John Gray and F. A. Hayek -Theory of Knowledge and Evolutionary Theory-

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

John Gray and F. A. Hayek -Theory of Knowledge and Evolutionary Theory- View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by DSpace at Waseda University 33 社学研論集 Vol. 17 2011年3月 論 文 John Gray and F. A. Hayek -theory of knowledge and evolutionary theory- Shota Mitsushima* Ⅰ.History and Philosophy John Gray was educated at the Exeter College, Oxford University, where he gained his Ph.D. ‘( Liberty and human nature in the liberal tradition’) and taught as a Fellow of Jesus College. He published a book titled Mill on liberty: A defence. And he brought out Hayek on Liberty. This book is originated in a monograph:‘ F.A. Hayek and the Rebirth of Classic Liberalism’ and published on the anniversary of Hayek’s Road to Serfdom. He set out in this book Hayek’s systematic and philosophical, particularly Kantian, characters. After this, he brought out Liberalism soon. This work consists of historical and philosophical parts, and its construction, it seems, gives us a key to understand his subsequent works. As he had been saturated with Mill and Hayek in those days, the conclusion of this book is as follows:“ no one can predict the outcome of the current revival of liberal thought. But, if there is hope for the future of liberty, it is in the fact that, as we approach the end of a century of political frenzy, we see a return to the wisdom of the great liberal writers. For it is in the works of the classical liberal thinkers that we have the most profound reflective response to the dangers and opportunities of the modern age.” [Gray 1986: 93]However, I think that he became more conscious of the fact that‘ the end of a century of political frenzy’ was one among many and mainly meant only an end of ideological conflict against Socialism for the meantime. In other words, we were seeing the demise of Socialism, against which Hayek, whose final work The fatal conceit is subtitled‘ the errors of Socialism’, had fought in his life. But we were not seeing the final stage in the development of the world. Therefore it seems that Gray has come up agaist historical events and has kept a philosophical enquiry. (1) His historical perspective of that time can be generally described as follows : at first, the demise of Soviet system, in which totalitarian order had suffocated the institution of civil society. But, at the same time, stable free civil society was not attained anywhere in the region of decommunization and economical and human costs to achieve them was on the increase at every turn. In addition, the erosion of totalitarian institutions brought out racial and religious conflicts rather than civil society.‘ The end of history’ was illusion there. Another is that *早稲田大学大学院社会科学研究科 博士後期課程4年(指導教員 古賀勝次郎) 34 post-war system or framework became weak in the joints because of, for example, the demise of communism in East Europe, reunification of Germany, and the presence of EU. The other is the presence of some Asian countries. In the wake of these circumstances, Gray had considered the validity of philosophical foundations of liberalism, which some liberal thinkers had underpinned, and has searched for the way to protect the liberal heritages. The comparatively important work among his opuses in this light is Liberalisms ─ studies in political philosophy. In the preface to this book, he says that“ [t]his collection, which begins and ends with a paper on J.S. Mill, contains a dozen essays, written over as many years, together with a new postscript written specially for this volume. The essays collected here were neither written nor selected haphazardly. They embody a single project, pursued continuously over the period in which they were written ─ the project of defining liberalism and giving it a foundation. The enterprise ended in failure. The upshot of the arguments developed in these essays is that the political morality that is constitutive of liberalism cannot be given any statement that is determinate or coherent and it has no claim on reason. The various projects of grounding liberalism (conceived as a set of universal principles) in a comprehensive moral theory ─ rights-based, utilitarian, contractarian or whatever ─ are examined in turn and found wanting. Recurrently in these essays, I conclude that a particular path of justification of liberalism is a dead end and a liberal ideology an impossibility ─ only to take up later another, and apparently more promising, justificatory strategy.” [Ibid.1989: vii] Now this book also collects an article (2) ‘Hayek on liberty, rights and justice’, which is prior to the forementioned monograph, and we can see that he had recognized there the difficulties of sustaining some aspects of Hayek’s thought. Then, the aim of my article is to describe his arguments for and against Hayek so that we can make sense of where he places a distance from Hayek’s thought and we can see his further arguments onward. In order to make them clear, I will particularly focus on their differences of theory of knowledge and evolutionary theory. But, before that, we need to take a look into his work Hayek on Liberty. Ⅱ.John Gray and Hayek on Liberty ⅰ)theory of knowledge (3) Gray is among who played a pioneering role for studies on Hayek’ thought . The late Norman Barry, for example, was also a forerunner and presented us solid survey of Hayek’s comprehensive thought. But Gray’ s work is distinctive in that he extensively read the philosophical dimension of Hayek’s thought and brought up his Kantian characters, which Hayek favorably recognized later in some extent. Gray insists that Hayek’s philosophical dimension partakes of post-Kantian critical philosophy, and this Skeptical Kantianism, what he calls, comes under the influence of, particularly, Mach, Popper, Wittgenstein and M.Polanyi and is found in the entirety of Hayek’s works. According to Gray, Hayek is Kantian in the way that we cannot know the things as it is and the order which we find by experience is not given by the external world alone but created by the process of our minds. With that, Hayek is against the ground of such as essentialism, which makes an attempt to seek for John Gray and F. A. Hayek 35 the essence behind the veil of appearance, and reductionism, in which, like behaviorism, the statements about mental order understood as physical processes can be reduced to that about empirical phenomena. Instead, Hayek emphasizes that the whole thing in our sensory order is created through the activity of our minds and is abstract and conceptual, and the world is understood by way of theories in character. Meanwhile, though Gray (4) points out its tension , Hayek also puts stress that human knowledge is au fond practical or tacit knowledge which is embodied in our skills, dispositions to act in a rule-following manner, and tradition and which cannot be theorized nor articulated all the time. Gray calls this dimension of Hayek’s though‘ thesis of the primacy of practice’ and by this means that theoretical reconstruction of our knowledge, which is of necessary abstract or pattern prediction and conduces to an explanation of the principle, is not able to avoid being imperfect. The things derived by this skeptical Kantian critical philosophy is that, because we cannot attain to the position― like Archimedian point, from which we can command a view of society as a whole, the task of philosophy is not to give account of the necessary feature of the thing nor to construct anything like metaphysical system but to (5) make sure of the limits of our reason . And the proper criticism of our moral traditions is immanent criticism in which a part of our whole practices we have inherited induce to illustrate and correct the rest. What is the implication of these philosophical characters for social theory? Gray recognized that the main response of this question is that, against Cartesian or Hobbesian rationalism, say, social order is not the construction of directing human mind. It may well be that to grasp the basic rules which operate human mind is beyond our ability in the first place and the rules we find in our society are the result of evolutionary selection and modification. And most of our knowledge is unable to be concentrated in a single person or unified scheme, because these are embodied in customs or propensities. It is from this insight that we can see that the central social panning is epistemological impossible. Central planning authorities, by and large, fail to recognize the market as a discovery procedure, in which generates and uses not only explicit knowledge but tacit knowledge (including that of individual’s preference through price mechanism). And Gray insists that the thing Hayek posed in social theory is that“ a way of assessing different social systems more fruitful than the traditional method of appraising their moral content is to be found in illuminating the demands they make upon the powers of the mind and the uses they are able to make of human knowledge. His[Hayek’s] conclusion is that, once we have arrived at a realistic picture of the powers and limitations of the human mind, we see that many important social doctrines ─ those of socialism and interventionist liberalism, for example, ─ make impossible demands upon our knowledge.”[Gray 1998: x] ⅱ) Spontaneous Order According to Hayek,‘ constructivistic rationalism’ is the error in that the order we find in society is designed by human mind. In contrast, Hayek encourages us to pay attention to the order which is the result of human action, but not of human design. Though the theory of this type of order has long tradition, this type of 36 idea enable us to transcend the dualism which views the social phenomena as a comprehension of natural (physis) and conventional (nomos), and to focus to another dimension of social phenomena which is the evolvable and self-regulating structures through the natural selection of rules as to action and perception.
Recommended publications
  • A Hayekian Theory of Social Justice
    A HAYEKIAN THEORY OF SOCIAL JUSTICE Samuel Taylor Morison* As Justice gives every Man a Title to the product of his honest Industry, and the fair Acquisitions of his Ancestors descended to him; so Charity gives every Man a Title to so much of another’s Plenty, as will keep him from ex- tream want, where he has no means to subsist otherwise. – John Locke1 I. Introduction The purpose of this essay is to critically examine Friedrich Hayek’s broadside against the conceptual intelligibility of the theory of social or distributive justice. This theme first appears in Hayek’s work in his famous political tract, The Road to Serfdom (1944), and later in The Constitution of Liberty (1960), but he developed the argument at greatest length in his major work in political philosophy, the trilogy entitled Law, Legis- lation, and Liberty (1973-79). Given that Hayek subtitled the second volume of this work The Mirage of Social Justice,2 it might seem counterintuitive or perhaps even ab- surd to suggest the existence of a genuinely Hayekian theory of social justice. Not- withstanding the rhetorical tenor of some of his remarks, however, Hayek’s actual con- clusions are characteristically even-tempered, which, I shall argue, leaves open the possibility of a revisionist account of the matter. As Hayek understands the term, “social justice” usually refers to the inten- tional doling out of economic rewards by the government, “some pattern of remunera- tion based on the assessment of the performance or the needs of different individuals * Attorney-Advisor, Office of the Pardon Attorney, United States Department of Justice, Washington, D.C.; e- mail: [email protected].
    [Show full text]
  • CATALLACTICS: Hayek's 'Evolutionary' Theory of Economics, Applied to Public Policy and Education Through Competition and Market Forces
    DEV99089 CATALLACTICS: Hayek's 'evolutionary' theory of Economics, applied to public policy and education through competition and market forces. ® Nesta Devine, University of Waikato In this paper I am going, loosely, to use the method described by Michel Foucault as 'genealogy' to shed some light on the assumptions and practices of those who construct education in the form of a series of exchanges between interested parties. By examining the ancestry of these ideas and practices I aim to shed some doubt on their claims to pre- emptive rationality. In part this relies on a challenge to the 'displacement' as Derrida calls it, of ideas from one discipline to another through the medium of metaphor. I am not trying to establish a series of causal links, and I do not discuss here the method of dissemination of these ideas. For listeners/readers interested in the process by which this set of ideas have become common currency, I recommend Thinking the unthinkable by Richard Cockett, (1994) and for New Zealand readers, particularly, First Knights by Paul Harris and Linda Twiname (1998). In this paper I shall use the writings of the 'Austrian School' economist F.A. Hayek, who has been an important source of ideas for economists and public officials seeking to use the principles of economics to reform the nature of government. More recent followers of Hayek in the belief that economics offers guidelines for practice in other fields have called themselves 'Public Choice Theorists'. The principle architects of 'Public Choice Theory' are James Buchanan and Gordon Tullock. Many economists who do not identify themselves in such a way have also adopted the view that the principles of economics can be generally applied to all fields of human interaction, among them Milton Friedman, and the very significant New Zealand public policy bodies, the Treasury and the State Services Commission, who have been the principal agents in the reform of education in New Zealand along economistic lines.
    [Show full text]
  • Notes on Review Essay on Ebenstein and Caldwell
    Friedrich Hayek: Austrian Economist A review of Alan Ebenstein’s Hayek’s Journey and Bruce Caldwell’s Hayek’s Challenge Steven Horwitz Department of Economics St. Lawrence University Canton, NY 13617 TEL (315) 229 5731 FAX (315) 229 5709 email [email protected] Prepared for the Journal of the History of Economic Thought, Spring 2004 Friedrich Hayek: Austrian Economist 1 Friedrich A. Hayek was an Austrian economist. Although this is perhaps not the most controversial claim put forward in the history of economics, it is one that needs to be repeated and revisited from time to time. Over the last twenty to thirty years, there has been an avalanche of scholarly and popular work on Hayek. The scholarly work was likely prompted by his having received the Nobel Prize in 1974 and the subsequent revival of Austrian economics (and the continuing criticisms of, and searches for alternatives to, the mainstream of modern economics). The popular work reflects the revival of classical liberalism more broadly, both in the world of ideas and in the events of the 1980s and 1990s, such as the fall of the Berlin Wall and the rise of the global marketplace. Hayek’s name is invoked as the source of a great number of economic and political ideas these days, both for the better and the worse. Often times, these treatments, especially but not only the popular ones, misunderstand key Hayekian themes. The main reason they do so is that they forget that the entire edifice of Hayek’s social and political thought is built upon the foundations of the ideas he first engaged as a young man, those of the Austrian school of economics.
    [Show full text]
  • A Critique on the Social Justice Perspectives in the Works of Friedrich A. Hayek
    RESEARCH ASSOCIATION for RAIS INTERDISCIPLINARY DOI: 10.5281/zenodo.1215124 MARCH 2018 STUDIES A Critique on the Social Justice Perspectives in the Works of Friedrich A. Hayek Anusha Mahendran Curtin University [email protected] ABSTRACT: Given that the academic work of Friedrich Hayek has received eminent accolades (including the 1974 Nobel Memorial Prize in Economics Sciences) and has been well recognised and widely referenced, this paper reviews the denial of the concept of social justice in many of the academic economic theory papers written by the renowned British-Austrian economist. The paper therefore effectively provides a critical analysis of some of Hayek’s socio-political and economic theories relating to this issue. It attempts to do this by adopting the perspective of an objective and analytical economist with reference to and by examining the content of three of Hayek’s well known economic texts, namely The Road to Serfdom (1944); Law, Legislation and Liberty (1973-79) and the Fatal Conceit Conceit: The Errors of Socialism (1988). KEYWORDS: social justice, economics, Friedrich Hayek 1. Introduction Friedrich August von Hayek (who was also commonly referred to as F.A. Hayek) was an Austrian-British economist and was well known for his staunch defence of classical liberalism (Birner and van Rip 1994). Hayek was born in Vienna, Austria in 1899 and the majority of his perspectives were derived from theories and philosophies from the Austrian School of Economics (Birner and van Rip 1994). 82 MAHENDRAN: A Critique on the Social Justice Perspectives The primary basis of the Austrian School of Economic Thought is centred around the concept of methodological individualism which entails the ideology that the motivations and actions of individuals drive social phenomenon (Boettke and Leeson 2003).
    [Show full text]
  • Hayek on Mill Bruce Caldwell
    Hayek on Mill Bruce Caldwell It is perhaps an understatement to say that trying to understand F. A. Hayek’s assessment of John Stuart Mill is a complicated matter. Hayek referred to Mill frequently. Sometimes, and particularly in The Consti- tution of Liberty (1960), he praised him. What may surprise those who associate both Mill and Hayek with the classical liberal tradition is that more often, and this in writings that both preceded and followed publi- cation of The Constitution of Liberty, Hayek criticized Mill. Moreover, the criticisms were not all of a piece, but focused on different aspects of Mill’s work. Part of the problem is that Mill, like Hayek, made so many different contributions: among those mentioned by Hayek were his System of Logic ([1843] 1973), the Principles of Political Economy ([1848] 1965), and of course On Liberty ([1859] 1977). In addition, Mill’s own views evolved, sometimes rather dramatically, over time. Which Mill—the doctrinaire utilitarian, the romantic, the one impressed by Auguste Comte or the one who disavowed him, the Mill of the early or of the later editions of The Principles, the pre– or post–Harriet Taylor Mill—is the one whose ideas Hayek is examining? Furthermore, it was not just Mill’s own thought, but Correspondence may be addressed to Bruce Caldwell, Department of Economics, Box 90097, Duke University, Durham, NC 27708; e-mail: [email protected]. This paper was pre- pared for a Liberty Fund colloquium, titled “Hayek and the Liberal Tradition,” held in Miami, Florida, on 7–10 December 2006.
    [Show full text]
  • Hayek and After: Hayekian Liberalism As a Research Programme/ Jeremy Shearmur
    HAYEK AND AFTER This book offers a distinctive treatment of Hayek’s ideas as a ‘research programme’. It presents a detailed account of aspects of Hayek’s intellectual development and problems that arise within his work, and offers some broad suggestions of ways in which the programme initiated in his work might be developed further. The book opens with an overview, and then discusses how Popper and Lakatos’s ideas about research programmes might be applied within political theory. There then follows a distinctive presentation of Hayek’s intellectual development up to The Road to Serfdom, together with critical engagement with his later ideas. The discussion draws on a full range of his writings, makes use of some neglected earlier work on social theory and law, and also draws on archival material. The book also makes some unusual comparisons, including discussions of Gaventa and of E.P.Thompson, and presents controversial suggestions on how a ‘Hayekian’ approach should be further developed. The book will appeal to anyone with an interest in Hayek’s work and to those concerned with twentieth century intellectual history. It offers a distinctive interpretation of his views and a particularly wide-ranging survey of what in the author’s view now needs to be done in the pursuit of a Hayekian approach to classical liberalism. Jeremy Shearmur was educated at the London School of Economics, where he also worked as Assistant to Professor Sir Karl Popper. He has taught at the universities of Edinburgh and Manchester, at George Mason University and is a former Director of Studies at the Centre for Policy Studies in London.
    [Show full text]
  • F. A. Hayek on the Role of Reason in Human Affairs Linda Catherine Raeder
    University of Richmond UR Scholarship Repository Master's Theses Student Research 8-1993 F. A. Hayek on the role of reason in human affairs Linda Catherine Raeder Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.richmond.edu/masters-theses Part of the Political Science Commons Recommended Citation Raeder, Linda Catherine, "F. A. Hayek on the role of reason in human affairs" (1993). Master's Theses. Paper 831. This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Research at UR Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of UR Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. F. A. HAYEK ON THE ROLE OF REASON IN HUMAN AFFAIRS by Linda Catherine Raeder Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the University of Richmond in Candidacy for the Degree of M.A. in Political Science August 1993 Thesis Director: Dr. Ellis M. West This-study examines the views of F. A. Hayek on the role of reason in human affairs. The author explicates certain elements of Hayekian theory that bear on this issue-his views on the nature of mind, rules, law, and cultural evolution-and discusses the characteristics of both the constructivist and critical "kinds of rationalism" Hayek identifies. She then examines the views of various critics who have challenged Hayek's argument. She concludes that, contrary to certain critics, 1) the distinction he draws between constructivist and critical rationalism is meaningful and that the two kinds of rationalism appear to be related to certain political views; 2) whether Hayek, despite his criticism of the constructivistic conceit, should himself be considered a constructivist depends on whether one adopts a broad or narrow interpretation of constructivism; and 3) Hayek's method of social criticism-what he terms "immanent criticism"-does provide the basis for a meaningful critical theory.
    [Show full text]
  • ECONOMIC FLAWS in COMPUTERIZED SOCIALISM by Joseph Kane
    No. 17-40 Summer 2017 MERCATUS GRADUATE POLICY ESSAY ECONOMIC FLAWS IN COMPUTERIZED SOCIALISM by Joseph Kane The opinions expressed in this Graduate Policy Essay are the author’s and do not represent official positions of the Mercatus Center or George Mason University. Abstract Voices from Oskar Lange in the 1970s to those more contemporary hold that if only technology could become advanced enough, central planning would work. This paper analyzes whether current, or any conceivable, proposals that the radically connected modern age could solve the knowledge problem and make central planning a viable method of economic organization. It finds that claims that technology can solve the problems with central planning simply miss the point of the Austrian critique in the socialist calculation debate. Central planning, using the Internet or any other means, still cannot dispense with the competitive market process without which the discovery of the information necessary for economic calculation is impossible. Author Bio Joe Kane is a Technology Policy Associate at R Street Institute and an Alumnus of the Mercatus MA Fellowship. He holds an MA in economics from George Mason University and a BA in political science from Grove City College. Committee Members Peter Boettke, University Professor of Economics and Philosophy, George Mason University, vice president and director of the F. A. Hayek Program for Advanced Study in Philosophy, Politics, and Economics, Mercatus Center at George Mason University Virgil Storr, Senior Research Fellow, Senior Director of Academic and Student Programs, and Don C. Lavoie Research Fellow with the F. A. Hayek Program for Advanced Study in Philosophy, Politics, and Economics at the Mercatus Center at George Mason University Jayme Lemke, Senior Research Fellow, Associate Director of Academic and Student Programs, and Senior Fellow with the F.
    [Show full text]
  • Hayek's 'Extended Order'
    The Irrationality of the Extended Order: The Fatal Conceit of F. A. Hayek Larry J. Sechrest* Sul Ross State University Friedrich A. Hayek (1899-1992) is considered by many to have been one of the true intellectual giants of the twentieth century. He was without doubt one of the most influential thinkers of his time. Moreover, Hayek is almost universally characterized as a dedicated-even radical-proponent of capitalism. The questionable validity of such a characterization is one of the key issues to be dealt with in this essay. Part of Hayek's fame stems from the fact that, in 1974, he shared the Nobel Memorial Prize in Economic Science with the socialist Gunnar Myrdal. The prize was awarded "for their pioneering work in the theory of money and economic fluctuations and for their penetrating analysis of the interdependence of economic, social, and institutional phenomena" (Machlup 1976, xv-mi). 1 There seem to have been, in other words, two different reasons why Hayek was deemed worthy of the award. The primary reason was his brilliant technical work during the 1930s on money and credit conditions and their impact on business cycles. The secondary reason was his provocative analysis of the comparative efficiency of socioeconomic systems undertaken during the 1940s and 1950s. During the last fifty years of Hayek's life, however, most of his work was devoted to political and social philosophy, legal theory, and the philosophy of science rather than to economic theory. Both the breadth of his knowledge and the scope of his work were .enormous.2 He discussed everything from anthropology to the evolution of language to the role of religion in Western civilization.
    [Show full text]
  • The Fatal Conceit of Foreign Intervention
    The Fatal Conceit of Foreign Intervention Christopher J. Coyne and Rachel L. Mathers ∗ Abstract The fatal conceit is the assumption that the world can be shaped according to human desires. This paper argues that the logic of the fatal conceit can be applied to foreign interventions which go beyond the limits of what can be rationally constructed by reason alone. In suffering from the fatal conceit, these interventions are characterized by: (1) the realization that intentions do not equal results, (2) a reliance on top-down planning, (3) the view of development as a technological issue, (4) a reliance on bureaucracy over markets, and (5) the primacy of collectivism over individualism. These characteristics explain why interventions extending beyond the limits of what can be rationally constructed tend to fail. JEL Codes: B53, O1, P00 Keywords: fatal conceit, foreign aid, foreign intervention, rational constructivism ∗ West Virginia University, Department of Economics, P.O. Box 6025, Morgantown, WV 26506-6025. Christopher J. Coyne ( [email protected] ) and Rachel L. Mathers ( [email protected] ). Coyne was the F.A. Hayek Fellow at the London School of Economic and Political Science during the initial writing of this paper and gratefully acknowledges the support of the STICERD Centre at the LSE. The Fatal Conceit of Foreign Intervention “The curious task of economics is to demonstrate to men how little they really know about what they imagine they can design.” --F.A. Hayek (1988: 76) 1. Introduction In his last book, F.A. Hayek (1988) analyzed the “fatal conceit,” which is the presumption that “man is able to shape the world around him according to his wishes” (27).
    [Show full text]
  • Economics, Knowledge, and Ignorance: the Case of F.A. Hayek and T.W
    1 Economics, Knowledge, and Ignorance: The case of F.A. Hayek and T.W. Hutchison. Keanu Telles (University of Brasília). ABSTRACT. In the controversial methodological disputes of the 1930s, F.A. Hayek and T.W. Hutchison were on opposite sides. Hutchison is well-known for being the first economist to introduce, in some broadly and loosely sense, the influences of logical positivism, the Popperian falsificationism and a testability criterion into economics. Hutchison was mainly reacting in opposition to the aprioristic deductivism of Ludwig von Mises and, in Hutchison’s view, Lionel Robbins and F.A. Hayek - Hutchison associated the tautological apodictic method as essentially empirically empty, anti-fallible and utopian. Though the severe critics to Hayek in the 1930s, in Hutchison’s mature methodological writings a remarkable convergence is noticed with Hayek’s methodology of complex phenomena and his emphasis in the limitations of explanation, prediction and control in social and economic sciences. I explore the connections, similarities, and differences in Hayek mature methodology and Hutchison’s later view of a more humble scope of economics than he advocated. I argue that Hayek and Hutchison have in common an appreciation for the epistemic dimension of fallible knowledge, ignorance, and uncertainty - although each one internalizes this notion differently in respective to their singular and particular methodological position. Key-words: F.A. Hayek, T.W. Hutchison, knowledge, ignorance, methodology, empiricism, inductivism, falsificationism, explanation of principle, pattern prevision. JEL: B25, B31, B41, B53. RESUMO. Nas controvérsias metodológicas dos anos 1930, F.A. Hayek e T.W. Hutchison estavam de lados opostos. Hutchison é notório por ter sido o primeiro economista a introduzir de forma consistente as influências do positivismo lógico, do falsificacionismo Popperiano e um critério de testabilidade na teoria econômica.
    [Show full text]
  • Europe and China: the Fatal Conceit Andrew Neil Fourteenth Annual
    1 Europe and China: the Fatal Conceit Andrew Neil Fourteenth Annual Hayek Lecture Sponsored by the Institute of Economic Affairs and CQS Management Ltd One Great George Street, Westminster, London 28 November 2005 IEA web publications are designed to promote discussion on economic issues and the role of markets in solving economic and social problems. Copyright remains with the author. If you would like to contact the author in the first instance please contact [email protected]. As with all IEA publications, the views expressed in IEA web publications are those of the author. 2 Of all the great insights that Friedrich August von Hayek bequeathed to us in his work, one in particular shines out today. For its truth has never been more evident, its application never more universal. And it is one that the Institute of Economic Affairs has done most to educate politicians and opinion formers about. It is that running through the ideological and political divisions of human history are two distinct and different ways of looking at the world. Between them is a deep and irreconcilable divide. One Hayek called constructivist rationalism. The other he called evolutionary rationalism. Not phrases to trip off the tongue, to be sure. JK Galbraith was always the better wordsmith - if not the better economist. Hayek spent a lifetime arguing that constructivist rationalism is economically and philosophically flawed because it assumes that 3 “all social institutions are, or ought to be, the product of deliberate design”.1 Hayek later famously called this the Fatal Conceit2. Those who follow this route believe they have it within their power to build, organise and mould society so that it conforms to their concept of what is just and efficient.
    [Show full text]