability following a fixed routine.” I cannot prove the mapping is recursive—there is nothing to prove! Of course, mathematicians can prove many theorems about recursiveness, moving forward, so to speak, once the definition of the concept “recursive” has been isolated. Moving backwards is more difficult and this is as it should be: for how can one possibly hope to prove that a mathematical
    [Show full text]
  • Interpreting Gödel: Critical Essays Edited by Juliette Kennedy Frontmatter More Information
    Cambridge University Press 978-1-107-00266-1 - Interpreting Gödel: Critical Essays Edited by Juliette Kennedy Frontmatter More information INTERPRETING GÖDEL: CRITICAL ESSAYS The logician Kurt Gödel (1906–1978) published a paper in 1931 formulating what have come to be known as his “incompleteness theorems,” which prove, among other things, that within any formal system with resources sufficient to code arithmetic, questions exist which are neither provable nor disprovable on the basis of the axioms which define the system. These are among the most celebrated results in logic today. In this volume, leading philosophers and mathemat- icians assess important aspects of Gödel’s work on the foundations and philosophy of mathematics. Their essays explore almost every aspect of Godel’s intellectual legacy including his concepts of intu- ition and analyticity, the Completeness Theorem, the set-theoretic multiverse, and the state of mathematical logic today. This ground- breaking volume will be invaluable to students, historians, logicians, and philosophers of mathematics who wish to understand the current thinking on these issues. juliette kennedy is an Associate Professor in the Department of Mathematics and Statistics at the University of Helsinki. © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-1-107-00266-1 - Interpreting Gödel: Critical Essays Edited by Juliette Kennedy Frontmatter More information © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-1-107-00266-1 - Interpreting Gödel: Critical Essays Edited by Juliette Kennedy Frontmatter More information INTERPRETING GÖDEL Critical Essays edited by JULIETTE KENNEDY University of Helsinki © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-1-107-00266-1 - Interpreting Gödel: Critical Essays Edited by Juliette Kennedy Frontmatter More information University Printing House, Cambridge cb2 8bs, United Kingdom Cambridge University Press is part of the University of Cambridge.
    [Show full text]
  • Simplicity: Ideals of Practice in Mathematics and the Arts
    Mathematics, Culture, and the Arts Simplicity Ideals of Practice in Mathematics and the Arts Roman Kossak · Philip Ording Editors Mathematics, Culture, and the Arts Series editors Jed Z. Buchwald Jeremy Gray Marjorie Senechal The series Mathematics in Culture and the Arts will publish books on all aspects of the relationships between mathematics and the mathematical sciences and their roles in culture, art, architecture, literature, and music. This new book series will be a major resource for researchers, educators, scientifically minded artists, and students alike. More information about this series at http://www.springer.com/series/13129 Roman Kossak • Philip Ording Editors Simplicity: Ideals of Practice in Mathematics and the Arts 123 Editors Roman Kossak Philip Ording Department of Mathematics Department of Mathematics The Graduate Center Sarah Lawrence College City University of New York Bronxville, NY, USA New York, NY, USA ISSN 2520-8578 ISSN 2520-8586 (electronic) Mathematics, Culture, and the Arts ISBN 978-3-319-53383-4 ISBN 978-3-319-53385-8 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-53385-8 Library of Congress Control Number: 2017935487 © Springer International Publishing AG 2017 This work is subject to copyright. All rights are reserved by the Publisher, whether the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any other physical way, and transmission or information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar or dissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed. The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Set Theory
    Philosophy of Set Theory LPS 247 Fall 2016 - Winter 2017 The mathematical theory of sets is both a foundation (in some sense) for classical mathematics and a branch of mathematics in its own right. Both its foundational role and its particular mathematical features -- the centrality of axiomatization and the prevalence of independence phenomena -- raise philosophical questions that have been debated since the birth of the subject at the end of the 19th century: what is a ‘foundation’ supposed to do?, what makes one system of axioms ‘better’ than another?, how can problems independent of the axioms, like Cantor’s famous Continuum Hypothesis, be addressed? Our goal in this course is to survey these matters, from their beginnings to contemporary debates. Some familiarity with the mathematical fundamentals of the theory (say at the level of Herbert Enderton’s Elements of Set Theory) and with the central results of intermediate logic (completeness, compactness, Löwenheim-Skolem, non- standard models, Gödel’s incompleteness theorems) will be presupposed. The rest will be sketched in readings and/or in class. The default requirement for those taking the course for a grade (other than S/U, which involves only reading and attending) is three short papers (750-1250 words) due at the beginning of class in the 4th week, 7th week, and 10th week. These papers should isolate one localized philosophical, conceptual or methodological point within one of the readings and offer some analysis and/or critique. The thesis and its defense needn’t be earth-shattering in any way; this is really just an exercise in finding a topic of the right size and crafting a thesis and defense to match.
    [Show full text]
  • Front Matter
    Cambridge University Press 978-1-107-01257-8 — Gödel, Tarski and the Lure of Natural Language Juliette Kennedy Frontmatter More Information Gödel, Tarski and the Lure of Natural Language Is mathematics “entangled” with its various formalisations? Or are the central con- cepts of mathematics largely insensitive to formalisation, or “formalism free”? What is the semantic point of view and how is it implemented in foundational practice? Does a given semantic framework always have an implicit syntax? Inspired by what she calls the “natural language moves” of Gödel and Tarski, Juliette Kennedy considers what roles the concepts of “entanglement” and “formalism freeness” play in a range of logical settings, from computability and set theory to model theory and second order logic to logicality, developing an entirely original philosophy of mathematics along the way. The treatment is historically, logically and set-theoretically rich, and topics such as naturalism and foundations receive their due, but now with a new twist. JULIETTE KENNEDY is Associate Professor of Mathematics and Statistics at the University of Helsinki. Her research focuses on set theory, history of logic and phi- losophy of mathematics, and she is Editor of Interpreting Gödel: Critical Essays (Cambridge University Press, 2014). © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-1-107-01257-8 — Gödel, Tarski and the Lure of Natural Language Juliette Kennedy Frontmatter More Information © in this web service Cambridge University
    [Show full text]
  • The System That Destroys Itself, Or Greenberg's Modernism & the Liar's
    C Abstract: This paper reconsiders the unraveling of modernism in the R visual arts in the middle 1960s. Building on Craig Owens’ observation I S The System that that “eruption of language” in the visual arts signaled “the emergence I of postmodernism,” we here argue that the linguistic-based projects S of John Baldesarri, Dan Graham and others catalyzed the rupturing of & modernist aspirations to autonomy and completeness by creating the Destroys Itself, or C possibilities of pernicious self-reference. This argument draws from a R remarkable set of parallelism from the distal domain of mathematics, I in which the “modernist” aspirations to purity and self-sufficiency were T I Greenberg’s similarly disrupted by the introduction of seemingly paradoxical self- Q referential statements, most notably Gödelian incompleteness. This is U E not to suggest that Baldessari et al. were influenced by Gödel, but rather to argue that, as in the case of Gödel’s theorems, the work of these artists / Modernism & constitutes a clear response to a property of systematicity itself, namely Volume 5 / that increasing denotative power can lead to the collapse of the system. Issue 1 the Liar’s Paradox Keywords: modernism, postmodernism, Greenberg, Godel, incompleteness, art, mathematics “Could anyone ten years ago,” asked the artist and critic Mel Bochner in 1971, “have imagined that ‘modern art’ would become a period style?”1 Nearly five decades after the posing of this rhetorical question, Bochner’s Juliette Kennedy & incredulity seems to spur an incredulity of its own. The now sprawling directions of contemporary artistic practice are driven by the rapid coalescing and dissolving of so many approaches and trends, it can be difficult to imagine an art world in which the grand force of art history Michael Maizels was still seen as a kind of actor in the world of artists, critics and dealers.
    [Show full text]
  • Turing, Lebensform, and the Emergence of Wittgenstein's Later
    Nordic Wittgenstein Review 5 (2) 2016 INVITED PAPER Juliet Floyd jfloyd @ bu.edu Chains of Life: Turing, Lebensform, and the Emergence of Wittgenstein’s Later Style Abstract This essay accounts for the notion of Lebensform by assigning it a logical role in Wittgenstein’s later philosophy. Wittgenstein’s additions of the notion to his manuscripts of the PI occurred during the initial drafting of the book 1936-7, after he abandoned his effort to revise The Brown Book. It is argued that this constituted a substantive step forward in his attitude toward the notion of simplicity as it figures within the notion of logical analysis. Next, a reconstruction of his later remarks on Lebensformen is offered which factors in his reading of Alan Turing’s “On computable numbers, with an application to the Entscheidungsproblem“ (1936/7), as well as his discussions with Turing 1937-1939. An interpretation of the five occurrences of Lebensform in the PI is then given in terms of a logical “regression” to Lebensform as a fundamental notion. This regression characterizes Wittgenstein’s mature answer to the question, “What is the nature of the logical?” 1. Introduction Lebensform is an important gauge of the development of Wittgenstein’s thought. It represents, from a regressive point of view, the place he finally chased down to. In foundational matters such as these, it is often the simplest, naïve perspective that comes 7 Juliet Floyd CC-BY last in a thinker’s (or a tradition’s) evolution, the working through of how to get back home to the primordial basis, the extraction of fundamentals from a jungle of technical accretions.
    [Show full text]
  • JULIET FLOYD Addresses: Department of Philosophy, Boston
    FloydCV.doc JULIET FLOYD Addresses: Department of Philosophy, Boston University 745 Commonwealth Avenue, Boston, MA 02215 Telephone: Work: (617) 353-3745 E-mail: [email protected] Fax: (617) 353-6805 Education: 1982-1990 Harvard University, Department of Philosophy, M.A., PhD. Dissertation: The Rule of the Mathematical: Wittgenstein’s Later Discussions 1978-1979, Wellesley College, Department of Philosophy, B.A. 1981-1982 Highest Honors (Durant Scholar, Phi Beta Kappa) 1980-1981 London School of Economics and Political Science Department of Logic, Philosophy and Scientific Method Academic Positions: Spring 2012 Visiting Professor, Philosophy, Université Michel de Montaigne Bordeaux 3 Spring 2009 Visiting Professor, Philosophy, Université de Paris I Panthéon-Sorbonne Spring 2007 Visiting Professor, Philosophy, University of Vienna 2006- Professor of Philosophy, Boston University; 2003- Affiliated faculty member at Boston University in the following programs: Institute of Editorial Studies, Institute for the Philosophy of Religion, Department of Religion 1996-2006 Associate Professor of Philosophy, Boston University 1995 (spring) Visiting Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Boston University 1993-1994 Deputy Executive Officer, Graduate Program in Philosophy, C.U.N.Y. 1992-95 Graduate Faculty Member in Philosophy, C.U.N.Y. 1990-1995 Assistant Professor of Philosophy, City College of New York, C.U.N.Y. Fellowships, Awards: 2009-2010 Fellow of the Lichtenberg-Kolleg Institute of Advanced Study, Georg August Universität, Göttingen 2008, fall Berlin Prize Fellowship, American Academy in Berlin 2003-2004 American Philosophical Society Sabbatical Fellowship 2003-2004 Fulbright Senior Research Award, Vienna, Austria 2003-2004 Mary Elvira Stevens Research Fellowship, Wellesley College 1998-1999 Senior Fellowship, American Council of Learned Societies 1998-1999 Senior Fellowship, Dibner Institute for the History of Science, M.I.T.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction. Gödel and Analytic Philosophy: How Did We Get Here? Juliette Kennedy
    Cambridge University Press 978-1-107-00266-1 - Interpreting Gödel: Critical Essays Edited by Juliette Kennedy Excerpt More information chapter 1 Introduction. Gödel and analytic philosophy: how did we get here? Juliette Kennedy 1 Introduction It is often said about Kurt Gödel that he was the greatest logician of the twentieth century. His work in mathematical logic, when it does not constitute the very ground out of which its various subfields grew and developed, made the continuation of the subject possible at a time when fundamental concepts had not even been identified, and proofs of key theorems – in those cases when they had been stated – had not material- ized in anything like their final form. This is not to say that Gödel was intellectually infallible; one could also point to the richness of Gödel’s logical milieu. But there is no doubt that a gigantic intelligence had turned to the field of mathematical logic – and how much better off the subject was for it! Gödel’s philosophical work on the other hand, work to which he devoted himself almost exclusively from the mid-1940s until his death in 1978, has not been as well received. Put another way, any praise of Gödel’s contributions to the foundations of mathematics has largely been limited 1 to his theorems. Gödel the philosopher – and indeed even today it is a matter of debate, whether Gödel can be regarded as a philosopher at all – has traditionally been seen as advocating a crude form of Platonism in his philosophical writings, one entangled with the views of Kant and Leibniz in a way which was seen as philosophically naive and primarily historical; and one which, anachronistically, seemed to give no quarter to what turned out to be the single most important development in twentieth 1 See for example Boolos’s introduction (Gödel 1995, pp.
    [Show full text]
  • Turing on “Common Sense”: Cambridge Resonances
    To appear as Chapter 4 in J. Floyd and A. Bokulich eds., Philosophical Explorations of the Legacy of Alan Turing – Turing 100 (Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science Series, Springer, expected date of publication 2016) Turing on “Common Sense”: Cambridge Resonances Juliet Floyd Abstract Turing was a philosopher of logic and mathematics, as well as a mathematician. His work throughout his life owed much to the Cambridge milieu in which he was educated and to which he returned throughout his life. A rich and distinctive tradition discussing how the notion of “common sense” relates to the foundations of logic was being developed during Turing’s undergraduate days, most intensively by Wittgenstein, whose exchanges with Russell, Ramsey, Sraffa, Hardy, Littlewood and others formed part of the backdrop which shaped Turing’s work. Beginning with a Moral Sciences Club talk in 1933, Turing developed an “anthropological” approach to the foundations of logic, influenced by Wittgenstein, in which “common sense” plays a foundational role. This may be seen not only in “On Computable Numbers” (1936/7) and Turing’s dissertation (written 1938, see (1939)), but in his exchanges with Wittgenstein in 1939 and in two later papers, “The Reform of Mathematical Phraseology and Notation” (1944/5) and “Solvable and Unsolvable Problems” (1954). 4.1. Introduction Turing’s philosophical attitude has often been distorted by controversies in recent philosophy of mind—above all, those that have associated his thought with computationalist and behaviorist reductionisms. Of course, Turing pioneered philosophical discussion of computational explanation and modelling in such far- flung fields as cognitive science, artificial intelligence, neurological connectionism, and morphogenesis.
    [Show full text]
  • Gödel and the Metamathematical Tradition
    G¨odeland the metamathematical tradition∗ Jeremy Avigad July 25, 2007 Abstract The metamathematical tradition that developed from Hilbert’s pro- gram is based on syntactic characterizations of mathematics and the use of explicit, finitary methods in the metatheory. Although G¨odel’s work in logic fits squarely in that tradition, one often finds him cu- riously at odds with the associated methodological orientation. This essay explores that tension and what lies behind it. 1 Introduction While I am honored to have been asked to deliver a lecture in honor of the Kurt G¨odelcentennial, I agreed to do so with some hesitations. For one thing, I am not a historian, so if you are expecting late-breaking revelations from the G¨odel Nachlass you will be disappointed. A more pressing concern is that I am a poor representative of G¨odel’s views. As a proof theorist by training and disposition, I take myself to be working in the metamathemat- ical tradition that emerged from Hilbert’s program; while I will point out, in this essay, that G¨odel’s work in logic falls squarely in this tradition, one often senses in G¨odela dissatisfaction with that methodological orientation that makes me uneasy. This is by no means to deny G¨odel’s significance; von Neumann once characterized him as the most important logician since Aristotle, and I will not dispute that characterization here. But admiration doesn’t always translate to a sense of affinity, and I sometimes have a hard time identifying with G¨odel’s outlook. ∗This essay is only slightly modified from the text of a lecture presented at the spring meeting of the Association for Symbolic Logic in Montreal in May, 2006.
    [Show full text]