Topics in Foundations of Game Theory

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Topics in Foundations of Game Theory Topics in Foundations of Game Theory Module I. Introduction to Axiomatic Decision Theory A typical agent in economics maximizes some utility function. The underlying jus- tification is, as long as the agent has a stable preference and makes choices consistently according to it, then it is as if he maximizes this utility function. This “as if” approach plays the critical role in economics research. In this module we look at the axiomatic foundation of single-person decision theory. This line of research makes it precise what this “as if” approach means, what are the underlying behavioral assumptions behind a utility function, what are the implications of observed behavioral anomalies in light of the axioms, and so on. We’ll use Kreps’ book “notes on the theory of choice” for basic material. The course will combine lectures, students presentations and discussions. No prerequisite. The class meets every Wednesday evening 6-8:30pm, Allen 306. Module plan. 1. (Oct. 18) Lecture one: representation of preference relations; revealed preference approach Readings: Kreps Ch. 1-3 2. (Oct. 25) Lecture two: vNM model, the mixture space Readings: Kreps Ch. 4-5, (optional: ch 6) 3. (Nov. 1) Lecture three: Allais paradox, the state space approach to uncertainty and subjective probabilities; Student presentation: AA model. Readings: Kreps Ch. 7; Anscombe and Aumann (1963); 4. (Nov. 8) Lecture four: Savage Readings: Kreps Ch. 8-9 5. *(Nov. 15) Lecture five: “bounded rationality” models – temptation and self- control, preference for flexibility, ambiguity, maximin, interactive decision theory (games), (macro: robust control, Epstein and Zin) 6. *(Nov. 29) Lecture six: new trend – behavioral anomalies, neuroeconomics Readings: (all articles are available online, try google!) Kahneman and Tversky ed., (2000) choices, values, and frames 1 Rabin (1998), psychology and economics Gul and Pesendorfer (2005), the case for mindless economists Rubinstein (2006), Comments on Behavioral Economics * subject to changes. 2 Topics in Foundations of Game Theory Module II. Information, Knowledge, Belief and Rationality These are the key concepts in modeling players who can reason. In this module we study the formal modeling of these concepts, and use them to investigate issues such as the foundations of popular solution concepts in games, when do rational agents trade, etc. This is a research-oriented course meant to engage everyone in asking questions about things often taken for granted and thinking about new ideas. There is no textbook. We’ll read selected book chapters and papers, and since there are many, many interesting works in the frontier, will try to adjust to what interests the class most. The course will combine lectures, students presentations and discussions. Familiarity with basic game theory is a plus (it can be taken simultaneously with first-year game theory course). The class meets every Wednesday evening 4:25-6:55pm at Allen 226. Module plan: 1. (Jan 10) Lecture one: the standard state space models and their conceptual issues; Readings: Aumann (1999a, 1999b), Geanakoplos (1992), Optional readings: Bacharach (1985); (for unawareness) Dekel, Lipman and Rusti- chini (1998a), Li (2006a); (for syntactic approach) Fagin, Halpern, Moses and Vardi (1995). 2. (Jan 17) Lecture two: no trade theorems; Readings: Aumann (1976), Rubinstein and Wolinsky (1990); Optional readings: Milgrom and Stokey (1982), Geanakoplos (1989); Homework: Read Aumann (1987, 1998) and Gul (1998), prepare for discussion next week in class. 3. (Jan 24) Lecture three: the CPA. Readings: Brandenburger and Dekel (1993), Morris (1995), Lipman (2003); Optional readings: Mertens and Zamir (1985), Samet (1998a, 1998b), Heifetz (2003), Bergemann and Morris (2005), Ely and Peski (2006); 4. (Jan 31) Lecture four: approximate common knowledge; Readings: Rubinstein (1989), Monderer and Samet (1989), Morris (1999); 3 Optional reading: Neeman (1996a), Morris (2002), Morris, Postlewaite and Shin (1995a); (applications in game theory) Morris, Rob and Shin (1995b), Kajii and Morris (1997); (applications on no-trade type results) Neeman (1996b); 5. (Feb 7) Lecture five: global games; Readings: Morris and Shin (2003), Atkeson (2000); Optional reading: Morris and Shin (1998), Carlsson and van Damme (1993), Morris and Shin (2000); 6. (Feb 14, 21) Lecture six/seven: epistemic foundation for games Readings: Dekel and Gul (1997), Brandenburger (2006), Bernheim (1984), Batti- galli and Siniscalchi (1999); Optional readings: Aumann and Brandenburger (1995), Ben-Porath (1997), Bran- denburger (2006), Brandenburger and Dekel (1987), Brandenburger, Friedenburg and Keisler (2006), Myerson (1986b), Blume, Brandenburger and Dekel (1991), Brandenburger, Friedenburg and Keisler (2006b), Reny (1993), Pearce (1984). References Atkeson, Andrew, “Discussion of Morris and Shin’s “Rethinking Multiple Equilibria in Macroeconomic Modelling,” NBER Macroeconomics Annual, 2000, 15. Aumann, Robert J., “Agreeing to Disagree,” Annals of Statistics, 1976, 76 (4), 1236– 1239. , “Correlated Equilibrium as an Expression of Bayesian Rationality,” Econometrica, 1987, 55 (1), 1–18. , “Common Priors: A Reply to Gul,” Econometrica, 1998, 66 (4), 929–938. , “Interactive Epistemology I: Knowledge,” International Journal of Game Theory, 1999, 28, 263–300. , “Interactive Epistemology II: Probability,” International Journal of Game Theory, 1999, 28, 300–314. and Adam Brandenburger, “Epistemic Conditions for Nash Equilibrium,” Econometrica, 1995, 63 (5), 1161–1180. 4 Bacharach, Michael, “Some Extensions of a Claim of Aumann in an Axiomatic Model of Knowledge,” Journal of Economic Theory, 1985, 37, 167–90. Battigalli, Pierpaolo and Marciano Siniscalchi, “Hierarchies of Conditional Beliefs and Interactive Epistemology in Dynamic Games,” Journal of Economic Theory, 1999, 88, 188–230. Ben-Porath, Elchanan, “Rationality, Nash Equilibrium and Backwards Induction in Perfect-Information Games,” Review of Economic Studies, 1997, 64, 23–46. Bergemann, Dirk and Stephen Morris, “Robust Mechanism Design,” Econometrica, 2005, 73, 1521–1534. Bernheim, B. Douglas, “Rationalizable Strategic Behavior,” Econometrica, 1984, 52, 1007–1028. Blume, Lawrence, Adam Brandenburger, and Eddie Dekel, “Lexicographic Prob- abilities and Choice Under Uncertainty,” Econometricca, 1991, 59, 61–79. Brandenburger, Adam, “The Power of Paradox: Some Recent Developments in In- teractive Epistemology,” 2006. forthcoming, International Journal of Game Theory. , Amanda Friedenberg, and H. Jerome Keisler, “Admissibility in Games,” 2006. memeo. , , and , “Notes on Relationship between Strong Belief and Assumption,” 2006b. memeo. and Eddie Dekel, “Rationalizability and Correlated Equilibria,” Econometrica, 1987, 55 (6), 1391–1402. and , “Hierarchies of Beliefs and Common Knowledge,” Journal of Economic Theory, 1993, 59, 189–198. Carlsson, Hans and Eric van Damme, “Global Games and Equilibrium Selection,” Econometrica, 1993, 61 (5), 989–1018. Dekel, Eddie and Faruk Gul, “Rationality and Knowledge in Game Theory,” in David M. Kreps and Kenneth F. Wallis, eds., Advances in Economic Theory, Seventh World Congress, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997. , Barton L. Lipman, and Aldo Rustichini, “Standard State-Space Models Preclude Unawareness,” Econometrica, 1998a, 66 (1), 159–173. Ely, Jeffrey and Marcin Peski, “Hierarchies of Belief and Interim Rationalizability,” Theoretical Economics, 2006, 1, 19–65. 5 Fagin, Ronald, Joseph Y. Halpern, Yoram Moses, and Moshe Y. Vardi, Rea- soning About Knowledge, The MIT Press, 1995. Feinberg, Yossi, “Characterizing Common Priors in the Form of Posteriors,” Journal of Economic Theory, 2000, 91, 127–179. Geanakoplos, John, “Game Theory without Partitions, and Applications to Specula- tion and Consensus,” 1989. Cowles Foundation Discussion Paper No. 914. , “Common Knowledge,” Journal of Economic Perspectives, 1992, 6 (4), 53–82. Gul, Faruk, “A Comment on Aumann’s Bayesian View,” Econometrica, 1998, 98 (4), 923–928. Halpern, Joseph Y., “Characterizing the Common Prior Assumption,” Journal of Economic Theory, 2002, 106, 316–355. Heifetz, Aviad, “The Positive Foundation of the Common Prior Assumption,” 2003. Forthcoming, Games and Economic Behavior. Kajii, Atsushi and Stephen Morris, “The Robustness of Equilibria to Incomplete Information,” Econometrica, 1997, 65 (6), 1283–1309. Li, Jing, “Information Structures with Unawareness,” 2006a. Working paper, University of Pennsylvania. Lipman, Barton L., “Finite Order Implications of Common Priors,” Econometrica, 2003, 71, 1255–1267. , “Finite Order Implications of Common Priors in Infinite Models,” 2005. Working paper. Mertens, Jean-Francois and Shmuel Zamir, “Formulation of Bayesian Analysis for Games with Incomplete Information,” International Journal of Game Theory, 1985, 14 (1), 1–29. Milgrom, Paul and Nancy Stokey, “Information, Trade and Common Knowledge,” Journal of Economic Theory, 1982, 26, 17–27. Monderer, Dov and Dov Samet, “Approximating Common Knowledge with Common Beliefs,” Games and Economic Behavior, 1989, 1, 170–190. Morris, Stephen, “The Common Prior Assumption in Economic Theory,” Economics and Philosophy, 1995, 11, 227–253. 6 , “Approximate Common Knowledge Revisited,” International Journal of Game Theory, 1999, 28, 433–445. , “Coordination, Communication, and Common Knowledge: A Retrospective on the Electronic-Mail Game,” Oxford Review of Economic Policy, 2002, 18 (4), 385–408. and Hyun Song Shin, “Unique Equilibrium in a Model of Self-Fulfilling Attacks,” American Economic Review, 1998,
Recommended publications
  • Lecture Notes
    GRADUATE GAME THEORY LECTURE NOTES BY OMER TAMUZ California Institute of Technology 2018 Acknowledgments These lecture notes are partially adapted from Osborne and Rubinstein [29], Maschler, Solan and Zamir [23], lecture notes by Federico Echenique, and slides by Daron Acemoglu and Asu Ozdaglar. I am indebted to Seo Young (Silvia) Kim and Zhuofang Li for their help in finding and correcting many errors. Any comments or suggestions are welcome. 2 Contents 1 Extensive form games with perfect information 7 1.1 Tic-Tac-Toe ........................................ 7 1.2 The Sweet Fifteen Game ................................ 7 1.3 Chess ............................................ 7 1.4 Definition of extensive form games with perfect information ........... 10 1.5 The ultimatum game .................................. 10 1.6 Equilibria ......................................... 11 1.7 The centipede game ................................... 11 1.8 Subgames and subgame perfect equilibria ...................... 13 1.9 The dollar auction .................................... 14 1.10 Backward induction, Kuhn’s Theorem and a proof of Zermelo’s Theorem ... 15 2 Strategic form games 17 2.1 Definition ......................................... 17 2.2 Nash equilibria ...................................... 17 2.3 Classical examples .................................... 17 2.4 Dominated strategies .................................. 22 2.5 Repeated elimination of dominated strategies ................... 22 2.6 Dominant strategies ..................................
    [Show full text]
  • Collusion Constrained Equilibrium
    Theoretical Economics 13 (2018), 307–340 1555-7561/20180307 Collusion constrained equilibrium Rohan Dutta Department of Economics, McGill University David K. Levine Department of Economics, European University Institute and Department of Economics, Washington University in Saint Louis Salvatore Modica Department of Economics, Università di Palermo We study collusion within groups in noncooperative games. The primitives are the preferences of the players, their assignment to nonoverlapping groups, and the goals of the groups. Our notion of collusion is that a group coordinates the play of its members among different incentive compatible plans to best achieve its goals. Unfortunately, equilibria that meet this requirement need not exist. We instead introduce the weaker notion of collusion constrained equilibrium. This al- lows groups to put positive probability on alternatives that are suboptimal for the group in certain razor’s edge cases where the set of incentive compatible plans changes discontinuously. These collusion constrained equilibria exist and are a subset of the correlated equilibria of the underlying game. We examine four per- turbations of the underlying game. In each case,we show that equilibria in which groups choose the best alternative exist and that limits of these equilibria lead to collusion constrained equilibria. We also show that for a sufficiently broad class of perturbations, every collusion constrained equilibrium arises as such a limit. We give an application to a voter participation game that shows how collusion constraints may be socially costly. Keywords. Collusion, organization, group. JEL classification. C72, D70. 1. Introduction As the literature on collective action (for example, Olson 1965) emphasizes, groups often behave collusively while the preferences of individual group members limit the possi- Rohan Dutta: [email protected] David K.
    [Show full text]
  • Correlated Equilibria and Communication in Games Françoise Forges
    Correlated equilibria and communication in games Françoise Forges To cite this version: Françoise Forges. Correlated equilibria and communication in games. Computational Complex- ity. Theory, Techniques, and Applications, pp.295-704, 2012, 10.1007/978-1-4614-1800-9_45. hal- 01519895 HAL Id: hal-01519895 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01519895 Submitted on 9 May 2017 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Correlated Equilibrium and Communication in Games Françoise Forges, CEREMADE, Université Paris-Dauphine Article Outline Glossary I. De…nition of the Subject and its Importance II. Introduction III. Correlated Equilibrium: De…nition and Basic Properties IV. Correlated Equilibrium and Communication V. Correlated Equilibrium in Bayesian Games VI. Related Topics and Future Directions VII. Bibliography Acknowledgements The author wishes to thank Elchanan Ben-Porath, Frédéric Koessler, R. Vijay Krishna, Ehud Lehrer, Bob Nau, Indra Ray, Jérôme Renault, Eilon Solan, Sylvain Sorin, Bernhard von Stengel, Tristan Tomala, Amparo Ur- bano, Yannick Viossat and, especially, Olivier Gossner and Péter Vida, for useful comments and suggestions. Glossary Bayesian game: an interactive decision problem consisting of a set of n players, a set of types for every player, a probability distribution which ac- counts for the players’ beliefs over each others’ types, a set of actions for every player and a von Neumann-Morgenstern utility function de…ned over n-tuples of types and actions for every player.
    [Show full text]
  • Characterizing Solution Concepts in Terms of Common Knowledge Of
    Characterizing Solution Concepts in Terms of Common Knowledge of Rationality Joseph Y. Halpern∗ Computer Science Department Cornell University, U.S.A. e-mail: [email protected] Yoram Moses† Department of Electrical Engineering Technion—Israel Institute of Technology 32000 Haifa, Israel email: [email protected] March 15, 2018 Abstract Characterizations of Nash equilibrium, correlated equilibrium, and rationaliz- ability in terms of common knowledge of rationality are well known (Aumann 1987; arXiv:1605.01236v1 [cs.GT] 4 May 2016 Brandenburger and Dekel 1987). Analogous characterizations of sequential equi- librium, (trembling hand) perfect equilibrium, and quasi-perfect equilibrium in n-player games are obtained here, using results of Halpern (2009, 2013). ∗Supported in part by NSF under grants CTC-0208535, ITR-0325453, and IIS-0534064, by ONR un- der grant N00014-02-1-0455, by the DoD Multidisciplinary University Research Initiative (MURI) pro- gram administered by the ONR under grants N00014-01-1-0795 and N00014-04-1-0725, and by AFOSR under grants F49620-02-1-0101 and FA9550-05-1-0055. †The Israel Pollak academic chair at the Technion; work supported in part by Israel Science Foun- dation under grant 1520/11. 1 Introduction Arguably, the major goal of epistemic game theory is to characterize solution concepts epistemically. Characterizations of the solution concepts that are most commonly used in strategic-form games, namely, Nash equilibrium, correlated equilibrium, and rational- izability, in terms of common knowledge of rationality are well known (Aumann 1987; Brandenburger and Dekel 1987). We show how to get analogous characterizations of sequential equilibrium (Kreps and Wilson 1982), (trembling hand) perfect equilibrium (Selten 1975), and quasi-perfect equilibrium (van Damme 1984) for arbitrary n-player games, using results of Halpern (2009, 2013).
    [Show full text]
  • Correlated Equilibria 1 the Chicken-Dare Game 2 Correlated
    MS&E 334: Computation of Equilibria Lecture 6 - 05/12/2009 Correlated Equilibria Lecturer: Amin Saberi Scribe: Alex Shkolnik 1 The Chicken-Dare Game The chicken-dare game can be throught of as two drivers racing towards an intersection. A player can chose to dare (d) and pass through the intersection or chicken out (c) and stop. The game results in a draw when both players chicken out and the worst possible outcome if they both dare. A player wins when he dares while the other chickens out. The game has one possible payoff matrix given by d c d 0; 0 4; 1 c 1; 4 3; 3 with two pure strategy Nash equilibria (d; c) and (c; d) and one mixed equilibrium where each player mixes the pure strategies with probability 1=2 each. Now suppose that prior to playing the game the players performed the following experiment. The players draw a ball labeled with a strategy, either (c) or (d) from a bag containing three balls labelled c; c; d. The players then agree to follow the strategy suggested by the ball. It can be verified that there is no incentive to deviate from such an agreement since the suggested strategy is best in expectation. This experiment is equivalent to having the following strategy profile chosen for the players by some third party, a correlation device. d c d 0 1=3 c 1=3 1=3 This matrix above is not of rank one and so is not a Nash profile. And, the social welfare in this scenario is 16=3 which is greater than that of any Nash equilibrium.
    [Show full text]
  • Correlated Equilibrium Is a Distribution D Over Action Profiles a Such That for Every ∗ Player I, and Every Action Ai
    NETS 412: Algorithmic Game Theory February 9, 2017 Lecture 8 Lecturer: Aaron Roth Scribe: Aaron Roth Correlated Equilibria Consider the following two player traffic light game that will be familiar to those of you who can drive: STOP GO STOP (0,0) (0,1) GO (1,0) (-100,-100) This game has two pure strategy Nash equilibria: (GO,STOP), and (STOP,GO) { but these are clearly not ideal because there is one player who never gets any utility. There is also a mixed strategy Nash equilibrium: Suppose player 1 plays (p; 1 − p). If the equilibrium is to be fully mixed, player 2 must be indifferent between his two actions { i.e.: 0 = p − 100(1 − p) , 101p = 100 , p = 100=101 So in the mixed strategy Nash equilibrium, both players play STOP with probability p = 100=101, and play GO with probability (1 − p) = 1=101. This is even worse! Now both players get payoff 0 in expectation (rather than just one of them), and risk a horrific negative utility. The four possible action profiles have roughly the following probabilities under this equilibrium: STOP GO STOP 98% <1% GO <1% ≈ 0.01% A far better outcome would be the following, which is fair, has social welfare 1, and doesn't risk death: STOP GO STOP 0% 50% GO 50% 0% But there is a problem: there is no set of mixed strategies that creates this distribution over action profiles. Therefore, fundamentally, this can never result from Nash equilibrium play. The reason however is not that this play is not rational { it is! The issue is that we have defined Nash equilibria as profiles of mixed strategies, that require that players randomize independently, without any communication.
    [Show full text]
  • Maximum Entropy Correlated Equilibria
    Maximum Entropy Correlated Equilibria Luis E. Ortiz Robert E. Schapire Sham M. Kakade ECE Deptartment Dept. of Computer Science Toyota Technological Institute Univ. of Puerto Rico at Mayaguez¨ Princeton University Chicago, IL 60637 Mayaguez,¨ PR 00681 Princeton, NJ 08540 [email protected] [email protected] [email protected] Abstract cept in game theory and in mathematical economics, where game theory is applied to model competitive economies We study maximum entropy correlated equilib- [Arrow and Debreu, 1954]. An equilibrium is a point of ria (Maxent CE) in multi-player games. After strategic stance between the players in a game that charac- motivating and deriving some interesting impor- terizes and serves as a prediction to a possible outcome of tant properties of Maxent CE, we provide two the game. gradient-based algorithms that are guaranteed to The general problem of equilibrium computation is funda- converge to it. The proposed algorithms have mental in computer science [Papadimitriou, 2001]. In the strong connections to algorithms for statistical last decade, there have been many great advances in our estimation (e.g., iterative scaling), and permit a understanding of the general prospects and limitations of distributed learning-dynamics interpretation. We computing equilibria in games. Just late last year, there also briefly discuss possible connections of this was a breakthrough on what was considered a major open work, and more generally of the Maximum En- problem in the field: computing equilibria was shown tropy Principle in statistics, to the work on learn- to be hard, even for two-player games [Chen and Deng, ing in games and the problem of equilibrium se- 2005b,a, Daskalakis and Papadimitriou, 2005, Daskalakis lection.
    [Show full text]
  • Online Learning, Regret Minimization, Minimax Optimality, and Correlated
    High level Last time we discussed notion of Nash equilibrium. Static concept: set of prob. Distributions (p,q,…) such that Online Learning, Regret Minimization, nobody has any incentive to deviate. Minimax Optimality, and Correlated But doesn’t talk about how system would get there. Troubling that even finding one can be hard in large games. Equilibrium What if agents adapt (learn) in ways that are well-motivated in terms of their own rewards? What can we say about the system then? Avrim Blum High level Consider the following setting… Today: Each morning, you need to pick Online learning guarantees that are achievable when acting one of N possible routes to drive in a changing and unpredictable environment. to work. Robots R Us What happens when two players in a zero-sum game both But traffic is different each day. 32 min use such strategies? Not clear a priori which will be best. When you get there you find out how Approach minimax optimality. long your route took. (And maybe Gives alternative proof of minimax theorem. others too or maybe not.) What happens in a general-sum game? Is there a strategy for picking routes so that in the Approaches (the set of) correlated equilibria. long run, whatever the sequence of traffic patterns has been, you’ve done nearly as well as the best fixed route in hindsight? (In expectation, over internal randomness in the algorithm) Yes. “No-regret” algorithms for repeated decisions “No-regret” algorithms for repeated decisions A bit more generally: Algorithm has N options. World chooses cost vector.
    [Show full text]
  • Correlated Equilibrium
    Announcements Ø Minbiao’s office hour will be changed to Thursday 1-2 pm, starting from next week, at Rice Hall 442 1 CS6501: Topics in Learning and Game Theory (Fall 2019) Introduction to Game Theory (II) Instructor: Haifeng Xu Outline Ø Correlated and Coarse Correlated Equilibrium Ø Zero-Sum Games Ø GANs and Equilibrium Analysis 3 Recap: Normal-Form Games Ø � players, denoted by set � = {1, ⋯ , �} Ø Player � takes action �* ∈ �* Ø An outcome is the action profile � = (�., ⋯ , �/) • As a convention, �1* = (�., ⋯ , �*1., �*2., ⋯ , �/) denotes all actions excluding �* / ØPlayer � receives payoff �*(�) for any outcome � ∈ Π*5.�* • �* � = �*(�*, �1*) depends on other players’ actions Ø �* , �* *∈[/] are public knowledge ∗ ∗ ∗ A mixed strategy profile � = (�., ⋯ , �/) is a Nash equilibrium ∗ ∗ (NE) if for any �, �* is a best response to �1*. 4 NE Is Not the Only Solution Concept ØNE rests on two key assumptions 1. Players move simultaneously (so they cannot see others’ strategies before the move) 2. Players take actions independently ØLast lecture: sequential move results in different player behaviors • The corresponding game is called Stackelberg game and its equilibrium is called Strong Stackelberg equilibrium Today: we study what happens if players do not take actions independently but instead are “coordinated” by a central mediator Ø This results in the study of correlated equilibrium 5 An Illustrative Example B STOP GO A STOP (-3, -2) (-3, 0) GO (0, -2) (-100, -100) The Traffic Light Game Well, we did not see many crushes in reality…
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae
    Curriculum Vitae ALDO RUSTICHINI April 2011 email: [email protected] Marital Status: Married; Citizenship: Italian EDUCATION B.A. Philosophy University of Florence Italy 1977 M.A. Economics University of Manchester UK 1980 Ph.D. Mathematics University of Minnesota USA 1987 CURRENT AFFILIATION and POSITION Professor of Economics, Department of Economics, University of Minnesota. Center for Cognitive Sciences, University of Minnesota. RESEARCH INTERESTS Decision Theory, Game Theory, General Equilibrium Theory, Neuroscience and Economics, Experimental Economics, Behavioral Economics, Microeconomic The- ory, Models of Bounded Rationality; Economic Dynamics and Macroeconomics, Political Economy. EDITORIAL ACTIVITY 1 Referee for Econometrica, Journal of Economic Theory, Review of Economic Stud- ies, Journal of Economic Dynamics and Control, American Economic Review. Associate Editor of Games and Economic Behavior, Journal of Mathematical Economics, PLOS One Past Associate Editorships: Journal of of Economic Theory; Review of Economic Dynamics; FELLOWSHIPS Fellow of the Econometric Society, Council of the Game Theory Society 2 PUBLICATIONS Decision Theory, Experimental Economics and Neuroeconomics Published papers 1. (with Gary Charness), Gender differences in cooperation with group mem- bership reference, Games and Economic Behavior, forthcoming. 2. Ifat Levy, Jason Snell, Amy Nelson, Aldo Rustichini, and Paul Glimcher, "The neural representation of subjective value under risk and ambiguity", Journal of Neurophysiology, 103, 10361047, (2010). 3. Uri Gneezy, Aldo Rustichini, Alexander Vostroknutov, "Experience and In- sight in the Race game", Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 75, 2010, 144-155. 4. Aldo Rustichini, Neuroeconomics: what have we found, and what should we search for, Current Opinions in Neurobiology, 19, 672-677 5. John Dickhaut, Aldo Rustichini, and Vernon Smith, A Neuroeconomic theory of the decision process Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA, 106, 52, December 29, 2214522150, (2009) 6.
    [Show full text]
  • Rationality and Common Knowledge Herbert Gintis
    Rationality and Common Knowledge Herbert Gintis May 30, 2010 1 Introduction Interactive epistemology is the study of the distributionof knowledge among ratio- nal agents, using modal logicin the traditionof Hintikka(1962) and Kripke (1963), and agent rationality based on the rational actor model of economic theory, in the tradition of Von Neumann and Morgenstern (1944) and Savage (1954). Epistemic game theory, which is interactive epistemology adjoined to classical game theory (Aumann, 1987, 1995), has demonstrated an intimate relationship between ratio- nality and correlated equilibrium (Aumann 1987, Brandenburger and Dekel 1987), and has permitted the rigorous specification of the conditions under which rational agents will play a Nash equilibrium (Aumann and Brandenburger 1995). A central finding in this research is that rational agents use the strategies sug- gested by game-theoretic equilibrium concepts when there is a commonality of knowledge in the form of common probability distributions over the stochastic variables that arise in the play of the game (so-called common priors), and com- mon knowledge of key aspects of the strategic interaction. We say an event E is common knowledge for agents i D 1;:::;n if the each agent i knows E, each i knows that each agent j knows E, each agent k knows that each j knows that each i knows E, and so on (Lewis 1969, Aumann 1976). Specifying when individuals share knowledge and when they know that they share knowledge is among the most challenging of epistemological issues. Con- temporary psychological research has shown that these issues cannot be resolved by analyzing the general features of high-level cognitive functioning alone, but in fact concern the particular organization of the human brain.
    [Show full text]
  • Correlated Equilibrium in a Nutshell
    The University of Manchester Research Correlated equilibrium in a nutshell DOI: 10.1007/s11238-017-9609-9 Document Version Accepted author manuscript Link to publication record in Manchester Research Explorer Citation for published version (APA): Amir, R., Belkov, S., & Evstigneev, I. V. (2017). Correlated equilibrium in a nutshell. Theory and Decision, 83(4), 1- 12. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-017-9609-9 Published in: Theory and Decision Citing this paper Please note that where the full-text provided on Manchester Research Explorer is the Author Accepted Manuscript or Proof version this may differ from the final Published version. If citing, it is advised that you check and use the publisher's definitive version. General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the Research Explorer are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Takedown policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please refer to the University of Manchester’s Takedown Procedures [http://man.ac.uk/04Y6Bo] or contact [email protected] providing relevant details, so we can investigate your claim. Download date:25. Sep. 2021 Noname manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) Correlated Equilibrium in a Nutshell Rabah Amir · Sergei Belkov · Igor V. Evstigneev Received: date / Accepted: date Abstract We analyze the concept of correlated equilibrium in the framework of two-player two-strategy games. This simple framework makes it possible to clearly demonstrate the characteristic features of this concept.
    [Show full text]