Free Speech and Private Law in German Constitutional Theory Peter E

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Free Speech and Private Law in German Constitutional Theory Peter E Maryland Law Review Volume 48 | Issue 2 Article 3 Free Speech and Private Law in German Constitutional Theory Peter E. Quint Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.law.umaryland.edu/mlr Part of the International Law Commons Recommended Citation Peter E. Quint, Free Speech and Private Law in German Constitutional Theory , 48 Md. L. Rev. 247 (1989) Available at: http://digitalcommons.law.umaryland.edu/mlr/vol48/iss2/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Academic Journals at DigitalCommons@UM Carey Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Maryland Law Review by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@UM Carey Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. MARYLAND LAW REVIEW VOLUME 48 1989 NUMBER 2 0 Copyright Maryland Law Review, Inc. 1989 Articles FREE SPEECH AND PRIVATE LAW IN GERMAN CONSTITUTIONAL THEORY PETER E. QuiNT* TABLE OF CONTENTS I. Introduction ........................................... 248 II. T he Li'th Case ......................................... 252 A. Historicaland Doctrinal Background ................... 252 B. The Liuth Opinion, Part I.- The "Influence" of the Constitution on Private Law .......................... 258 C. The Theory of the Lith Case and the American "State Action" Doctrine .................................... 2 65 D. A Return to the Lith Opinion, Part II: Free Speech and "General Laws .... ................................ 281 III. The M ephisto Case ..................................... 290 A. Artistic Endeavor and the Rights of Personality .......... 290 B. The Scope of Constitutional Review in Mephisto ........ 302 C. Mephisto: Implications and American Contrasts ........ 307 1. Deference and the "Preferred Position"............. 307 2. Primacy of Principle or Primacy of Result ........... 310 0 Copyright 1989 by Peter E. Quint. * Professor of Law, University of Maryland School of Law. A.B., Harvard Univer- sity, 1961; LL.B., 1964; Diploma in Law, Oxford University, 1965. For helpful com- ments on earlier drafts of this article I am grateful to Professors Wolfgang Vitzthum (University of Tubingen), Winfried Brugger (University of Mannheim), and William Reynolds, Edward Tomlinson and Robin West (University of Maryland School of Law). I have benefited greatly from their advice, but I bear full responsibility for any remaining errors of commission 'or omission. I am also indebted to Eva Holland for editorial assistance. 248 MARYLAND LAW REVIEW [VOL. 48:247 3. Constitutional Balancing and Judicial Deference ...... 312 4. Libel, State Interests, and State Action .............. 314 IV. The Deutschland-Magazin Case .......................... 318 V. Free Speech and Private Law in the 1980s: B6'l and Wallraff ................................................ 330 VI. Conclusion ............................................ 339 A PPEN D IX ................................................. 348 I. INTRODUCTION The promulgation in 1949 of the Bonn Constitution--or Basic Law-marked the re-emergence of German political life. The fram- ers of the Basic Law rejected the authoritarian style of previous political traditions and sought to erect, on a more durable founda- tion, a political order reflecting the republican and libertarian prin- ciples of the Weimar Constitution.' The framers also undertook an experiment that was almost completely new in German constitu- tional history-and, indeed rare anywhere in the world-a compre- hensive system of judicial review of legislative and executive action for conformity with constitutional principles. Although the propriety of constitutional review had been widely debated under the Weimar Constitution, and there were some in- stances of judicial review by the ordinary courts, the institution was by no means firmly established during that period.2 In contrast, the 1. The political history of Germany in the 19th and 20th centuries can be seen as a struggle for hegemony between liberal and authoritarian movements, with the authorita- rian movements most often in the ascendant until the founding of the present Federal Republic. Against the background of the conservative reaction to the French Revolution in the first half of the 19th century, the abortive liberal revolution of 1848 gave rise to the Frankfurt (Paulskirche) Constitution of 1849 which, however, never came into effect. See generally P. STEARNS, 1848: THE REVOLUTIONARY TIDE IN EUROPE ch. 7 (1974). This was followed in 1871 by Bismarck's Constitution for a united Germany which, although it established a parliamentary assembly, rested on the theory that all political power was derived from the princes whose dominions coalesced to form the empire. G. CRAIG, GERMANY: 1866-1945, at 43-44 (1978). After the defeat of Germany in World War 1,the Constitution of the new Weimar Republic broke with this tradition by proclaiming that all political power was derived from the people. WEIMAR CONSTITUTION [WRV] art. I. The Weimar Constitution established representative institutions, sought to protect indi- vidual liberty against the state, and provided certain guarantees of social welfare. The Weimar Republic was destroyed by the Nazi dictatorship which proclaimed the so-called "Fifhrer-principle" in which all "law" was derived from the will of one man. After World War lI-and in reaction to the Nazi period-the Basic Law of 1949 was founded essentially on the liberal, social and democratic notions of the Weimar and Frankfurt (Paulskirche) Constitutions and traces its lineage to those documents. 2. K. SCHLAICH, DAS BUNDESVERFASSUNGSGERICHT 1-3, 60-63 (1985); D. KOMMERS, JUDICIAL POLITICS IN WEST GERMANY: A STUDY OF THE FEDERAL CONSTITUTIONAL COURT 30-42 (1976); Casper, Guardians of the Constitution, 53 S. CAL. L. REV. 773, 777-78 (1980). 19891 GERMAN CONSTITUTIONAL THEORY 249 Basic Law established the Federal Constitutional Court, a tribunal whose principal function was the adjudication of constitutional questions. In creating a special court for constitutional matters, the framers took account of the continental tradition that viewed the regular judiciary as a special kind of bureaucracy, whose pretentions and abilities would not ordinarily extend to the invocation of consti- tutional norms against statutory law.' In light of this tradition a spe- cial court for the decision of constitutional questions was required.4 The Bonn Constitution was a product of the western liberal tra- dition which addresses certain central issues of popular sovereignty and individual rights. Many of the concerns reflected in the Basic Law are similar to those addressed in the American Constitution and it was to be expected that many of the constitutional issues that over the years were subject to adjudication in the United States would ultimately come before the West German Constitutional Court. Of those common concerns, the protection of freedom of expression holds a central position. The struggle over the law of seditious libel formed the background of an important aspect of American constitutional history; the totalitarian information policy See also Deik & Rheinstein, The Development of French and German Law, 24 GEO. L.J. 551, 581 n.86 (1936). 3. See, e.g., M. CAPPELLETTI, JUDICIAL REVIEW IN THE CONTEMPORARY WORLD 62-63 (1971) ("IT]he bulk of Europe's judiciary seems psychologically incapable of the value- oriented, quasi-political functions involved in judicial review"); see also Cappelletti & Ad- ams,Judicial Review of Legislation: European Antecedents and Adaptations, 79 HARV. L. REV. 1207, 1215-16 (1966);J. MERRYMAN, THE CIVIL LAW TRADITION 34-38 (2d ed. 1985). But see BASIC LAW IGG] art. 1, § 3 (ordinary judiciary also bound by constitution); K. SCHLAICH, supra note 2, at 13-15. 4. In contrast to the ordinary judiciary-which resembles the career civil service in appointment, tenure and promotion-the judges of the Federal Constitutional Court are chosen equally by the two houses of the German parliament. GG art. 94, § i. This political process of choice is intended to encourage the selection of individuals whose views and experience are broader than those of the ordinary judiciary. Nonetheless, any prospective judge must have completed a legal education, and a significant minority of the judges of the Constitutional Court must be drawn from the ordinary courts. See Bundesverfassungsgerichtsgesetz [BVerfGG] § 2-3 (Constitutional Court Act). The concept of a special Constitutional Court, distinct from the ordinary judiciary, is derived from a similar institution created in Austria in the 1920s under the intellectual influence of Hans Kelsen. See M. CAPPELLETTI, supra note 3, at 46-47. Like a number of other German courts, the Constitutional Court almost never sits as a single body. Rather, it is divided into two separate panels or "senates" which have distinct areas of jurisdiction and are, for almost all purposes, two separate courts. Moreover, an increas- ingly important segment of the Court's work is performed by "chambers" of three judges, which have the power to sustain or reject certain constitutional complaints in clear cases. See BVerfGG § § 15a, 93b, 93c; Zuck, Die Ftinfie Novelle zum Bundesverfassungs- gerichtsgesetz, 1986 NEUE JURISTI$CHE WOCHENSCHRIFT [NJW 968. See also infra n.254. See generally Vitzthum, Das Vorprifungsverfahrenfir Verfassungsbeschwerden, in FESTSCHRIFT Rl OTTO BACHOF ZUM 70.GEBURTSTAG 293-320 (G. Piitmer ed. 1984). 250 MARYLAND LAW REVIEW [VOL. 48:247 of Josef Goebbels had an immediate cautionary effect on the draft- ers of the
Recommended publications
  • The Framers' Constitution: Toward a Theory of Principled Constitutionalism
    The Framers’ Constitution: Toward a Theory of Principled Constitutionalism By Geoffrey R. Stone and William P. Marshall September 2011 All expressions of opinion are those of the author or authors. The American Constitution Society (ACS) takes no position on specific legal or policy initiatives. The Framers’ Constitution: Toward a Theory of Principled Constitutionalism Geoffrey R. Stone* & William P. Marshall** For the past forty years, political conservatives have effectively framed the national debate over constitutional interpretation. According to the conservatives’ narrative, their approach to constitutional interpretation adheres to the true meaning of the Constitution and to the Rule of Law, whereas “liberal” jurisprudence is concerned only with achieving specific desired outcomes, without regard to the text, history or meaning of the Constitution. The gains that conservatives have achieved by characterizing the debate in this manner cannot be overstated. Because the public has generally accepted the conservative account, Republican presidents have been much more aggressive than their Democratic counterparts in appointing judges with strongly ideological inclinations, and constitutional doctrine has veered sharply to the right as conservative jurists have become ever bolder in their pursuit of politically conservative results. Meanwhile, at the grassroots level, a new strain of conservative constitutionalism has recently emerged that insists that even such traditional legislative measures as civil rights laws and social welfare programs are unconstitutional, reflecting an even more aggressive conception of conservative judicial ideology. The conservative constitutional narrative is deeply unprincipled and patently wrong, both in its defense of conservative judicial ideology and in its attack on what conservatives deride as a result-oriented “liberal” jurisprudence.
    [Show full text]
  • Guantanamo, Boumediene, and Jurisdiction-Stripping: the Mpei Rial President Meets the Imperial Court" (2009)
    University of Minnesota Law School Scholarship Repository Constitutional Commentary 2009 Guantanamo, Boumediene, and Jurisdiction- Stripping: The mpI erial President Meets the Imperial Court Martin J. Katz Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.umn.edu/concomm Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Katz, Martin J., "Guantanamo, Boumediene, and Jurisdiction-Stripping: The mpeI rial President Meets the Imperial Court" (2009). Constitutional Commentary. 699. https://scholarship.law.umn.edu/concomm/699 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the University of Minnesota Law School. It has been accepted for inclusion in Constitutional Commentary collection by an authorized administrator of the Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Article GUANTANAMO, BOUMEDIENE, AND JURISDICTION-STRIPPING: THE IMPERIAL PRESIDENT MEETS THE IMPERIAL COURT Martin J. Katz* INTRODUCTION In Boumediene v. Bush,1 the Supreme Court struck down a major pillar of President Bush's war on terror: the indefinite de­ tention of terror suspects in Guantanamo Bay, Cuba. The Court held that even non-citizen prisoners held by the United States government on foreign soil could challenge their confinement by seeking a writ of habeas corpus in federal court, and that the procedures the government had provided for such challenges were not an adequate substitute for the writ." As a habeas corpus case, Boumediene may well be revolu­ tionary.3 However, Boumediene is more than merely a habeas * Interim Dean and Associate Professor of Law. University of Denver College of Law; Yale Law School. J.D. 1991: Harvard College. A.B. 1987. Thanks to Alan Chen.
    [Show full text]
  • Religion in the Public Schools November 2019
    Religion in the Public Schools Published online in TASB School Law eSource TASB Legal Services Texas Association of School Boards 512.467.3610 • 800.580.5345 [email protected] Religion in the Public Schools TASB Legal Services Legal Background Several federal and state laws form the foundation that guides public school districts in navigating the complex area of religion in schools. First Amendment The First Amendment to the U.S. Constitution states, “Congress shall make no law respecting an establishment of religion, or prohibiting the free exercise thereof; or abridging the freedom of speech . .” U.S. Const. amend. I. The First Amendment applies to school districts as political subdivisions of the state through the Fourteenth Amendment. Engel v. Vitale, 370 U.S. 421 (1962). Together, these laws protect private religious expression but prohibit government action to advance, coerce, or endorse religion in the public schools. Plaintiffs may sue the government for violations of the First Amendment through 42 U.S.C. § 1983 (Section 1983). Establishment Clause The First Amendment Establishment Clause, “Congress shall make no law respecting an establishment of religion . ,” prohibits school districts and their employees from establishing religion. U.S. Const. amend. I. Schools must not advance, coerce, or endorse a particular religion or religion over non-religion. Cnty. of Allegheny v. ACLU Greater Pittsburgh Chapter, 492 U.S. 573 (1989). The U.S. Supreme Court has exercised special vigilance over compliance with the Establishment Clause in elementary and secondary schools because “families entrust public schools with the education of their children, but condition their trust on the understanding that the classroom will not purposely be used to advance religious views that may conflict with the private beliefs of the student and his or her family.” Edwards v.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 6 Constitutional Principles Affecting a Locality's Land Use
    Chapter 6 Constitutional Principles Affecting a Locality’s Land Use Powers 6-100 Introduction The power to regulate the use of land is a legislative power, residing in the state, which must be exercised in accordance with constitutional principles. Board of Supervisors of Fairfax County v. Southland Corp., 224 Va. 514, 297 S.E.2d 718 (1982). A locality’s exercise of its land use powers, particularly the zoning power, invokes numerous constitutional principles: Constitutional Principles That May Be Affected By the Exercise of Local Land Use Powers Procedural due process Free exercise of religion Substantive due process Free speech Equal protection The right to bear arms Just compensation or takings Search and seizure (see section 27-400) Establishment of religion Supremacy (preemption) (see chapter 7) The numerous constitutional principles that may be affected by local land use regulations may have inspired a United States Supreme Court justice to ask in a dissenting opinion: “[I]f a policeman must know the Constitution, then why not a planner?” San Diego Gas & Electric Co. v. San Diego, 450 U.S. 621, 661, 101 S. Ct. 1287, 1309, 579 fn. 26 (1981) (Brennan, J.). At bottom, in the land use context these constitutional principles seek to ensure: (1) fairness in the procedures; (2) fairness in the regulations; (3) fairness in the implementation of the regulations; (4) protection of certain individual activities; and (5) freedom from certain governmental activities. 6-200 The due process clause The Fifth Amendment to the United States Constitution provides in part that “No person shall . be deprived of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law .
    [Show full text]
  • Human Rights and Constitution Making Human Rights and Constitution Making
    HUMAN RIGHTS AND CONSTITUTION MAKING HUMAN RIGHTS AND CONSTITUTION MAKING New York and Geneva, 2018 II HUMAN RIGHTS AND CONSTITUTION MAKING Requests to reproduce excerpts or to photocopy should be addressed to the Copyright Clearance Center at copyright.com. All other queries on rights and licenses, including subsidiary rights, should be addressed to: United Nations Publications, 300 East 42nd St, New York, NY 10017, United States of America. E-mail: [email protected]; website: un.org/publications United Nations publication issued by the Office of the United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights (OHCHR) Photo credit: © Ververidis Vasilis / Shutterstock.com The designations employed and the presentation of the material in this publication do not imply the expression of any opinion whatsoever on the part of the Secretariat of the United Nations concerning the legal status of any country, territory, city or area, or of its authorities, or concerning the delimitation of its frontiers or boundaries. Symbols of United Nations documents are composed of capital letters combined with figures. Mention of such a figure indicates a reference to a United Nations document. HR/PUB/17/5 © 2018 United Nations All worldwide rights reserved Sales no.: E.17.XIV.4 ISBN: 978-92-1-154221-9 eISBN: 978-92-1-362251-3 CONTENTS III CONTENTS INTRODUCTION .................................................................................. 1 I. CONSTITUTIONAL REFORMS AND HUMAN RIGHTS ......................... 2 A. Why a rights-based approach to constitutional reform? .................... 3 1. Framing the issue .......................................................................3 2. The constitutional State ................................................................6 3. Functions of the constitution in the contemporary world ...................7 4. The constitution and democratic governance ..................................8 5.
    [Show full text]
  • A Tale of Two Textualists: a Critical Comparison of Justices Black and Scalia Michael J
    College of William & Mary Law School William & Mary Law School Scholarship Repository Faculty Publications Faculty and Deans 1994 A Tale of Two Textualists: A Critical Comparison of Justices Black and Scalia Michael J. Gerhardt Repository Citation Gerhardt, Michael J., "A Tale of Two Textualists: A Critical Comparison of Justices Black and Scalia" (1994). Faculty Publications. 990. https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/facpubs/990 Copyright c 1994 by the authors. This article is brought to you by the William & Mary Law School Scholarship Repository. https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/facpubs ARTICLES A TALE OF TWO TEXTUALISTS: A CRITICAL COMPARISON OF JUSTICES BLACK AND SCALIA MICHAEL J. GERHARDT* The idea that Justices Hugo Black and Antonin Scalia have anything in common jurisprudentially is counterintuitive. Justice Black is associated with the progressive social and economic legislation symbolized by the New Deal and with judicial activism in protecting the poor and disen­ franchised.1 He is beloved by many liberals as a champion of individual rights, especially freedom of speech and of the press. In contrast, Justice Scalia is revered by conservatives as a true believer-combating the rising tide of liberalism, big government, and judicial activism-set on restoring traditional notions of federalism and judicial restraint.2 Any effort to liken these two Justices makes both liberals and conservatives recoil. * Professor of Law, Marshall-Wythe School of Law, The College of William and Mary. B.A. Yale University; M.Sc. London School of Economics; J.D. University of Chicago. I am grateful for the encouragement and helpful comments on earlier drafts I received from Marc Arkin, Erwin Chemerinsky, George Cochran, Neal Devins, Jill Fisch, Tracy Higgins, Michael Herz, Sandy Levinson, Chip Lupu, Tracey Maclin, John McGinnis, Peter Shane, Bill Treanor, Steve Wermiel, and Ron Wright.
    [Show full text]
  • What the Heller?: an Originalist Critique of Justice Scalia's Second Amendment Jurisprudence
    University of Cincinnati Law Review Volume 82 Issue 3 Article 3 August 2018 What the Heller?: An Originalist Critique of Justice Scalia's Second Amendment Jurisprudence Enrique Schaerer Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.uc.edu/uclr Recommended Citation Enrique Schaerer, What the Heller?: An Originalist Critique of Justice Scalia's Second Amendment Jurisprudence, 82 U. Cin. L. Rev. 795 (2018) Available at: https://scholarship.law.uc.edu/uclr/vol82/iss3/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by University of Cincinnati College of Law Scholarship and Publications. It has been accepted for inclusion in University of Cincinnati Law Review by an authorized editor of University of Cincinnati College of Law Scholarship and Publications. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Schaerer: What the Heller?: An Originalist Critique of Justice Scalia's Sec WHAT THE HELLER?: AN ORIGINALIST CRITIQUE OF JUSTICE SCALIA'S SECOND AMENDMENT JURISPRUDENCE Enrique Schaerer* In District of Columbia v. Heller, Justice Scalia construed the Second Amendment based on sound textualist principles, as guaranteeing an individual right to keep and bear arms. But to the extent he defined the scope of this right indeterminately, he failed to abide by his originalist principles. This Article argues that the Second Amendment should protect, as a threshold, weapons that can be fairly traced back to weapons in common use at the time of the Framing, rather than, as Justice Scalia suggested, weapons in common use at some ever- changing "present" time. To subject the Second Amendment right to a present-daypopularity contest, as Justice Scalia appears to do, is to put this right on ground that is forever uncertain, unstable, and ultimately nonoriginalist.
    [Show full text]
  • Constitutional Complaint and the Protection of Citizens the Constitutional Rights
    Constitutional Complaint and the Protection of Citizens the Constitutional Rights I Dewa Gede Palguna Judge at the Constitutional Court of the Republic of Indonesia Jalan Medan Merdeka Barat No. 6,Central Jakarta E-mail: [email protected] Abstract Constitutional complaint is one of important issues to be dealt with by severral countries issues adopting constitutional court in their national legal system and the Federal Constitutional Court Germany (Bundesverfassungsgericht) is considered by expert as one of the most advance mechanism among countries in dealing with the issue. Generally speaking, constitutional complaint can be described as a complaint or lawsuit filed by an individual citizen who deems his or her constitutional right (s) has been violates by act or omission of public institution or public official. Mostly, such a complaint can only be filed it theere is no other legal remedy available or all legal remedies available have been exhausted. The Constitutional Court of The Republic of Indonesia however is not entrusted with authority to hear constitutional complaint case not withstanding the fact that statistical data on judicial review cases filed by many petitioners before the Court were substantially constitutional complaint issues. It means that, empirically giving the Court to hear constitutional complaint case is necessarily pivotal and theoritically, the Court has the very foundation to be entrusted withq such authority. Considering the complex mechanism to amend the Constitution of 1945, which exhaustively deserible the court’s authorities, this article offers the lawmaker a theoretical insight tio give the Court a limited authority to hear constitutional complaint case by the way of amending the law on Constitutional Court.
    [Show full text]
  • Three Concepts of Children's Constitutional Rights: Reflections on the Enjoyment Theory
    THREE CONCEPTS OF CHILDREN'S CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHTS: REFLECTIONS ON THE ENJOYMENT THEORY Laurence D. Houlgate I. THE CHILD: A PERSON ORA NON-PERSON IN CUSTODY? Attempts to extend constitutional rights to children did not succeed in American law until the late 1960s, when the Su- preme Court declared that "neither the Fourteenth Amend- ment nor the Bill of Rights is for adults alone."' In the case of In re Gault, the Supreme Court pronounced that juveniles are entitled to a variety of procedural protections under the Con- stitution.2 For example, they must be given adequate, timely, written notice of any allegations against them.' If they are in danger of losing their liberty they are to be afforded the right to counsel,4 the right against incrimination,5 and the right to confront and cross-examine opposing witnesses under oath." Subsequent cases have emphasized juveniles' rights to proof beyond a reasonable doubt' and protection against double jeopardy.8 There is a temptation to characterize the Court's decisions on children's rights during the period from 1968 to 1980 with the statement of Justice Blackmun in Planned Parenthoodof CentralMissouri v. Danforth.9 In writing the majority opinion, Blackmun wrote that "[clonstitutional rights do not mature and come into being magically only when one attains the state-defined age of majority. Minors, as well as adults, are protected by the Constitution and possess constitutional rights."'0 Almost as frequently cited in characterizing this pe- riod is the statement of Justice Fortas, who wrote the major- ity opinion in a case that extended free speech rights to chil- Professor of Philosophy, California Polytechnic State University.
    [Show full text]
  • The Constitutionality of Federal Jurisdiction-Stripping Legislation and the History of State Judicial Selection and Tenure, 98 Virginia Law Review
    Vanderbilt University Law School Scholarship@Vanderbilt Law Vanderbilt Law School Faculty Publications Faculty Scholarship 2012 The onsC titutionality of Federal Jurisdiction- Stripping Legislation and the History of State Judicial Selection and Tenure Brian T. Fitzpatrick Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.vanderbilt.edu/faculty-publications Part of the Constitutional Law Commons, Judges Commons, and the Jurisdiction Commons Recommended Citation Brian T. Fitzpatrick, The Constitutionality of Federal Jurisdiction-Stripping Legislation and the History of State Judicial Selection and Tenure, 98 Virginia Law Review. 839 (2012) Available at: https://scholarship.law.vanderbilt.edu/faculty-publications/592 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at Scholarship@Vanderbilt Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Vanderbilt Law School Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of Scholarship@Vanderbilt Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. +(,1 2 1/,1( Citation: 98 Va. L. Rev. 839 2012 Content downloaded/printed from HeinOnline (http://heinonline.org) Wed Jan 9 12:51:39 2013 -- Your use of this HeinOnline PDF indicates your acceptance of HeinOnline's Terms and Conditions of the license agreement available at http://heinonline.org/HOL/License -- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text. -- To obtain permission to use this article beyond the scope of your HeinOnline license, please use: https://www.copyright.com/ccc/basicSearch.do? &operation=go&searchType=0 &lastSearch=simple&all=on&titleOrStdNo=0042-6601 Retrieved from DiscoverArchive, Vanderbilt University’s Institutional Repository Originally Published as Brian T. Fitzpatrick, The Constitutionality of Federal Jurisdiction-stripping Legislation and the History of State Judicial Selection and Tenure in 98 Va.
    [Show full text]
  • Rule of Law and Due Process: a Comparative View of the United States and Japan
    RULE OF LAW AND DUE PROCESS: A COMPARATIVE VIEW OF THE UNITED STATES AND JAPAN NORIHO URABE* I INTRODUCTION: RULE OF LAW AND RECHTSSTAAT Although this author does not know whether the phrase "Rule of Law" is popular in the United States outside of jurisprudential discussions, it seems that in Japan the term "Rule of Law" (ho no shihai) is used less often than the word Rechtsstaat (hochi-koku or hochi kokka), or "state based on law" or "ruled by law." For instance, when a serious illegal activity or crime has been committed, a prosecutor or other concerned government official often states, "This kind of illegal activity is never permissible in the state ruled by law (hochi kokka)." The hochi kokka means something like a state that preserves the public peace or protects people from crime. This is far different from the Anglo-American concept of the Rule of Law. Therefore, when Japanese legal scholars discuss the Rule of Law, the first problem to be discussed is the difference between the Rule of Law and the Rechtsstaat, both of which have been imported into Japanese law despite their disparate origins in Anglo- American and German law. Since Albert Venn Dicey advanced it as the pride of the English Constitution in the nineteenth century,' the modern Rule of Law has meant many things to many people. Therefore, it is difficult to define the meaning of the Rule of Law briefly and exactly. But we can say that the core of the Rule of Law, which has been supported consistently as a fundamental principle of the English and American Constitutions, is that governmental power be bound strictly by law in order to protect individual freedom or liberty.
    [Show full text]
  • The Rule of Law, the Separation of Powers and Judicial Independence in Canada
    Chapter 48 The Rule of Law, the Separation of Powers and Judicial Independence in Canada Warren J. Newman* The Constitution of Canada was modelled on the British tradition of unwritten principles and conventions governing the exercise of legal power to produce a constitutional mon- archy, parliamentary democracy, and responsible government, as well as the American paradigm of constitutional supremacy embodied in written provisions, required in turn by the federal rather than unitary structure of the state. This hybrid model is reflected in the Canadian understanding of the rule of law, which is embodied implicitly in the preamble to the Constitution Act, 1867— Canada was to enjoy ‘a Constitution simi- lar in Principle to that of the United Kingdom’—and explicitly in the preamble to the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms (itself a part of the Constitution Act, 1982)— ‘Whereas Canada is founded upon principles which recognize the supremacy of God and the rule of law’. The idea of the rule of law is also intrinsic to provisions such as section 7 of the Charter, guaranteeing the right to life, liberty, and security of the per- son and the right not to be deprived thereof ‘except in accordance with the principles of fundamental justice’; section 15, protecting and expanding upon Dicey’s1 understanding * BA, BCL, LL.B (McGill), LL.M (Osgoode), Ad E; of the Bars of Quebec and Ontario; Senior General Counsel, Constitutional, Administrative and International Law Section, Department of Justice of Canada. The views expressed in this chapter do not bind the Department. 1 Albert Venn Dicey, Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution, 10th ed.
    [Show full text]