Fundamentalist Christian Schools

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Fundamentalist Christian Schools Fundamentalist Christian Schools Is the Sexual Revolution Over? An Interview with Sol Gordon and Rob Tielman Sidney Hook Debates Rabbi Homnick on Jewish Fundamentalism Also: Dr. Benjamin Spock, Konstantin Kolenda, Matthew les Spetter, Michael Ruse, Betty McCollister, Edd Doerr on Fetal "Personhood," and Peter Popoff's Broken Window! FALL 1987, VOL. 7, NO. 4 Contents ISSN 0272-0701 3 LETTERS TO THE EDITOR 19 EDITORIALS 20 ON THE BARRICADES 61 CLASSIFIED 62 IN THE NAME OF GOD 22 VIEWPOINTS Papal Stakes, Tom Flynn / The Judge and Adam's Navel, Betty McCollister / Fetal "Personhood" and Abortion Rights, Edd Doerr / Judge Hand Erred in Holding that Secular Humanism Is a Religion, Ronald Lindsay FUNDAMENTALIST CHRISTIAN SCHOOLS: A NATIONAL SCANDAL 4 A Call for Public Scrutiny The Editors 5 The Truth and Consequences of Fundamentalist Christian Schooling Alan Peshkin 11 Children Are Not Chattel Kathy L. Collins 12 Reading, Writing, and Religion Mary Beth Gehrman 15 Selections from Fundamentalist School Textbooks 17 The World According to the Reverend Barney Lee AN EXCHANGE 28 Hook Is Mired in Secular Confusion Yaakov Homnick 29 A Common Moral Universe? Sidney Hook 32 The Challenge of Literalism Harry White A FREE INQUIRY INTERVIEW 34 Is the Sexual Revolution Over? An Interview with Sol Gordon and Rob Tielman ARTICLES 41 The Imagination: A Double-Edged Sword Linda Emery 47 Peter Popoffs Broken Window David Alexander 49 James Randi and The Faith-Healers Robert Basil PERSONAL PATHS TO HUMANISM 50 Human and World Care Benjamin Spock 52 Hope for Living Matthew les Spetter 53 The Testament of a Humanist Konstantin Kolenda BOOKS 54 Argument Without End? Michael Ruse 57 Community Was the Curriculum Robert Basil Benjamin Spock't article was adapted with permission from The Courage of Conviction, edited by Philip Berman, published in hardcover by Dodd, Mead. and Company and in paperback by Ballantine Books. Editor: Paul Kurtz Senior Editors: Vern Bullough, Gerald Larue Associate Editors: Doris Doyle, Steven L. Mitchell, Lee Nisbet, Gordon Stein Managing Editor: Andrea Szalanski Executive Editor: Robert Basil Contributing Editors: Lionel Abel, author, critic; Robert S. Alley, professor of humanities, University of Richmond; Paul Beattie, president, Fellowship of Religious Humanists; Jo-Ann Boydston, director, Dewey Center; Paul Edwards, professor of philosophy, Brooklyn College; Albert Ellis, director, Institute for Rational-Emotive Therapy; Roy P. Fairfield, social scientist, Union Graduate School; Joseph Fletcher, theologian, University of Virginia Medical School; Antony Flew, philosopher, Reading University, England; R. Joseph Hoffmann, chairman, Department of Philosophy and Religion, Hartwick College, Oneonta, N.Y.; Sidney Hook, professor emeritus of philosophy, NYU; Marvin Kohl, philosopher, State University of New York College at Fredonia; Jean Kotkin, executive director, American Ethical Union; Ronald A. Lindsay, attorney, Washington, D.C.; Delos B. McKown, professor of philosophy, Auburn University; Howard Radest, director, Ethical Culture Schools; Robert Rimmer, author; Svetozar Stojanovic, professor of philosophy, University of Belgrade; Thomas Szasz, psychiatrist, Upstate Medical Center, Syracuse; V. M. Tarkunde, Supreme Court Judge, India; Richard Taylor, professor of philosophy, Union College; Sherwin Wine, founder, Society for Humanistic Judaism Editorial Associates: Thomas Flynn, Thomas Franczyk, James Martin-Diaz Executive Director of CODESH, Inc.: Jean Millholland Public Relations: Tim Madigan Systems Manager: Richard Seymour Typesetting: Paul E. Loynes Art Director: Alain Kugel Audio Technician: Vance Vigrass Staff. Darrell Crawford, Steven Karr, Jacqueline Livingston, Valerie Marvin, Anthony Nigro, Alfreda Pidgeon FREE INQUIRY (ISSN 0272-0701) is published quarterly by the Council for Democratic and Secular Humanism (CODESH, Inc.), a nonprofit corporation, 3159 Bailey Avenue, Buffalo, NY 14215. Phone (716) 834-2921. Copyright 01987 by CODESH, Inc. Second-class postage paid at Buffalo, New York, and at additional mailing offices. National distribution by International Periodicals Distributors, San Diego, California. Subscription rates: $20.00 for one year, $35.00 for two years, $48.00 for three years, $3.75 for single copies. Address subscription order, changes of address, and advertising to: FREE INQUIRY, Box 5, Buffalo, NY 14215-0005. Manuscripts, letters, and editorial inquiries should be addressed to: The Editor, FREE INQUIRY, Box 5, Buffalo, NY 14215-0005. All manuscripts should be accompanied by two additional copies and a stamped, self-addressed envelope. Opinions expressed do not necessarily reflect the views of the editors or publisher. of words and images. That being the case, I choose to believe in a theistic cosmos, a universe completely pervaded by conscious- LETTERS TO THE EDITOR ness, in which my human self is a vehicle by which the Anentropic—i.e., the one thing that would not have been accidental—can "play" at games of order and chaos. That A Positive Defmition Bang theory is certainly clear, concise, and choice is an act of faith, not blind belief, of Humanism fascinating to read. However, his attempt to but an active choice in an unprovable matter. conclude that the observed physical proper- I choose that one because it enables me to Robert Detzell makes a good point (FI, ties of black holes "prove" anything with behave as a humanist without suppression Summer 1987), regarding my definition of respect to the existence of supra-physical and of my spirituality, and because I find it humanism, and I offer one that starts with pretemporal conscious will confirms my esthetically much more beautiful as drama, a more positive emphasis: opinion that neither the smallest possible more fulfilling as adventure, and ever so "Naturalistic humanism is a life-affirming time-space continuum (the Planck-time much more loving and joyful ontologically. philosophy with supreme commitment to the sphere?) nor the largest extant continuum It also enables me to easily detect and avoid welfare and happiness of all humanity, with (our present universe?) can be of itself the mind-traps of the various oil-of-pilgrim no belief in supernatural entities and with "proof' or "disproof" of the existence of sellers who go about their business in the reliance on the methods of reason and sci- "God." world in the name of religion. ence, democracy and compassion." It appears to me that, while the "scientific Like Stenger, I doubt very much that Since humanism supports many high method demands excessive conservatism," it proof of God or a Grand Design will ever ethical and social values, its "main thrust" is need not necessarily mandate atheism. Sci- be found; unlike him, I doubt that empirical certainly not "to put down" God and im- entific fundamentalism can be as narrow a knowledge of pre-universe or extra-universe mortality. Nonetheless, humanism remains mind-space as the biblical turf, and attempts conditions can be found by any means of incomplete unless it rejects these two reli- to force science to prove any theological examining the inside of the bubble. If there gious concepts as inconsistent with a scien- notion, including atheism, will most often were no photons until after Planck time, tific view of man and the universe. While leave one up against the limitations of one's then "Let there be light!" is as far back as we gladly accept some of the ethical ideas own definitions. we can see. Clearly, whether as Stenger's of Christianity, we must make clear that we For example, Stenger's conclusion, atheistic "accident," or as the theistic-deci- disagree with its theology. Otherwise, "There could not have been any Grand sion process I have suggested, this new pic- humanism loses a basic part of its philo- Design at the Planck time" could be valid ture of the creation will never agree with sophic structure. only if qualified this way: "if such Design the primitive mythological image of Judeo- were stipulated as formulated of the sub- Christian tradition. But as for insisting that, Corliss Lamont stance of the extant universe." If our uni- because science confounds Abraham, there New York, N.Y. verse is an expanding bubble within which is no God... I would far prefer to believe all of our experience is contained, and from that Abraham was a self-deluded, guilt-cult Secular Humanism's Moral which all of our evidential information must huckster whom time has inflated to idol- Creativity be taken, we have no particular reason to hood, and that God is a physicist. assume that all of the "exterior" Void was Congratulations on your editorial "The Af- or still is in a state of total entropy. James Nathan Post firmations of Humanism: A Statement of My conclusion is not intended to lend Las Cruces, N.M. Principles and Values" (FI, Spring 1987). I weight to the notion of Grand Design, nor was also moved by Robert Basil's "Friend- in any way to support the clearly-deluded Explaining Reincarnation ship Center Report" and the articles by Genesis junkies' absurd Melodrama-in-the- Robert Meyer and James Christopher on Garden scenario. To begin with, the notion Paul Edwards's case against reincarnation Secular Sobriety Groups, which appeared that all post-Planck-time events in the ex- can hardly be called a "free inquiry." His in the same issue. Secular humanists, it panding black hole we call Home have come articles are pervaded by the same tone fun- seems to me, in the past have run the risk of about as the random selections made
Recommended publications
  • Augustinian Christian Philosophy
    AUGUSTINIAN CHRISTIAN PHILOSOPHY How does Christianity bear on philosophy? Is there such a thing as Christian philosophy, or are there only Christians who are also philoso­ phers? How should Christianity and philosophy be related? Should they be related? In "Advice to Christian Philosophers" I said that Christian philosophers should display more autonomy: they have their own fish to fry, their own projects to pursue, (or their own axes to grind, as some might prefer to put it). Here I want to say more about what these projects (or fish, or axes) are like. And the right way to think about these matters, so it seems to me, is broadly Augustinian. Accordingly, I want to propose a program­ matic sketch (a very programmatic sketch) of a conception of Christian philosophy that grows out of some central Augustinian emphases. I don't claim, however, that Augustine in fact thought of Christian philosophy the way I shall suggest. The primary focus of my paper is not historical (that would in any event be beyond my competence); what I want to do is make a suggestion as to how we should think about Christian philosophy now; but this way of thinking of the matter grows out of Augustinian roots.! It's worth noting, furthermore, that what is at issue is not just a way of thinking about Christianity and philosophy, but about Christianity and scholarship more generally. There are at least four elements in Augustinian Christian philosophy. The first two of these are widely recognized and relatively uncontroversial: I shall therefore be brief about them.
    [Show full text]
  • The Etienne Gilson Series 21
    The Etienne Gilson Series 21 Remapping Scholasticism by MARCIA L. COLISH 3 March 2000 Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies This lecture and its publication was made possible through the generous bequest of the late Charles J. Sullivan (1914-1999) Note: the author may be contacted at: Department of History Oberlin College Oberlin OH USA 44074 ISSN 0-708-319X ISBN 0-88844-721-3 © 2000 by Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies 59 Queen’s Park Crescent East Toronto, Ontario, Canada M5S 2C4 Printed in Canada nce upon a time there were two competing story-lines for medieval intellectual history, each writing a major role for scholasticism into its script. Although these story-lines were O created independently and reflected different concerns, they sometimes overlapped and gave each other aid and comfort. Both exerted considerable influence on the way historians of medieval speculative thought conceptualized their subject in the first half of the twentieth cen- tury. Both versions of the map drawn by these two sets of cartographers illustrated what Wallace K. Ferguson later described as “the revolt of the medievalists.”1 One was confined largely to the academy and appealed to a wide variety of medievalists, while the other had a somewhat narrower draw and reflected political and confessional, as well as academic, concerns. The first was the anti-Burckhardtian effort to push Renaissance humanism, understood as combining a knowledge and love of the classics with “the discovery of the world and of man,” back into the Middle Ages. The second was inspired by the neo-Thomist revival launched by Pope Leo XIII, and was inhabited almost exclusively by Roman Catholic scholars.
    [Show full text]
  • The Problematic of the Augustinian Doctrine of Grace for Contemporary Theology D
    Journal for Christian Theological Research Volume 5 Article 2 2000 Nature Dis-Graced and Grace De-Natured: The Problematic of the Augustinian Doctrine of Grace for Contemporary Theology D. Lyle Dabney Marquette University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.luthersem.edu/jctr Part of the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Recommended Citation Dabney, D. Lyle (2000) "Nature Dis-Graced and Grace De-Natured: The rP oblematic of the Augustinian Doctrine of Grace for Contemporary Theology," Journal for Christian Theological Research: Vol. 5 , Article 2. Available at: http://digitalcommons.luthersem.edu/jctr/vol5/iss2000/2 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Digital Commons @ Luther Seminary. It has been accepted for inclusion in Journal for Christian Theological Research by an authorized editor of Digital Commons @ Luther Seminary. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 12/18/2017 Nature Dis-Graced and Grace De-Natured: The Problematic of the Augustinian Doctrie of Grace for Contemporary Theology D. Lyle Dabney, "Nature Dis­Graced and Grace De­Natured: The Problematic of the Augustinian Doctrine of Grace for Contemporary Theology," Journal for Christian Theological Research [http://apu.edu/~CTRF/articles/2000_articles/dabney.html] 5:3 (2000). Nature Dis­Graced and Grace De­Natured: The Problematic of the Augustinian Doctrine of Grace for Contemporary Theology D. Lyle Dabney Marquette University , Milwaukee, Wisconsin 1. "Contemporary theology" Kilian McDonnell writes, "has turned from a theology of the Word to a theology of the world".(1) That statement, it seems to me, neatly sums up the current situation in theology.
    [Show full text]
  • Analysis of Justice in St. Augustine's Political Philosophy and Nigerian
    International Journal of Education and Human Developments, Vol. 6 No 2; July 2020 ISSN 2415-1270 (Online), ISSN 2415-1424 (Print) Published by Center for Global Research Development Analysis of Justice in St. Augustine’s Political Philosophy and Nigerian Political System ONUCHE, Joseph PhD. Department of Philosophy Kogi State University Anyigba, Kogi State Nigeria Abstract St Augustine of Hippo (354-430CE) is the most influential Christian philosopher in western Christianity after Paul the Apostle. This paper analyses justice in Augustine‟s political philosophy as contained in His „City of God‟. It will be argued that, we could learn from his answers to bad politicking which resulted in destruction of State. His answers on various theological and philosophical issues have continued to be relevant in modern theological and philosophical debate. A lot can still be learnt from him even in the area of Church‟s response to bad governance. Augustine‟s argument is that Kingdoms (Countries, nations) without justice are robberies, as Kings (Governors) of such are robbers. This supposition is illustrated with three historical allusions namely: the encounter of Alexander the Great with a Pirate, the establishment of Roman Empire by Romulus, and the establishment of Assyrian Empire by Ninus. Contextually, Nigeria as it is today falls into this category of robberies as the British colonial masters forced this unequal union for their personal, self-seeking and self-interest, to satisfy their libido dominandi. An analysis of what Augustine meant by justice will be carried out. Philosophically, Augustine evaluated justice from Neo-Platonic background and theologically from Pauline concept of justice.
    [Show full text]
  • Unamuno, Ortega Y Gasset, Buero Vallejo, Sastre. Thomas Mark Mctigue Louisiana State University and Agricultural & Mechanical College
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses Graduate School 1969 Spain's Christian Existentialism: Unamuno, Ortega Y Gasset, Buero Vallejo, Sastre. Thomas Mark Mctigue Louisiana State University and Agricultural & Mechanical College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_disstheses Recommended Citation Mctigue, Thomas Mark, "Spain's Christian Existentialism: Unamuno, Ortega Y Gasset, Buero Vallejo, Sastre." (1969). LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses. 1677. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_disstheses/1677 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses by an authorized administrator of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This dissertation has b een microfilmed exactly as received —79 0077 McTIGUE, Thomas Mark, 1929- SPAIN'S CHRISTIAN EXISTENTIALISM: UNAMUNO, ORTEGA Y GASSET, B U E R O VALLEJO, SASTRE. [Portions of T e x t in Spanish]. The Louisiana State University and A gricultu ral and Mechanical College, Ph.D., 1969 Language and Literature, modern University Microfilms, Inc., Ann A rbor, M ichigan (c) Thomas M ark McTigue 19 7 0 ALL RIGHTS RESERVED SPAIN'S CHRISTIAN EXISTENTIALISM: UNAMUNO, ORTEGA Y GASSET, BUERO VALLEJO, SASTRE A Dissertation Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in The Department of Foreign Languages by Thomas Mark McTigue M.A., Louisiana State University, 1966 August, 1969 I DEDICATION A mi esposa, Patricia, sin cuyo apoyo, devocion y amor, nada de esto hubiera sido posible.
    [Show full text]
  • Skepticism and the Problem of Atheism in Early-Modern France
    ALAN CHARLES KORS SKEPTICISM AND THE PROBLEM OF ATHEISM IN EARLY-MODERN FRANCE The early-modern Christian, and, especially, Catholic learned world possessed a complex and ambivalent set of attitudes towards philosophical skepticism. It was not only that the various schools of Christian philosophy responded quite differently to formal issues of certainty and the limits of human knowledge, but that the same schools and individuals could respond quite diversely depending upon the context in which these issues were raised and the per­ ceived nature and purposes of the interlocutors. Two tendencies coexisted uneasily within a Catholic learned world whose educa­ tion and traditions linked it both to the mystery of revealed faith and to the philosophical systems of the Greeks. On the one hand, it believed that it possessed a creed whose superior truth and wisdom would be foolish to the profane world and whose salvific character­ istics were categorically beyond the fruits of natural learning; on the other, it believed that its doctors and educated believers could prevail in philosophical and theological disputations with the sages of all the nations. From the first tendency, it could be deeply moved by the humbling of natural human reason and natural scientia; philosophical skepticism was a wondrous means of achieving that end. From the other, it could be deeply offended and threatened by claims that natural certainty was not among the gifts of philosophy; philosophical skepticism was an arrogant and insidious means of making such claims. Piety admired humility and sought ataraxia, and it feared the pride and concupiscence of natural mind; learned theology gloried in disputation and demonstration, and it feared the anarchy of a natural reason that suspended judgment where philosophers offered compelling proofs.
    [Show full text]
  • What Does the Happy Life Require? Augustine on What the Summum Bonum Includes 1. Introduction
    What Does the Happy Life Require? Augustine on What the Summum Bonum Includes Caleb Cohoe, forthcoming in Oxford Studies in Medieval Philosophy 1. Introduction Many critics of religion insist that believing in a future life makes us less able to value our present activities and distracts us from accomplishing good in this world.1 Augustine is a frequent target, given his insistence that this life is a vale of tears, where we must wait in hope for a better life, while only loving things insofar as they relate to God. Martha Nussbaum insists that “Augustinian love is committed to denying the importance of worldly losses and injustices.”2 She claims that an orientation towards God and towards a future life leads one to neglect the importance of justice and charity in this life. “Death is irrelevant, real suffering in this world is irrelevant, all that is relevant is coming into God’s presence.”3 Instead of looking to the next life, we should be “directing compassion altogether toward the theater of history and not at all toward the shadowy and uncertain realm that may or may not lie outside it.”4 Augustine’s focus on connection to God leaves him without a strong foundation for caring “when people are hungry, when they mourn, when they are persecuted.”5 In this paper, I show that Nussbaum has things backwards. It is while Augustine is trying to achieve happiness in this life that he denies “the importance of worldly losses and injustices,” treats suffering as “irrelevant,” and focuses on cultivating his own divine contemplation, neglecting the material world.
    [Show full text]
  • Scholasticism and the Problem of Intellectual Reform
    Tilburg University Introduction Wisse, P.M.; Sarot, M. Published in: Scholasticism reformed Publication date: 2010 Link to publication in Tilburg University Research Portal Citation for published version (APA): Wisse, P. M., & Sarot, M. (2010). Introduction: Reforming views of reformed scholasticism. In P. M. Wisse, M. Sarot, & W. Otten (Eds.), Scholasticism reformed: Essays in honour of Willem J. van Asselt (Published on the occasion of the retirement of Willem J. van Asselt from Utrecht University) (pp. 1-27). (Studies in theology and religion; No. 14). Brill. General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 30. sep. 2021 Reforming Views of Reformed Scholasticism Introduction Maarten Wisse and Marcel Sarot 1 Introduction The title of the present work is intentionally ambiguous: Scholasticism Reformed. It may be read, firstly, as a simple reversion of “Reformed scholasticism,” as indeed some of the contributions to this volume study aspects of the type of theology between the early Reformation and the Enlightenment that continued to use the traditional methods rooted in the medieval period.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter Twelve
    chapter twelve THE ARAGONESE CIRCLE OF “JEWISH SCHOLASTICS” AND ITS POSSIBLE RELATIONSHIP TO LOCAL CHRISTIAN SCHOLARSHIP: AN OVERVIEW OF HISTORICAL DATA AND SOME GENERAL QUESTIONS Mauro Zonta Some years ago, I published Hebrew Scholasticism in the Fifteenth Century.1 The book’s very title was the first suggestion of the existence of a previously unnoticed historical phenomenon: a sort of Scholasticism in late medieval Jewish philosophy and thought, which was very similar, sometimes identi- cal, and in any case parallel to contemporary Latin Scholasticism, that is to say, late medieval Christian philosophy and thought as expressed by many authors of the thirteenth, fourteenth, and fifteenth centuries in western and central Europe. Other scholars, including Giuseppe Sermoneta, Shlomo Pines, Jean-Pierre Rothschild, Warren Zev Harvey, Yossef Schwartz, Tamar Rudavsky, Hava Tirosh-Samuelson, Ruth Glasner, Ari Ackerman, and Cate- rina Rigo, had studied aspects of this phenomenon in a number of articles,2 but there had never been an attempt to offer a general historical overview of it. In fact, two different enterprises can be distinguished within this phe- nomenon: “Hebrew Scholasticism” and “Jewish Scholasticism.” We can speak of Hebrew Scholasticism when Jewish authors simply continued Latin Scholastic discussions in Hebrew, with no input from their own culture. They merely reproduced the structure and the concepts of their Latin col- leagues, directly (and sometimes even openly) employing their works as sources. They merely exchanged the Latin for their own cultural language, 1 Mauro Zonta, Hebrew Scholasticism in the Fifteenth Century. A History and Source Book (Dordrecht: Springer, 2006). 2 For a historical overview, based mainly on the contents of these works, see ibid., pp.
    [Show full text]
  • Medieval Theories of Natural Law: William of Ockham and the Significance of the Voluntarist Tradition Francis Oakley
    Notre Dame Law School NDLScholarship Natural Law Forum 1-1-1961 Medieval Theories of Natural Law: William of Ockham and the Significance of the Voluntarist Tradition Francis Oakley Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.nd.edu/nd_naturallaw_forum Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Oakley, Francis, "Medieval Theories of Natural Law: William of Ockham and the Significance of the Voluntarist Tradition" (1961). Natural Law Forum. Paper 60. http://scholarship.law.nd.edu/nd_naturallaw_forum/60 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by NDLScholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in Natural Law Forum by an authorized administrator of NDLScholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. MEDIEVAL THEORIES OF NATURAL LAW: WILLIAM OF OCKHAM AND THE SIGNIFICANCE OF THE VOLUNTARIST TRADITION Francis Oakley THE BELIEF in a natural law superior to mere positive enactment and the practice of appealing to it were common to the vast majority of medieval political thinkers'-whether civil lawyers or philosophers, canon lawyers or theologians; and, all too often, it has been assumed that when they invoked the natural law, they meant much the same thing by it. It takes, indeed, little more than a superficial glance to discover that the civil or canon lawyers often meant by natural law something rather different than did the philoso- phers or theologians, but it takes perhaps a closer look to detect that not even the theologians themselves were in full agreement in their theories of natural
    [Show full text]
  • MYSTICISM Christina Van Dyke
    P1: SJT Trim: 6in 9in Top: 0.625in Gutter: 0.875in × CUUK851-52 CUUK618/Pasnau ISBN: 978 0 521 86672 9 May 20, 2009 20:18 52 MYSTICISM christina van dyke Current scholars generally behave as though the medieval traditions of mysticism and philosophy in the Latin West have nothing to do with each other; in large part, this appears to be the result of the common perception that mysticism has as its ultimate goal an ecstatic, selfless union with the divine that intellectual pursuits such as philosophy inhibit rather than support. There are, however, at least two central problems with this assumption. First, mysticism in the Middle Ages – even just within the Christian tradition1 – was not a uniform movement with a single goal: it took different forms in different parts of Europe, and those forms changed substantially from the eleventh to the fifteenth century, particularly with the increased emphasis on personal piety and the feminization of religious imagery that emerges in the later centuries.2 The belief that mysticism entails the rejection or abandonment of reason in order to merge with the divine, for instance, represents only one strain of the medieval tradition. Although this view is explicitly advocated in the Christian West by such influential figures as Meister Eckhart and Marguerite Porete, the prevalent identification of the allegorical figure of Wisdom with Christ provides the grounds for equally prominent figures such as Hildegard of 1 In several respects, mysticism played a more integral role in Arabic and Jewish philosophy than in Christian philosophy from late antiquity through the Middle Ages.
    [Show full text]
  • Calvinist Natural Law and Constitutionalism, 39 Austl
    +(,121/,1( Citation: Constance Youngwon Lee, Calvinist Natural Law and Constitutionalism, 39 Austl. J. Leg. Phil. 1, 41 (2014) Content downloaded/printed from HeinOnline Fri Sep 29 00:39:02 2017 -- Your use of this HeinOnline PDF indicates your acceptance of HeinOnline's Terms and Conditions of the license agreement available at http://heinonline.org/HOL/License -- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text. -- To obtain permission to use this article beyond the scope of your HeinOnline license, please use: Copyright Information Use QR Code reader to send PDF to your smartphone or tablet device Calvinist Natural Law and Constitutionalism CONSTANCE YOUNGWON LEEt I. Abstract The continuity between Calvinist natural law and the constitutional tradition of limited government is often overlooked. This article aims to engage with Calvin's natural law theory on its own terms to explore what authority it can provide for modern constitutionalism. The article begins by exploring some important points of distinction between Calvinist and Thomist approaches to the idea of natural law. I then contend that the focus of modern constitutionalism on subjecting government power to the 'rule of law' is continuous with Calvinist natural law concepts of human depravity and God's sovereignty. The article is structured broadly into three main parts. The first section engages with the concept and history of Christian natural law, framing them by reference to the Two Kingdoms doctrine. The second section discusses the central tenets of Calvinist natural law theory, namely the sovereignty of God, the doctrine of humanity's total depravity and the Two Kingdoms doctrine as a unified concept.
    [Show full text]