Agents of the People Studies in the History of Political Th ought

Edited by Terence Ball, Arizona State University Jörn Leonhard, Albert-Ludwigs-Universität Freiburg Wyger Velema, University of Amsterdam

Advisory Board Janet Coleman, London School of Economics and Political Science, UK Vittor Ivo Comparato, University of Perugia, Italy Jacques Guilhaumou, CNRS, France John Marshall, Johns Hopkins University, Baltimore, USA Markku Peltonen, University of Helsinki, Finland

VOLUME 4 Agents of the People

Democracy and Popular Sovereignty in British and Swedish Parliamentary and Public Debates, 1734–1800

By Pasi Ihalainen

LEIDEN • BOSTON 2010 On the cover: Th e House of Commons 1793–1794, by Karl Anton Hickel, oil on canvas, 1793–1795. Given by Francis Joseph I, Emperor of , 1885. On display at the Palace of Westminster, London. © National Portrait Gallery, London.

Th e Prime Minister, William Pitt, is speaking, probably in connection with the outbreak of war with France. Th e opposition leader is seated, wearing a hat, on the right side of the Speaker.

Th is book is printed on acid-free paper.

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

Ihalainen, Pasi. Agents of the people : democracy and popular sovereignty in British and Swedish parliamentary and public debates, 1734–1800 / by Pasi Ihalainen Brill. p. cm. — (Studies in the history of political thought, ISSN 1873-6548 ; v. 4) Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-90-04-18336-0 (hardback : alk. paper) 1. Representative government and representation—Great Britain—History—18th century. 2. Representative government and representation—Sweden—History—18th century. 3. Great Britain. Parliament—History—18th century. 4. Sweden. Riksdagen—History—18th century. 5. Great Britain—Politics and government—18th century. 6. Sweden—Politics and government—18th century. I. Title. II. Series.

JN539.I43 2010 321.8–dc22 2010000468

ISSN 1873-6548 ISBN 978 90 04 18336 0

Copyright 2010 by Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, Th e Netherlands. Koninklijke Brill NV incorporates the imprints Brill, Hotei Publishing, IDC Publishers, Martinus Nijhoff Publishers and VSP.

All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, translated, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without prior written permission from the publisher.

Authorization to photocopy items for internal or personal use is granted by Koninklijke Brill NV provided that the appropriate fees are paid directly to Th e Copyright Clearance Center, 222 Rosewood Drive, Suite 910, Danvers, MA 01923, USA. Fees are subject to change. printed in the netherlands For Sari and in memory of Fridolf

CONTENTS

Acknowledgements ...... xi Abbreviations ...... xv

Introduction ...... 1

Chapter One British and Swedish Parliamentary Debates in a Comparative Study of Political Vocabularies ...... 29 Th e Signifi cance of Parliamentary Debates for the History of Political Vocabularies ...... 31 Practical Arrangements and Argumentation ...... 36 Special Features of Parliamentary Rhetoric ...... 41 Ceremonial Speaking and Dialogues Between the Powers of the State ...... 45 Methodological Challenges Posed by the Use of Parliamentary Reports and Minutes ...... 50

Chapter Two Variations in British Parliamentary Conceptions of the People, 1734–1771 ...... 59 Th e Political Role of the People in the Septennial Act Debates of 1734: Walpole’s Defi nition of the Limits of Democracy ...... 67 Th e Standing Army and the Rights of the People in the Late 1730s ...... 78 Th e Prime Minister Challenged by a “Popular Government” in 1741–1742 ...... 89 Views on the Excessive and Insuffi cient Power of the People in the 1740s ...... 104 Consensual Conceptions of the People as Subjects during the Seven Years’ War ...... 119 Wilkes and America: Th e Increasing Relevance of ‘the People’ in Political Argumentation, 1763–1769 ...... 127 Redefi nitions of the Relationship between the People, Parliament and the Crown in the Aft ermath of the John Wilkes Case, 1770–1771 ...... 139 viii contents

Chapter Th ree Th e Swedish Case: Did Popular Sovereignty and Representative Democracy Exist in Sweden before 1772? ...... 157 Interpretations of the Age of Liberty as a Watershed in the Progress of Democracy ...... 160 Th e Relationship between the Nobility, the Nation and the People at the Beginning of the Riksdag of 1769–1770 ...... 175 Th e Concept of the People in Printed Literature and the Reactions of the Estates to Publicity in the Autumn of 1769 ...... 184 Th e Concept of the People in Debates on the Constitution ... 190 Th e Noble Estate and the Meaning of ‘Democracy’ in the Autumn of 1769 ...... 203 Increasing Contestability of the Concept ‘the People’ during the Riksdag of 1771–1772 ...... 209 Th e Concept of Democracy in the Rhetoric of the Deadlocked Parties ...... 220 Th e Political Role of the People in the Accession Charter and the Nomination of Senators ...... 226 Th e Concept of the People at the Time of the Coronation and the Royal Coup of 1772 ...... 239

Chapter Four Th e Re-Evaluation of the Representation of the People and Democracy in Westminster, 1772–1789 ...... 245 Th e American Crisis, Representation and the British People, 1772–1780 ...... 246 Enter Pitt and Fox: Democracy of the Pure Swedish and Mixed British Types Debated in the Early 1780s ...... 269 Prospects for a Parliamentary Reform and the People’s Ministry, 1782–1783 ...... 289 Further Debates on Parliamentary Reform, 1784–1785 ...... 306 Positive Understandings of Democracy before the French Revolution ...... 325 Th e Rise of a Representative Republic in America: no Comment from Westminster ...... 337 contents ix

Chapter Five Reactions to the Revolutionary Concepts of Democracy and Popular Sovereignty in Westminster, 1789–1800 ...... 343 Initial Responses to the Revolution in Britain ...... 348 Th e Heated Debate on Democracy in 1790 ...... 352 Strengthening Criticism of the French Model of Democracy in 1791 ...... 364 Proper British and Extreme French Democracy Contrasted in 1792 ...... 375 Combating both French and Domestic Conceptions of Democracy in 1793 ...... 392 Reactions to Robespierre’s Redefi nition of Democracy in 1794 ...... 409 Th e Political Rights of the People in a Time of Crisis ...... 423 Calls for Representative Government and Defences of Democracy 1796–1797 ...... 447 Post-Revolutionary Visions: the Sovereignty of Parliament Becomes the Sovereignty of the People ...... 457

Conclusion ...... 471

Bibliography ...... 497 Index of Persons ...... 517 Index of Subjects ...... 523

ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS

If there is a political forum in which things are done by using words, it is defi nitely Parliament. Aft er analysing the linguistic construction of national identities in Protestant parliamentary sermons in Protestant Nations Redefi ned: Changing Perceptions of National Identity in the Rhetoric of the English, Dutch and Swedish Public Churches, 1685–1772 (Brill, 2005), I felt a need to look at the more secular debate in the ple- nary sessions of the same institutions. Likewise, having analysed how and why ‘the nation’ began to supplement and even bypass religion as the major defi ner of political identity in one genre, it seemed necessary to analyse the changing uses of references to ‘the people’ in connection with the actual decision-making process. Th is change of emphasis took me from the study of the roots of modern nationalism to the study of the emergence of the modern concept of democracy in the context of late-eighteenth-century parliamentary institutions. In both cases, I was studying conceptual evolution that took place in traditional institu- tions—not revolutionary change, which has previously received much more scholarly attention. Several organizations and individuals have made this exploration of the early modernization of political references to the people, popular representation, democracy and the sovereignty of the people not only possible but also a pleasant experience. First of all, I need to thank the anonymous panelists and members of the Research Council for Culture and Society of the Academy of Finland for allowing me to concentrate on the preparation of this project as a Research Fellow in 2004–2006 and for providing me with supportive research funding during my work as a Professor in General History in 2006–2009. I am likewise grateful to the Department of History and Ethnology at the University of Jyväskylä for providing me with the latter position and a convenient research environment. I am particularly grateful for Professors Petri Karonen, Jari Ojala and Seppo Zetterberg for freeing me from much of administrative work and allowing me to focus on research and teaching. Th e other members of staff of the Department deserve an apology for my occasional absent-mindedness caused by the writing of this book and thanks for their help in solving various practical problems I have come across when working on it. Research on European history is by no means a lonely or discipline- bound adventure. Special thanks are due to Charlotta Wolff and Jouko xii acknowledgements

Nurmiainen, who cooperated with me in 2005–2007 in the Academy of Finland project “Enlightened Loyalties” and whose knowledge of the eighteenth-century Swedish Diet and critical comments on previous versions of some of the chapters have contributed signifi cantly to the fi nal result. I have also benefi ted considerably from the methodologi- cal inspiration provided by the Academy of Finland Centre of Excel- lence in Political Th ought and Conceptual Change (CoE PolCon), its research team “Political Th ought and Conceptual History” and more particularly by Academy Professor Kari Palonen. A shared interest in parliamentary discourse in Political Science and General History has brought the two areas of scholarship closer together, leading to the enrichment of the methodological and source basis of the research carried out in both. Papers given in conferences organized by CoE PolCon, the Depart- ment of History and Ethnology, the History of Political and Social Concepts Group, the International Commission for the History of Rep- resentative and Parliamentary Institutions, the Institute of Historical Research and the British and Finnish Societies for Eighteenth-Century Studies in Jyväskylä, Helsinki, Uppsala, Härnösand, London, Oxford, St Andrews and Istanbul have provided forums for testing some of my ideas. I would like to thank Alex Barber, Pim den Boer, Martin Burke, Piia Einonen, Michael Freeden, Taru Haapala, Jonas Harvard, Irène Herrmann, Helge Jordheim, Jussi Kurunmäki, Jörn Leonhard, Bo Lindberg, Jani Marjanen, Raymonde Monnier, Jonas Nordin, Kyösti Pekonen, Markku Peltonen, Kari Saastamoinen, Paul Seaward, Quentin Skinner, Marie-Christine Skuncke, Willibald Steinmetz, Hen- rik Stenius, Henrika Tandefelt, Adam Tomkins, Tapani Turkka, Timo Turja, Anthony F. Upton, Nadja Urbinati, Wyger Velema and Patrik Winton for their comments. It has been an equally motivating experi- ence to supervise master and doctoral students who are working on parliamentary discourses and to receive feedback from them. CoE PolCon has strengthened the infrastructure of this research by funding access to key databases, employing temporary research assis- tants and fi nancing fi rst-class copy-editing. Timo Särkkä helped me in database searches and the compilation of background information on speakers in autumn 2007. Oili Pulkkinen, Ph.D., as a co-editor, criti- cally pointed at weaknesses in my argumentation in autumn 2008. For those that remain, aft er our excellent cooperation, I alone am respon- sible. Th e same holds for my English language, which has at times acknowledgements xiii been considerably reformulated by Gerard McAlester, whose sensitiv- ity for historical discourse is remarkable. My wife and family have loyally supported my never-ending writing of the “dissertation” beyond reasonable working hours. As a demon- stration of my deep gratitude, I am dedicating this book to Sari and to the memory of my grandfather Fridolf, who tirelessly debated with me on interpretations of the past.

ABBREVIATIONS

Roman numerals given in brackets without any preceding abbreviation always refer to Cobbett’s Parliamentary History of England: From the Norman Conquest in 1066 to the Year 1803 (London 1806–1820), indi- cating the volume number and column number(s), e.g. (XII, 397–398).

BdP Bondeståndets riksdagsprotokoll BrP Borgarståndets riksdagsprotokoll ECCO Eighteenth Century Collections Online HPHC Th e History and Proceedings of the House of Commons of Great Britain MOMW Th e Making of the Modern World PR Th e Parliamentary Register; or, History of the Proceedings and Debates of the House of Commons PrP Prästeståndets riksdagsprotokoll PSUSJD Protocoller, hållne vid 1769 års Riksdag uti Sammanträdet mellan Secrete Utskottet samt Secrete och Justitiae Deputa- tionerne angående Lagarnes Verkställighet R Riksdagsarkivet, Riksarkivet, Stockholm SPL Sveriges periodiska litteratur SRARP Sveriges ridderskaps och adels riksdagsprotokoll från och med år 1719 SUP Sekreta utskottets protokoll SUBP Secreta Utskottets Beredrings Protocoller och Handlingar Rörande Svea Konunga Försäkran

INTRODUCTION

Th e rise of democracy is one of the great narratives of Western his- tory. Th e principle of political power originating from the people is so widely held an assumption in modern democratic states that we do not necessarily come to think about the far from self-evident rise of such a notion even in the history of countries that now regard themselves as leading democracies. “Popular sovereignty and representative democ- racy emerged with the Enlightenment and the American and French Revolutions,” we are apt to think, without delving any deeper into an analysis of the problematic aspects of the rise and association of these originally separate concepts in the eighteenth century. Th e rise of democracy has also been a constant object of interest for political scientists and philosophers, sometimes also for historians.1 Th is book does not follow a conventional approach to the history of political philosophy; it does not focus on the contextualization and analysis of the thinking of individual political philosophers. Instead, I suggest that the histories of the concepts of popular sovereignty and democracy should also be studied by analysing the debates in which leading political decision-makers were involved. I am thus interested in the practical everyday use of political language and the recycling and creation of new meanings for political concepts by their active use in political arguments. What is of special interest here is the use of references to the people to legitimate political order in the past, not some philosophical or sociological concept of ‘the people’. While the conceptualizations of past political phenomena by individual thinkers provide the starting point of the analysis, our main interest will rather lie in how entire political communities understood the political role of the people in a wide variety of ways. Th e object of study is the use of references to the political role of the people in eighteenth-century parliamentary debates by a large number of leading politicians. Th is is also a comparative study in that the debates are analysed not only in their relevant political contexts at the national level but also through

1 For an attempt to write a total history of the events of the late eighteenth century as a “democratic” movement, see Palmer 1959, 4, and Palmer 1964, 572. 2 introduction comparisons with parallel debates in the representative institution of another country. Th e main question is how—and to what extent—the political estab- lishments of two Western European countries with inherited rep- resentative institutions adopted the notions of democracy and the sovereignty of the people in the eighteenth century, which is when such concepts received clearer expression, recognition and acceptance in parliamentary and public debates. What was the actual reception of the notions of democracy and popular sovereignty—as formulated by philosophers—in parliamentary debates? And what kind of inter- action was there between political thinking and the practical every- day use of the language of politics? Aft er all, by the mid-eighteenth century, signifi cant debates on the political role of the people were emerging both within representative institutions and in the expand- ing and increasingly free published literature. It is worth considering the importance of the diff erent types of political discourse in mould- ing prevalent notions of democracy and the sovereignty of the people: was the agenda of political discourse set by the published literature or by parliamentary debates? And if both of them set it, did they do so separately or in interaction? Britain and Sweden have been chosen for comparison for three rea- sons. Firstly, the people of the time felt that the constitutions of the two countries had a lot in common and diff ered from those of the rest of Europe. Both were countries with a mixed constitution of some sort: Britain was a kingdom in which Parliament had enjoyed con- siderable fi nancial and legislative power ever since the 1690s, while Sweden was a kingdom in which royal political infl uence had been taken over by the Senate and a Diet controlled by the higher estates since the 1720s. Secondly, Britain and Sweden are countries in which there exist signifi cant comparable records of parliamentary debates at the national level. Th e third reason for choosing Britain and Sweden is that relatively little work on such evolutionary representative gov- ernments is available in comparison with the monumental amount of work done on the American and French Revolutions. Th e reception of ideas from these revolutions in systems that experienced no open revolution themselves yet contributed to the modernization of Euro- pean political cultures deserves more attention. Research has quite recently suggested that the British opposed rather than contributed to the formation of a modern concept of democracy in the 1790s, whereas the suggestion with regard to Sweden has been that an early introduction 3 democracy was already emerging there by 1772. Both claims call for qualifi cations. Th e representative institutions from which the debates analysed here have been selected are the Houses of Parliament in Britain and the Swedish four-estate Diet. Although these institutions diff ered signifi - cantly in structure and procedure, as we shall learn in Chapter One, the debates which took place in them had surprisingly many subjects, popular arguments and cross-border references in common so that a contextualized comparison of the use of political language in them seems highly applicable. Indeed, the contemporaries themselves car- ried out such comparisons. Th us there should be no impediment to describing the debates of the British House of Lords and discussions in some joint committees of the Swedish Estates under the umbrella concept ‘parliamentary debates’ or to studying them side by side, albeit in their own particular contexts.2 Naturally, such a procedure is not intended to imply that the estate system of the Swedish realm consti- tuted a “parliament” entirely like the British one. Th e relative impor- tance of the British House of Commons certainly grew towards the end of the eighteenth century, whereas the Swedish Diet lost most of its political signifi cance with the Gustavian coup in 1772. Both were rep- resentative institutions, however, and in both the leading statesmen of the time debated the issues of the day and, as a side eff ect, defi ned the classical political concepts of the people and democracy and adapted to new political ideas such as the sovereignty of the people. Th e con- temporaries were happy to view the two constitutions as comparable, although they did tend to regard their own constitution as superior to the other one. Th e Dutch estate system was also occasionally seen as comparable in some respects. A possible subject for future research would be the comparative analysis of the concepts of democracy and popular sovereignty in

2 For corresponding comparative research on the use of concepts in debates in the present-day British and Swedish parliaments, see Ilie 2004a, 1–3, which analyses the “cross-institutional conceptual features” of “the roughly comparable discursive uses and argumentative functions” of British and Swedish “key words (and their col- locates)” as used in parliamentary debates. Ilie has been particularly interested in “the shift ing semantic properties, as well as the discursive and argumentative functions” of two nearly synonymous English and Swedish words and in “the connotations that they acquire in connection with their respective collocates in [. . .] parliamentary debates.” Th e comparative study of the semantics of parliamentary debates thus turns out to be highly relevant from the point of view of present-day linguistics as well. 4 introduction parliamentary speaking in all late eighteenth-century representative assemblies. Such a study should include not only Britain and Swe- den but also the United States, France and the Batavian Republic, and perhaps also Poland and some regional assemblies of the Ger- man-speaking countries, including . Th e people of the time occasionally regarded Poland as a free state alongside Britain, Sweden and the Dutch Republic, though almost always referring to it as a warning example rather than a model instance of such a state. Poland has been excluded from this study on the basis of its weaken- ing political situation as a country subject to divisions and because of the more limited availability of records on the debates. Th e German regional assemblies lacked equivalent national contexts with a free public debate. Th ere was free debate in Denmark for some time aft er 1770, but Denmark had no representative estates. Th ere are no extant minutes of the debates of the General Estates or the Estates of Holland, and the debates of the Batavian National Assembly are perhaps better compared with those of the French revolutionary assemblies. Immedi- ate democracy was realized in Switzerland only at the local and can- tonal levels, not at the national level. Debates in the assemblies of the early United States certainly came to play a role in the long run, but their infl uence on contemporary Europe remained limited and was communicated mainly through published literature. As far as France is concerned, this book utilizes the existing research on the political language of the Revolution rather than embarking on an analysis of the distinctly innovative revolutionary assemblies. Focusing on the British Parliament and the Swedish Diet, therefore, I shall address the following questions: how was the notion that all political power is derived from the people expressed in these tradi- tional representative institutions, and how strong was it at diff erent times in the eighteenth century? Th e emergence of neologisms such as “the sovereignty of the people” deserves extra attention here. It is also worth considering whether the idea of the popular origin of power led to calls for the active participation of the people in politics. Th is ques- tion can be extended to concern the limits of such participation and attempts to solve the contrast between original and active sovereignty of the people through the concept of representation. I am also interested in fi nding out at what point the people of the time began to view “democracy” in a positive way that diff ered from the pejorative classical concept of democracy. It is not evident that they yet used the concept to defi ne their political system, their political introduction 5 conceptions and their future goals. Th e various old counter-arguments used against democracy and the emerging anti-democratic arguments need to be addressed. As we shall see, existing research supports both the interpretation that democracy became a positive, progressive and future-oriented concept during the course of the eighteenth century and the view according to which only the French Revolution intro- duced this change. Perhaps both interpretations have a point: the French Revolution aff ected an already ongoing modernization of the meanings of democracy in countries with older representative institu- tions. Perhaps indeed—by demonstrating that the classical notion of democracy as just another form of anarchy was correct—it delayed a more evolutionary modernization of the concept. Th e combination of the notions of the sovereignty of the people and democracy also deserves attention. It may have been a result of the innovative political ideas of philosophers, radical writers and revolu- tionaries writing for the public, but it is also possible that major refor- mulations in the vocabulary of democracy emerged within traditional systems of representation as a result of creative parliamentary delib- eration on various political phenomena of the day. Th e latter modifi - cations, too, truly changed political cultures. Th ere may be a history of democracy within parliamentary debates that has gone unnoticed as a result of the fact that most attention has been paid to political philosophy proper and to the more dramatic events of the American and French Revolutions. Th e main argument of Agents of the People is that there is such a forgotten history, and that its exploration helps us to understand the formation of the more modern concepts of democracy and the sovereignty of the people as a process of interaction between tradi- tion and innovation, parliamentary debates and revolutionary ideas expressed in published literature, Britain and France and other coun- tries. Th is study shows that there was not only an intense debate on the political role of the people taking place in both the British Parlia- ment and the Swedish Estates from the 1760s on but also a period of revaluation of the concept of democracy in connection with the British parliamentary reform debates of the early 1780s. Th e French Revolution brought new dimensions to this debate by providing an alternative, more radical, defi nition of democracy, which led to fi erce confrontations between the supporters of diff erent understandings of the concept in the British Parliament. Even though this confl ict seems at fi rst to have led to the defeat of both the pre-revolutionary and 6 introduction revolutionary concepts of democracy, when the British government declared itself the main opponent of French democracy internation- ally and at home, this is not the whole story. Th e debates between the advocates of the more traditional and the modifi ed understandings of democracy led to arguments in which the British parliamentary system was redefi ned as one based on the previously rejected revolutionary principle of the sovereignty of the people. Th is reconsideration of the character of the political system in Parliament took place in interac- tion with the published literature. Above all, the redefi nition opened possibilities for the further democratization of the representative sys- tem in the course of the nineteenth century. Of course, the principle of political power being derived from the people already played a role in classical political thought—in one way or another—and was widely recognized by natural law theorists in the seventeenth century. Th ese philosophers, however, did not necessarily associate the origin of power in the people with some distinct concept of ‘popular sovereignty’, as we might be inclined to do in reading their texts. Th e history of the concept ‘democracy’ is likewise full of concep- tual change and contestation. We need to take care not to misinterpret “democracy” when we either encounter the term or wonder about its absence in early modern texts which we regard as “democratic”. Fur- thermore, we easily assume that everyone knows what democracy is even if the meaning of the concept has altered radically since the eight- eenth century, changing from being completely negative to uncritically positive, and even if we ourselves continue to hold a variety of con- fl icting understandings of the concept. Th e pejoratively understood concept of democracy had existed in a quite stable form from 500 BC to the late eighteenth century— that is from the criticism of Athenian democracy to the days of the French Revolution. In general terms, we can say that well into the last decades of the eighteenth century, democracy was viewed as just one of the three classical theoretical forms of government. In its pure form, on the other hand, it was considered obsolete; ever since the time of Aristotle, democracy had been viewed pejoratively as the form of government that entailed the greatest number of potential risks, because power would be given into the hands of the self-interested common people. Democracy—still generally understood in the sense of direct democracy of the Athenian type—was not only considered impractical but was also seen as leading to the despotism of the poor and uneducated, and ultimately to utter anarchy. Th e characteristics introduction 7 of the classical model of democracy included the principle of equal- ity among citizens, their direct participation in popular assemblies, the capacity of the assemblies to decide on any matters of the city- state and exclusive criteria of citizenship. Despite the long survival of Athenian democracy, democracy was understood by most members of eighteenth-century political establishments as a stage in an inevitable cycle of forms of government derived from a cyclical conception of time. Because of its supposedly inherent degenerative characteristics, democracy could only be considered acceptable as one of the three controlled elements of a balanced mixed constitution as recommended by Aristotle and Polybius.3 Th e mixed constitution had been adopted as the ideal form of government among the political elites in early-modern aristocratic “republics” like Venice, Britain, the Dutch Republic, Poland and Swe- den. In all of these countries, theoretical debates on ‘democracy’ and the political power of ‘the people’ continued to be dominated by the classical pejorative understanding of democracy well into the latter half of the eighteenth century. In this period, conventional notions of mixed government were increasingly challenged by revolutions, fi rst in America and then in France. It would take a long and complicated process before eighteenth-century politicians distanced themselves from the Aristotelian tradition of viewing democracy pejoratively. Yet the political establishments did reconsider their concept of democracy in important ways as a reaction to the revolutions—and even indepen- dently of them. Th ese reconsiderations and revaluations are the major topic of this book. One factor that enabled the reconsiderations was the fact that the political elites of countries with representative institutions had also inherited a positive classical understanding of the people as distinct from the pejorative concept of democracy. In the course of the eigh- teenth century, some thinkers also started to combine positive Roman notions of res publica with the initially separate Greek concept of democracy. According to Margaret Canovan, the extraordinary exam- ple of the Roman Republic supported a positive understanding of the people as holders of political power that ‘democracy’ lacked until the end of the eighteenth century. Th e Roman legacy provided a chance to view the people (populus) either as the political community and

3 Held 1989, 34; Hanson 1989, 70–71. 8 introduction the mixed constitution as a whole (populus Romanus), or as a name for the plebeian citizens. By the fi ft eenth-century, the classical concept of the people was already being used in European political thought to support theories according to which all forms of political power were based on popular consent. Late sixteenth- and seventeenth-cen- tury theorists developed the idea of popular consent further. Th ey claimed that the people had at some time in the past surrendered all their power to the rulers or, alternatively, that the popular origin of all power implied the possibility of popular authority being restored at times of revolution. Th e latter assumption suggested that monarchs were accountable to the people and could be resisted, that the people could remould their constitution, and fi nally even that the people were entitled to permanent self-government.4 A major problem with the Roman tradition was that while the polit- ical elite could invoke the accountability of the rulers to the people in the sense of the political community, they usually avoided appeals to the people in the sense of the population at large. Th e aristocracy rather saw themselves as the representatives of the people.5 Th is double meaning of the concept of the people continued to be a major challenge in political discourse throughout the eighteenth century: it remained unclear whether the common people belonged to the political com- munity or whether they were merely represented by the higher orders. Disagreements were unavoidable because of the indefi nite, amorphous and essentially contested meaning of the concept of the people.6 Th e principle of the representation of the people had also been artic- ulated in a number of countries before the eighteenth century.7 Th e concept ‘the people’, although increasingly popular in political argu- ments as a description of the political community, was oft en still used in a vague sense, rather as it had been in classical political thinking. Oft en it was only the most politically active estates that were seen as constituting the true people, not all the inhabitants of the country. Alternatively, the people could mean specifi cally those not belong- ing to the political elite, ‘the common people’.8 Whenever the con- cept of the people appears in early modern political texts, we thus

4 Canovan 2005, 11–12, 15–17. 5 Canovan 2005, 69. 6 Canovan 2005, 140. 7 See Pitkin 1989, 139–140, 142; Urbinati 2007, 17. 8 Canovan 2005, 5. introduction 9 have to consider the variety of meanings that this amorphous concept could carry and its exact reference. Representation was, aft er all, not yet “democratic” in any modern sense in the eighteenth century; the democratization of representation and the extension of the suff rage to whole adult populations would only take place much later, ultimately not until the twentieth century. Th e concept of sovereignty, as understood in the aft ermath of Jean Bodin’s writings in the late sixteenth century, referred to the perma- nent power of the state, which was independent of all other powers. Over the course of the early modern period, the meaning of the con- cept was secularized and sovereignty was increasingly understood as referring to the state as a collective and not to any particular person. However, it continued to be the convention to refer to the reigning monarch as “the sovereign”; most theorists and practising politicians still regarded the monarch as the nucleus of political power. Th e key question was whether this power of the monarch originated directly from God, or whether it had been given to him or her by the subjects through a contract. Another question concerned the practical impli- cations of such a contract: to what extent did it allow the people to be involved in the political process?9 Generally speaking, sovereignty was not associated with the people. Expressions referring to “supreme power” occurred more frequently and could at times—at least meta- phorically and with reference to the origin of political authority in the past—be associated with the people. A long history of the theoretical concepts of democracy, the people, representation and sovereignty thus already existed. Its continuation in the eighteenth century can be studied from a number of points of view. In the history of political philosophy, it has oft en been the over- all development of political theory as refl ected by the texts of some selected canonical theorists that has interested scholars. Th e concepts of democracy and popular sovereignty have oft en been connected in political theory, and scholars have located them in early modern texts regardless of the fact that clear expressions for these concepts may have been lacking, that the concepts have separate histories, and that they were associated with each other only aft er the French Revolution, or even the 1830s.10 Although such an analysis of the overall history

9 Hunter & Saunders 2002, 3−4; Lindberg 2006, 88–89, 92. 10 Rosanvallon 1995, 140, 150, 152; Rosanvallon 2000, 32; cf. Monnier 2001, 3, 18. 10 introduction of political theory is an entirely legitimate fi eld of inquiry, it may also direct attention away from the examination of the wider contempo- rary use of the language of politics in the past.11 We can legitimately ask whether ‘popular sovereignty’ or ‘representative democracy’, for instance, could exist before the people of the time had exact words to express such notions. Th e histories of the concepts of democracy and popular sovereignty in their modern, self-evidently positive senses have been previously studied from a number of perspectives, particularly in countries which have long traditions of representative institutions, such as the Dutch Republic, Poland,12 Britain and Sweden. It is necessary to emphasize the distinction between the conceptual history of democracy and that of the sovereignty of the people, particularly as this distinction has sometimes been ignored in previous research. Th e principle of politi- cal power being ultimately derived from the people is a classical one, to be sure, and it has been asserted by natural law theorists since the seventeenth century. However, some confusion may have arisen from the tendency to use the later universal concept ‘popular sovereignty’ to refer to any ideas emphasizing the role of the people in politi- cal decision-making and to teleologically associate demands for the strengthening of the popular element in the mixed constitution with the post-French Revolution meanings of the concept of democracy. For much of the period studied, the principle of political power as originating initially from the people (however defi ned) was supported by many members of the parliamentary establishments but not asso- ciated with some explicit concept of the sovereignty of the people and even less with the word “democracy” as an independent form of government by the people. Th e practical implications of the contract between the people and the rulers, concluded in the immemorial past at the time of the foundation of the political community, remained debatable as well. Not even John Locke, the foremost late-seventeenth-century advo- cate of the popular origin of political power and generally regarded as a radical defender of popular sovereignty, connected the concepts of sovereignty and the people in his Two Treatises of Government. Locke did write about “the Consent of the People” as marking the founda-

11 Cf. Hanson 1989, 76; Edelstein 2003, 47. 12 Jedruch 1998; Greśkowiak-Krwawicz 2002. introduction 11 tion of all forms of government and about “a delegated Power from the People” possessed by the legislative assembly. He argued that the people had “reserved to themselves the Choice of their Representa- tives” and that “there remains [. . .] in the People a supream Power to remove or alter the Legislative”.13 He also referred to the “Doctrine of a Power in the People of providing for their Safety a-new, by a new Legislative”. Th e last two expressions come closest to what we cus- tomarily call “popular sovereignty”, although even here, “the supreme Power” was returned to the people, or “the People become Free and Superiour”, only in cases when the government had been dissolved during an interregnum.14 While Locke’s book strongly implies that the majority of adult male people were the ultimate source of political authority,15 to view this as a fully formulated and universally held doctrine of the sovereignty of the people would be an oversimplifi cation. While Lockean politi- cal theory recognized the role of the people as the original source of power, the post-revolutionary concept of popular sovereignty should perhaps not be automatically used to interpret early eighteenth-cen- tury ways of thinking. Instead, the actual language used to refer to the political roles of the people by the contemporaries should be investi- gated with a view to writing a “pre-history” of the revolutionary and more modern senses of the concepts ‘the sovereignty of the people’ and ‘democracy’. Th is study explores the means by which, and the extent to which, the inherited notions of political power as originating from the people were expressed in eighteenth-century parliamentary debates and in public debates related to them. Th is will be a history of the formation of the concepts of democracy and popular sovereignty, not an application of some established and generally accepted con- cepts to the interpretation of early modern sources. Some historians have recently suggested that the concepts of popu- lar sovereignty and democracy emerged even before the eighteenth century. In the Dutch case, Martin van Gelderen and Wyger Velema have shown that ideas concerning the supreme power of the provincial estates and the representation of the people by them already began to

13 John Locke, Two Treatises of Government, (London 1713), 271, 295, 300, 322, 358; Th e last statement entailed a distinction between Parliament and the people. Canovan 2005, 103. 14 John Locke, Two Treatises of Government, 1713, 301, 361, 373, 379. 15 Canovan 2005, 24. 12 introduction appear during the late sixteenth century. Van Gelderen has suggested that the principle of “popular sovereignty” was already beginning to emerge and the concept of democracy to be advocated by leading Dutch political writers in the mid-seventeenth century. According to Velema, Pieter De la Court and Baruch Spinoza advocated “a more democratic type of republic”.16 Jonathan Scott has also pointed out that Spinoza understood democracy as inherently positive and argued that sovereignty was something which should belong to all members of society.17 Th ese interpretations are, no doubt, based on frequent references to the political role of the people in the texts of the studied writers; however, it is by no means certain that the explicit concepts of democ- racy and popular sovereignty fi gure prominently in them. Defences of the democratic element in a mixed constitution undoubtedly already appeared in seventeenth-century discourse. We must remember, however, that Spinoza, a Jewish dissident from Amsterdam, was and remained an exception in the sphere of European political thought and that the above mentioned Dutch writers were predominantly politi- cal thinkers whose ideas were not necessarily widely shared among practising statesmen. Despite the tradition of advocating the political infl uence of the people in the Dutch Republic and some other far- reaching seventeenth-century republican ideas, it was, according to Velema, “during the revolutionary years of the late eighteenth-cen- tury” that Dutch republicanism “came to mean the permanent and active sovereignty of the people”.18 Searches in Dutch library databases also suggest that the term “popular government” (volks-regeering) did not begin to appear in book titles until the Patriot period of the 1780s and that the French Revolution led to a dramatic increase in the use of references to “democracy” there. In the case of England, several historians have maintained that the Levellers of the late 1640s not only developed the radical idea of ‘popular sovereignty’ but were also the fi rst “modern democrats”. Th e same scholars admit, however, that while the Levellers were in favour

16 Velema 2002, 11, 14–15; Velema 2005, 200; Van Gelderen 2002, 200–201, 215; for an even more extensive interpretation of the concept ‘democracy’ independently of seventeenth-century usage as well as for the conclusion that the Dutch invented democracy, see Mijnhardt 2005, 82. 17 Scott 2002, 78–80. 18 Velema 2007, abstract. introduction 13 of the political infl uence of “the people”, they certainly did not refer to themselves as “democrats” but were rather condemned as such by their critics.19 One question any historian interested in the authentic political language of the people of the time must ask is whether the much later content of the concept ‘democrat’ can be applied at all to seventeenth-century actors without producing teleological interpreta- tions and leading to anachronisms.20 Aft er all, we know that the fi rst positive uses of the term “democrat” as a form of self-identifi cation only began to appear from the late 1780s onwards.21 Aft er the French Revolution, to be sure, the seventeenth-century radical republicans were readily given the name “democrats”. As for France, historians have been in general agreement about the importance of the Revolution as a turning point in the history of democracy, but they have also sometimes made Enlightenment think- ers the earliest defenders of democracy. D’Argenson’s statements in the 1730s in favour of complementing monarchy with democracy are the best-known example of this prehistory of democracy.22 Generally speaking, in French, the concept of democracy still stood for some of the political systems of the ancient world.23 Among those Enlighten- ment philosophers who provided the basis for much of the eighteenth- century theoretical debate, Montesquieu defi ned ‘republic’ as a political system “in which the body or only a part of the people are possessed of the supreme power”.24 Montesquieu viewed democracy as a possible form of republic, although he detested it, especially in what he saw as its English form, as he made a distinction between representation and democracy. He was among the fi rst to argue that “when the body of

19 Morgan 1988; Hanson 1989, 73, 75; Wootton 1992; Worden 2002; Canovan 2005, 35; Urbinati 2006, 19. According to Urbinati, revealingly, the Levellers identi- fi ed the problems of popular sovereignty “before any doctrine of popular sovereignty was formulated”. 20 Skinner 2003, 76. 21 Palmer 1953, 205–207; Hanson 1989, 72. 22 Palmer 1953, 205; Rosanvallon 1995, 143; Rosanvallon 2000, 24; Dunn 2005, 93–96. 23 Rosanvallon 1995, 140–141. 24 Charles de Secondat, Baron de Montesquieu, Th e Spirit of Laws. Translated from the French of M. de Secondat, Baron de Montesquieu. With Corrections and Additions Communicated by the Author. Vol. 1 (London 1750), 11, cited here from the fi rst English translation which was most likely to be read by British parliamentarians. Cf. Wright 2002, 293, who refers to “sovereign power” in a modern translation. 14 introduction the people in a republic are possessed of the supreme power, this is called a democracy”.25 In later French Enlightenment debates, the concept of democracy occasionally took on positive meanings, which highlights the French origin of much of the ongoing conceptual change. However, even Rous- seau continued to view democracy in its classical sense as ill-suited to any contemporary government larger than that of a tiny city state. Rather than arguing in favour of the active sovereignty of the people, he warned of its potential consequences. According to Rousseau, the community as a whole could not run the government. At the same time, his writings contained references to “the people collectively in quality of sovereign”.26 Th is was a creative combination of these terms that provided an idea that the French revolutionaries would take much further, but Rousseau himself consistently distinguished between rep- resentation and sovereignty.27 Th e early development of a positive concept of democracy in Swe- den has been recently advocated by Bo Lindberg. Lindberg has located evidence of there having been at least some sympathy for the principle of democracy in seventeenth-century Swedish political theory. He has interpreted the so-called Age of Liberty (1719–1772), when the four- estate Diet in practice ruled the country, and particularly its fi nal phase, as revolutionary with regard to the breakthrough of certain modern ideas. Th ese ideas included a view of the Swedish people as a politi- cal agent and democracy as a positively understood phenomenon that began to defi ne the Swedish political system at that time. We do, of course, have plenty of statements from the higher estates in the 1760s emphasizing the necessity of securing the rights and liberties of “the people” and the need to serve their interests, but these rights and liber- ties oft en constituted merely an empty phrase that was not given any defi nite meaning other than the rule of law or the right of the estates to be heard. It may hence be an exaggeration to suggest that Swedish authors were arguing for “a representative democracy as opposed to a direct one” or that fully developed “popular sovereignty” had been

25 Montesquieu, Th e Spirit of the Laws, 1750, 11; Urbinati 2006, 7. 26 Jean-Jacques Rousseau, An Inquiry into the Nature of the Social Contract; or Prin- ciples of Political Right. Translated from the French of John James Rousseau (Dublin 1791), 159, 163, 168, 188, 190–191, 287; Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Emilius and Sophia: or, a New System of Education, Vol. 4 (London 1763), 247–248; Hampson 1983, 4; Rosanvallon 2000, 23. 27 Urbinati 2006, 7. introduction 15 established in Sweden.28 In the Swedish case, too, we encounter the risk of post-French Revolution meanings of democracy and popular sovereignty being applied in the interpretation of mid-eighteenth- century texts which could not yet have advocated such ideas. Th is study focuses on the long-term formation of political concepts through debates in representative bodies and in published literature. It is not my intention to provide normative defi nitions of democracy or popular sovereignty and apply them to an interpretation of the sources. Instead, I analyse the content of original arguments in which references to the political role of the people were made, focusing on the exact choice of words and the moulding of language referring to the people through time. Th ere is no doubt that the political infl uence of the people was defended by early modern authors in countries with mixed governments and representative institutions. However, some problems arise out of the trend in current research to apply the post- French Revolution concepts of democracy and popular sovereignty to the interpretation of eighteenth-century texts without suffi cient atten- tion being paid to exactly what the contemporaries said and to the nature of the concepts that they actually possessed. Most studies that emphasize a break with the classical concept of democracy prior to the French Revolution have been carried out in the context of a single nation state. Indeed, one cannot avoid getting the impression that the context of the nation state has led historians to compete in trying to fi nd the appearance of democracy and popu- lar sovereignty fi rst in the sources of their own mother countries and thereby prove that these were pioneers of the rise of democracy. Th ey do refer to research in other countries, but they have not used compa- rable primary sources from several countries, which may give rise to semantic confusion in this seemingly comparative history of democ- racy and popular sovereignty. By the eighteenth century, as we shall see, the key concepts had already taken on diff erent connotations in diff erent languages. Th ere is also the risk that a historian will base his or her conclusions regarding the history of democracy on texts written either by philoso- phers who have been later widely studied or by individual political polemists pursuing some particular purpose. As a result, defences of democracy and popular sovereignty may be found in texts in which

28 Lagerroth 1934, 5/1, 170; Lindberg 2006. See Chapter Th ree for detailed references. 16 introduction neither term actually appears, or in which they are not used in posi- tive and universal post-French Revolution senses, or which were not generally accepted by practising statesmen or by the public at large. Sources refl ecting the more actual use of political language, such as parliamentary debates, diff er from such theoretical debate and tell us about the real pace of change in the language of democracy at the level of entire political communities. Studies which have viewed democracy from a more global and theo- retical perspective also provide a foundation for doubts about the full reliability of certain conclusions locating the rise of ‘democracy’ and ‘popular sovereignty’ in a period before the late eighteenth century. Th e most recent contributors to this debate include Margaret Cano- van’s book on language referring to the people, John Dunn’s interpre- tation of the history of democracy and Nadia Urbinati’s analysis of the genealogy of representative democracy. Th e approach of these scholars is that of political theory; however, the late eighteenth-century trans- formation from classical to more modern forms of democracy plays a dominant role in their interpretations. Canovan focuses specifi cally on the use of language referring to the people in Anglophone countries, emphasizing the separate nature of the histories of the concept of the people in various European lan- guages. She regards the American Revolution rather than the French as the turning point in the history of the concept of the people. Like Edmund Morgan, she argues that the American revolutionaries devel- oped “the characteristically modern understanding of the sovereign people”, building on the idea of the people as wielders of political power in reserve, activated only in times of emergency. Claiming that these ideas had initially been put forward by the Levellers dur- ing the English Civil Wars and the Whigs of the Glorious Revolution, Canovan calls them “popular sovereignty” and “the sovereignty of the people” without regard for the time of their appearance. Th e impetus for modernization came from America, but the British constitution had already been previously reinterpreted as a limited monarchy and mixed constitution of the Roman type. While there were suggestions that all political authority originated from the people and that the House of Commons represented the people, the strengthening offi cial view in mid-eighteenth-century Britain was that the collective entity of the King, Lords and Commons was the representative of the peo- ple and that Parliament alone practised sovereign power on behalf of the people. According to this view, every member of the people was introduction 17 present in Parliament, and whatever Parliament did was done by the people. Th e people in reserve, on the other hand, became an alterna- tive argument used by the opposition.29 Canovan sees the American Republic as a revolutionary model for the redefi nition of the political role of the people and has little to say about the British late-eighteenth-century debate on the political role of the people. She regards the French Revolution as no more than a warning instance of anarchy of the common people for the British and suggests that thinking in Britain only changed with the reforms of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries.30 However, parliamentary sources show that, while the American challenge infl uenced the British debates indirectly in the 1780s, French democracy became an important point of comparison in the 1790s. Dunn, who focuses on the concept of democracy, argues that only in the most radical phase of the French Revolution did a provocative redefi nition of the concept of democracy take place. At the beginning of 1794, Maximilien Robespierre challenged the traditional meanings assigned to democracy. He linked the originally Greek concept of democracy with the Roman concept of republic and argued in favour of the establishment of a ‘republic’ that was simultaneously a ‘democ- racy’. In Dunn’s view, Robespierre’s monumental speech act made it possible to reject the classical notion of democracy as an essentially direct form of government and to replace it with the concept of rep- resentative democracy. ‘Representation’ and ‘republic’ had been con- nected in the American Constitution (1789), but it had still rejected ‘democracy’. Robespierre’s innovation was to bring ‘democracy’, ‘republic’ and ‘representation’ together and set them as the goals of the Revolution—both in France and internationally. Th is latter move turned the new French type of ‘democracy’ into an expansionist con- cept that was seen as threatening the established order around Europe.31

29 Canovan 2005, 10–11, 20–22, 35, 69, 106. Some mention of eighteenth-century popular governments in Poland, Sweden or the Dutch Republic might have been useful here; Morgan 1988. Morgan’s essential contribution is the notion of popular sovereignty as a deliberate fi ction invented by political elites to legitimate their rule in the name of the people. See Canovan’s criticism of this interpretation in Canovan 2005, 130–133. 30 Canovan 2005, 33–34, 70. 31 Dunn 2005, 115–118; cf. Urbinati 2006, 66, according to whom the idea of repre- sentative democracy already emerged in France during the second half of 1792. 18 introduction

In Dunn’s view, it needed a radical revolution before the history of the modern concept of democracy could begin. Urbinati, like the other two theorists, makes use of eighteenth-cen- tury political thinking in her contribution to the theoretical debate on the nature of popular sovereignty, representation and democracy today. She actually turns eighteenth-century authors into participants in a universal debate and objects of criticism in her defence of rep- resentative democracy. Urbinati’s work demonstrates that there were several competing ways of conceptualizing sovereignty, representa- tion and democracy in the late eighteenth century. Th omas Paine and Condorcet fi rst combined these concepts and opened the way for an understanding of representation as democratic and not merely as a substitute for democracy proper. Both distanced themselves from the classical model of direct democracy and from the new model of representative government. Th eir claims about the incompatibility of democracy and representation followed from Montesquieu’s and Rousseau’s unwillingness to connect democracy, sovereignty and rep- resentation in an era when no positive notion of democracy had yet emerged.32 In this study, I suggest three possible ways of writing a more precise history of democracy and popular sovereignty in the late eighteenth century. Instead of the history of political philosophy or theory in a conventional sense, what is off ered here is a contextualized conceptual history of the reception of the notions of democracy and the sover- eignty of the people based on the analysis of past political language exactly as it was used in the primary sources. I am also suggesting that we proceed from studies carried out in national contexts to inter- national comparisons. Such comparisons based on parallel primary sources from several countries aim at creating a post-nationalist his- toriography in which both the specifi c features of individual political cultures and the shared characteristics of diff erent yet in some ways related political cultures are taken into consideration. Th e purpose of the inquiry is not to “rank” political cultures according to their inno- vativeness in conceptualizing politics, but to better understand the gradual transition towards a more modern concept of democracy. Transnational infl uences feature prominently in such a study, as the contemporary political elites were educated in classical political

32 Urbinati 2006, 4, 6–7, 11, 54. introduction 19 thought and rhetoric and oft en eagerly compared the forms of govern- ment of their respective countries, both when speaking in represen- tative assemblies and when writing their publications. References to other countries are considered in this study in order to locate possible conceptual transfers between political cultures. A transnational read- ing of the debate forces us to pay attention to phenomena of individ- ual political cultures that might otherwise be viewed as self-evident or simply overlooked. Th ey relate national debates and individual speech acts to a wider pattern of European conceptual change in the Age of the Enlightenment and the Age of Revolutions. Th ey also show how more modern notions of democracy and popular sovereignty emerged as a result of encounters between various national ways of viewing democracy. In particular, this concerns the infl uence of English politi- cal thought on Sweden and the mutual infl uence of French and British political thought and everyday political debates. I also see it as important that the study of the history of political thought should move from the exegeses of political theorists and sum- maries of somewhat unstructured debates in the published literature to an analysis of actual political debates connected with decision-mak- ing processes. Parliamentary debates, above all, provide us with source material enabling the study of how political key concepts were used by the decision-makers. Parliamentary debates have been used in the study of the political history of events, but they have been ignored by many scholars of eighteenth-century political cultures. Th is important aspect of past political debate needs to be brought more into to the limelight of the linguistic study of political cultures. In eighteenth- century studies, the tendency has been to emphasize the role of the growth of published literature in changing the world of politics. With- out questioning the signifi cance of the expansion of printed literature and the connected rise of the public sphere, this study defends the importance of the forums which already had established practices of deliberation, in which political decisions were really made, and which may hence have played an equally or even more signifi cant role in changing the conceptual world of each political culture than the some- times ephemeral debates in the published literature. Th e debates within representative institutions and in the published literature became, of course, increasingly interconnected in the late eighteenth century. Publishers were becoming more interested in the content of parliamentary debates, and the representative institutions also began more frequently to discuss the content of controversial 20 introduction publications of the day. Many parliamentarians themselves published actively, addressing a wider audience with their pamphlets. Parlia- mentary debates were thus integrated into public debates in several ways. Th eir signifi cance within the published literature was quite con- siderable in comparison with what it is today. Parliamentary debates thus need to be contextualized against the publicity of the day and the interaction between the two arenas of political discourse must be considered. Th e public debate could either repeat the same points or off er alternative, more radical, understandings of the political role of the people. Th is study concerns political discourse which took place both inside and outside representative institutions, concentrating on cases where the two were explicitly interconnected. Th e main empha- sis will, however, be on the parliamentary debates, using comparative references to parallel debates in the published literature to contextual- ize them. Th e third strategy followed here emphasizes nominalism in the anal- ysis of past political cultures. Th is means that we endeavour to avoid the excessive use of modern analytical terminology, which can lead to teleological interpretations about just how “democratic” (in some modern sense) eighteenth-century political actors considered them- selves to be. Th e reconstruction of this kind of past political vocabu- laries is far from easy given the temptation to look for the modern concepts of democracy and popular sovereignty in historical sources. In searching for an answer to the question of when it became legiti- mate to speak about democracy and popular sovereignty as recognized and approved principles in their modern senses, we should concen- trate on establishing when expressions that can unarguably be seen as having modern meanings actually begin to emerge in the historical sources. Earlier arguments that seem to contain related ideas need to be distinguished and their diff erent nature emphasized. Th is study will thus explore references to the political role of the people and democ- racy, attempting to estimate the timing of the evaluative shift s in the use of such references as they occurred in parliamentary speaking. Th e contextualized contemporary uses of language will thus be at the cen- tre of the analysis throughout. Th e methodological approach I follow combines conceptual analysis at the macro and micro levels. I use linguistically oriented research strategies of past political thinking by applying methodological tools provided by various continental conceptual historians and by the Cambridge School of the history of political ideas. Aft er carrying out introduction 21 the contextualization of quotations in which a particular political key term or metaphorical expression appears and deducing its basic mean- ing in those contexts, some historians proceed to the more abstract level of historical semantics at which comparisons not only within one political culture over an extended period of time but also between sev- eral political cultures become possible.33 Other historians concentrate on the analysis of individual speech acts and the intended meanings of the language users as revealed by the person speaking, the audience, the conventions of speaking and the context in which the speaker operates.34 An approach combining the study of these semantic and pragmatic aspects of past political languages with a comparative analysis provides the most balanced methodological solution. Such a study begins with a basic contextualization of each reference to the people, the nation, sovereignty, representation and democracy in particular arguments and debates in order to deduce whether the concept was used in a conventional or a potentially innovative sense. Next it proceeds to an analysis of the long-term developments in the meanings of these terms within an individual political culture on the macro level, and fi nally extends to a comparison between two political cultures. Th is approach aims at fi nding answers to the basic question of how the meanings of the concepts have emerged and changed through their history as a result of their repeated use in a wide variety of texts and contexts. It is inspired by Reinhart Koselleck’s Begriff sgeschichte, although it is not my intention to build on the same hypotheses of the changing character of concepts during the late eighteenth-century transition to modernity or to write a mere history of words. Th e analysis must return to the micro level particularly when macro-level comparisons reveal unusual speech acts in which the ana- lysed vocabulary has obviously been used to achieve particular politi- cal goals in contemporary contexts and in which new meanings have accordingly been assigned to them. Further contextualization must follow, applying the methods advocated by Quentin Skinner and his pupils. Th e basic question that this part of the study attempts to answer is how the meanings of the concepts changed as a result of their

33 See Leonhard 2001 and Leonhard 2008, for example. 34 For an analysis of parliamentary speech acts with an emphasis on the unrefl ect- ing use of language, see Steinmetz 1993, Steinmetz 2002 and Chapter One below. 22 introduction unconventional and innovative use by individual speakers doing things with words in particular contexts. As Iain Hampsher-Monk has rightly pointed out, “Redefi nitions of ‘the people’ [. . .] are classic examples of this kind of tactical speech act, in and through which political change is eff ected through verbal agency.”35 Th is part of the analysis brings the individual language-user back into the picture. Both entire communi- ties of language-users and their individual members played signifi cant roles in conceptual change.36 An individual speaker was oft en respond- ing to what some preceding speaker had just said. Th e mere analysis of the meanings assigned to political concepts in individual arguments would not, of course, reveal the developmen- tal trends of the vocabulary of democracy and the sovereignty of the people at the level of an entire political culture. We should, in the end, extend our study to include at least a degree of international com- parison and combine conceptual analyses of a single political culture over an extended period of time with comparisons between diff er- ent contemporaneous political cultures. Such comparisons can reveal both common European and specifi c national features in conceptual change. Th is comparative research strategy can stimulate new research questions, reveal interesting special cases, demonstrate interaction between various political cultures, produce hypotheses on the shared and individual cultural factors and make us question conventional his- torical interpretations of the studied phenomenon.37 Comparisons are particularly relevant in the case of late-eighteenth-century references to the political role of the people, as the vocabulary was common to a number of political cultures and representative institutions. Further- more, the key concepts were sometimes defi ned in debates where for- eign political cultures were explicitly commented upon. I am thus suggesting an alternative approach to writing the history of democracy and popular sovereignty based on the close analysis of a large number of political arguments in which related vocabulary was used. Such an analysis entails the elucidation of the group of words

35 Hampsher-Monk 2007, 149. 36 On the duality of linguistic approaches in French and German history writing on the one hand and in Anglophone historiography on the other, see Hampsher-Monk 2007, 136; Note also Conal Condren’s point that the system and agency are interde- pendent, i.e. while an agent can make points only just by making use of the linguistic system, the system is created through the action of agency. Th ese two aspects of politi- cal language are hence inseparable, not mutually exclusive. Condren 2007, 325, 336. 37 Haupt & Kocka 1996, 12–14; Leonhard 2001, 67. introduction 23 used in a past natural language to discuss the political role of the people, with a particular focus on linguistic associations between the people and power, i.e. on expressions such as “democracy” and “the sovereignty of the people”. It also entails the contextual investigation of the use of these words in a wide variety of political arguments, which could refl ect either the recycling of their already existing meanings or the introduction of new meanings intended to change the political reality and prevailing conceptions of it. Finally, it also involves com- parisons between such political vocabularies in two natural languages in order to fi nd the common and particular features of the political cultures. Th e concepts used to describe and discuss the power of the people are thus analysed in several contexts: in their immediate con- text as part of particular arguments and debates, in their context as part of the long-term discourse on the people as a political agent and democracy as a form of government both within a representative insti- tution and within a general political culture, and in an international context provided by the use of related concepts in another represen- tative assembly and public discourse at around the same time and in similar circumstances. All the selected parliamentary debates are ana- lysed from two perspectives. On the one hand, the debates are seen as records of how speakers recycled political concepts whose meanings were assumed to be familiar to, and shared by, all the members of the respective political establishments. On the other hand, speeches by individual politicians are taken as examples of the use of political concepts in innovative speech acts aimed at infl uencing the views of the audience and changing the political reality. Writing a comparative history of political vocabularies has entailed the study of parallel primary sources originating from two northwest European political cultures side by side. It has involved the explica- tion of the range of the meanings of particular key words on the basis of the primary sources, without excessive reference to social scientifi c theories or previous research. While many existing studies facilitate the contextualization of individual debates and arguments, placing too much faith in previous research from individual countries might pro- duce confusion with regard to the exact meanings of past concepts. I have considered it essential to read political texts in the broadest possible sense so as not to exclude some as “non-political” or “practi- cal” and therefore less relevant. From the point of view of conceptual change, even less signifi cant parliamentary debates and contemporary pamphlets written by anonymous writers can be revealing about how 24 introduction the key concepts were defi ned through their uses. Such a broad source basis renders the use of technical solutions a prerequisite for this type of analysis. In the search for the debates and publications to be ana- lysed, I have used electronic databases, bearing in mind the fact that search strategies must be constantly updated on the basis of instances already found. Th e full text databases that have been used in this study include various versions of records of the parliamentary debates found in Th e Making of the Modern World (MOMW) and Eighteenth Century Collections Online (ECCO), as well as the extensive collections of pub- lic debates contained in the latter. Th e body of the analysed primary sources is comprised of selected debates held in the two British Houses of Parliament between 1734 and 1800 and in the four estates and the Secret Committee of the Swedish Riksdag in the period 1769–1772. Th e analysed debates have been selected on the basis of their consti- tutional topics or on the basis of the occurrence of utterances com- bining words such as “the people” and “representation”, “the people” and “power” or “the people” and “sovereignty” or direct references to “popular government” or “democracy”. In each of the chosen debates, all references to “the people” and “the nation” with a political meaning have been taken into account. Th e annual Speeches from the Th rone and the Addresses of Th anks of the two Houses—as well as debates on the formulations of the Addresses—have been analysed as a continu- ous series of sources, and all references to the people or nation in them have been taken into consideration. Th e special character of these pri- mary sources is discussed more extensively in Chapter One. As already pointed out, the use of concepts in parliamentary debates must be contextualized by comparing them with parallel uses in related public debates. In the case of Britain, the comparison can be carried out using ECCO. Th e example public debates have been selected from contributions to the discourse on democracy and the political role of the people. As it is not possible to carry out an entirely comprehen- sive analysis of the uses of the vocabulary referring to the people and democracy in British public discussions, these have been used primar- ily to contextualize the parliamentary debates. Th e late 1760s and early 1770s constituted an exceptional period in Swedish history, too, in that an act allowing the freedom of the press was passed in 1766 and remained in force until 1772, enabling the rise of an unprecedented volume of debate in the public sphere. By 1769 at the latest, political journals were taking up the same issues as the concurrent debates of the Estates. Th e press debates tended at times introduction 25 to be highly polemical and radical. I have read the books and periodi- cals mentioned by the members of the Estates during the debates as well as a wide selection of political pamphlets containing the keyword folket (the people) in their titles. In 1772, Swedish published literature once again came under strict regulation, and the Diet lost much of its political signifi cance aft er a royal coup, which is why I have limited my examination of the Swedish case to the period 1769 to 1772. Th e body of the book is divided into four chapters. Th e focus is on the Westminster Parliament in the years 1734−1800—from the debates on the need to change the Septennial Act in the aft ermath of the Excise Crisis of 1733−1734 to the point at which the French Revolutionary Wars were turning into the Napoleonic Wars. Th e period begins with the fi rst ever recorded references to democracy in British parliamentary debates, originating from the fi rst minister (Walpole), and ends with the fi rst explicit claims that the existing British parliamentary system was based on “the sovereignty of the people”, a concept propagated by the French revolutionaries only ten years earlier. For much of the early period before the early 1770s, studied in Chapter Two, a classical sceptical notion of democracy predominated on those rare occasions when the concept was discussed in Westminster. Democracy could only be recognized as a controlled element in the mixed constitution, and even then only with reservations. Nevertheless, language referring to the rights of the people, the representation of the people, the sen- timents and voice of the people and even popular government were used by both the opposition and the government. Aft er the challenges to Robert Walpole with this language, a period of calm of some twenty years followed. Towards the end of the 1760s, however, the concept of the people began to acquire an entirely new potential in parliamentary debates, thanks to Wilkite radicalism. Not only the extra-parliamen- tary opposition but also the parliamentary majority increasingly rep- resented themselves as the spokesmen of the people. Th e case of the Swedish Diet in the period 1769−1772 has oft en been passed over in international accounts of eighteenth-century political thought and culture, despite the fact that Sweden (and hence also pres- ent-day Finland) had for its time an exceptional political system based on the rule of the Estates. At the same time, there has been a tendency among historians to emphasize the unique role played by the Swed- ish Estates as forerunners of what has sometimes been characterized as “popular sovereignty” and even “representative democracy”. Th e international comparisons in this fi eld are limited, dated and mostly 26 introduction not based on the analysis of parallel sources from Sweden and a com- parable country like Britain by the same historian. Th e analysis off ered in Chapter Th ree diff ers from the mainstream of Scandinavian history writing and produces fi ndings that give us rea- son to reconsider interpretations regarding the degree of radicalism in the late Age of Liberty in Sweden. It shows that the concept of democ- racy was rarely used at the Riksdag and was employed by individual noblemen mainly to oppose undesired phenomena or sometimes to make radical points. Th e use of the political concept of the people was growing in frequency, but the concept by no means dominated the debates. Its radicalized meanings were to a great extent determined by the particular purposes of the competing parties and estates. An explicit expression equivalent to “popular sovereignty” remained inconceiv- able in the Swedish language of politics. Some radical descriptions of the power of the people did occur in the press, but the concept of the people seems to have been predominantly used in the Diet to legiti- mize the existing system, based on estate privileges as it was. Most of the meanings given by diff erent groups to “the people” in various debates are explained by contextual factors; no “democratic” reform was being propounded. Chapters Four and Five return to the British debate aft er 1771. Brit- ish parliamentarians’ conceptions of the political role of the people were challenged in this period by the American War of Independence, by domestic calls for parliamentary reform in which representation would be more equally distributed between constituencies and fi nally by the French Revolution. Th e infl uence of the American war is trace- able in the calls for parliamentary reform in the 1780s, although the infl uences remained implicit. Defi nitions of the proper form of the representation of the people and increasingly positive revaluations of democracy within the mixed constitution were characteristic of the debates of the early 1780s, when William Pitt the Younger, Charles James Fox and Edmund Burke constituted a trio who repeatedly rede- fi ned the classical concept of democracy in a manner that has escaped the attention of previous research. Th eir redefi nitions of democracy and the counterarguments these provoked are analysed in Chapter Four. We shall never know what the result of this revaluation of democ- racy within the mixed constitution would have been without the French Revolution. Th e Revolution ensured that the vocabulary of democracy and the sovereignty of the people became increasingly introduction 27 common in the debates of the British Parliament and that the two available understandings of “democracy” led to a fi erce but in the long run fruitful conceptual confrontation. Clashes between the emerging new understanding of ‘democracy’ within the mixed constitution and the French revolutionary notions of ‘democracy’ and ‘the sovereignty of the people’ as the basis of all government are analysed in Chapter Five. Th e Revolution thus forced the British members of parliament to engage in further conceptual redefi nitions. Th e British parliamentarians were no mere opponents of French democracy but discussed the two alternative concepts of democracy intensively. Th e reception of these French revolutionary concepts in Westminster was varied and changed over time. Whereas many initially welcomed the idea of the people taking power, the political establishment took a much more reserved stand and gradually became major critics of the Revolution. Even those politicians who considered the strengthening of the popular element in the French monarchy to be a good thing tended to denounce the French type of democracy. At the same time, we fi nd numerous vindications of the British political system as representing a proper version of democracy; the parliamen- tarians participated in the conceptual struggle not only by denouncing the French version of “democratic tyranny” as a dangerous innova- tion but also by defi ning the contested concept in ways that suited the defence of the established order. By the late 1790s, on the other hand, some speakers were prepared to go as far as to claim that the Brit- ish Parliament, too, was based on the sovereignty of the people. Th is conceptual change would not immediately become widely accepted, adopted or implemented, but it did lead to a transition towards a more modern understanding of the popular legitimacy of the political sys- tem. Th ere was no need for a revolution if the British system could be regarded as already suffi ciently democratic and based on the sover- eignty of the people. Th e main hypotheses of this book can be summarized as follows. Firstly, the originally classical meanings of the concept of democracy continued to be upheld to a considerable extent throughout the eigh- teenth century. Th e ideas of representation were still primarily based on the medieval traditions of estate representation, and before the French Revolution notions of a representative democracy existed only in a very limited sense. Secondly, political systems based on estate representation must not be interpreted from an excessively teleologi- cal perspective. Th ey did not constitute any evident evolution towards 28 introduction democracy. Th irdly, even an emerging parliamentary system was capa- ble of conceptual revision. Quite signifi cant redefi nitions of democ- racy can be found in the period preceding the French Revolution, not only among radicals and abstract theorists but also among the leading political actors who participated in parliamentary debates. Fourthly, the French Revolution forced the political establishments of countries with older forms of representation to re-evaluate their conceptions of democracy and fi nally to adopt at least some of the ideas involved in the principle of the sovereignty of the people. Th e political elites were forced to either totally oppose these notions or to redefi ne the existing systems in a way that would permit them to meet the challenges of a rapidly changing and modernizing world. CHAPTER ONE

BRITISH AND SWEDISH PARLIAMENTARY DEBATES IN A COMPARATIVE STUDY OF POLITICAL VOCABULARIES

Historians have traditionally used the records of eighteenth-century parliamentary and estate debates to write the political history of the respective states and representative institutions. Particular speeches have occasionally been summarized in analyses of political thought and action.1 However, there have been few analyses of eighteenth- century parliamentary debates as such. As Christopher Reid has pointed out: Parliamentary discourse—by any reckoning one of the central elements of British political culture—has never been systematically surveyed. Most studies of British political history make extensive reference to par- liamentary debates, without paying much attention to their formal and rhetorical qualities.2 Peter Jupp has pointed out likewise with reference to interaction between print culture and Parliament: Th e impact on the substance of parliamentary debate of the fl owering of political and moral philosophy, the increased public knowledge of par- liamentary speeches, and the exponential growth of information about all aspects of actual or potential policy has never been the subject of the research that it deserves.3 Relations between the printed literature and Parliament are, however, a fi eld that has recently gained increasing attention among historians of political culture.4

1 Christie 1962; Pole 1966; Dickinson 1977; Goodwin 1979; Morgan 1988; An ear- lier version of this chapter has been published in Ihalainen 2008. 2 Reid 1985, 96–98. Th e strategy chosen by Reid for studying Edmund Burke’s selected parliamentary speeches is that of dramatic criticism, paying attention not only to the text but also to the conditions and conventions governing its production, in the same way as the stage, the prevailing styles, the expectations of the audience and so on govern a dramaturgical text. See also Reid 2000. 3 Jupp 2006, 207. 4 Peacey 2007, 2. 30 chapter one

It is evident that parliamentary records constitute much more than mere documents recording the actual actions of certain leading politi- cians. Th ey provide an extensive record of the practical language of politics in the past, and a contextual analysis of the language of par- liamentary debates enables an understanding of long-term continuities and changes in the meanings of key political concepts at the macro level of each political culture. Th is concerns particularly concepts that were frequently used in representative institutions and which actually constituted part of the justifi cation for the existence of these institu- tions in the fi rst place. For this kind of analysis, the parliamentary and estate records provide hundreds of instances of how leading politi- cal speakers and decision-makers used concepts in the most respected political forum of each country. At the same time, they reveal a num- ber of individual speech acts in both their long-term and their tem- porary contexts. Furthermore, parliamentary debates provide us with sources that are directly comparable and which can be used to write comparative long-term histories of key political vocabularies in emerging parlia- mentary regimes. Such simultaneous case studies make it easier to reveal both common European trends in the development of politi- cal cultures during the modernization process and the context-related features peculiar to each political culture. Even though there were considerable diff erences in the procedure, content and recording of parliamentary debates, similar questions were discussed and the con- cepts used in them were interrelated. It is possible to carry out analyses of nearly simultaneous debates or debates involving parallel concep- tual changes in diff erent national contexts. Such analyses increase our understanding of both universal European and specifi c national con- ceptual developments. More particularly, they add to our knowledge of the language of politics ‘below’ abstract political theory, in the prac- tical everyday use. Records of parliamentary debates provide us with sources which permit a considerable degree of contextualization of individual uses of key political terms—or of the performance of speech acts—within specifi c debates and particular arguments. Th e political context of the speaking situation, the background of the speakers and the potential reactions to the speeches expressed in the published literature are reasonably easy to reconstruct on the basis of existing research. Th e presence of the reactions, counterarguments and conceptual moves of the other speakers in the chamber make it possible to reconstruct the british and swedish parliamentary debates 31 range of meanings that could be assigned to a particular concept by the leading statesmen and major political groups of the time. It is also pos- sible to analyse the intentions of individual speakers, particularly when the speaker was using a concept in an unconventional, surprising or innovative way with the obvious intention of achieving certain specifi c goals in the context concerned. Such speech acts oft en become visible only within the macro-level context of a long series of debates.

Th e Signifi cance of Parliamentary Debates for the History of Political Vocabularies

In an article written together with Kari Palonen, I have suggested that historians of political cultures should consider making parliamentary sources a major object of study in tracing the history of key politi- cal concepts in Europe. We propose an examination of both the new political vocabulary created by parliamentary procedures and speak- ing and the older political vocabulary used with traditional and new meanings in connection with parliamentary debates.5 Th e latter vocab- ulary includes the concepts of popular sovereignty, democracy and representation. Th e suggested notion of parliaments as central forums for the formation of the language of politics complements the widely held assumption that it was the pre-political public sphere rather than par- liamentary speaking that was vital for the formation of the language of politics and political culture more generally. Historians of political cul- tures have carried out important studies of political debates in printed literature in the late eighteenth century. Th ey have oft en emphasized the role of the press as a provider of an alternative forum for politi- cal education and politicization that would later be used by radical movements to present their claims. Th ese studies, though invaluable in many ways, have tended to ignore a closer analysis of parliamen- tary records as indicators of an equally, or possibly more, important dimension of past political debate.6 Any simplistic categorization of sources into those belonging to ‘political history’ and those proper for ‘the history of political thought’ should be dismissed in the compara- tive study of political vocabularies. Both practising politicians using

5 Ihalainen & Palonen 2009. 6 See Brewer 1976; Wilson 1995; Skuncke 2002, 1–22; Barker 2002, 93–112. 32 chapter one the language of politics in everyday debates and political thinkers of various levels of abstraction publishing their views in printed literature contributed to the formation of the language of politics. An excessive stress on the role of the public sphere in political dis- course may lead to over-generalizations about how the political values of past political cultures changed. Jeremy Black has pointed out that in eighteenth-century Britain, the agenda of the public debate was set by Parliament more than by the press or popular politics at the hustings. Parliamentary debates were always intimately linked to deci- sion-making processes, giving rise to discussion even if they did not necessarily change the policies that were adopted. On the other hand, the infl uence of debates in the press on political decisions remains uncertain and indirect. In principle, parliamentary debates were sup- posed to communicate the views of the people to the government. In practice, of course, this was not always the case, even if both the ministry and the opposition eagerly used terms referring to the people to legitimate their points of view. Yet the debates allowed diverging opinions between the government and opposition and also within the government to be expressed, which was equally important in that they reveal the diff erent values held by the various groups in the governing establishment. As Black puts it: Parliament was important not so much as a forum where the govern- ment could be defeated, a relatively rare occurrence, but as one that encouraged a change in the nature of political debate, by creating a regu- lar agency for publicly representing political views. [. . .] the importance of Parliament to discussion and contention within government has been underrated, or, more commonly, neglected. And yet, its role in this fi eld was of major signifi cance. [. . .] Th is helped to make Britain a functioning parliamentary monarchy, one in which, despite problems, Parliament and Crown sought to operate in harmony. As Parliament was the public forum in which the ministry formally presented and defended its policy and was criticised in a fashion that obliged it to reply, it was Parliament where the public debate over policy can be seen as most intense and eff ective. Th ere was an obligation to respond that was lacking in the world of print, and an immediate linkage between the debates and the taking of decisions, the debates themselves being occasioned by the discussion of these very decisions.7

7 Black 2001, 212–221; Black 2004, 1, 6–7. british and swedish parliamentary debates 33

Following Black, I argue that the practice of continual parliamentary debate as such supported a change in political culture and the language of politics by providing a forum for the expression of political opin- ions through the use and defi nition of concepts in both conventional and innovative ways. Arguments for and against a particular motion, which Jeremy Bentham regarded in his analysis of late eighteenth- century parliamentary procedure as consistent with the “natural instinct” of men,8 revealed diff ering understandings of the political reality not only between the government and the opposition but also within these groups. As all participating sides were forced to present their points of view clearly when replying to each other,9 the central political concepts of the day inevitably entered the debates, and disagreements over their meanings came to the fore. Th ese conceptual diff erences were by no means ‘mere rhetoric’ but refl ected diff ering ideological points of view and could really aff ect the decision-making processes. Black has seen the eighteenth-century British Parliament as a suc- cessful institution which became a real forum of fi rst-rank political debate. According to him, the status of Parliament in the British politi- cal system was—despite restrictions on parliamentary infl uence in a system that was essentially oligarchic—unique and not really com- parable with other eighteenth-century national representative bodies. Th e Swedish Estates, the Dutch General Estates and the Polish Diet were all characterized by confl icts, delays and a loss of status in the course of the century. No other representative body was as universally admired as the British Parliament.10 Th is emphasis on the uniqueness of the British Parliament as a forum of intense political debate has some justifi cation, but it goes too far. We should not overemphasize the incomparability of Brit- ain with the rest of Europe in this respect. Th e other representative bodies in mixed constitutions also played key roles in the political debates of their respective countries, and they have—at least in the case of Sweden from the 1720s to the early 1770s, France in the 1790s and the Batavian Republic in the late 1790s—produced records of

8 Jeremy Bentham, An Essay on Political Tactics, or Inquiries Concerning the Disci- pline and Mode of Proceeding Proper to be Observed in Political Assemblies; . . ., James, Michael et al. (eds). Oxford 1999 (partly printed in 1791, this edition in 1838−43), 127−128. 9 Bentham, An Essay on Political Tactics, 1838−43, 128. 10 Black 2001, 217–218; Swann draws the same overall conclusion but suggests that the Hungarian Diet was somehow equivalent. Swann 2000, 35–36. 34 chapter one parliamentary debates that are eminently suitable for a comparative study of the history of concepts like ‘the people’, ‘popular sovereignty’ and ‘democracy’.11 In Sweden during the Age of Liberty from 1719 to 1772,12 the four- estate Diet was the leading forum for political debate when it was in session—it convened once every three years and then oft en sat for over a year. Particularly as no unregulated public debate was allowed before 1766, the Diet was the arena in which information was obtained and distributed and where the representatives formulated and articulated opinions in order to infl uence the members of their own and the other estates. It was also a forum where not only legislative but to some extent executive decisions were made. Th e sessions of the Diet pro- duced a mass of records, including detailed discussion minutes. Th ese, undeniably the best records of any eighteenth-century representative body, are—particularly in the case of the Noble and Burgher Estates— highly comparable with British reports of parliamentary debates.13 Furthermore, the debate over the political power of the people and democracy was, because of the classical tradition on which much early modern political theory was based, transnational to the highest degree. Even the etiquette of debating questions like these was closely related as a result of the common education of the political elites in classical rhetoric. Th ere was lively political, economic and intellectual interac- tion between the two countries, and comparisons between them were constantly drawn by contemporaries themselves. Hence, a transna- tional comparative perspective off ers the most opportune approach for analysing the debates. Records of parliamentary and estate debates in countries such as England and Sweden enable us to locate, date, contextualize and com- pare both gradual and sudden, unconscious as well as intentional changes and revisions in the vocabulary of political concepts—perhaps

11 Some records on debates in the Polish Sejm are also extant, but it has not been possible to integrate them into this study. 12 Th e only comparative accounts of the national representative institutions in eighteenth-century Sweden and Britain are Roberts 1973 and Roberts 1986. Th ese are mainly based on older Swedish studies, contain few references to British primary sources and use a limited selection of printed primary sources for Sweden. Roberts argued that the Swedish constitution was in many respects more advanced than that of England, even though it too was beset by some major problems. 1973, 3, 26; 1986, 91. 13 Cf. Steinmetz 1993, 45, who also sees the British debates as unique. british and swedish parliamentary debates 35 better than most of the sources found in published literature would allow us to do.14 Th e records show us what types of actual speaking situations the concepts were used in and what sort of concrete politi- cal points they were used to make. Unlike much published literature, we can oft en fi nd the immediate responses of the other speakers (as practical ‘political thinkers’) belonging to the parliamentary elite. Th is makes it possible to draw conclusions about what kinds of conceptual choices and speech acts were generally acceptable to the participants and what aroused criticism. Th is kind of interactive debate demon- strates the range of meanings that could be assigned to a particular concept among the diff erent groups of the political establishment in the context of a particular debate. In the British Parliament, in particular, regular debate with views expressed from a variety of competing perspectives had been an integral part of the decision-making process for centuries. In its houses, diff er- ences of opinion between the government and the opposition could be very clear, and these are also refl ected in the conceptual choices of the speakers. In the records of these debates, we can locate changes in the meanings of concepts caused by speech acts that either intentionally reinforce the original signifi cances or introduce new ones. Much more frequently, however, we can fi nd choices of words that merely unre- fl ectingly repeated current ways of speaking among the political elite as a whole or some part of it. In most cases, the speakers just wanted to express some meaning of a concept that would be easily shared by their audience. Parliamentary debates were, of course, only one dimension of politi- cal debate. Together with them we need to study other forms of pub- lic discourse—particularly those directly linked to current debates in Parliament. Such contextualization with other primary sources ensures the consideration of a wider range of the meanings assigned to the key concepts in the period studied. Th e relative importance of the two types of sources is quite apparent in this study. Th e public debate intensifi ed considerably in the course of the eighteenth cen- tury, but as Black has reminded us, public opinion certainly did not determine the policies that eighteenth-century governments followed. It rather provided a forum for the expression of a greater plurality of opinion—and hence further uses of political concepts—and it also

14 Ihalainen & Palonen 2009. 36 chapter one increased nationwide political awareness of these opinions. Th ere was an obvious link between the two debates, particularly as parliamen- tary reporting became, certainly aft er the 1770s, a regular feature of the British press.15 Reporting linked Parliament and the public sphere and led in Britain to what Charles Tilly has seen as the increasing parliamentarization of popular politics.16 According to Peter Jupp, too, Parliament became a major producer of political information, particu- larly in the form of printed debates, and thereby infl uenced the forma- tion of the strengthening public opinion.17 As the following chapter will show, British parliamentarians adapted to the circumstances of increasing publicity, made effi cient use of printed literature to distrib- ute their views to wider audiences and set the agenda of public debate to an extent that is quite unimaginable today.18 A similar tendency, though on a more modest scale, was evident in Sweden in the period 1769−1772. On the other hand, using parliamentary records in the reconstruc- tion of the conceptual world of past political cultures does have its methodological challenges, which will be addressed here with refer- ence to eighteenth-century British and Swedish sources. We shall look at the practical organizational framework of the debates, which has to be taken into account in their analysis, some special features of parlia- mentary rhetoric in the late eighteenth century and the implications of the methods used to make parliamentary records in diff erent countries for this type of research.

Practical Arrangements and Argumentation

Th e ways in which the debates were conducted within diff erent par- liamentary and estate traditions aff ected the structure of arguments and hence the use of concepts. Th e choice of discussion topic and the order of the debate eff ectively structured what could be argued by

15 Black 2001, 225–226. 16 See Tilly 1997, 246–248. According to Tilly, Parliament became the object of ordinary people’s attention, and the same issues could be debated by Parliament and the people. 17 Jupp 2006, 226, 229, 264. 18 Cf. Steinmetz 1993, 65, and Reid 2000, 122–134, according to whom it was rather the rise of the public sphere that aff ected parliamentary discourse so that negotiations were replaced by a new form of public speaking. british and swedish parliamentary debates 37 the speakers in the fi rst place. In the British Parliament, the subjects could either be determined by an Order of the Day or sometimes be initiated freely by an individual member. Th e order of speaking was in principle free and decided by the Speaker during the debate.19 Th e Speaker controlled the subjects which the speakers discussed, and the prevalent manner of arguing for and against the motion usually forced them to stick to the topic of the day.20 Even so, speeches sometimes contained various arguments that diverged from the original subject of the debate, particularly in connection with regular debates of a general character. Th ese occurrences were unpredictable, and consequently it would be almost impossible to fi nd the most interesting instances of usage in the entire corpus of reports without the help of the search engines provided by modern databases. Even though the titles do not yield all those debates in which the political role of the people was discussed, we can note that debates concerning parliamentary repre- sentation and the French Revolution, for instance, were among those in which the relevant vocabulary was most likely to occur. Th us a com- bination of various constantly updated search strategies has been used to locate these debates. In Sweden, debates were initiated in a number of ways. In principle, any authority or individual could raise a question at the Diet. Th e most important practical limitation on the topics to be discussed was time,21 which became a scarce resource with the complicated estate system and the procedure of the Diet, where a discussion of the same ques- tion in a number of special committees and the four estates could last for a considerable time, particularly when communication between the estates was carried out by inter-estate delegations. Much of the debate concerned procedure rather than the subject being discussed as such. Th e positive side of this complicated process is that we have a plethora of debates off ering potentially interesting material. In Sweden, the speaker of an estate determined the subjects for debate in each plenary session, the goal being that the four estates would all discuss the issues simultaneously. In practice, decision-mak- ing was far from synchronized, as the infl uential Noble Estate did not

19 Th omas 1971, 187–188. 20 John Hatsell, Precedents of Proceedings in the House of Commons; under Sepa- rate Titles. With Observations, Vol. 2, London 1818 (reprinted Shannon 1971), 107; Steinmetz 1993, 44. 21 Lagerroth 1934, 6/2, 71, 74–78, is based on Lagerroth 1915. 38 chapter one want its timetable to be dictated by the other estates and the fact that its sessions were attended by perhaps a thousand members, dozens of whom were highly conversant with the subject, meant that a consider- able amount of time was needed before a decision could be reached.22 Th e other estates also took their time, particularly as motions could be amended only by the original proposers, and much time was spent reading out reports and minutes and receiving delegations from the other estates. Each member also had the right to speak as many times as he wanted to.23 In the Burgher Estate, this meant that a member might make as many as fourteen speeches during a single debate. In Sweden, the division between the Senate and the opposition was not quite clear-cut, even though party divisions did guide the allegiance of individual speakers, and this meant that a wide variety of view- points were expressed in the debates. In Britain, the procedure was less complicated, and the contrasts between the government and the opposition more distinct and stable, which led to more exhaustive and sometimes openly ideological debates. As a consequence, the alterna- tive ways of conceptualizing questions can be recognized more easily in British debates. Members of the representative bodies were free to speak at least once in each debate,24 but there were always those who hardly ever participated in the debates, lacking the special interest, knowledge, electoral pressure, courage or linguistic abilities to do so, or who were ignored by the recorders because of their lack of fl uency.25 Th e num- ber of particularly active speakers was low both in the Westminster Parliament and at the Swedish Diet. It is also evident that the reports and journals do not include every contribution. Speeches that were not considered signifi cant were cut out, especially by British journalists

22 Lagerroth 1934, 6/2, 79–86. 23 Lagerroth 1934, 6/2, 114; Roberts 1973, 30; Roberts 1986, 69, 91, 96. 24 Generally speaking, only one speech per debate was allowed in Britain. See Hat- sell, Precedents, Vol. 2, 1818, 105. 25 True silent members can be found among the Finnish-speaking peasants at the Swedish Diet; oft en not understanding Swedish, they were set apart by the language barrier. Th ey usually intervened only to ask for a postponement in decision-making so that the interpreter would have time to translate and explain to them what the debate was all about. Th is extra time was usually granted to them, which shows that the rep- resentatives of the Finnish peasantry were regarded as an organic part of the system: they were made part of the debate by their mere presence and their understanding of the main points. It was unthinkable for a decision to be made at the Swedish Diet without their at least formal consent. british and swedish parliamentary debates 39 who only attended a part of a debate. Th ey may also have favoured the best speakers, even though it is obvious that most debates were anyway dominated by a few leading members.26 Th e British assembly was undoubtedly dominated by the best speak- ers and those whose position in the ministry gave them special author- ity. Th e true orators also knew when to enter a debate, aware that the order of speaking could aff ect the outcome. Th e principal goal of speaking was, aft er all, to make the opponents change their minds, and hence the last speech before a division was considered potentially the most telling.27 Th e Speaker could always manipulate the order of speakers, although the ideal practice was to let the advocates and opponents of the motion take the fl oor alternatively. Th is practice led to a constant exchange of opinions and, consequently, to interestingly diff erent uses of the key terms of the debate. Th e British opposition, despite its minority in the House, oft en had more active and eloquent speakers than the government,28 even though the oratorical ability of leading British ministers was also considerable, including the ability to make eff ective use of language referring to the people. Th e ministry always considered it essential to attend and participate in debates in Britain.29 As a consequence, the diff ering policies advocated by the head of government and the oppo- sition received clear expression, particularly as the common academic rhetorical model encouraged both sides to carefully respond to all the arguments presented.30 In Sweden, only the presence of some senators in the Noble Estate created similar circumstances for debate at the highest level. Th e question of the spontaneity of the speeches and the infl uence of this on the use of concepts deserves particular attention. Longer speeches were obviously prepared beforehand, whereas shorter ones were spontaneous interventions in the debate. Interruptions occurred and were sometimes recorded in reports, but they have only a mar- ginal role in this analysis. In Britain it was not acceptable to simply read a speech from a script, but preparation was certainly needed to

26 Th omas 1971, 192, 202, 230–231. 27 Th omas 1971, 198–199; Jupp 2006, 208. 28 Th omas 1971, 240–241. 29 Th omas 1971, 201, 234. 30 Mack 2002, 250. 40 chapter one formulate articulate arguments.31 Th is practice of not writing down entire speeches is an explanation of the limited number of scripts of what exactly was said in Parliament. Th e number of scripts produced by the Swedish Estates was overwhelming by comparison. Th ere were no restrictions on reading from paper at the Swedish Diet; indeed, the speaker could pass his script to the secretary to have it copied in the minutes and sometimes even to be read aloud by the latter in place of the author. Written memoranda might also be seen as a type of speech that was read aloud by the offi cials, but they did not constitute actual debate and have been excluded from this analysis.32 Nor are entries of dissent in the minutes included owing to their monologic character. Scholars have suggested that the use of pre-planned rhetoric may have decreased and spontaneity risen towards the end of the century. Th e suggestion is that the speakers regarded their speeches as ephem- era, for use in Parliament on one particular occasion. Th ey would not have seen themselves as speaking to the people. It has been argued that Charles James Fox, for instance, was not keen on addressing the pub- lic through the press, while Edmund Burke made use of this medium especially in the early 1790s to educate and infl uence his audience.33 It is not quite clear, however, that Fox defi nitely avoided pre-planned speaking to the people. In fact, we fi nd long speeches by both mem- bers of parliament that were issued separately in printed form aft er a considerable amount of preparation.34 Th e texts diff er little from the records written down during debates, which suggests that the use of political language in all of them was well-planned. It has been further suggested that the tendency to deliver speeches ex tempore in Brit- ain explains the sometimes unclear content of the surviving records.35 However, it is diffi cult to fi nd any such inconsistencies in those argu- ments that dealt with the political role of the people. Many speakers were highly educated masters of logic, and anyway the editors could leave out the most glaring blemishes caused by spontaneity. It goes without saying that speeches for solemn occasions were particularly

31 Th omas 1971, 203; Steinmetz 2002, 89; Black 2004, 177. 32 Cf. Bentham’s point on the necessity to exclude academic written discourse from a political assembly. Betham, An Essay on Political Tactics, 1838−43, 132−133. 33 Th omas 1971, 203; Reid 1985, 118–119; Barker 2002, 96; Harris 2007, 112. 34 Burke had been the fi rst member of parliament to publish one of his speeches in 1775. Bullard 2005, 325. 35 Th omas 1971, 205; Steinmetz 2002, 89. british and swedish parliamentary debates 41 carefully prepared, taking into consideration all the conventions to be observed—or, if the occasion warranted it, fl outed. At the same time, the British records demonstrate that spontane- ity, wit and humour were highly valued in that political culture. Th is may have decreased the number of pre-planned speech acts aiming at conceptual redefi nitions, but it by no means ruled them out. Sponta- neity could also produce slips of the tongue and unintended concep- tual modifi cations. As Willibald Steinmetz has argued, much was said in Parliament without the choice of words being carefully considered either by the speaker himself or by his audience. On the basis of his analysis of British debates between the 1780s and the late nineteenth century, he suggests that semantic innovations that challenged con- ventional concepts seldom occurred in deliberate contributions to the debate. Indeed, they may be evident only to an historian in the context of mainly conventional arguments. Sometimes they were recognized by another member of parliament, who adopted the innovation in his own speeches. Even this could happen without the speaker noticing that a change in the language of politics had taken place.36 Another important source of transformation was in the elaboration or answer- ing of previously presented points. Conceptual change could thus emerge in a variety of ways, and it was by no means always intended.

Special Features of Parliamentary Rhetoric

Surprisingly little historical research on eighteenth-century parliamen- tary speaking exists, either for Britain or Sweden. Th e lack of entirely trustworthy records of parliamentary debates is undoubtedly one rea- son for this. Source problems are less evident in relation to twentieth- century and present-day parliamentary speaking, and this has been a subject of comprehensive study in fi elds such as linguistics and politi- cal theory. Admittedly, some important historical work on past parliamentary debates is available. We have excellent analyses of English parliamen- tary rhetoric in the late Tudor and early Stuart periods, when debates were recorded even more sporadically than in the eighteenth century, by David Colclough and Peter Mack.37 We also have an analysis of

36 Steinmetz 2002, 88–89. 37 Colclough 2002; Mack 2002. 42 chapter one

British political argumentation between the late eighteenth and late nineteenth centuries by Willibald Steinmetz, who has focused on the rules of parliamentary language and the linguistic moves and shift s that made it possible for the Commons to accept parliamentary reforms in the nineteenth century. Steinmetz has pointed out that parliamentary debates not only refl ected conceptual change within the political com- munity but also caused it. According to him, the debates also became increasingly interactive with public discourse in the period studied.38 Th e late eighteenth century, which has oft en been presented as the golden age of British parliamentary speaking, has rarely been sub- jected to more extensive analysis. Th ere are, however, some studies of individual speakers and their relation to the public sphere.39 Palonen, a political theorist whose interests focus more on the rhetorical aspects of parliaments in general than on any particular historical period, has argued that politics in parliamentary regimes has always been essen- tially rhetorical. Together with the present author, he has pointed out that parliamentary debates provided possibilities for the recycling of conventional concepts and also for conceptual revisions and modifi - cations. Th is was particularly true aft er politics became increasingly competitive as a result of the parliamentarization and democratiza- tion of politics from the late eighteenth century on.40 An empirical study of late eighteenth-century parliamentary speaking will provide an important backdrop to the history of democratization, which is currently being actively studied by political scientists in a number of countries.41 Cornelia Ilie has studied parliamentary debates as a sub-genre of political discourse, seeing them as “an institutionalised deliberation ritual”42 occurring in “basically confrontational settings”.43 She views the debates as communicative interaction taking place in a dialogical form and analysable by a pragma-rhetorical approach that focuses on linguistic strategies in specifi c contexts at the micro-level and on peo- ple’s intentional use of language in such contexts.44 Ilie has created a comparative dimension by combining a semantico-pragmatic analysis

38 Steinmetz 1993; Steinmetz 2002, 86–87. 39 See, for example, Bullard 2001; Reid 1985, 122–134. 40 Ihalainen & Palonen 2009. 41 Palonen, Pulkkinen & Rosales 2009. 42 Ilie 2001, 242. 43 Ilie 2004, 5. 44 Ilie 2007. british and swedish parliamentary debates 43 with institutional discourse analysis. Th e former means “the mapping of the semantic fi elds” of the terms and analysing their “semantic associations, collocational distributions and semantic roles.” She sees the pragmatic functions and implications of the uses of a concept as objects of further study. Ilie argues, not unlike historians of ideas, that “the connotations associated with key words are oft en interpretable in terms of the political allegiance of the members of parliament, ideo- logical convictions and personal commitments.”45 In other words, the political and personal context of speaking opens up the senses of a concept used in a particular context. Th is kind of linguistic research on modern parliamentary speaking is also inspiring from the point of view of the historical study of the political vocabularies used in parliaments. Th anks to the available research, we already know about some of the enduring conventions of parliamentary rhetoric in the British Parlia- ment. In the eighteenth century, Parliament was, and had been for sev- eral centuries, the most important forum for a political elite that held debate and disputation in high regard. Ever since the reign of Eliza- beth, the skilful use of words in Parliament had been considered an indispensable professional attribute of any successful statesman. Th e purpose of speaking in Parliament was to secure and win votes in a possible division, to convince one’s own side and perhaps to persuade individual members of the other side. Th is basic function meant that the debate could easily turn into a heated dispute and into what Ilie has characterized as “interpersonal verbal duelling”. Th e debates were also fi erce as a result of the widespread recognition within the political community that the speakers, protected by their parliamentary immu- nity, had a right, indeed a duty, to give an expression to ideas that were not favoured by the government. Th ey were entitled to speak freely pro et contra on any matter under discussion, and this allowed them to use the entire conceptual arsenal that was available to them. One of the essential points of parliamentary debates was that, even if the government would almost always win the division in the end, every member of parliament had a free opportunity to express his oppos- ing views. Quite a number of members used this opportunity skilfully, and it was even possible for the opposition to win the argument even if they lost the division. If they argued well enough, they might also

45 Ilie 2004a, 3–4. 44 chapter one persuade opponents to change their opinions, introduce changes into the legislation, and initiate new measures. On the other hand, it is evident that the tendency of members of parliament to seek confrontation between the parties oft en created two distinct debating sides, which reinforced the existing political polarization rather than changed it.46 It was above all in such argumentation that diff erent understandings of the meaning of key political concepts became manifested. Parliamentary speeches were also acts. As Colclough has pointed out, they were certainly not just mere preamble for decision-making or a commentary on political action; rather they themselves consti- tuted a form of political action. Th e debaters were practising politics through their use of words. Th ey were actively involved in the forma- tion of the political reality through their uses of concepts rather than merely refl ecting some separate political reality independent of the language of politics.47 Steinmetz has gone even further in emphasizing that speaking was action. According to him, every single sentence of a parliamentary speech should be interpreted as an action. Th is notion follows from the fact that it was the only form of action available to most members of parliament in the fi rst place. Despite this empha- sis on the speeches as acts, they should not, according to Steinmetz, be analysed as highly intentional texts of the type found in abstract political philosophy.48 Both genres of political debate can be used for historical research, but we need to remember that the degree of inten- tionality varied between these. Th ere were likewise diff erences between parliamentary and forensic speaking, which had been the object of interest of much classical rhetoric. It follows, therefore, that rhetorical models originating from judicial contexts may not have been directly applicable to parliamentary debates. Th e emphasis in this study will be throughout on the use of con- cepts rather than on rhetorical strategies as such. Nevertheless, classical rhetoric did constitute an important context for speaking, particularly as it seems to have become fashionable again during the last decades of the eighteenth century and was present in the parliamentary procedure as well.49 Classical rhetorical theory had been part of the education of practically every speaker, and its precepts for speaking and persuasion

46 Mack 2002, 215, 251; Ilie 2004b, 19, 23. 47 Colclough 2005, 125. 48 Steinmetz 2002, 88–90. 49 Jupp 2006, 208; Palonen 2008, 150. british and swedish parliamentary debates 45 aff ected the content and techniques of parliamentary discourse, the ways in which the audience was approached and the organization of the arguments. Classical rhetoric was also infl uential because mem- bers of the British Parliament and the Swedish Noble Estate regarded their roles as identical to those of the Roman Senators. Th e speakers were familiar with the rhetorical principle of strengthening their ethos, authority, in order to make their arguments more persuasive. Th ey knew that logos, the appeal to reason, and pathos, the appeal to emo- tions, needed to be skilfully combined in speaking. Th e speaker might also try to question the ethos, and hence the authority, of his oppo- nent. All these elements appear in the speeches, although they will not be specifi cally analysed below. Both the countries studied here also had long domestic traditions of parliamentary speaking. Precedents were given considerable weight, and the parliamentary tradition led to the development of new conven- tions of speaking. Th us instances not only from the ancient Greek and Roman traditions but also from domestic history could be invoked. Academic models of dialectic might be followed in debating speeches. Th e conventional strategy was to fi rst summarize the argu- ments of some previous speaker and then to reply to them point by point. Previous points were customarily rejected by the means of logi- cal contradiction, enthymemes and hypothetical syllogisms and by making distinctions between the various ways in which the key words could be understood. At the end of his speech, the speaker was sup- posed to state his views clearly and perhaps add a further argument to support them.50 Such a dialectic approach made it possible for the speaker to defi ne concepts in diff erent ways or to replace those used by previous speakers with more appropriate ones. Th is model thus needs to be borne in mind in analysing the use of concepts in individual speeches.

Ceremonial Speaking and Dialogues between the Powers of the State

Parliamentary speaking was not always persuasive, aiming at win- ning votes in divisions; it also had ritualistic and ceremonial purposes aiming at the consolidation of the political community51 through the

50 Mack 2002, 232, 250. 51 Mack 2002, 215, 251; Helmrath & Feuchter 2008, 10–11. 46 chapter one formulation of presumed shared values and concepts. Ceremonial speaking may at fi rst sight appear to be the mere reiteration of old formulas that lacked any concrete political content, but this is not the case. Speeches made in connection with the opening ceremonies of the British Parliament and the Swedish Diet provide examples of political arguments and concepts that could be used without arousing oppos- ing reactions among the majority of the audience. A minority might not agree, but that usually made little diff erence. It was usual for the speakers to invoke histories and arguments which were already gener- ally accepted by the audience. Th is recitation of arguments and con- cepts was an eff ective means of reinforcing a shared history, interests and identity and of creating unity among the political elites.52 Cer- emonial speaking can thus be as interesting as innovative speech acts as it reveals which concepts were generally or offi cially held and what meanings were usually associated with them. Moreover, when con- cepts and their meanings changed in ceremonial speaking, the change was most likely to have already taken place at the macro level. In Britain, the opening speeches of the King and his ministry and the Addresses of Th anks of the two Houses constitute an unusually uniform series of repeated speech acts that contrasted with the vari- able and spontaneous parliamentary debates. Embracing every session from 1734 to 1800, they enable the study of long-term continuities and changes in offi cial formulations of the political role of the people in the context of votes of confi dence in the ministry.53 Th e texts of the Royal Speeches were formulated by the ministry well in advance54 and the Addresses by the houses, in principle collectively, aft er a proposal, possible discussion and sometimes proposed amendments. Th ey can thus hardly be interpreted as mere individual speech acts. Th ey were

52 Mack 2002, 216, 251; for a parallel analysis of ritualistic speaking which, despite continuity in form, went through considerable transformations in content, see Ihalainen 2005 and Ihalainen 2008d. 53 Jones 2006, 232–262. 54 During the debate of 1734, William Shippen said: “I believe it has always been taken for granted, that the Speeches from the throne are the compositions of ministers of state; upon that supposition we have always thought ourselves at liberty to examine every proposition in them; even without doors people are pretty free in their remarks upon them.” (IX, 189) In 1754, Th omas Potter similarly stated: “Th e speech from the throne at the opening of a session is the speech of the ministers.” (XV, 342) It is, of course, most likely that it was the Prime Minister who fi nally formulated or at least made decisions about the content of these texts. As the Duke of Argyle put it, the speech was “composed by the minister” (XII, 283); Jones 2006, 235. british and swedish parliamentary debates 47 undoubtedly infl uenced by a number of political considerations which need to be taken into account but which are not always discernable. Th ese carefully considered, discussed and mutually negotiated offi cial documents convey what the majority of the British political elite considered to be the most relevant political terminology on each occasion. Th ey are particularly revealing about the constitutional rela- tionship between the monarch, the government, parliament and the people.55 Th e unwritten constitution provided constant possibilities for a fruitful debate on the exact nature of this relationship, and that debate took place through these documents as well. Despite the party political background of the speeches and addresses, they were offi cially seen as texts expressing the will of the King himself or the House as a collective, which increased their authority. Horace Mann appealed to this authority in 1781: [. . .] he thought the House were most dutifully complying with the words of his Majesty from the throne, on the opening of the present session of Parliament, in proceeding to pass a bill like that before them. His Majesty had expressly desired to know the wishes of his people; and in the speech immediately subsequent to the late disgraceful outrages [the Gordon riots], had declared, that he wished to make the happiness and the welfare of the people his own. What could more immediately or more forcibly convey to the royal mind an authentic proof of the sentiments of the people, than the Commons of England agreeing to pass a bill, the avowed objects of which were public reform and public oeconomy? (PR, II, 32).56 Th e speeches authored by the ministry obviously defi ned the agenda of at least the majority of the House of Commons. From our point of view, it is important that practically every speech and address made use of vocabulary referring to the people or the nation. Taken together, the royal speeches and the parliamentary addresses create a series of sources that enables the study of long-term changes in constitutional terminology. An analysis of the language used to refer to the people at the macro level also provides a necessary coun- ter-balance to the more micro-level analyses of the uses of the concept of democracy and related terminology in individual parliamentary

55 As Dowdeswell pointed out on 13 November 1770: “Parliamentary Addresses, are considered not only by this nation, but by all others, as the best criterions of the confi dence which the House reposes in the king and his ministers.” (XVI, 1055). 56 Th e Parliamentary Register; or, History of the Proceedings and Debates of the House of Commons, (London, 1782–1796), Vol. 2, 32. 48 chapter one debates. Together, these two strategies of analysis provide a more bal- anced account of conceptual change at both the collective and the individual levels. Th ere is little doubt as to the accuracy of the representations of these speeches and addresses in the records. Offi cial royal and parliamentary documents were not intentionally misrepresented but were published by a parliamentary decision.57 Th e contemporaries considered these documents important despite their ceremonial and repetitive nature. Th ey were always reported in great detail in papers, as were most of the related debates. John Campbell, the Duke of Argyle, described the weight of the addresses by stating in 1741: “[e]very address [. . .] ought to be considered as a public record, and to be drawn up, to inform the nation.” (XII, 283).58 In the Royal Speeches and in the Addresses of Th anks of the two Houses, the diff erent powers of the British state were speaking in and about their constitutional roles, searching for ways to express their mutual relationships in a manner acceptable to all sides. Th is was the only occasion when the monarch—or his ministry who had compiled the speech—and the representatives of ‘the people’ (or, theoretically in Aristotelian terms, ‘aristocracy’ and ‘democracy’) offi cially met and communicated with each other. While the speeches and addresses may generally seem to use conventional language, times of crisis brought about some noteworthy changes in its content and connotations, includ- ing the frequency, applications and meanings of vocabulary referring to the people. Diff erent strategies were used by the government side to persuade Parliament (seen as ‘the people’) or ‘the people’ (seen as separate from Parliament). Th e two houses, for their part, looked for appropriate ways to express the loyalty of the people or sometimes to demonstrate the role of Parliament and the people together as a politi- cal agent independent of the monarchy. Some opposition members might suggest during the debates that the voice of the people and that of Parliament were not in accord in the fi rst place. Th e speeches and addresses were thus eff ectively used to com- municate messages to the other powers of the state. Th e Crown was likely to appeal to ‘the people’ to diff erent degrees and in diff erent

57 See Black 2004, 157. 58 Cobbett’s Parliamentary History of England: From the Norman Conquest in 1066 to the Year 1803 (London 1806–1820), Vol. 12, column 283; abbreviated (XII, 283). british and swedish parliamentary debates 49 ways depending on its relative position at the time of the opening of the session. Th e House of Lords was usually cautious in its formula- tions, seeing itself as the mainstay of the monarchy, but the House of Commons did occasionally send implicit (and at times actually quite explicit) messages to the monarch and the ministry emphasizing its own constitutional role. A considerable amount of diversity in the responses can be found in the Commons debates on the Addresses of Th anks. Regular parliamentary debates such as those on the Address of Th anks in Britain—or those on the constitution in Sweden—pro- vided opportunities for making unexpected political points, as the sub- ject was such a broad one. Th e intensity and length of the debates in both houses can be considered an indicator of the degree of crisis in which the political community was felt to be at the time of the opening of each session. During the debates on the Addresses of Th anks, the members of par- liament felt freer to discuss any question, however tenuous its relation to the Royal Speech; in this they diff ered from the usual debates, which had clearly defi ned subjects. Th is created opportunities for dissent- ing opinions on the political role of the people to be put forward. As the debates took place on the opening day of the session every seven years aft er general elections, some members of parliament, hav- ing recently returned from their constituencies, may have wished to voice the views of their electors. It was, aft er all, the very purpose of Parliament to bring “the sense of the people” to the knowledge of the monarch and the government, and what better forum to do so than the debates on the Addresses of Th anks to the King.59 We have several instances of amendments to the text of the Address being proposed by the opposition, of debates on the messages conveyed by alternative formulations and of divisions, in which the original text was almost always accepted. Th e address was delivered with nominal unanimity and usually according to the original proposal. Th is being the case, some speakers merely used the opportunity to make particular political

59 Note on references: Th e direct citations have been furnished with exact refer- ences in brackets, including the number of the volume and column of Cobbett’s Par- liamentary History. Th ese should enable the reader to locate the full text of the royal speeches, the addresses of the two Houses, the debates on the addresses and the royal answers without it being necessary to refer to every single one of the hundreds of documents individually. 50 chapter one points in which they disagreed with the ministry even if they knew that no amendment would be passed.

Methodological Challenges Posed by the Use of Parliamentary Reports and Minutes

Th e documentation of parliamentary debates will always remain to some extent imperfect, distorted and possibly partisan in one way or another. Each record of parliamentary speaking needs to be interpreted in the context of its production. Th e Swedish Estates, for instance, produced very extensive offi cial records, which makes the location of relevant speech acts challenging. In Britain, the records were more selective, but they were unoffi cial and thus at least potentially subject to distortions. A contrast between these two types of records raises some methodological issues that deserve further consideration. Th e approved discussion minutes of the Swedish Noble and Burgher Estates are very detailed. Whatever was written down in the Swed- ish minutes was approved in conjunction with some later plenary session. Th is probably aff ected them in two ways: on the one hand, it increased correspondence between the intended key arguments of the original speeches and the record, as the speakers had a chance to correct ‘mistakes’ in the minutes; on the other, the practice may have led to speakers remembering their points diff erently or changing their minds aft er the debate, so that a new formulation was recorded.60 Con- scious manipulation of the records must have been rare, however, as the other members were able to monitor all changes during the offi cial approval of the minutes. In many ways, and despite the indirect nature of political argumentation in the consensual language that was used, the Swedish records are the best we have for much of the eighteenth century. Th e Swedish Nobility was the dominant estate; it had numerous members and interests to defend, and it contained articulate speakers who had no fear of expressing their views. Because of their social and political superiority and their over-representation in committees the members of the estate played key roles.61 Th ey were the most highly educated of the estates, and their political thinking was infl uenced by

60 See also Winton 2006, 53. 61 Roberts 1973, 12; Gustafsson 1994, 50. british and swedish parliamentary debates 51 links with the outer world and by a long tradition that regarded the estate as the heart of the nation. It is thus no surprise that concep- tual revisions were most likely to receive linguistic expression in the plenary sessions of the Noble Estate as the noblemen debated among themselves. Inside the House of Nobility, the members might make use of radical republican language, but outside it they tended to be rather more cautious, though any such attempts to maintain the status quo seem to have been forgotten during the period of free publication aft er 1766. Th e Burgher Estate could talk almost endlessly on economic issues, and creative political thought was oft en overshadowed by particular interests. Th ere the only radical notions were put forward by indi- vidual speakers, while most burghers concentrated on advocating local economic interests. Th e records of the Clerical and Peasant Estates are more limited, but they also contain reports of some interesting debates. Th e Peasant Estate had few experienced speakers and favoured consensual decision-making without voting, while the Clerical Estate was the smallest in number and practised collegial decision-making, dissention perhaps being considered unworthy of the estate. Some- times the minutes of these two estates only report the key points of the speakers.62 However, in this study I have not considered it enough just to con- sult the records of related debates in the plenary sessions of the Estates. Th e important Secret Committee, which mostly focused on questions of foreign and economic policy, has also been taken into account, even if the meanings of the concept of the people were rarely discussed there. Some of the most interesting debates were actually found in the manuscripts of a joint committee on the constitution in 1769 and of an extended Secret Committee discussing the royal oath in 1771–1772. In both, all four estates were represented and debated the formulation of the constitution, including the political role of the people. Th is is very unusual for the eighteenth century. Th e Peasantry may not have been reformist in its political views, but its demands for representation in the joint committee of 1772 were certainly unconventional.63 It may be

62 Lagerroth 1934, 6/2, 108, trusted the ability of the secretaries to catch even improvised statements, which is quite unlikely to have happened. 63 In theory, the Peasant Estate represented all the commoners of the countryside (allmoge), but in practice they belonged to the well-to-do echelons of the land-owning and tax-paying peasantry, constituted members of local elites and formed a type of 52 chapter one possible to fi nd further debates between the estates as their members met in deputations and committees to discuss particular questions and further uses of the relevant concepts in memoranda written by the members and in correspondence between and within the four estates. However, my chosen strategy has been to focus on plenary sessions and special joint committees, as we can assume that the most important conceptual changes were refl ected in speeches given in them. Anyway, by the 1760s the plena had also regained much of their infl uence from the Secret Committee. In Britain, the state of the records is quite diff erent. Th e extant press reports are of diverse degrees of reliability, depending on the circumstances of reporting. Th ere are undeniable diff erences between what actually was said and what was written down, even though the arguments were generally speaking represented identically and consis- tently in simultaneous reports. Nevertheless, some passages that were included by some reporters were omitted by others. Some reporters may have misunderstood parts of the text or consciously changed the formulations—and even the arguments themselves. It should also be noted that many of the speeches were recorded in reported rather than direct speech. Some of the potentially most interesting debates were never recorded at all. Th is needs to be borne in mind if we want to study the use of pre-planned rhetoric and the execution of intentional speech acts in specifi c contexts.64 From the point of view of recon- structing the meanings of the overall political vocabulary in a macro- level political culture, such distortion is not necessarily a problem; rather it can actually be regarded as a object of further study. We can ask what the alternative ways of expressing the same argument con- ceptually in that period were. What kind of vocabulary was available, and what kinds of meanings did they carry at the time of speaking and writing the report? Th e records tell us what may, could or should have been said in Parliament. We are dependent on the press reports as no offi cial minutes of the debates in Parliament were kept in the eighteenth century.65 In gentry. Th ey did not necessarily share interests with the lowest orders and hence did not speak on behalf of the peasant society at large. Gustafsson 1994, 62, 73. Th ey can thus actually be seen as comparable to the landed interests of the House of Commons, while the Burghers represented the moneyed interests. 64 For the variation in reporting, see Reid 1932, 36. 65 Th e clerks were forbidden to make any notes on speeches. Hatsell, Precedents, Vol. 2, 1818, 265, 267. british and swedish parliamentary debates 53 principle, it was illegal for members of the public to publish parlia- mentary debates,66 the parliamentary elite considering it their privilege to debate behind closed doors. Even so, parliamentary debates were published despite the restrictions. From the 1740s we have several, not always identical accounts of the same speeches. At that stage, the reports were not always written down during the actual debate but in the reporter’s own chambers possibly aft er a considerable time lag. In fact, Samuel Johnson reported on the debates in Parliament (or, as he called it, the Senate of Lilliput) without ever attending it. However, there is evidence to suggest that even these accounts were based on trustworthy sources and were reasonably reliable.67 Th e reports analysed in this study for the 1730s and 1740s were published in London newspapers, collected in Richard Chandler’s History and Proceedings of the House of Commons, and reprinted in Cobbett’s Parliamentary History, which is available in electronic form via the Making of the Modern World/Economy database and the Google Books. In the 1750s and 1760s, debates were rarely reported in the press, which explains the limited extent of sources from that period. Th e situation changed around 1770, and for the rest of the century Cobbett provides a reasonably good collection of debates.68 Especially for the 1790s, we have alternative records as well, including William Woodfall’s Impartial Report of the Debates, 1794–1803. Th ese sources are so extensive that they can safely be used for a macro-level analysis of the development of vocabulary referring to the people. We shall come back to debates related to the change of 1770 towards the end of Chapter Two. Th is change is signifi cant from a source criti- cal point of view because it meant that debates could then be published more frequently despite the protests of the Commons. Th e demand

66 Th omas 1971, 336; A similar kind of secrecy was long maintained in the Swedish Diet as well, where only extracts from the records were made available to the other estates. Nevertheless, in 1756 the Riksdag decided to begin publishing an offi cial Riks- dag journal that included notices to the public of matters on which the Riksdag had been able to make decisions. In 1766, Anders Chydenius campaigned for a freedom of the press that could include the possibility of publishing the minutes of the Riksdag so that the electors would be informed about the actions of their delegates at the Riksdag, but this was not approved in such a broad form. Lagerroth 1934, 5/1, 177, 196. 67 Herzog 1998, 71–72. 68 Steinmetz has used the same collection for his analyses of the debates of the early 1780s. Steinmetz 1993, 46; Wahrman, in contrast, has questioned Cobbett as a trust- worthy source for the study of rhetoric and argumentation in Parliament. Wahrman 1992, 90–91, 108. 54 chapter one for more extensive reports was obviously rising, and the reports in turn enabled growing interaction between the Commons and public political debate. Th e House of Lords also tried to control the publish- ing of its debates, and hence some records are missing or incomplete. Wider reporting began in the upper house around 1775, as restrictions on strangers attending its sessions were relaxed and opposition to the press disappeared. Even if Cobbett’s Parliamentary History off ers far from a complete account of what was said in the two houses,69 we do have a suffi cient source basis for studying the language used to refer to the people by the members of the Lords as well. It can at times be complemented by the Parliamentary Register and other collected reports. Th e reports became increasingly reliable aft er the American War of Independence. Even in the early nineteenth century, however, mem- bers of parliament might still protest against accounts printed in news- papers, some of them claiming that the reports were contrary to what they had argued. In 1798 James Martin suggested: “Th ose who wrote the reports made gentlemen say just what they themselves pleased.” (XXXIV, 153) Other members of parliament had already started to sell corrected copies of their speeches to the papers in the 1790s or had had them printed at their own cost.70 Th e attitudes of the members of parliament were divided but obvi- ously changing. By 1798, it was being suggested that publishing reports strengthened the democratic element of the constitution, the word ‘democratic’ being used conventionally in a pejorative sense. William Windham, Secretary at War, opposed reporting as an attempt to turn Britain from a representative system into a democratic system of the French kind: [. . .] the general tendency of publishing the proceedings of that House was to change the government from a representative, to an entirely dem- ocratic one. What would be the natural eff ect of such publication? It must be that of changing the present form of government, and of making it democrat- ical; for it was calling every day on the public to judge of the proceedings of parliament. By these daily publications the people were taught to look

69 Namier & Brooke 1964, 522; Th omas 1971, 141–143, 229, 336; Ditchfi eld 1989, 204–205; Wahrman 1992, 86; Black 2004, 158–159. 70 Th orne 1986, 368–369; Herzog 1998, 72–74; Wahrman 1992, 88–89; Reid 2000, 127. british and swedish parliamentary debates 55

upon themselves as present at the discussion of all the proceedings of parliament, and sitting in judgment on them. Th e practice of publishing debates was an appeal from the representa- tive body, to the people at large out of doors, of all orders, from the highest to the lowest.71 Windham aptly summarized exactly what was happening in Britain: Parliamentary and public debates were becoming intertwined as a con- sequence of the publication of parliamentary debates. Parliamentarians became more frequently engaged in public debates, sometimes appeal- ing to the people at large rather than just the chamber. Th e members of parliament were highly aware of what was published in the name of the people. Political consciousness may also have been increasing among the public in all orders. As Charles Tilly has suggested, popular politics became parliamentarized in the sense that the public became interested in what was going on in Parliament and wanted to actively infl uence its decision-making.72 Already in 1798, many contemporaries understood just what was at stake in the publication of the debates. William Wilberforce main- tained that their publication was both “benefi cial to the country” and “perfectly constitutional”, allowing the people to observe the conduct and language of their representatives (XXXIV, 167). Here we have an early statement advocating the active participation of the people in the parliamentary decision-making process as observers informed by the publication of debates. Th e conceptions of the politicians revealed by their choice of language also came under public scrutiny. Wilberforce’s view of the relationship between Parliament and the public became possible in the aft ermath of the French Revolution. We can be sure that these arguments were presented in the Com- mons, although there may be some variance in the exact wording. Some further reservations need to be made, however. Dror Wahrman has shown how in debates related to class issues in the 1790s, papers supporting opposite political views could summarize the same speech quite diff erently. He suggests that the newspaper reports were recon- structions of the debates aff ected by the political stances of the report- ers and the rhetorical usage of the reporting newspaper, not facsimile

71 Mr. Tierney’s Complaint against “Th e Times” Newspaper for misrepresenting the Speeches of the Members, XXXIV, 158–159, 164; misleading reporting was also a subject of complaint during this debate. Black 2004, 159. 72 Tilly 1997, 245–273. 56 chapter one reproductions of them. Th e political language of the reports was infl u- enced by the concepts and rhetorical practices of those who produced them, even though this infl uence may have been unconscious. Parlia- ment could be made to serve the divergent interests of the public.73 Reporters might hear, understand, remember and write down argu- ments in diff erent ways, perhaps making use of competing political vocabularies. At best, a newspaper could report only selected parts of major debates, simply because of the lack of space in the midst of a variety of topics, and hence the reporters tended to focus on the most famous speakers and omit less interesting ones. Th e reporters them- selves conceded that their reports contained “rather the substance than the circumstance”, “the leading points” or “the substance and purport” of the debates, not every argument or formulation.74 Jennifer Mori has advised scholars not to rely excessively on reports of William Pitt’s speeches from the 1790s, although she and Pitt’s biographer, William Hague, have quoted them. Th e records were certainly not complete, as Pitt is known to have handed in a script of his speech only three times, but the content of the speeches is relatively well known.75 As we shall see, despite the variety of reporters the reports of what Pitt said about democracy were consistent to a high degree, which suggests that they are reasonably trustworthy. Th e records are, therefore, not perfect, but they are still extremely useful as historical sources. Diff erent reports of the same speeches usu- ally represent the same basic arguments even though they may diff er as to exactly how the arguments were expressed. Despite contempo- rary claims about misleading reporting, conscious signifi cant distor- tions were probably rare, particularly as so much political language was shared. Th e distortions mainly concerned some highly contested concepts.76 Th e members of parliament carefully supervised the printed reports and were prepared to make complaints about them, and this made reporters careful not to change the content of the speeches on purpose too oft en or too much (see also Wilberforce in XXXIV, 168). A number of members of parliament also trusted the accuracy of

73 Wahrman 1992, 85, 88, 90, 110. 74 Ditchfi eld 1989, 206 (fi rst citation); Wahrman 1992, 86–87 (second citation); Black 2004, 138, 158 (third citation); Bullard 2005, 321, 324; cf. Colclough 2005, 129. 75 Mori 2004, 68. 76 Steinmetz 1993, 46; Herzog 1998, 74. british and swedish parliamentary debates 57 the reports, thanking the newspapers and citing them to attack their opponents.77 Th e reports refl ect contemporary language use even in those cases where reporting modifi ed the exact formulation of the argument. Even if they did not always follow the arguments exactly as the speakers would have liked to see them published, the British reports illustrate the language use that was possible at that time in Parliament. Th ey tell us what was probably said in Parliament, or what may or could or should have been said there. Th e reports tell us about macro-level con- ventional language use, and from them we can discern the redefi ning speech acts executed by individual politicians. Parliamentary speaking in earlier periods has been successfully studied on the basis of much scantier evidence, and thus there is no reason why we should dismiss the extensive eighteenth-century records. Th e vocabulary constituted by the expressions “the people”, “repre- sentation”, “democracy” and later on also “the sovereignty of the peo- ple” was, undoubtedly, a contested fi eld in Parliament and potentially in parliamentary reports as well. Yet it remains to be shown that there existed any particular reasons for newspapers to manipulate instances of the use of this vocabulary. Th e reports refl ect the overall change in political vocabulary among the British parliamentary elite and politi- cal discourse more broadly. When we analyse past political language using printed reports, we are simultaneously studying both parliamen- tary and public debates. Even though the individual speaker is always important, it is even more important to understand how the collec- tive body, the British political community as a whole, either continued to represent the political role of the people in conventional terms or changed its language through time, and indeed quite radically as a consequence of the French Revolution.

77 Black 2004, 161–162.

CHAPTER TWO

VARIATIONS IN BRITISH PARLIAMENTARY CONCEPTIONS OF THE PEOPLE, 17341771

Parliaments have had a good Eff ect on the People, by keeping them quiet; and the People on Parliaments, by keeping them within Bounds.1 I pay no regard whatever to the voice of the people: it is our duty to do what is proper, without considering what may be agreeable: their business is to chuse us; it is our business to act constitutionally, and to maintain the independency of parliament: [. . .] (XVII, 149).2 Th e early eighteenth-century debate on ‘democracy’ tended to still be limited to learned circles and their deliberations about various forms of government. Th ese were oft en dominated by an Aristotelian scep- ticism about the possibility of making the rule of the people, that is direct or “pure” democracy, work in practice. Pure democracy was considered an historical phenomenon that had occurred only in very small and simple states such as ancient Athens. As far as contemporary regimes were concerned, democracy was sometimes seen as applicable to the Dutch Republic, some Swiss cantons and a few German cities.3 In this period, democracy was nowhere yet understood as compatible with the principle of representation. Only within the framework of mixed governments such as England, Venice or Sweden could demo- cratic elements play even a theoretical role, side by side with monarchy and aristocracy. By the early eighteenth century, political principles and practices resembling in some respects later systems of representative government had already emerged in Britain, the Netherlands and Sweden, and to a lesser extent in Poland. In these countries, the original principle of the consent of the subjects being required for new taxation had been

1 Henry St. John, Viscount Bolingbroke, A Dissertation upon Parties; in Several Letters to Caleb D’Anvers, Esq; dedicated to the Right Honourable Sir Robert Walpole. Th e third edition, (London 1735), 158–159. 2 Charles James Fox in the Commons on 25 March 1771. 3 Palmer 1953, 204–205; Maier 1972, 839, 842. Th e Swedish or English forms of government were also sometimes viewed as democracies by critical outside observers. 60 chapter two extended to concern laws more generally. Th e principle of representa- tion (the term “representation” was not yet always used) had also been established for practical reasons, as the governing of large areas called for representation when consent for taxes and laws was sought. Th e principle of delegates or representatives being elected to their posts had also become widely accepted. Free subjects thus met in elected representative legislatures every now and then at local, regional and national levels.4 In some countries, the relationship between national representative institutions and the people had already become quite strong and mutual, as suggested by Viscount Bolingbroke in the quo- tation above. In principle, the British members of parliament paid attention to what they understood to be the sentiments of the people, and parliamentary proceedings were followed by the public, as far as that was possible under limits set by strict parliamentary privilege. Generally speaking, the parliaments and estates of the early eight- eenth century continued to defend the existing privileges of the higher orders, particularly those of the nobility and the clergy. Th e repre- sentatives of the common people still constituted only a minority in representative assemblies. Th e delegates of the so-called people thus actually represented the higher orders. Even when the Swedish peas- ants, for instance, sent their representatives to the Diet, the spokesmen of the common people did not always have full participatory rights in decision-making. Th e British House of Commons, for its part, was dominated by the gentry rather than by freeholders. Furthermore, the representatives of the people in the House of Commons represented no more than fi ve percent of the population over the age of twenty in the period preceding the Reform Act of 1832. Despite these limita- tions to representation, a balance of power had been reached in the British constitution, aft er the confl icts of the seventeenth century, in which the monarch and Parliament limited each other’s power. Also within Parliament itself, a much admired balance between aristocratic and democratic elements of the constitution had been achieved in that the power of the hereditary aristocracy of the Lords was countered and oft en bypassed by the Commons, which could, in principle, be interpreted as representing the power of the people. Parliament met annually, held lengthy sessions and infl uenced governance, particularly

4 Dahl 1998, 22. the westminster parliament and the people, – 61 through its power to decide on economic and fi nancial matters.5 Th e relative signifi cance of the Commons rose in the period 1734–1771, but the infl uence of the Lords also remained considerable. Marilyn Morris has summarized the seventeenth-century back- ground of the political role of the people in the terminology of mod- ern political theory—something that the following analysis replaces with an analysis of contemporary uses of language. According to Mor- ris, even in republican political theory “the sovereignty of the people rested in the gentry.” Th e republicanism of the Levellers derived “pop- ular sovereignty” from natural rights, but even “they were not true democrats”. In the Leveller case, “sovereignty” was considered to have remained with the people and not to have been transferred to their representatives. Th e interpretation of the majority of the Republicans who abolished the monarchy, by contrast, was that they themselves constituted the people and hence “the sovereignty of the people rested in the people’s elected representatives.”6 Th e republican tradition, as incorporated in English political thought in the eighteenth century, taught that the people had a political role, but that the members of parliament constituted the people who were politically signifi cant. While the principle of political power being derived from popular con- sent had been reinforced by the Revolution of 1688 and had become generally recognized by the British political elite by the 1730s, exces- sive involvement of the people in the political process continued to be treated with suspicion. Even so, the inheritance of the seventeenth century never disap- peared: England had witnessed demands for the liberty and power of the people during the Civil Wars,7 and the Whig party adopted the principle of the consent of the people as the principal basis of its ideology, even though this did not entail an open defence of the sovereignty of the people. Th e early eighteenth century saw quite an extensive debate on the political role of the people, in which, increas- ingly, Parliament was seen as the forum in which the voice of the

5 Dahl 1998, 21, 23; Jupp 2006, 54–82. 6 Morris 1998, 82; For a similar kind of “history” of the sovereignty of the people without the history of the actual phrase being taken into consideration, see Golds- worthy 1999, 176–177. 7 Skinner 2006, 156–168. 62 chapter two people was heard, insofar as the existence of this political phenom- enon was recognized at all.8 In any case, in the early eighteenth century, the British people pos- sessed relatively wide suff rage. Britain had a comparatively free press aft er 1695, which supported the emergence, mobilization and expres- sion of the views of the people. Th e press informed politicians about the sentiments of the people and taught the people about the actions, goals and divisions of the political elite. According to John Markoff , this political culture made Britain “a major pioneer in modern, disor- derly politics, in the forms and modalities by which ordinary people have challenged powerholders”.9 Charles Tilly has further suggested that the British system contributed signifi cantly to the parliamenta- rization of politics more generally. Popular politics was by the 1790s taken into account in Parliament, while the public actively attempted to infl uence Parliament. As a consequence, Britain became a pioneer in the combination of a national representative parliamentary body with widespread popular mobilization.10 Th is gives us a good reason to start our analysis with the British case. Th e self-understanding of this political community was not yet based on any clear concept of democracy, however. To fi nd out how the political role of the people was understood in this period, it is not only the word “democracy” but also the language referring to the people as a whole that we need to construct, analyse and compare with that used in other eighteenth-century representative bodies. For much of the period 1734–1771, language alluding to the people rose to a position of major political signifi cance in only a few particular parlia- mentary debates. Ceremonial defi nitions of the people were character- ized by continuity. Around 1770, however, the concept of the people gained a new degree of political importance in parliamentary and pub- lic debates in both Britain and Sweden. Before proceeding to a more detailed analysis of the evolving use of references to the people, democracy and, later on, to the sover- eignty of the people in British parliamentary debates, let us summarize some of the main arguments on democracy put forward by European political theorists in the period which preceded the outbreak of the

8 Dickinson 1977, 130; Gunn 1983, 73–79, 271–272. 9 Markoff 1999, 684, 686. 10 Tilly 1997, 245−273. the westminster parliament and the people, – 63 fi rst modern revolutions. Of the Continental debates, the French one was—despite British prejudices against its political system—the most relevant. French treatises on political theory were much more frequently translated into English than those published in any other European language. Th eir infl uence on the English language of politics was indirect but still considerable. In early eighteenth-century France, démocratie was still considered a foreign word that was mostly used with reference to ancient history. Democracy was a defi ned as a “form of government in which the peo- ple have all authority” and as one that “only fl ourished in the repub- lics of Rome and Athens”. Furthermore, the common assumption was that “seditions and turmoil happen oft en in Democracies” and “the worst of all outbursts is a democratic one”. Democracy was thus seen as no more than an historical form of government that had existed in the classical world, and one that possessed considerable inherent shortcomings.11 Th e implications were that, in democracy, it was not the most qualifi ed people but those capable of winning the constantly changing favour of the uneducated people who were in charge of pub- lic aff airs. Th e impracticality and irrelevance of democracy as a form of government had already been demonstrated two thousand years pre- viously.12 Democracy was not seen as a system for the contemporary world, and particularly not for France.13 However, there also existed an alternative tradition of viewing the power of the people. Jean Bodin’s late sixteenth-century theory on sovereignty suggested that sovereignty could belong to the people as a whole without this necessarily leading to a democracy. Bodin also emphasized equality as the essence of democracy and referred to some contemporary Swiss city states as instances of democracy, in addition to the conventional cases of Athens and Rome. Despite his advocacy of the monarchy, Bodin recommended the inclusion of some demo- cratic elements in monarchy in order to make it more stable.14 Such an approach made it possible to view democracy also as a contem- porary element in the constitution that was capable of having some good eff ects. In the 1730s, the Marquis d’Argenson elaborated Bodin’s ideas in an unpublished text, calling for a “democratic administration”

11 Dippel 1986, 58–59; Markoff 1999, 661, 664. 12 Dippel 1986, 59. 13 Wright 2002, 291. 14 Dippel 1986, 59–60. 64 chapter two and suggesting that monarchy and democracy could be combined by opening the political system to the “middling sorts”.15 According to him, monarchical regulation and democracy of the Dutch type, which he saw as functioning through deputies elected by the people, would produce the best results. Th e democratic element, consisting of an assembly of men equal among themselves, would cooperate with the monarchy, decrease aristocratic infl uence, and help the monarch to deduce what the common good was. Th e advancement of equality within such a monarchical system appeared as “the fortunate progress of Democracy”, “democracy” standing for the commoner estates. Yet even d’Argenson did not deny that democracy was apt to lead to divi- sions and revolts.16 It would go too far to interpret d’Argenson’s speculations as a combination of democracy and representation. He still understood democracy in traditional terms as “popular Government, in which the whole people shares equally” and as a form of government which could degenerate into anarchy if it became “the Government of the multitude”. True democracy functioned in d’Argenson’s view through deputies.17 Th e relevance of d’Argenson’s points is also decreased by the fact that they were fi rst published posthumously only in the 1760s, and disseminated more generally only aft er the French Revolution. Similarly, Gabriel Bonnot de Mably’s unpublished dialogue (Des droits et des devoirs du citoyen, 1758) which contained a passing reference combining sovereignty and the people and a recommendation for a return to a mixed government in France hardly changed the overall anti-democratic nature of the debate.18 As we saw in the introduction, Montesquieu, Rousseau and the other leading Enlightenment philosophers did not redefi ne democ- racy or even consider it a particularly relevant form of government. Even so, we have some evidence of the conception of democracy being modifi ed by the French Enlightenment. One of the fi rst positive defi ni- tions of the concept dates from the Encyclopédie (1754), when Louis de Jaucourt described democracy as “that admirable government”. In the edition of 1779, he suggested, much as Montesquieu had done: “A republic in which the sovereignty lies in the hands of the people

15 Dippel 1986, 60–61. 16 Palmer 1953, 205; Rosanvallon 1995, 143; Dunn 2005, 93–96. 17 Dunn 2005, 95–96. 18 Wright 2002, 297. the westminster parliament and the people, – 65 is a democracy.” While this form of government had a tendency to degenerate and was unthinkable in large states, some ancient exam- ples demonstrated that it had its virtues and elevated the spirits of the people.19 Th e customary suggestion has been that it was only the American and French Revolutions that made democracy a relevant alternative in political discourse. Turning this assumption into a hypothesis to be tested, I have divided my analysis of eighteenth-century British parlia- mentary debates into three parts: debates before the American crisis, debates during and aft er the American Revolution, and debates in the 1790s during and aft er the French Revolution. We shall begin in this chapter with the era that preceded the troubles in America and see what kind of continuities and transformations took place in language referring to the people before the constitutional challenge from across the Atlantic. Th ree previous studies—by Harry Dickinson, Kathleen Wilson and Hannah Barker—provide a good starting point for such an analysis. Dickinson, combining the study of political theory and popular politi- cal activism, has pointed out that the aristocratic elite who ruled Britain in the eighteenth century were convinced that they had a natural right to political power over the lower orders. Th ey had been taught to view pure democracy as an inherently unstable form of government likely to degenerate into anarchy, and hence, for them, it remained out of the question to let the people at large meddle with government. Political authority was to be shared by the monarch and a Parliament consist- ing of wealthy men capable of controlling how the Crown spent the taxes they paid. Th e parliamentary elite saw themselves as constituting ‘the people’—insofar as they actually used the concept in a political sense at all. Active political rights were limited to the political elite and, during elections, to a patriarchally guided electorate. However, the parliamentary elite had to come to terms with a fast developing and increasingly diversifi ed political culture in which a considerable number of people eager to infl uence the parliamentary decision-mak- ing process participated.20 Within such a popular political culture, var- ious calls for the “the people” to be given a central position in politics

19 Maier 1972, 841; Dippel 1986, 63; Th is view would be adopted by Charles James Fox, among others. 20 Dickinson 1995, 4–5, 7, 161; see also Gunn 1983, 273; Rogers 1989. 66 chapter two arose. It is not even quite clear whether the members of the governing establishment were united by “their fear of popular sovereignty”, as Dickinson suggests.21 As we shall see, the parliamentary elite debated the political role of the people quite intensively, using the concept of the people in a variety of senses. According to Dickinson, too, the ref- erence of the concept of the people came closer to that of the electorate in the course of the eighteenth century.22 Wilson has added the suggestion that, as a consequence of both the widely held principle of the monarchy being limited by the voice of the people (or, rather, by that of the governing elite) and the develop- ing political culture of the time, representing the “sense of the people” (a contemporary expression for what was later called “the will of the people”) developed into a central rhetorical strategy upon which a wide variety of political arguments could be based. As a rhetorical tool, the concept of the people referred to a vague community invented for the purposes of political argumentation. Th is community was oft en assumed, by the opposition in particular, to exist outside Parliament as opposed to consisting of the members of parliament, and it was seen as potentially supporting views and interests that might diff er radically from those of the members of the political elite. Wilson’s own research has mostly focused on the extra-parliamentary political culture of the “sense of the people” as expressed in print and other forums of the public sphere.23 A broad and deliberately ambiguous concept of the people was widely used in various spheres of political discourse, both inside and outside Parliament. Appeals to the people could be used to legitimate very diverse political views both by members of the political estab- lishment and by those challenging the existing political order. Most members of the political elite, including many leading ministers, will- ingly argued that they were keenly aware of and indeed actually rep- resented—at least in theory—the sentiments of the people outside the establishment. Similarly, many oppositional groups made rhetorical use of the concept of the people in attempts to justify their existence and alternative political views. By using the concept of the people they were able to defi ne themselves as a counter-balance to what they saw

21 Dickinson 1995, 256; cf. Turkka 2007, 28. According to Turkka, “a role for the people in political life was still a thing of the future”. 22 Dickinson 1976, 204. 23 Wilson 1995, 3–5, 17–19. the westminster parliament and the people, – 67 as the abuses of those in power endangering the interests of the peo- ple. Wilson concludes that a notion of popular sovereignty lay behind much populist political argument in the eighteenth century.24 Barker has added the observation that the terms “the people” and “the pub- lic” were increasingly used in the press with reference to wider and vaguely defi ned sections of the population. Th e papers liked to claim that it was in their columns that the voice of the people was to be heard.25 Dickinson’s, Wilson’s and Barker’s approaches to, and conclusions on, eighteenth-century British references to the people will be sup- ported by much of what is presented below, although further nuances of the parliamentary concepts of the people and democracy will be added. It is now time to explore the parliamentary dimension of language alluding to the people and democracy in mid-eighteenth- century Britain, keeping in mind the growing extra-parliamentary political culture with which Parliament was interacting. In this inter- action, Parliament was not always as a mere reactionary force.

Th e Political Role of the People in the Septennial Act Debates of 1734: Walpole’s Defi nition of the Limits of Democracy

According to available British parliamentary records, the concept of democracy fi rst emerged in a debate held in 1734 on the proposed repeal of the Septennial Act of 1716. Th is Act, which remained in force throughout the eighteenth century, had extended the maximum term of each Parliament from three to seven years. It had strengthened the status of Parliament as the centre of political debate and the exercise of political power over the more direct power of the people realized in connection with general elections. In that sense, the Septennial Act had created a wider gulf between the people and Parliament. On 13 March 1734, the Commons debated a Tory motion, sup- ported by a considerable group of Whig Patriots, to repeal the Sep- tennial Act. William Bromley (Jr.), as an experienced Tory critic of the Walpole ministry, had been selected to propose the bill. In his opening speech, he maintained that the people in general disliked long parliaments, whereas triennial parliaments were “supported by the

24 Wilson 1995, 19–20. 25 Barker 2002, 94. 68 chapter two common Voice of the People”. According to Bromley, the people saw the Septennial Bill as an attack on their inherent liberties and thus as a dangerous innovation in the constitution. One of the main purposes of the frequent meetings and limited duration of parliaments since 1694 had, aft er all, been to balance the power of the monarch and the rights of the subjects by securing the liberties of the people.26 In Bromley’s opinion, frequent elections had enabled the people to change its rep- resentatives within a reasonably short period of time, and this right should now be restored.27 Bromley did not build his argument on any sophisticated concept of the sovereignty of the people; such a concept was not yet even available then. However, he connected the concept of the people and the ideal of the people being represented. “Repre- sentation” was not yet the exact term for this ideal, but the verb “to represent” and the noun “representative” fi gured prominently in this kind of discourse (HPHC, III, 140–141). More generally also, those opposing Walpole and the Act appealed to the rights of the people and to the principle of its being represented. According to Sir John St. Aubyn: “Th e People have an unquestionable Right to frequent new Parliaments by ancient Usage.” And it was “the most indubitable, the most essential Privilege of the People” to choose “their own Representative” and to do so frequently. While frequent parliaments would allow the monarch to receive “the fresh Sense of the Nation” and “the Opinion of his People” oft en enough to keep him informed about what “the people” felt at any given moment, long parliaments encouraged electoral bribery and increased the ministers’ infl uence over the ruler to the extent that he could no longer consult “the natural Representation of the People” (HPHC, III, 141, 143–144).

26 Because of diff ering notions of liberty, what these rights actually consisted of remained a topic of debate through the eighteenth century. Another constant disa- greement between the government and the opposition was whether the ministry and Parliament were protecting the rights of the people or endangering them. Dickinson 1995, 162–163. 27 Th e History and Proceedings of the House of Commons of Great Britain (HPHC) (London 1741), Vol. 3, 137–140 (HPHC, III, 137–140). Bromley himself would lose his seat in the elections of 1734; Th e dates of the persons are given only in cases where there is a risk of two homonymous persons being confused. If no reference is given, biographical information on the speakers is based on relevant articles in the Oxford Dictionary of National Biography (2004), and sometimes on articles in the older Dictionary of National Biography or in Th e History of Parliament. References to the authors of these biographical works are given only if a major conclusion on the signifi cance of the actions of the political agent is cited. the westminster parliament and the people, – 69

From the opposition point of view, the status of the Commons as rep- resenting the people was thus threatened by the alleged corruption of the regime. Th e government side, by contrast, insisted that the people had good reason to be pleased with what their representatives in Par- liament—representing the entire body of the commoner estates—had accomplished since the introduction of the Septennial Act (HPHC, III, 150–151, 184). Th e concept of the nation was used in this and similar debates as a close synonym of “the people”. However, the nation was seen mainly as a community whose interests, welfare, freedom, safety, tranquil- lity and happiness the members of parliament were safeguarding; the nation was not so much represented as an active political agency which the members were representing, and hence the political potential of the nation did not appear so great as that of the people. Th e nation remained an object of the actions and control of the members of par- liament as opposed to being seen as a primary political agent. Rival groups were oft en accused of abusing the nation by causing unneces- sary ferment within it. Because of the rather passive role of the nation as a political collective, most of our attention below will be focused on the uses of the concept of the people. “Th e nation” will come up when it is used as a synonym of “the people” in a political sense. While the concepts of the people and the verb “to represent” were combined in the above-mentioned manner, the notion of sovereignty remained one associated solely with monarchical power; this would be the rule at least until the constitutional confrontations with the Ameri- cans in the 1760s. Th e defi nition of the concepts of the monarchy and sovereignty made by the Duke of Beaufort, Charles Noel Somerset, illustrates the interconnection between them and the distinction of the people from sovereignty. Th e association between the people and rep- resentation was much clearer: [. . .] this House is properly the grand Inquest of the Nation, they are to represent the Grievances of the People to their Sovereign; and the People are always to choose proper Representatives for that Purpose (HPHC, III, 159). Annual elections would, according to this Jacobite Tory and constant critic of Walpole, ensure that each members of parliament would remain “a proper Representative of the People”. Another infl uential Jacobite, Watkin Williams-Wynn, emphasized the need for the regime to enjoy the support of the people, which 70 chapter two would indeed supplement parliamentary support if the people were allowed to express their sentiments through annual elections. Frequent elections would also demonstrate to both the monarch and the entire world “the true Sense of the Generality of the People” and strengthen the monarchical form of government. Th e very purpose of Parliament was, as Somerset had said, to function as “the great Council of the Nation” and “to represent to his majesty the Grievances of the People”. Th is could only happen when the members of parliament were the “most proper Representatives of the People” in their communities and were chosen without corruption (HPHC, III, 165, 168–169). Th e rhet- oric of the people functioned here, too, as a means to express Tory, even Jacobite, discontent with the Walpole ministry. Many speakers in favour of more frequent elections rejected the government claims that the members should see themselves as inde- pendent of their electors between elections. Th ey thus actually spoke in favour of an imperative mandate, carrying on the old debate on whether members of parliament were representatives who voted entirely freely or delegates who should observe the instructions given by their voters.28 Walter Plumer, a leading opposition Whig with a commercial background, insisted that he always listened to the wishes of those he represented and argued: If those the People chose to represent them in this House, were to con- tinue in that Station only during the Pleasure of the People, the Repre- sentatives would, I believe, have a proper Regard for the Interests of the People (HPHC, III, 175; see also 180). Th e veteran Tory, Sir William Wyndham, a leading fi gure of the Whig opposition to Walpole and a close political ally of Viscount Boling- broke, regarded compliance with the expectations of the people as self- evident: [. . .] this is what the People have reason to expect from Parliament; there is nothing now desired but what the People have a Right to; they have now, they always had a right to frequent new Parliaments (HPHC, III, 189–190). Th e people were clearly a core concept in the opposition argument in favour of more frequent elections. Th ese would, of course, enable the opposition to challenge the government more oft en while simul-

28 Dickinson 1995, 38. the westminster parliament and the people, – 71 taneously also making it less easy for the government to manipulate Parliament by corruption. Wyndham saw no problem in holding fre- quent elections “when the Nation is in a Ferment”, as he considered elections “one of the chief Supports of the Freedom of the Nation” (HPHC, III, 191–192). He maintained, with an implicit reference to the preceding Excise Crisis, that political fermentation occurred only when “the People’s Rights” were violated and would best be solved by the organization of new elections. Without elections, the legal curtail- ment of the actions of those who threatened their rights would be “out of the Power of the People” (HPHC, III, 192).29 Wyndham’s appeal to the wishes of the people as an argument in favour of the repeal of the Septennial Act and in support of annual elections was clear: [. . .] this is what the People desire; [. . .] Th e Members of Parliament may for one Year be look’d on as the real and true Representatives of the People (HPHC, III, 197). No wonder Wyndham was warmly applauded by the opposition for this speech. It shows how central the idea of representation of the peo- ple through Parliament—albeit not yet the concept of democracy—was in the language of the opposition already in the 1730s. Th e defenders of the ministry used language referring to the peo- ple in a diff erent way in 1734. First and foremost, these Court Whigs emphasized the need for keeping the popular infl uence over the gov- ernment in check. [Th omas?] Robinson warned of the inherent dan- ger of making sudden changes in electoral practices, particularly if “the lower Class of the People” became parties in politics. Th is was a problem because they did not necessarily represent the interests of the people proper at all. Past experience indicated to Robinson that long-sitting parliaments in particular had been willing to defend the rights of the people vis-à-vis the Crown. He also doubted whether the majority of the electors really wanted to change this practice; it was rather the mob who clamoured for change. In fact, the unenfranchised populace were “fond of Noise and Bustle” and “glad of any Change by which they might have a more frequent Chance to get drunk and idle” (HPHC, III, 149–155).

29 In the Excise Crisis of 1733–1734, urban tradesmen and the parliamentary oppo- sition had successfully, in the name of the defence of liberty and property, opposed Walpole’s proposal to increase the number of armed excise offi cers. Dickinson 1977, 182; Gunn 1983, 79; Wilson 1995, 124–125. 72 chapter two

In the aft ermath of the popular petitions and riots of the Excise Crisis, which could be regarded as evidence of the validity of the les- sons of classical political theory concerning the character of the popu- lace, the government side had a deep distrust of the populace at large. Ministry supporters in the Commons did not hesitate to represent the interests of the true people and those of the populace as a whole as potentially confl icting. According to this defi nition of the people, in its vindication of septennial parliaments the government appeared as a defender of the true interests of the people. Th e argument of the ministry was put diff erently by Sir William Yonge, a Lord of the Treasury, who pointed out that a principal rea- son for opposing the repeal of the Septennial Act was the tendency of the common people to become so provoked by elections that their animosities endangered the safety of the country. Furthermore, “the Desires of the Nation in general” were virtually impossible to deter- mine. Recalling the riots of the Excise Crisis, Yonge likewise believed that it was rather “the Mob, I mean such as have no Business with Elec- tions” who wished to get drunk, to be idle and to riot in connection with annual elections. He maintained that the voters would not want to see the implementation of a change that would so needlessly jeop- ardize the government (HPHC, III, 185–188). Because the populace as distinct from the people proper would abuse frequent elections, mob rule had to be countered by the power of a well-managed Parliament. Yonge also had a personal reason for opposing frequently contested elections: he had spent considerable sums of money in order to win his seat in every election in which he had stood. Having benefi ted from offi ces distributed by the Whig oligarchy, he eagerly defended ministe- rial patronage and infl uence in the Commons, frequently suggesting that the opposition was attempting to subvert the constitution.30 Sir John Willes (1685–1761), a staunch supporter of Walpole, also wished to save on election expenses aft er some costly contests. He emphasized the independence of the members of parliament once they had taken their seats. Th ough the candidates were dependent upon the people at election time, the power of the people was transferred to them through the elections once and for all, and hence the people themselves were unable to rule the country. If allowed to do so, the people would be easily misled. Furthermore, it was better to keep the

30 Dickinson 2004. the westminster parliament and the people, – 73 working people employed than to increase their agitation with more frequent elections (HPHC, III, 172, 174). Th at would only harm the true interests of the people proper. Th en Robert Walpole made one of his most famous speeches before the House. Th e prime minister was, indeed, the fi rst to introduce the concept of democracy (in the form of the adjective “democratical”) to British parliamentary discourse in this context.31 Walpole was clearly a linguistic innovator: only a month earlier he had also warned the Com- mons that the opposition was advocating “stratocracy”, the power of the streets. Th e use of the pejorative classical concept and the descrip- tion of the proposed innovation as an excessive form of democracy was evidently a conscious speech act partly motivated by Walpole’s personal experience of mob violence the year before.32 It also had a connection with current public debates. Th e concept of democracy had not appeared that frequently in the public debates of the preceding years. Charles Rollin, for instance, had referred to the risk of tyranny “in a state purely democratical”, as lib- erty could only survive in such a state if there was complete equal- ity.33 Elsewhere in the public debate, democracy had occasionally been viewed in neutral terms. Ephraim Chamber (1728) had connected ‘the people’ and ‘sovereignty’ and presented the Roman Republic as a democracy. For Chambers, “republic”, “democracy” and “popular government” were nearly synonymous terms, though democracy was essentially a form of government of the past: Democracy, a Form of Government, wherein the Sovereignty, or Supreme Authority, is lodged in the People, who exercise the same by Persons of their own Order, deputed for that Purpose. Th is is the most ancient Form of Government. Th e most fl ourishing Democracies were those of Rome and Athens. Th e modern Republicks, as Venice, and the United Provinces, are rather Aristocracies than Democracies. Th e Government of Basil, however, is a Democracy; so are some of the free Cities in .34

31 Th e uniqueness of Walpole’s speech act can be verifi ed by consulting Cobbett’s Parliamentary History of England in MOMW. 32 Walpole had himself been attacked by a crowd in April 1733. Wilson 1995, 126; Black 2001, 244. 33 Charles Rollin, Th e Method of Teaching and Studying the Belles Letters . . . (London 1734), 285. 34 Ephraim Chambers, Cyclopædia: or, an Universal Dictionary of Arts and Sciences . . . (London 1728), Vol. 1, 184; Vol. 2, 996. Chambers connected the concepts 74 chapter two

Nathan Bailey’s dictionary (1733) represented democracy as a sys- tem in which “the Supreme or Legislative Power” was “lodged in the common People, or Persons chosen out from them.”35 According to Th omas Dyche’s dictionary (1740), democracy was “a form of govern- ment, wherein the supreme authority is in the hands of the people.”36 A book referring to Walpole had, however, recently taken up the concept of democracy: the Dissertation upon Parties, written by Vis- count Bolingbroke, an opposition leader without a seat in Parlia- ment and an old political rival of Walpole, and previously published in the opposition organ Th e Craft sman, 37 was obviously the text to which Walpole was responding in his speech. No member had spoken about democracy during the preceding debate, whereas the opposi- tion headed by Bolingbroke was seriously challenging Walpole at this time.38 Th e Craft sman had, indeed, suggested that the people might resist the supreme legislative power in extraordinary circumstances and return to its original, natural right. Th e result of the Excise Cri- sis was interpreted as a demonstration of “the original Power of the People, in their collective Body”.39 As far as forms of government were concerned, Bolingbroke defended “this Mixture of Monarchical, Aris- tocratical and Democratical Power, blended together in one System, and by these three Estates balancing one another”, seeing this as the foundation of a free constitution. Bolingbroke had also advocated “Parliamentary Methods” of governing the British people, arguing that “Parliaments have had a good Eff ect on the People, by keeping them quiet; and the People on Parliaments, by keeping them within Bounds”.40 Parliament enabled politics to be carried out through delib- eration rather than by direct popular action. Consistent with classical notions of democracy, Bolingbroke had rejected “Absolute Democracy” as leading to tyranny and anarchy if it

of sovereignty and the people, which was rare in early eighteenth-century English literature. 35 Nathan Bailey, An Universal Etymological English Dictionary . . . Th e sixth edition, (London 1733). 36 Th omas Dyche, A New General English Dictionary . . . Th e third edition, (London 1740). 37 Pole 1966, 415–416; Langford 1989, 25. 38 Skinner 1974, 95–96. 39 Wilson 1995, 134; Goldsworthy 1999, 176. 40 Bolingbroke, A Dissertation upon Parties; in Several Letters to Caleb D’Anvers, Esq; dedicated to the Right Honourable Sir Robert Walpole. Th e third edition, (London 1735), 158–159. the westminster parliament and the people, – 75 followed “the Will of the whole Community”.41 Instead, he had recom- mended “the Parliamentary Controul of the Crown” by the combined eff orts of democracy and aristocracy,42 a suggestion that was not unlike d’Argenson’s contemporary reasoning in France. In Bolingbroke’s view, there was no threat of the Commons establishing some “Demo- cratical Tyranny”. Th e problem was, on the contrary, that the ministry impeded the possibilities of the Commons to assert its “independent Share in the supreme, legislative Power” by practising corruption and preventing “the Democratical Power of our Constitution” to act as a balance to the Crown and the Lords.43 In Bolingbroke’s description, a strong democratic element in the constitution was thus present in Parliament. For Walpole, Bolingbroke’s extra-parliamentary writings presented a constitutional challenge that he could not ignore. He gave the Com- mons his own defi nition of democracy, providing a model for genera- tions of Whig parliamentarians to come. Importantly, he recognized the existence of a democratic element in the British constitution. Th is view well befi tted a leading parliamentarian with a high respect for the Commons. At the same time, Walpole was highly critical of democ- racy, accusing the opposition of promoting it in a dangerous and extreme form. Th e popular protests of the Excise Crisis had recently forced the ministry to give up its taxation scheme, which was certainly a background factor when Walpole outlined the offi cial and conven- tional understanding of the mixed constitution: It is certain, that ours is a mixt Government, and the Perfection of our Constitution consists in this, that the Monarchical, Aristocratical and Democratical Forms of Government are mixt and interwoven in ours, so as to give us all the Advantages of each, without subjecting us to the Dangers and Inconveniencies of either. Th e Democratical Form of Government, [. . .] is liable to these Inconveniencies, Th at they are gen- erally too tedious in their coming to any Resolution, and seldom brisk and expeditious enough in carrying their Resolutions into Execution: Th at they are always wavering in their Resolutions, and never steady in any of the Measures they resolve to pursue; and that they are oft en involved in Factions, Seditions and Insurrections, which exposes them to be made the Tools, if not the Prey of their Neighbours: Th erefore in all the Regulations we make, with respect to our Constitution, we are to

41 Bolingbroke, A Dissertation upon Parties, 1735, 160. 42 Bolingbroke, A Dissertation upon Parties, 1735, 194, 197. 43 Bolingbroke, A Dissertation upon Parties, 1735, 202, 207. 76 chapter two

guard against running too much into that Form of Government which is properly called Democratical: [. . .] (HPHC, III, 203–205). According to Walpole, the Septennial Act had managed to keep such excesses of democracy under control in the spirit of the mixed con- stitution, whereas the advocates of its repeal would open the gates for a form of democracy that should be regarded as undesirable by every true supporter of the British constitution.44 While the fi rst minister might indirectly recognize the existence of some potentially benefi cial features in democratic systems, he explic- itly rejected pure democracy as a form of rule that was inconsistent with a balanced constitution. He based his argument on the classi- cal tradition of viewing democracy as a potential catalyst for the rise of tyranny. According to him, as a consequence of overly frequent elections, [. . .] there would be so much Power thrown into the Hands of the Peo- ple, as would destroy that equal Mixture, which is the Beauty of the Constitution: In short, our Government would really become a Demo- cratical Government, and might from thence very probably diverge into a tyrannical (HPHC, III, 207). Th e existing level of the democratic element in the British constitu- tion was suffi cient; extending the element of the demos by awarding political power to the people by means of constant elections, as the opposition was suggesting, was highly undesirable. More frequent elections would render government less consistent and effi cient, as the ministry would need to observe not only “the Pulse of the Parliament” but also “the Pulse of the People” before it could decide on anything—much as in the excise question. Further- more, the opposition would abuse constant campaigning by rendering all government measures odious in the eyes of the people even before the government had had a chance to make its case—the Excise Cri- sis once again providing an example. Th e worst scenario was that the opposition might even win an election by such questionable means (HPHC, III, 205). A number of problems would arise out of the well- known tendency of “the Populace” or “the People in general” (the two

44 Th is was well in line with general Court Whig notions of a mixed form of gov- ernment. Dickinson 1977, 144. the westminster parliament and the people, – 77 terms being used synonymously here) to constantly change its mind, thus forcing the government too to change its policy: [. . .] what is called the Populace of every Country, are apt to be too much elated with Success, and too much dejected with every Misfor- tune; this makes them wavering in their Opinions about Aff airs of State, and never long of the same Mind: and as this House is chosen by the free and unbyassed Voice of the People in general, if this Choice were so oft en renewed, we might expect, that this House would be as waver- ing, and as unsteady as the People usually are; and it being impossible to carry on the publick Aff airs of the Nation without the Concurrence of this House, the Ministers would always be obliged to comply, and consequently would be obliged to change their Measures as oft en as the People changed their Minds (HPHC, III, 206). While this statement contained a recognition of the principle of listen- ing to the “Voice of the People” and a formulation of a limited govern- ment in that sense, Walpole insisted that the popular voice should not be sounded too oft en or too attentively. Th e very strength of ministe- rial rule combined with a well managed Parliament was, aft er all, that it was more consistent than the rule of the people.45 A government- centred form of parliamentary rule was clearly not the same thing as outright popular rule. Th e British mixed government, with elections held every seven years, was regarded as ideal by Walpole because it allowed the government to steer the people in a balanced manner: With Septennial Parliaments, [. . .], if the Ministers, aft er having felt the Pulse of the Parliament, which they can always soon do, resolve upon any Measures, they have generally Time enough before the new Election comes on, to give the People a proper Information, in order to shew them the Justice and the Wisdom of the Measures they have pursued; and if the People should at any Time be too much elated, or too much dejected, or should without a Cause change their Minds, those at the Helm of Aff airs have Time to set them Right, before a new Election comes on (HPHC, III, 206). Th e Prime Minister won the division, and the motion to repeal the Sep- tennial Act was rejected. Th is was a signifi cant victory for the Walpole ministry aft er the challenges to its authority in the preceding year.46 Th e idea of appealing more frequently to the people had a considerable

45 For similar arguments in the government press, see Gunn 1983, 79. 46 O’Gorman 1997, 82. 78 chapter two number of supporters in the Commons, but Britain remained a mixed government in which the share of the people in the exercise of political power was eff ectively controlled, among other means, by the organiza- tion of elections every seven years. Th e importance of listening to the voice of the people and the existence of a democratic element in the constitution might be recognized in principle, but the need to keep them in due check was strongly emphasized. In the Royal Speech of 1734, the King’s people was accordingly viewed as the object of the good governance of the King and his min- istry. Th e general elections of that year were described as a chance for “taking again the Sense of my People” so that the new Parliament would communicate “the justice and wisdom of the nation” (IX, 182– 184). Th e Lords added, interestingly, a passing reference to the “liber- ties of the people”, using the word “people” with the defi nite article, and suggesting that they themselves controlled the realization of those liberties (IX, 187), as befi tted an aristocracy. Th is formulation may have been meant to remind the ministry of the political role of the truly relevant people in the aft ermath of the crisis of 1733–1734. Aft er all, Lockean references to natural rights had appeared in election pro- paganda.47 Th e majority of the Commons, by contrast, underlined the shared interests of the monarch and his people, avoiding all challenges to the King and his ministry.

Th e Standing Army and the Rights of the People in the Late 1730s

Th e Royal Speech of 1735 repeated the formula “my Parliament and people”, refl ecting a monarchical notion of both Parliament as an advi- sory body and the political community as subjects of their King (IX, 671). Th e Lords responded by representing the liberties of the nation as intimately linked to the government of George II, despite the oppo- sition claim that such uncritical compliments to the ministry would just “dazzle the eyes of the people” or make them suspicious about Parliament’s ability to infl uence the course of events. Th e ministerial side replied by suggesting that the people would wonder whether the Lords truly appreciated the royal words if their Address took a form diff erent from the Royal Speech (IX, 642–643, 647, 654, 660). In the

47 Wilson 1995, 133. the westminster parliament and the people, – 79

Commons, in words recalling the debate of 1734, Sir William Wynd- ham insisted that the loyalty of the Commons to both the monarch and the people called for a commentary on the Royal Speech and a censure of the foreign policy of the ministry: Th is House is the grand inquest of the nation, appointed to inquire diligently, and to represent faithfully to the king, all the grievances of his people, and all the crimes and mismanagements of his servants; and therefore it must always be a breach of our fi delity to our sovereign, as well as a breach of our duty to his people, to approve blindly the conduct of his servants (IX, 673–674). Th e opposition also suggested that “the majority of the nation” and “the generality of the nation” had views diff ering from those of the ministry. Hence the members of parliament should formulate the Address so as to give “our constituents, the people who sent us hither” proper information about the policies of the ministry (IX, 684, 686– 687). Th e constitutional relationship of the Crown, Parliament and the people thus became a topic indirectly discussed during the debate on the Address of Th anks. In the Royal Speech of 1736, the King’s people (“my people”) appeared consistently as the object of the kind services of the monarch (IX, 971, 985, 990). In the Lords, a noteworthy detail was a discussion on the infl uence of their Address “upon the minds of the people”, on the lower house and on foreign powers. Th e suggestion was that the Address should be interpreted as an expression of the support of the nation for the policies pursued by the ministry (IX, 979–980). When toleration for the Protestant Dissenters became an issue divid- ing the Anglican political establishment during the following year,48 the Royal Speech of 1737 put more emphasis on the joint interests of the monarchical and popular elements of the constitution by emphasizing (without any concretization) the rights and properties of the people (IX, 1273–1274, 1279–1280). Th e Commons used this opportunity to refer to the need of the Crown to consistently observe “the strictest regard to the rights and properties of your people” (IX, 1277–1280). Against this background, the absence of references to the people in the Royal Speech of 1738 deserves some attention. It is partly explained by the recent death of the Queen, but a threat of war with Spain may also have played a role. Th e Lords did not hesitate to remind the Crown of

48 Holmes & Szechi 1993, 7. 80 chapter two their need to maintain not only the welfare of the King’s people but also “the religious and civil rights of your people” (X, 367), the rights being understood collectively, referring perhaps to what the British possessed as a political community when compared with their potential Continental enemies. Likewise, the Commons presented themselves as “representatives of the people of Great Britain”, mainly in expressing the collective condolences of the national community to their King (X, 373–374). However, the opposition also had a message they wanted to convey in opposing spending on a standing army.49 Wat- kin Williams-Wynn insisted that the Commons should “always look upon ourselves as the trustees of the people, and endeavour to speak their sense in our addresses”. He justifi ed the actions of his group by maintaining that among “the representatives of a free people” there should always be an opposition that protected the freedom of debate (X, 370–371). Th e second debate in the 1730s which illustrates contemporary par- liamentary language referring to the people took place on 3 February 1738 and concerned the size of the standing army, to which the rights of the people were opposed. Th e issue of a standing army had been debated ever since the seventeenth century, a professional army hav- ing traditionally been seen as an engine for extending Crown patron- age and even tyranny.50 During this particular debate, some leading speakers also associated the concept of democracy with the issue. Th e implication was once again that there was a democratic element in the British Constitution—but no more than that. Th e starting point was a government proposal to grant a supply for a standing army of 18,000 men. Both sides viewed the issue from the perspective of the rights of the people. George Barclay, Lieutenant- Colonel in the Army, suggested that the ministry had decided “to make themselves feared by the people” by proposing an army of a size that was “dangerous to the liberties of the people” (X, 376). On the government side, William Hay declared, by contrast, that the unfounded dissatisfaction among “the people without doors” required the maintenance of a considerable standing army. Th e army protected the constitution and the parliamentary form of government at a time when the opposition was abusing the freedom of the press, educating

49 Holmes & Szechi 1993, 8. 50 Dickinson 1995, 171. the westminster parliament and the people, – 81 the lower orders in politics and making the people fear the army and suspect their governors (X, 377–379). William Shippen, a known but isolated Jacobite, reminded the House of the expenses of a standing army and its risks for the people’s liberties and suggested that it was the Tories rather than the Whigs who had become the true defenders of the rights of the people (X, 380–382). Th is was the context in which Charles Noel Somerset, a sympathizer of the Jacobite cause, set out to explain to the House “the true and genuine form of our government”, and he included a limited demo- cratic element in his description. Th ough already a defender of the political infl uence of the people against the Whig oligarchy in 1734, Somerset followed the conventions of the mixed constitution, stating in accordance with classical political theory: [. . .] many sorts of governments have been invented by men, all of which may be resolved into these three, to wit, the monarchical, the aristocrati- cal, or the democratical; for every form of government must either be a monarchy, an aristocracy, or a democracy; or it must be a mixture of some two of these, or of all the three. By experience, Sir, it has been found, that when the supreme power is lodged either in a sole monarch, or in a set of nobles, it oft en deviates into tyranny; and that when it is lodged in the people in general, there is no possibility of preventing it from running into anarchy; and the next step which follows is commonly a monarchical or aristocratical tyranny; especially, if the people of the society be numerous, and their dominions extensive (X, 384). Here Somerset was reciting the traditional repudiation of pure democ- racy together with other simple forms of government. Th ere was, in principle, a possibility of the supreme power being placed in the hands of the people at large, but this appeared to be an absurd scenario in an wide empire like that of Britain. It was best to maintain “an equal mixture of the monarchical, aristocratical, and democratical forms of government” inherited by the British from their ancestors, “the Ger- mans”, so that the three independent elements—“with the assistance of the people”—would balance one another if someone attempted to oppress the people. Th e Lords, for instance, would not be able “to set themselves up as sovereign and arbitrary masters of our government” (X, 385–386). Th is statement recognized the democratic element as being equally as important as aristocracy and monarchy in the British constitution. For Somerset, history provided the justifi cation for a representative 82 chapter two government uniting monarchy and Parliament: among the Germans, the supreme power had belonged to “an assembly of their king or gen- eral, their nobles or chiefs of families, and their people or soldiers in general”. Th e people had had the right to accept or reject the proposals of the King and nobles, and this was the political role exercised by the Commons representing “the people [. . .] in general” (X, 385). Th e peo- ple was also given a supportive and opposing role in case two of the elements should try to remove the rights of the people. In a way, they constituted an independent fourth element in Somerset’s scheme. He further suggested that the ministry had achieved an excessive control of Parliament, which had caused such discontent among the people that the constitution was in danger of being destroyed (X, 386, 391). Th e solution was to be found in an increased respect for the political role of the people. Th e government should always [. . .] cultivate and retain the aff ections of our people; and if our people should, from the folly or wickedness of an administration, become gen- erally discontended, the parliament, while it continues free and indepen- dent, will always be able to remove that discontent, by giving satisfaction to the people, [. . .] (X, 394). Walpole himself responded to this challenge of the Jacobite opposition. He recognized the threat that an excessively large standing army of mercenaries, if abused by “some future ambitious king”, might consti- tute for the liberties of the people, probably referring to experiences in the reigns of Stuart kings. He acknowledged Somerset’s constitutional views as “a very just description of our constitution”, but he denied the possibility that a small army of British soldiers would endanger the constitution, maintaining that such an army “would never be suf- fi cient for supporting a government against the united force of the whole people of Great Britain”. Quite the contrary, the army would protect the people against both domestic troubles and foreign inva- sions. Walpole next questioned the motives of the opposition speakers and referred to the threat of Jacobitism, suggesting that “opposition” and “Jacobitism” were identical terms and shared the pernicious goal of persuading the people that the constitution was in danger (X, 395, 398–399, 401).51

51 For similar accusations of Jacobitism in government newspapers, see Wilson 1995, 135. the westminster parliament and the people, – 83

George Lyttelton, a favourite of Prince Frederick, who was fre- quently in disagreement with his father, countered the fi rst minister by emphasizing both the right of the people to legislate and control the administration of a free country and the need to maintain confi - dence between the King and the people. Th is might mean that those responsible for the poor state of the nation could lose their offi ces. Th e opposition, by contrast, should be seen as “the people’s friends in parliament” who were trying to save the country (X, 407, 411, 413– 414). By the late 1730s, this opposition to Walpole had extended well beyond the Jacobites, including men like Lyttelton and future prime ministers from the Pitt and Grenville families. Th e reply of William Yonge, the Secretary at War, to the opposi- tion claims revealed the attitude of the Walpole ministry and further increased the heat of the debate: Th e insolence of the people in all parts of the kingdom is risen to a height that makes it unsafe for the civil magistrate to do his duty without the assistance of the military power (X, 431). In Yonge’s view, “the meaner sort of our people” should be guided to industry and frugality instead of being so ready to complain (X, 432). John Barnard, a country Whig who had supported a campaign of the London merchants against Walpole’s policies towards Spain,52 responded by arguing that magistrates had a duty to make themselves popular, i.e. serve the interests of the people. If they were not popular and were not obeyed by the people, their governance was at fault (X, 434). Th is was an argument that the opposition would develop in the coming years, until the fall of Walpole. William Pulteney reinforced the opposition arguments by claiming that there were legitimate com- plaints among the common people about Walpole’s policies, and that a standing army would never “make a free people quiet subjects” but would rather produce “humble slaves”. Th is opposition leader boldly declared that only a virtuous opposition could save the country (X, 435, 438). Language referring to the people had evidently become a major weapon in the hands of the parliamentary opposition. Walpole felt a need to rebut the claims that his ministry was unpop- ular and even anti-popular by defl ecting the accusation about the ori- gin of the discontent back onto the opposition. In his view, it was

52 Dickinson 1995, 210. 84 chapter two the opposition’s propagation of discontent among the common people that caused them to question the current political order and even to rebel against it. Jacobitism was, once again, the driving force of the opposition, who, in the minister’s view, abused any political problem the nation encountered (X, 442–443). Th e opposition was not yet quite ready to surrender, and the attack was continued by Pulteney, who insisted on the need of every government to preserve the liberties of the people. Indeed, the essence of the constitution was that the inter- ests of the people and those of the establishment were inseparable. If the people were happy with their government, there would exist no chances for the Jacobites to succeed in restoring the House of Stuarts (X, 444). Th e debate of 1738 illustrates the degree to which the inter- ests and opinions of the people had become a major subject of dis- pute in parliamentary debates. Th e opposition presented themselves as defenders of the cause of the people, while the ministry consistently questioned all such claims. Th e public debates of the time on democracy and the political role of the people diff ered little from what we fi nd in parliamentary speak- ing. In 1736, Philip Skelton viewed democracy in highly satirical terms, presenting it as violating the principles of the mixed constitution; democracy would merely allow anyone to behave like a king and to profess whatever religion he liked.53 James Erskine (1679–1754), Lord Grange, an opposition man suspected of Jacobitism, proposed that a free government was preferable to democracy. However, a free gov- ernment could degenerate into “a pure and simple Democracy, where the People have reserved intirely to themselves, both the Supremacy and the Government of the Society”. Democracy might lead to either a civil war or abuses by overly popular magistrates, the fi nal result being the abolition of all free government because the vulgar were unable to understand the common good and see conspiracies against their liberties. Th e fate of the Roman Republic, above all, demonstrated the results of the introduction of excessive democracy in government.54 Th e essence of the British mixed government was that in it “the Supremacy was lodged in the People, (including King and Chiefs) and the Exercise

53 Th e London Magazine, and Monthly Chronologer (London) [1736–1746], Vol. 5, 113. 54 James Erskine, Lord Grange, Th e Fatal Consequences of Ministerial Infl uence: or, the Diff erence between Royal Power and Ministerial Power, Truly Stated . . . (London 1736), 11–12. the westminster parliament and the people, – 85 of the Supremacy, in the general Assemblies of the People”. Grange’s concept of the people thus included all three elements of the mixed constitution, which he saw as an equal combination of “the Democrat- ical, the Aristocratical, and the Monarchical”, albeit one in which the diff erent powers constantly challenged each other and brought about necessary changes.55 In 1736, the monarchical element seemed to have become too dominant because of ministerial infl uence in elections and Parliament.56 Th is opposition claim was put forward most forcefully in Th e Craft sman, which, referring to the seventeenth-century radical thinkers John Locke and Algernon Sidney, suggested that parliamen- tary legislation was no longer based on “the People’s Power”.57 Th e opposition may have presented itself as the champion of the popular cause, but many authors remained suspicious of the abilities of the people at large to rule without a directing authority.58 Democracy was certainly not their programmatic goal. Th e Royal Speeches at the turn of the 1730s and 1740s demonstrate continuity in offi cial conceptualizations of the political role of the peo- ple. While the true interest, advantage and general benefi t of the peo- ple were emphasized in the speech of 1739, the inseparable nature of the interests of the King and the people was also presented as a given fact (X, 874–875). Th e Lords repeated much of this but retained a ref- erence to the collective rights of the people (X, 938). Th e Commons chose to refer to “the just demands and expectations of your Majesty and your people” (X, 961), meaning the defence of the interests of the political community abroad rather than any negotiation between the Crown and the people. Even these formulations did not go without

55 Erskine, Th e Fatal Consequences of Ministerial Infl uence, 1736, 16–18. 56 Erskine, Th e Fatal Consequences of Ministerial Infl uence, 1736, 22. 57 [Anon.], Craft sman, No. 548, 1 January 1737, cited in Th e London Magazine, and Monthly Chronologer, Vol. 6, London, [1736-1746], 13. Also in 1737, an edition of James Harrington’s Oceana was published by John Toland in Dublin. Harrington had written with respect about ancient “popular states” but had had relatively little to say about ‘democracy’ as a realistic form of stable government in the long run, even if he had recognized the hypothetical possibility of democracy being “rightly founded and rightly order’d” or “well-regulated” and lauded the successes of Athens and Florence. In a dialogue, Harrington had even suggested that the government of old Israel had been ordered like in “all other Democracies”. James Harrington, Th e Oceana of James Harrington, Esq; and his other works . . . (Dublin 1737), 38, 512, 573–574. 58 George Berkeley, A Discourse Addressed to Magistrates and men of Authority . . . (Dublin 1738), 16. 86 chapter two controversy at a time when there was a dispute about foreign policy and general unhappiness over the treaty with Spain.59 Among the Tory opposition in the Lords, John Leveson, the Earl of Gower, insisted that the House should inform the King that the mea- sures of the ministry were by no means “agreeable to the sense of the people in general”. According to this respected aristocrat, there was no evidence that “the heads of our ministers are equal to the hearts of our people” (X, 886, 888). On the government side, James, the Earl of Cholmondeley, an offi cer himself, recognized the need to observe “the sense of the people” but rejected direct appeals to the biased people in questions of war. Referring to the campaign of the opposition press, he said that it was inconceivable that [. . .] the sense of the people, or rather a faction of the people, ought to infl uence, far less determine, us in our deliberations about aff airs of which the people have no right information, and which they can only see with the eyes of those whose interest it is to mislead them (X, 909). Like Gower, John Carteret, the Earl of Granville, a leading opposi- tion man and an excellent speaker, saw it as the duty of the Lords to demonstrate “to his Majesty the sense of his people, and to the people the sense of this House.” In other words, the Lords should never make the King believe that the people were happy when they were not; nor should the Lords give the people a wrong impression of their views. A failure to express the discontent of the people would actually undo “the spirit of our people” (X, 917–918). Th e people could no longer trust Parliament if the Lords did not express their dissenting views on the measures of the ministry (X, 923). John Hervey, a public sup- porter of Walpole and a friend of Prince Frederick, saw no reason to make “the people without doors” suspicious of the ministry by stating something unconventional in the Address (X, 930). In the Commons, Walpole himself accused the opposition of deceiving the people with suggestions of an easy victory against Spain (X, 947, 951, 956). Th e debates that followed led to opposition lead- ers walking out and denying, in private correspondence, any connec- tion between “the voice of the House of Commons” and “the sense of the nation”.60 Th e opposition to Walpole certainly knew how to make

59 Holmes & Szechi 1993, 8. 60 Colley 1982, 224–225. the westminster parliament and the people, – 87 political use of allusions to the people, but the political consequences were as yet insignifi cant. Th e declaration of war on Spain in October 1739 forced the parties to reconsider their choice of words. In the Royal Speech, the minis- try repeated a formulation borrowed from the preceding Commons’ Address, underlining “the just expectations of my people” (XI, 82) and implying that, in Britain, the expectations of the people were also heard during wartime. Th e Lords as a whole were entirely loyal in their Address (XI, 81), but individual peers were ready to contest the minis- terial defi nition of the political community. Philip Dormer Stanhope, the Earl of Chesterfi eld, maintained that there was a division in Britain “between the people of one side, and a few of our ministers on the other.” (XI, 43) With the support of John Campbell, the 2nd Duke of Argyll, he further claimed: “In this country, I think, the people and the administration are two terms that are generally made use of as oppo- site to each other.” He said that the unwillingness of the ministry to enter a war against Spain had just deepened the division (XI, 44, 75).61 Th e declaration of war had fi nally brought the two together so that the people had actually prevailed over the ministry (XI, 46). Lord Chancel- lor Philip Yorke, the Earl of Hardwicke, naturally enough rejected the way Chesterfi eld had used the concepts of the people and the ministry as opposites. His conclusion was that, as the ministry had a majority in both houses, it enjoyed the support of the majority of the people (XI, 62). Th is was the spirit of the British constitution as the government interpreted it. Th e Commons, too, used strong constitutional language in its Address. While acknowledging the royal care of the people and the need to defend “the honour of your crown”, they defi ned the Brit- ish monarchy as dependent on Parliament, with the King using “the power granted to you by parliament”. Th e Commons further empha- sized the popular nature of the British system by defi ning themselves as “the representatives of the people in parliament” (XI, 96–97). Th e implication of the Commons Address of 1739 was that the House fully supported the war eff ort provided that this was seen as a joint project of the popular and monarchical elements of the constitution. Th e out- break of war was used to assert the central position of the Commons

61 Argyll even suggested that the ministry had turned into “the enemies of the people”. 88 chapter two in the political system as the voice of the people, probably as a new strategy to justify the policies of the Walpole ministry. In the debates, no constitutional claims were made, which suggests that the Address was intended to be an expression of support for the war policy. In printed literature, opposition criticism of Walpole’s ministry soon took a radical turn. In January 1740, Th e London Magazine published a speech purporting to be an excerpt of recent parliamentary debates but possibly rather a refl ection of what the opposition would have liked to hear the members of parliament argue. Th e author maintained that the people were freest in societies where “the People have been so wise as to reserve in their own Hands the supreme and absolute Power of the Society” and where the Magistrates “are but the Servants of the People”. What was more, he presented a positive interpretation of democracy:62 [. . .] a Democracy is the only Sort of Government, under which the People can be deemed absolutely free; and those mixt Forms of Govern- ment, which have any Th ing of the Democracy in their Constitution, that is to say, where the People reserve in their own Hands any share of the supreme and absolute Power of the Society, the greater the People’s Share is, the more they are to be deemed free; [. . .] Th ere were still limits to such freedom in large societies such as Eng- land, with the possibility of losing all liberty looming in the back- ground. “An absolute free Government or pure Democracy” was not so desirable, as the degeneration of “a Sort of Government absolutely free, commonly called a Democracy” into “an absolute Monarchy” had demonstrated during the Interregnum. Th e recommended form of government continued to be a mixed one provided that the oppor- tunities of the Crown to intervene in the actions of the Commons, the principal element that ensured freedom, were eff ectively curtailed. Th e conclusion was that the people should possess at least “a Part of the supreme Power”, sharing it with the King and the Lords but acting independently of them, just as the provinces in the Netherlands acted independently of each other.63 Th e obvious point was that the Walpo- lean control of the Commons through placemen should be ended. But

62 Th e London Magazine, and Monthly Chronologer (London [1736–1746]), Vol. 9, 2–3, 7, 9. 63 Th e London Magazine, and Monthly Chronologer [1736–1746], vol. 9, 3, 8, 10–11. the westminster parliament and the people, – 89 we also have an unusually appreciative description of democracy here. Despite the mixed views of democracy among ancient and modern political philosophers like Niccolò Machiavelli and Algernon Sidney, democracy was nevertheless seen as welcome provided that aristocracy and monarchy were there to balance it.64 In his speech of 1740, George II also emphasized the combination of the monarchical and popular elements in the constitution, though only with the conventional goal of maintaining “the honour of my crown, and the undoubted rights of my people” (XI, 611). As several opposition leaders had recently passed away or been dismissed, the ministry had no need to make any particular concessions.65 Th e Lords set national unity as the goal, urging: “Your majesty’s government at home must be strengthened in the aff ections and support of your people.” Th ey repeated the royal promise about the rights of the King’s people (XI, 693–694), while the Commons and some lords spoke dur- ing the debate about “the undoubted rights” of the people (XI, 624, 645, 657, 697). John Carteret, an eminent opponent of Walpole, urged Parliament to speak “the language of the people” (i.e. that of its own) instead of the language of the ministry. Choosing the latter alterna- tive because of corruption meant ignoring “the sentiments of the peo- ple”. He argued that while Parliament could change the ministers, it could not change the sentiments of the people. Th erefore, instead of applauding the policy of the ministry, the Lords should preserve their dignity in the eyes of the people and indeed of the monarch by cen- suring it (XI, 681–682). Th e use of references to the people was thus once again made a programmatic part of the opposition to Walpole, and more such language was to come, uttered by Carteret and his allies in both houses.

Th e Prime Minister Challenged by a “Popular Government” in 1741–1742

Th ese statements anticipated the approaching end of Walpole’s ascen- dancy. A major moment in the history of the rise of responsible gov- ernment was witnessed in February 1742, when Walpole was forced

64 Bartholomew Shower, Cases in Parliament Resolves and Adjudged . . . Th e third edition, [London] (1740), preface. 65 Holmes & Szechi 1993, 8–9. 90 chapter two to resign aft er losing his majority in the Commons. Even in February 1741, motions for his removal had been debated in both houses. While descriptions of this event have conventionally focussed on the Com- mons,66 there was actually a more extensive use of allusions to the people in the Lords’ debate. Unlike most other parliamentary reports, Cobbett provides the Lords debate fi rst, which suggests that for the contemporaries it was the primary one. Carteret headed the joint attempt in the Lords, and Samuel Sandys, the Baron of Sandys, in the Commons. Th eir criticism focused on Walpolean foreign policy and on the concentration of power in his hands. Carteret made a better speech, but his motion was defeated in the Lords, and the same hap- pened to Sandys’ motion in the Commons.67 From our point of view, the arguments concerning the political role of the people in the two speeches are of particular interest. Carteret, who had already challenged the Walpole ministry in 1740, opened the debate in the Lords on 13 February 1741 with what he himself recognized as an “extraordinary” motion to remove the fi rst minister from offi ce. As an experienced opponent of the Walpole min- istry, he chose to use a combination of a traditional reference to the need of royal advisors to be generally respected and of a more chal- lenging one derived out of an explicit defi nition of the British political system as a popular government: A weak man is certainly, in any country, very unfi t for being in the king’s counsels: and, in a popular government, a man who has incurred the general odium of the people, ought not to be continued in the king’s counsels, because the unpopularity of the minister may at last aff ect the throne itself, and render the people disaff ected to their sovereign (XI, 1048, 1060–1061). Such a categorical defi nition of the British polity as a popular govern- ment rather than a mere mixed monarchy, even if it was derived from the Roman republican tradition, was unconventional and potentially a conceptual re-evaluation of the constitution. While Carteret empha- sized the role of the people as loyal subjects to the monarch and his government, he left no doubt as to their capacity to withdraw their support not only from an unpopular minister but, indirectly, also from the monarch himself. Th e formulation refl ects a developed understand-

66 Turkka 2007, 35. 67 Cruickshanks 1992, 40–41. the westminster parliament and the people, – 91 ing of the consent of the people as the foundation of all government and it represented a view that had seldom been expressed so clearly in Parliament; indeed this is the fi rst defi nition of England as a “popular government” that I have located in the available records. Nor was the choice of words merely accidental, as Carteret repeated the concept for emphasis. As a leading opposition Whig, he was thus actively defi ning the British polity as a “popular government” and using this defi nition to challenge the long-governing Walpole ministry: If the people be generally dissatisfi ed with the late conduct of our pub- lic aff airs, and if that general dissatisfaction be wholly directed against any one man in the administration, as our government is still, I hope, a popular government, it is a suffi cient cause for this House to let his majesty know the character of his ministry, by an Address to remove him from his counsels (XI, 1064). As Walpole was an “unpopular minister”, he could not continue in the leadership of “a free state” (XI, 1078). Parliament, as the incarnation of the people, must remove him. Th ere were diff erent ways of reporting Carteret’s argument. Accord- ing to an alternative account, authored by Samuel Johnson considerably aft er the actual debate, no mention of “popular government” had been made during it. However, even the traditionalist Johnson, suspicious of popular governments, commented on the eff ective use of references to the people by Carteret. Johnson used the rather more old-fashioned term vox populi.68 According to him, Carteret had pointed out how “the voice of the people [ . . .] ought always to be attended to, and gen- erally to be obeyed” (XI, 1153). Th is formulation did not change the basic argument that much. Th e possibility of the popular element of the constitution to complain about an unpopular minister was merely expressed with alternative phrases such as “the universal cry of the nation”, “the resentment of an unhappy people” and the principle that “a free people have a right of complaining when they feel oppression”. Johnson reported how Carteret had urged the Lords to “set the nation free from its distresses” and to “appease the people” (XI, 1154–1155). All this represented a more traditionalist version of language referring to the people. Johnson also mentioned how Carteret had described the arrogance of Walpole’s policies during the Excise Crisis, his habit of fostering corruption and ignoring the petitions of the people:

68 Gunn has suggested that this term had been increasingly replaced by more mod- ern expressions aft er 1734. Gunn 1983, 273. 92 chapter two

A whole nation was condemned to slavery, their remonstrances were neglected, their petitions ridiculed, and their detestation of tyranny treated as disaff ection to the established government, [. . .] (XI, 1166– 1167). While the concept of popular government remained foreign to John- son, the intimate relationship between the King and the people pro- vided a way of calling for the dismissal of the prime minister. Because of “the general discontent of the people”, Johnson’s Carteret argued, it had become necessary for the “man to whom the people impute their miseries” to retire (XI, 1169). Th e conceptualizations of the pop- ular element in the constitution varied between the diff erent reports, but even in the traditionalist version the sentiments of the people mattered. Th e two reports leave little doubt that Carteret had presented an argument based not only on an abstract notion of a contract between the ruler and the people in the past but also on the active potential of the people to remove unwanted ministers through their parliamen- tary representatives. Th e phrase ”popular government” represented a more republican understanding of the British constitution based on the active consent of the people. Th e use of the concept was certainly innovative in this context, which is probably why Johnson avoided it in his report. Even if we shall never now exactly what Carteret origi- nally said, the fi rst report, which was published immediately aft er the debate, illustrates the central role which the phrase ”popular govern- ment” obviously played in the argument. It was Johnson who edited Carteret’s speech. Language referring to the people also played a role in the rest of the debate, according to both reports. In the early report of the London Magazine, the speeches of Argyll, Hardwicke and Lord Balhurst con- tained more extensive arguments concerning the people and politics. Johnson reported the arguments of several other lords as well. Carteret was seconded by Willoughby Bertie, the 3rd Earl of Abing- don, who was convinced about the integrity of the opinions of the people. Th e people could not be misled in a question of this scale: If we consider the nature of popular opinions on public aff airs, it will be diffi cult to imagine by what means persuasion not founded on truth should universally take possession of a people; [. . .] the multitude, my lords, censure and praise without dissimulation, [. . .]; their voice is at least the voice of honesty, and has been termed the voice of heaven [. . .] (XI, 1170–1171). the westminster parliament and the people, – 93

Abingdon argued that political polemicists hired by the Walpole min- istry had had little eff ect on the opinion of the people, which demon- strated how mere persuasion was not capable of turning the minds of the people (XI, 1171). Th omas Pelham, the later Duke of Newcastle, countered this by conceding that the people never complained with- out cause but suggested that the sources of their diffi culties may have been misunderstood. He opposed the motion because it would only show that the popular protests had been justifi ed and productive (XI, 1173, 1175). Th e implication was that the political elite should not let the potentially gullible common people determine the course of the aff airs of state. Th e Duke of Argyll reiterated Carteret’s points by arguing that both the nation and the King were suff ering under a faction directed by a wicked minister and that such government gave rise to violent popu- lar grievances. According to his interpretation of the nature of the free monarchical constitution, unpopularity justifi ed the dismissal of a minister in a system in which the monarch had to interpret the opin- ion of the people (XI, 1098–1099): [. . .] the very nature of our constitution must convince us, that the pub- lic odium alone is suffi cient cause for the king to dismiss any minister that has drawn it upon himself, because in a free country, the king is to govern by the aff ections of the people (XI, 1100). Th e major problem was that the sentiments of the people—in this case “the general hatred of the people” for a minister—were not communi- cated to the King by his ministers, and hence Parliament should take the initiative to save the King from the risk of losing “the aff ections and esteem of the people” (XI, 1100). Walpole had to go simply because he no longer enjoyed the confi dence of the people. According to Argyll, “the people can never be easy whilst a man is in power who, in their opinion, is a traitor against the laws and constitution of his country” and more particularly so because he himself knew that he was “gen- erally hated by the people” (XI, 1104, 1117). Argyll cited the extent of the current public debate as evidence of widespread dissatisfaction among the people, claiming that only the pamphlets of the opposition sold well (XI, 1102). Th is showed that the people should not be seen as “a herd to be led or driven at pleasure, as wretches whose opinions are founded upon the authority of seditious scribblers, or upon any other than that of reason and experience” (XI, 1184). Argyll’s conclu- sion was that the Lords could satisfy the people only by asking the 94 chapter two

King to dismiss Walpole (XI, 1117). A failure to “attend impartially to the voice of the people” and any negligent attitude towards “the miseries of the people” would, according to his popular rhetoric, be potentially dangerous for the Lords themselves. Th e people should defi nitely not be considered “a herd to be led or driven at pleasure” (XI, 1183–1184). Th e government side was represented in the debate by Hardwicke, the Speaker of the Lords, who recognized the justifi ed demand of the people to have their legal rights protected and saw it as the privilege of the Commons “to watch over the state of the nation”. Th e establish- ment standpoint was, however, that the people were apt to complain even under the best of governments and that the opposition all too eagerly provoked the people to protest over mere trifl es. According to the Speaker, mischievous authors had fabricated the claims that the ministry had “designs against the liberties of the people”. Publicity was to blame, not the ministry: [. . .] in this country [. . .] every man may not only say, but print and publish almost whatever he pleases, and by the willing credulity of the people in such cases, suspicions may be raised and propagated so as to become general, without the least foundation; and therefore, those gen- eral rumours or suspicions can never be a proper or just foundation for any resolution in parliament, [. . .] (XI, 1119–1120, 1126, 1194). Suggestions based on opposition prejudices tended to be widely accepted and were now “echoed back from the people to the parlia- ment.” (XI, 1199) It was, according to the government view, the par- liamentary opposition who had abused the press and caused the entire crisis. Lord Balhurst was the third opposition speaker who put forward far-reaching arguments based on the principle that all political author- ity was ultimately derived from the people. In his view, the people con- trolled the actions of the government essentially through Parliament: It is the essential quality, the distinguishing character of a free govern- ment, that the conduct of every minister and magistrate ought, and may be strictly and impartially enquired into, by the assembly of the people (XI, 1137). Th e Lords thus wielded the use of this controlling power that was typi- cal of free government, indeed of popular government. Th e demands of the people—as interpreted by the opposition—were impossible to ignore as the people did not err in questions of this magnitude. the westminster parliament and the people, – 95

According to Balhurst, the integrity of the British people could be counted on: [. . .] I will venture to become an advocate for the people of England; I will venture to assert, that no general suspicion was ever raised among them without a just ground; that they never complained of any trouble they were put to, if it was really necessary for their own protection; [. . .] (XI, 1138). Th e fourth opposition lord to defend the constitutional status of the people was Henry Howard, the Earl of Carlisle. He understood the Lords as working simultaneously in cooperation with the King and the people while maintaining a balance between the two sides. His conclusion in this particular case was simple: “[I]t is our duty, as well as our right, to address the throne, that a minister should be removed who fears the people” (XI, 1203). Th e logic of the removal of an unpopular minister was that already proposed by Carteret, i.e. that suspicions against the minister endangered “the happiness of the people”, the goal of all government. A threat of “popular fury” called on the Lords to take action that would be favourable to all sides. Th e Lords were, aft er all, a hereditary council capable of conveying to the monarch “the sentiments of the people, without danger and without fear.” (XI, 1203–1204) Th e Lords had a major role in a system that was, ultimately, a popular government. Such a sympathetic view of the people as the source of government was by no means generally held. Th e Earl of Cholmondeley, repre- senting the aristocratic view from the government side, appealed to historical precedents. According to him, it was no more than “an acknowledgement of the insuffi ciency of arguments, when the people is called in to second them, and they are only to expect success from the violence of multitudes.” (XI, 1205). Th e political role of the people was not irrelevant for Cholmondeley, however: he recognized that their advantage, liberty and virtue should be looked aft er but this did not mean the adoption of popular direction in politics: Th at all government is instituted for the happiness of people [indefi nite form], that their interest ought to be the chief care of the legislature, that their complaints ought patiently to be heard, and their grievances speedily redressed, are truths well known, generally acknowledged, and, I hope, always predominant in the mind of every lord in this assembly. But, that the people cannot err, that the voice of same is to be regarded as an oracle, and every murmur of discontent to be pacifi ed by a change of measures, I have never before heard, or heard it only to disregard it (XI, 1205). 96 chapter two

Th e people tended to complain, but that was not to be made the guid- ing star of government: [. . .] it is no reproach to the people that they cannot be the proper judges of the conduct of the government, so neither are they to be censured when they complain of injuries not real, and tremble at the apprehen- sion of severities unintended (XI, 1206). Now that “the general voice of the nation” seemed to have risen against Walpole, the duty of Parliament consisted in “reforming the errors and regulating the heat of the people” rather than voting against the minister. Cholmondeley turned to a judicial analogy describing the proper place of the people within the British political system: Th e utmost claim of the people is to be admitted as accusers, and some- times as evidence, but they have no right to sit as judges, and to make us the executioners of their sentence (XI, 1208). In other words, Parliament should act independently of such an aggrieved people. George Montagu Dunk, the Earl of Halifax, was the last lord to take a stand in the controversy. He did not “conceive the people infallible” but was assured that, in an issue like the one at hand, the people sel- dom erred. If the people were miserable, they had to be able to give expression to their grievances, and the Lords had to take measures to relieve them. Joining the advocates of popular government who chal- lenged Walpole, Halifax repeated the point that Walpole’s major fail- ure had been his inclination “to oppress and ridicule the people, to plunder them, and set them at defi ance.” (XI, 1208–1210). Th e Lords debate already reveals highly diverging understandings of the political role of the people, with the opposition making use of extensive appeals to the people to challenge Walpole. A similar con- frontation was seen in the Commons. While the formulations in the two available reports are diverse, appeals to the sentiments of the peo- ple are present in both of them. Th e London Magazine reported how Samuel Sandys, just like Cart- eret, built his proposal for the removal of Walpole on an interpreta- tion of the role of the people in various forms of government. His formulation was based on his admiration of mixed government and the extension of the originally aristocratic Magna Charta to concern the people more generally: the westminster parliament and the people, – 97

Sir; among the many advantages arising from our happy form of gov- ernment, there is one which is reciprocal to king and people, which is, a legal and regular method by which the people may lay their griev- ances, complaints, and opinions, before their sovereign; [. . .] In absolute monarchies, the people may suff er, they may complain, but though their suff erings be public, their complaints must be private: they must not so much as murmur against their king’s measures and ministers; [. . .]. As members of this House, Sir, we are obliged to represent to his majesty, not only the grievances but the sentiments of the people, with regard to the measures he pursues, and the persons he advises with or employs in the executive part of our government: [. . .] (XI, 1224–1228). In such a reciprocal alliance between the monarch and the people, the political signifi cance of the people and the responsible nature of gov- ernment became undeniable. In the rest of his speech, Sandys analysed the numerous causes of the prevalent “popular discontent”, endeavour- ing to demonstrate that Walpole’s policies both at home and abroad had been so unpleasing “to the generality of the people” in and outside Parliament that they had brought “the curses of the people” on the prime minister. Th e Commons was, according to Sandys, representing “the sentiments of the people” to their King, it being evident that “a free people neither will nor can be governed by a minister they hate or despise”. No doubt was left as to the popular challenge to Walpole: In Sandys’ (probable) words, he had entered the ministry “with the gen- eral disapprobation of the people”, had never understood “the genius of our people” and by his policies had endangered “the liberties of the people”. Like Carteret, Sandys counted on the willingness of the King to retain “the aff ections of his people” by dismissing such a despised minister (XI, 1229–1230, 1241). Th is was a forceful argument that has been seen as moulding the history of parliamentarism.69 Even Johnson could not change the basic content of the argument in his more revised report: His Sandys was likewise a champion of the people as the source of political authority. However, Johnson’s Sandys would seem to have spoken more in the name of a Parliament that derived its authority from the people, not for a politically active people as such: [. . .] the authority of parliament is yet acknowledged though it has been long eluded; the people are still allowed to be the source of authority, though the authority which they have granted has been long used only

69 See Turkka 2007, 28, 35, 220. 98 chapter two

to injure and oppress them; [. . .] power which is established by our con- stitution as the superintendent of our government, and the guardian of our rights, [. . .] (XI, 1304). Even Johnson’s report communicated Sandys’ arguments that the power of Walpole’s ministry had been “in opposition to the interest and the voice of the people” and that the opposition was “animated by the general voice of the nation”. Johnson’s Sandys concluded his appeal to the wishes of the people by stating: “Th e people [. . .] desire a change not of their sovereign, but of his minister” (XI, 1308, 1312, 1321). Such a recognition of “the people” as “the source of authority” was certainly voiced in the Commons, and it was obviously shared by a considerable section of the political elite. Th e reports provide diff ering information about the reactions of the audience to Sandys’ speech yet leave no doubt as the centrality of the concept of the people in argumentation on both sides. James Hamilton, Lord Limerick, continued Sandys’ criticism by claiming that Walpole’s policies were leading to slavery for the people (XI, 1327). William Pitt the Elder argued that discontent among the people alone was a suf- fi cient reason to dismiss Walpole; for the government to be successful, it was essential that the people should believe that its liberties were safe (XI, 1363–1364). William Heathcote likewise suggested that “the general hatred of the people” and potential decrease in their aff ection for the King were enough for Walpole to be dismissed (XI, 1366). Th e government side could hardly deny the signifi cance of the opin- ion of the people, but they could always try to explain it away in an attempt to save Walpole. Phillips Gybbon simply denied the truth of accusations that Walpole had corrupted Parliament, which remained, in his view, “that assembly to which the rights of the people are intrusted” (XI, 1334). Stephen Fox, like Walpole many times before, presented the opposition as responsible for having aroused the people with their anti-government and downright anti-Hanoverian propa- ganda. Th e interpretation of Parliament as the representative of the people having been incorporated in this way into the liturgy of the Whig establishment, it was impossible for Fox to accept opposition suggestions that the Commons did not represent the true sentiments of the people. He considered it totally outrageous to represent the Commons as “a herd of slaves hired to drudge for their master, and to give up to his disposal the rights, the properties, and lives of their fellow-subjects”. Such a claim appeared to him to be merely a desper- the westminster parliament and the people, – 99 ate attempt by a “faction [. . .] to disturb the happiness and corrupt the loyalty of the people” (XI, 1337, 1354, 1358). John Howe elaborated on this interpretation, insinuating that the opposition had “alienated the people from the government, and fi lled the nation with distrust, suspicion, and resentment”. Furthermore, they had “fl attered the passions and corrupted the opinions of the people”, so that any constituency tended to view itself as capable of dictating its will to Parliament and the nation at large, blaming the ministry for any imaginable trouble that might emerge (XI, 1364–1365). In other words, the opposition seemed to be campaigning for an imperative mandate that would question the authority of Parliament in the face of popular demands. In contrast, Howe defi ned the balancing consti- tutional role of the Commons, in much the same way as that of the Lords had been defi ned by the government side. Th e essence of the argument was a distinction between the people as a whole and the representative body. Not all political power was to be understood as invested in Parliament: Th e business [. . .] of the parliament is to hold the balance between the court and the people, and to preserve at once the dignity of the crown, and the rights of the nation; nor are we to suff er the servants of the king to be torn from him by popular fury, any more than the liberties of the people to be sacrifi ced to the ambition of a minister (XI, 1365). In this confi guration, both houses were equal mediators between the monarch and the people and not mere advocates of the cause of the people. Howe’s interpretation also considerably limited the constitu- tional relevance of popular opinion. According to him, popular dis- contents were a common but mostly unfounded phenomenon caused by factors that no ministry could remove (XI, 1365). Th e strongest argument in support of Walpole was presented by Th omas Pelham, a rising Whig leader and future minister, who pointed at two weaknesses in the opposition claims. As befi tting an establishment Whig, Pelham presented it as a major strength in a minister not to be “the minion of the mob” trying to entertain “the populace”, which “in all countries love to be diverted with changes, and astonished with extraordinary events” (XI, 1246). Here he was expressing the classical notion of the nature of the common people. As the populace was always fi ckle in its opinions, no excessive weight should be laid on their views, particularly as there was no evidence that Walpole had lost the confi dence of the truly respectable people who alone needed to be represented in Parliament: 100 chapter two

[. . .] that this gentleman has incurred the hatred of the better sort of people in general, I believe, will appear to be a mistake, [. . .] for as the members of this House are their representatives, [. . .] (XI, 1246). With these words, Pelham expressed the fact that only the higher ranks were represented by the Commons, and argued that the system of representation refl ected the opinions of those people to a suffi cient degree. Pelham had a further argument against the compliance of Par- liament with the assumed opinion of the people. Even if all the people were dissatisfi ed with Walpole, their opinions were not to be depended upon because the people, even those of the better sort, are but very bad judges of a man’s virtue or wisdom, and they are much worse judges of a minister’s conduct in political aff airs; [. . .] (XI, 1246). Th e people of all orders simply lacked the capacity for evaluating the performance of a leading statesman, and hence it was inappropriate to condemn the policies of a minister “for no other reason but because it is complained of by the majority of the people”. According to Pel- ham, such a procedure would violate the spirit of the constitution by questioning the principle that the King should freely choose the best possible advisors. Th e British constitution was not a republican one, and hence the supervision of the ministers was not to be carried out directly by the people but through “the attachment of the people to their king” and the combined supervision of the monarch and Parlia- ment over the ministry (XI, 1246–1247, 1253–1254). Th ese views of a major statesman suggest that the British form of government was not yet purely parliamentary—even if the Whigs would later be on forced to change Walpole for Pelham. Pelham’s speech provoked John Barnard—a member of parliament elected by the votes of tradesmen and minor merchants rather than those of the Whig elite, and a major advocate of colonial war—to for- mulate the views of the opposition more explicitly and also to take up the question of the state of representation of the people. Barnard could not concur with Pelham’s claim that “the sentiments of the majority of the better sort of people in the nation” were seen in “what appears to be the sentiments of the majority of this House”. Such a view was unsustainable as a consequence of “how unequally the nation is rep- resented in this House” (XI, 1256). On the contrary, Barnard argued, “[T]he sentiments of the majority of the better sort of people are oft en very diff erent from what appears to be the sentiments of the majority the westminster parliament and the people, – 101 of this House” (XI, 1256). As a consequence, Walpole’s policies had actually been “disapproved of by a great majority of the better sort of people in the nation, though not by a majority of this House” (XI, 1257). Barnard did not hesitate to mention the obvious fact that the Whig oligarchy no longer followed the seventeenth-century maxim Vox populi est Vox Dei but instead rejected the views of “the populace, or what ministers and their friends call the mob” (XI, 1257). Any opponent could then be dismissed as a voice of the insignifi cant com- mon people. Such a ministerial attitude was dangerous, however, as it was unlikely that “the better sort” would continue to support the government while “the populace, or meaner sort” were unhappy with it. Barnard’s assumption of the unanimous nature of the sentiments of the people was based on the obvious fact that “the populace [. . .] are servants, and, unless when agitated by some fl ash of enthusiastical madness, speak the sentiments of the better sort.” (XI, 1257) Further- more, “the meaner sort, or the mob” would hardly protest without an initiative coming from their masters, and therefore a good minister will always [. . .] aim at popularity, even amongst the meanest sort of people, because from them he may most certainly learn his real character among those of the better sort (XI, 1257). Barnard went on to characterize a popular government, arguing that there was no problem involved in the willingness of the people to change ministers frequently. Indeed, in a free country, such changes were “necessary for the security and preservation of the rights and liberties of the people” (XI, 1257). He added a loyal monarchical jus- tifi cation for the replacement of Walpole. Walpole was to be replaced by the King to ensure a new parliament that was sympathetic to the Hanoverians: [. . .] if there be any connexion between the sentiments of the majority of this assembly, and the sentiments of the people; if we are to judge of the sentiments of the people, by what appears to be the sentiments of the majority of this assembly, we may on the other hand, judge of what will be the sentiments of the majority of the next parliament, from what are the present sentiments of the people; and if the majority of next parlia- ment should consist of such as have the same opinion of this minister as the people generally have, can his majesty expect any confi dence from such a parliament? (XI, 1259–1260). 102 chapter two

Th e suggestion was that the ruler would do better to listen to the wishes of the people at large and sack the prime minister in order to prevent his opponents—including Jacobites—from being elected to the Com- mons. An even worse scenario was that the composition of the new parliament would be determined by means of corruption instead of by free elections. A majority created with corruption would hardly respect “the liberties and privileges of the people” at all (XI, 1260). Th is would have meant that “an unpopular minister, or one who fears the resentment of the people” would gain “a corrupt majority in par- liament” (XI, 1268). In the arguments of the opposition, as voiced by Barnard, the spirit of popular government spoke strongly in favour of Walpole being removed from offi ce. Walpole himself, aware of his gradually diminishing majority, chose to focus on practicalities rather than attempting to respond to the accusations that the sentiments of the people were against him. Deny- ing the facts, he repeated the government stand that his ministry had taken the views of the respectable people into account: [. . .] all the objections now made to the conduct of the administration, have been already answered to the satisfaction of a majority of both Houses of Parliament, and, I believe, to the satisfaction of a majority of the better sort of people in the nation (XI, 1289–1290). Walpole represented the opposition complaints as wholly unfounded. For him, it remained impossible to concede that the opinion of the people as a whole had political relevance or to believe that the major- ity of the Commons, which he had toiled so hard to secure, no longer necessarily supported him. Walpole did not yet fall in February 1741. In May of that year, how- ever, as a result of a nationwide campaign against his management of the war against Spain, his ministry lost a considerable proportion of its support in a general election. Th e War of the Austrian Succes- sion was turning into a disaster, with military defeats and royal sup- port for Hanoverian possessions that was contrary to British interests. Th e opposition was successful in suggesting that the “universal voice of the people” was dissatisfi ed with the policies of the ministry.70 In these circumstances, the ministry used printed propaganda to attack opposition claims based on the maxim Vox populi vox Dei, the sug-

70 Black 1990, 43–44; Holmes & Szechi 1993, 9; Dickinson 1995, 212; Wilson 1995, 161. the westminster parliament and the people, – 103 gestion being that the popular voice in this case was merely the voice of a faction.71 An anonymous author suggested that any attempts to increase the relative power of the people in the constitution violated the principles of the Revolution of 1688.72 In a Speech from the Th rone in December, the Walpole ministry continued to ignore their loss of a majority in Parliament, referring conventionally to the need of the Crown to observe the sentiments of the King’s people as communicated by their representatives (XII, 221). Th e Lords, anticipating coming challenges, responded by reminding the executive power more bluntly about the need to hear “the ardent wishes of your people” as a way of securing “the loyalty and aff ections of your people” (XII, 289). Th e Duke of Argyll argued that “the voice of the people” indicated the existence of widespread discontent in the nation and emphasized the need for “a mutual confi dence between the government and the people.” According to this opposition lord, the proposed Address would give up “the rights of the nation” if it refrained from criticizing the war policy (XII, 269, 275, 283). Th e Address of the Commons made no reference to the people, probably because of the activities of Walpole’s supporters in formu- lating the response, but even Trevor who seconded the motion empha- sized the dignity of the members of parliament as the Representatives of the People of Great Britain, a People whose Birth- right gives them a Claim to approach their Sovereign, [. . .] with Lan- guage, which absolute Monarchs never hear from the Slaves by whom they are surrounded (HPHC, XIII, 23). Th e formulation was close to that used by Sandys in February when he proposed a motion against Walpole. Among the opposition members, William Shippen appealed to the duty of the Commons “to give such Advice as may most truly inform his Majesty of the Sentiments of his People, and most eff ectually establish in the People an Adherence to his Majesty”. Th e new Parliament, aft er all, off ered the King “an Opportunity of knowing the Opinions of their People without Dis- guise” (HPHC, XIII, 29–30).

71 [Briton], Public Clamours Traced to Th eir Original Sources . . . (London 1741), 13–14. 72 [Anon.], Th e True Principles of the Revolution Revived and Asserted. Being a Defence of the Present Administration . . . (London 1741), 14. 104 chapter two

Walpole’s ministry was replaced by a new coalition in February 1742. Arguments based on the concept of the popular authority of all government—together with several other arguments in favour of responsible government—had thus demonstrated their ability to per- suade the majority of the British political establishment. Aft er 1742, the politically potent concept of the people remained the preserve of the parliamentary opposition. It is probable therefore, that its use was curtailed, successfully, by the following Whig ministries for at least another two decades.

Views on the Excessive and Insuffi cient Power of the People in the 1740s

In November 1742, another year of the War of the Austrian Suc- cession caused the Pelham-Carteret ministry and its parliamentary majority to emphasize the defence of the national community in the Royal Speech, and all references to the people were avoided (XII, 832). Such a tactic was logical aft er the recent outburst of language referring to the people, the failed Tory attempt to repeal the Septennial Act, and the meagre progress made in the project to investigate Walpole’s administration and to reform Parliament.73 In the Lords, Philip Dor- mer, the Earl of Chesterfi eld (later Stanhope), would have liked the House to defend “the interest of his people” in clearer terms (XII, 844). John Pane (1686–1762), the Earl of Westmorland, a leading Jacobite, claimed that “the general voice of the people” demanded an inquiry into the extension of corruption during the Walpole administration and the ministries (XII, 849–850). In the Commons, the Whig leaders of the House managed to prevent any excessive use of language referring to the people. Th e only excep- tions were individual opposition members like Major John Selwyn, who reminded his audience of the struggle of previous parliaments for the liberties of the people. He combined the concepts of ‘Parlia- ment’ and ‘sovereignty’ in an unconventional manner, arguing that it was necessary that Parliament “[let] in the eye of sovereignty upon all the public calamities of the state, and [shew] a becoming vigilance for the preservation of our ancient rights and privileges” (XII, 866). Even

73 Holmes & Szechi 1993, 10; Wilson 1995, 165. the westminster parliament and the people, – 105 here, sovereignty was not necessarily invested in Parliament alone but rather in the King, whom Parliament was supposed to inform about the state of the national community. Barnard, the fi ercest spokesman of the opposition during the February 1741 debate, again reminded the Pelham ministry that corruption was likely to make the people suspicious of all government (XII, 868). Th e policies of the Pelham ministry remained unchanged in 1743 in that no references to the political role of the people were made in the Speech from the Th rone. Instead, the collective national inter- est was defended (XIII, 101) at a time when the King’s battles on the Continent were becoming increasingly expensive and unpopular.74 Offi cially, both houses were content with the ministerial formula- tions, which described the war as just and necessary for “glory to your majesty, and honour to this nation” (XIII, 231). In the debates of the Commons, Britain was commonly viewed as a national community engaged in war and led by a strong monarch. Only an experienced opposition man such as George Lyttelton complained about the min- istry not having sought the unanimous support of the Commons or “the general approbation of the people.” (XIII, 186). Th ere was rising criticism, too, of the running of the war by Car- teret, the Secretary of State for the North.75 Aft er France had entered the war, the ministry chose in November to once again refer to “the true interest of my people”, defi ned as analogous with that of the Crown and concerning fi rst and foremost international politics (XIII, 983, 993). Th e war with France was such a unifying experience for the British political community that even a ritual discussion of the prin- ciples of the political system was regarded as inappropriate in both houses that year. A further instance of a specifi c Commons debate in which popular government became a topic of discourse concerned a motion for a change in the government of the City of London. Th rough the motion, the opposition aimed at the removal of the veto of the aldermen in the decision-making of the City. Th is was part of a broader campaign by London merchants for a constitutional reform.76 Th e debate, taking place before the outbreak of the Jacobite Rebellion later in 1745, gave

74 Holmes & Szechi 1993, 10. 75 Holmes & Szechi 1993, 10. 76 Dickinson 1995, 210–211. 106 chapter two rise to an interesting discussion on the popular element in the consti- tution. It is noteworthy that an anonymous tract had recently viewed democracy in appreciative terms as a form of government that secured the liberty—even the “perfect freedom”—of the people, provided that property was equally distributed and a degree of noble counselling to the multitude was allowed. Th e author had suggested that a nation where democracy prevailed could be fl ourishing, prosperous and suc- cessful, just as Rome had been under “the people’s infl uence, in the management of aff airs.”77 Th e implicit message was that the Whig oli- garchy was monopolizing state offi ces and excluding the people from their proper share in the government. Th e Roman model provided a vehicle for advancing such a challenging argument. Such polemics hardly aff ected the views of the establishment. In Feb- ruary 1745, Pelham, as a leading minister and manager of the Com- mons, consistently opposed the above-mentioned motion, presenting it as one favoured mainly by “the people out of doors”. He, too, turned to Roman history, in order to demonstrate the point that the populace was always willing to see its share in government enlarged yet unable to make benefi cial use of its power. According to Pelham, “No free state ever long endured, where the populace had any great share in the government.” Such a state would be troubled by parties and factions. Furthermore, “the vulgar”—being unable to foresee the consequences of their passions for their interests—would allow some party leader to take over arbitrary power and abolish the free government (XIII, 1129).78 Pelham used history to make the point: in Rome, with the creation of a republic, the people had received “a very great share in the government”—but only in appearance in that the patricians had retained their infl uence over the people’s choices of magistrates. Popu- lar leaders had, however, stirred up them to seek more power, which had caused a decrease in the infl uence of the patricians and a rise in the licentiousness of the people. Once the people had gained power, they had chosen the idols of the popular party as their magistrates and,

77 [Anon.], An Essay on Civil Government. In Two Parts . . . (London 1743), 19–22. 78 Pelham had, of course, a plethora of classical authorities to base his argument on. Suitably for his purposes, a brand new translation of an anonymous commentary on Sallust was available, containing critical comments on popular states of all kinds. Factions, struggles, changes, calamities, the loss of liberty and fi nally tyranny appeared as the only results of the people becoming involved in government and introducing a “wild Power in the Many”. Sallust, Th e Works of Sallust, Translated into English. With Political Discourses upon that Author . . . (London 1744), 190. the westminster parliament and the people, – 107 before long, one of them, Julius Caesar, had abolished the liberties of the people (XIII, 1129–1130). According to Pelham, the Roman instance indisputably demon- strated the consequences of excessive popular power. To avoid this destiny, the British form of government called for a senate or assembly of nobles “vested with a power to give a check to the extravagances of the people” and thus maintain its liberty. Th e Commons provided the people “with a suffi cient power to prevent their being oppressed”, while the Lords balanced any extravagancy in the pursuit of power. Th e nearly perfect system had failed only once, during the Civil Wars, when “the people, by means of their representatives in this assem- bly, having got the whole power of the government in their hands, murdered the king, overturned the constitution of their country” and fi nally succumbed to arbitrary rule (XIII, 1132–1133). On the basis of the Roman and English precedents, the fi rst minister concluded that it was utterly dangerous in a free state “to lodge a great power, without any controul, in the people, or in any popular assembly”. Th is prin- ciple also concerned the government of the City of London, particu- larly as any “popular madness or frenzy” in the capital might lead to a national disaster (XIII, 1133–1134). Barnard, the usual defender of the popular cause in the Commons and a major advocate of the motion being debated, countered the government by recommending a better regard for “the opinion of the public” (XIII, 1138). According to him, it was ministerial corruption and a decrease in political virtue among the establishment that threat- ened the balance of power in England, not any usurpation of power by the people. Th e attitude of the governing elite constituted a further dimension of the current constitutional problem: Th ose who have been taught and accustomed to vilipend the knowledge, the judgement, or the discretion of the people in the exercise of power, may, perhaps, think, that the liberties of a country may be endangered by lodging too much power in the hands of the people, or what we in this country call the commons; but this can never be the case, as long as the nobles and the chief families among the commons preserve so much as the appearance of any virtue or public spirit among them (XIII, 1139–1140). Barnard described how the balance between the people and the nobil- ity could be retained as long as the nobility remained virtuous. If they lost virtue, a popular leader might take over, as the people would then prefer an absolute monarchy to an absolute oligarchy. Such a 108 chapter two

development could take place even within a seemingly free govern- ment with a parliament chosen by the people if the elections were governed by corruption (XIII, 1140–1141). Barnard insisted that the fall of the constitution during the Civil Wars had followed not from too much power being given to the people but from the lack of virtue among the nobility and their consequent loss of infl uence among the people (XIII, 1144). Th is remained true in 1745 as well: the liberties of the people would not be threatened by “any power that may be lodged in the hands of the people” provided that the political elite remained virtuous. Quite the contrary, the best way to preserve liberty was that of “lodging in as many hands as possible the exercise of those pow- ers and privileges vested in the people”. Such a method would make it impossible for the ministry to bribe all the decision-makers (XIII, 1145–1146). In this way, Barnard turned the historical precedents from Rome and the English Commonwealth into an apology for a popular government. Th e ministry obviously did not share Barnard’s views. William Yonge, the Secretary at War, challenged Barnard’s interpretation of Britain as a popular government. At the same time, his use of the phrase “popular government” demonstrates that by 1745 the concept had become established in parliamentary language. While express- ing concern that popular government could turn into an undesirable political system, if not kept within its due bounds, Yonge referred to popular government three times in his speech. His argument was, however, that the suggested reform would only add to Britain’s noto- riety as an unstable political community:79 [. . .] under a popular government, the people will always be turbulent, inconstant, and unsteady, [. . .]; and the more popular the form of gov- ernment is, the more turbulent the people will be, the more inconstant and unsteady their public measures. When the people have the govern- ment in their hands, they will be always fl ying from one extreme to the other; for as there is no perfect happiness in human aff airs, nor any form of government, or public regulation, but what is attended with inconve- niences, a great majority of mankind think only of the inconveniences they feel, and to get free of them, they fl y to the contrary extreme, [. . .] It is for this reason, that absolute monarchies are more steady in their pursuits, and more fi xed in their public regulations, than popular

79 Th is speech was reported in Th e London Magazine, and Monthly Chronologer in May 1746 aft er a delay of over a year. (London) [1736-1746], Vol. 15, 224–228. the westminster parliament and the people, – 109

governments; and of all sorts of government, those called aristocracies are the most steady and constant, especially if the number of their nobles be but small, and but a very few of them entrusted with the supreme direction of public aff airs; for if their nobility be very numerous, and all have a share in the supreme government of their country, they fall under the same inconveniences to which a popular government lies exposed (XIII, 1155). Yonge was thus highly sceptical of the abilities of the people to gov- ern. His ideal was an aristocratic form of government with a limited number of aristocrats participating in governance. Any democratic principles of government seemed to lead to excesses. Interestingly, Yonge also placed the British constitution in the Euro- pean context, which he knew well. Venice, the Dutch Republic and Poland were the countries with which the British system could be compared. Yonge thus did not view the British constitution as unique but as related to several aristocratic regimes. He depicted Venice positively, acknowledging its stability, although the Dutch Republic provided an even better example of a stable polity as a result of an aristocratic government in which “the people have no share”. Poland, by contrast, was not to be imitated as its form of government with a large aristocracy was incapable of making any decisions. According to the British Secretary at War: “In all countries where their form of government is too popular, they are never at peace within themselves” (XIII, 1155–1157). Yonge could not reconcile excessive popular power with his ideal of a balanced government. In the case of London, the proposed decrease of the power of the aristocratic aldermen would produce “all the inconveniencies of a too popular form of govern- ment” (XIII, 1157). George Heathcote, himself a wealthy merchant and alderman from London, continued to defend the suggested reform and popular power in general, referring to the need to save liberty from what he saw as growing monarchical power. For Heathcote, all Continental regimes appeared as equally productive of slavery in comparison with the sta- tus of the British as “a brave and a free people”. He did not care if the rest of Europe regarded the British as “a turbulent and unsteady people” because of their free government, as this simply meant that the British were ready to defend themselves against any ministry that threatened their liberties. Walpole’s administration provided a model case in that once a previous “idol of the people” had started to jeopar- dize liberty he had been stopped by the people (XIII, 1161–1162). As 110 chapter two for the current ministry, Heathcote implied that there was a general tendency among those aiming at arbitrary power to “rail at popular power, and to load all numerous popular assemblies with faction, sedi- tion, turbulence, unsteadiness, and I do not know how many other bugbears” (XIII, 1170). He himself was in favour of strengthening the popular dimension of the British government at all levels, including the government of London: [. . .] I hope, this House will take care to leave as much power in the hands of the people as may be suffi cient for preserving their liberties; and when we fi nd, that the power of the people has, by the arts and insinuations of ministers, been so much diminished as not to be a proper balance for the power of the crown, we ought, and, I hope, we always shall take care to increase the one, and diminish the weight of the other. When I consider our ancient constitution, and refl ect upon the great power formerly lodged in the hands of the people, I am really surprised, Sir, to hear any gentleman talk of the danger of throwing too much power into their hands. Th e power of the people! alas, Sir! they have scarcely any power left . Th e crown has already ingrossed the greatest part of what the people were possessed of by the ancient constitution of our government (XIII, 1170–1171). Heathcote’s interpretation of the ancient constitution not only defended the power of the people but also represented the necessary popular element as being endangered by the current Whig oligarchy. Consequently, he argued in favour of the liberation of “the power of the people” or “the people’s power” from excessive domination by the Crown in elections and the work of Parliament. Th e people seemed to have been constantly losing their power and the possibility to vote freely for their representatives in the Commons. London was, accord- ing to Heathcote, one of the few cities in which the people could still infl uence politics in accordance with the ancient constitution (XIII, 1171–1172). Th is speaker had a clear plan for extending popular infl u- ence in politics, starting with London: [. . .] it is our business in this House, to attend in the most serious man- ner to the ebbings and fl owings of the people’s power, and to restore it, as oft en as we fi nd it has been too much diminished by any rash or ill-judged regulation; . . . (XIII, 1172). It is hardly surprising that the opposition failed to win a majority for their plans to reform the government of London, but they managed to present their arguments in favour of popular government clearly in the Commons. Th e concept ‘the power of the people’ understood the westminster parliament and the people, – 111 in the active sense of a factor that aff ected the constitution of parlia- ments evidently existed in parliamentary discourse by the mid-1740s. Th e Jacobite Rebellion of 1745, however, curtailed the radicalization of defences of the people’s power for years to come. Indeed, it is not until two decades later that recorded parliamentary debates contain an equal number of references to the political role of the people as before 1745. One explanation for the standstill is the confl icts of the time; others include the stability of government and restrictions on parliamentary reporting. Even so, Speeches from the Th rone and related debates hint at some existing disagreements over constitutional questions. In October 1745, when the foreign wars had proved unsuccessful and the troops of the Pretender were making progress in Scotland,80 the vulnerability of the Hanoverian establishment called for a stronger rhetorical justifi cation of its position in the Royal Speech. George II now defi ned it as his major duty to preserve “the constitution in church and state, and the rights of my people”. Th e rights of the people had not been mentioned in Royal Speeches for fi ve years. It was made clear this time, too, that “[t]he interests of me and my people is always the same, and inseparable” (XIII, 1311–1312). In the Address of the Lords, the rights of the people were listed in imitation of the Royal Speech and only at the end of an acknowledgement of George II’s “paternal regard for the laws of the land, our constitution in church and state, and the rights of your people” (XIII, 1326–1327). Westmorland reminded the Lords in vain about the grievances of the people concerning corrup- tion in general elections and about the lack of rewards for the people’s support for the ministry during the rebellion. However, he remained a lone voice with his warnings about a change in the spirit of the people (XIII, 1321–1322, 1324). Th e majority of the Commons similarly aimed at appeasing the public by emphasizing the unity of the interests of the Crown and the people (XIII, 1363). Th e mover of the Address, Henry Legge, a loyal supporter of any Whig establishment, added an explicit refer- ence to the Hanoverian dynasty as “the choice of the people” (XIII, 1330), thus countering Jacobite calls for a Stuart restoration by recall- ing the Revolution Settlement of 1688. Some opposition members, however, suggested that the people might suspect the motives of the political establishment if nothing was done to decrease the infl uence

80 Black 2001, 245. 112 chapter two of placemen. Francis Dashwood (1708–1781), the Baron le Despen- cer, a major critic of the established system and a suspected Jacobite conspirator, maintained that the people expected a decrease in elec- tion corruption in order that they might feel that they would continue to be “a free people” in the future as well. While the interests of the King and the people could not be diff erent, those of the ministry and the people might be (XIII, 1337, 1339, 1341). Humphrey Sydenham suggested that “the true and genuine spirit of the people”, evident in instructions from the electors to their representatives, called for anti- corruption measures (XIII, 1351). Unsurprisingly, all such calls for reform were rejected as highly per- nicious at a time of war against the French and the Jacobites, particu- larly as the people had not petitioned in the issue (XIII, 1349–1351). Th ere was no reason to add to the fear that the people felt about the future of the constitution by taking up constitutional questions (XIII, 1358). It is noteworthy, in any case, that the British parliamentary system allowed this kind of argumentation for and against even at a time of open rebellion in parts of the country. Certainly, the years of rebellion were no time for extensive discussions on democracy, but Erasmus Head’s sermon in connection with the trial of the rebels in Carlisle in September 1746, while rejecting arbitrary monarchy, rec- ognized democracy as an element of the mixed form of government; democracy placed legislative power “in the Major Part of the Com- munity”.81 When Parliament was convened in November 1746, the Royal Speech made no reference to the people but, aft er expressions of popu- lar loyalty from the two houses, the King’s answers expressed all possi- ble goodwill towards “my people”, comprising the inhabitants of both England and Scotland (XIII, 1426–1428, 1432). Th e year 1747, one of extraordinary elections, already saw some intensifi cation in the public debate. John Campbell, the Duke of Argyll, wrote again in favour of “the truly national Representation” which would be achieved “by a fre- quent and periodical Change of the popular Representation”.82 Another author argued, by contrast, that government was always the business

81 Erasmus Head, Loyalty Recommended on Proper Principles. A Sermon Preached in the Cathedral Church of Carlisle, during the Special Assizes held there, for the Trial of the Rebels . . . on Sunday, September 14, 1746 (London 1747), 9. 82 John Campbell, Liberty and Right: or, an Essay, Historical and Political, on the Constitution and Administration of Great Britain . . . (London 1747), 62–63. the westminster parliament and the people, – 113 of a few in popular states.83 An anonymous propagandist defended the Hanoverians by appealing to the Whig maxim “the Voice or Choice of the People, is the Voice of God”.84 In more theoretical discourse, Francis Hutcheson recognized the potential virtue of democracies with “deputies elected by the people” although he conceded that “pure democracy” tended to be slow in decision-making.85 Aft er a favourable election result and other demonstrations of loy- alty to the ruling dynasty, the Royal Speech of November 1747 pre- sented the new Parliament in conventional terms as the executor of the sentiments of the people to its monarch. Once the domestic crisis was over and the position of the administration strong, the King was also free to thank his subjects for cooperation by emphasizing the united nature of the war eff ort (XIV, 94). In the Addresses and debates, the relationship between the Crown and the people appeared as entirely unproblematic, partly because of the relative weakness of the opposi- tion. None of the usual opposition rhetoric about the sentiments of the people was heard (XIV, 97–98, 100). Th e same kind of consensual language referring to “a fl ourishing and happy people” was echoed when the War of the Austrian Succes- sion fi nally ended in October 1748 (XIV, 321–322, 324, 352–353). Th e successful war and an overwhelming Whig majority had brought the British political elite into agreement over the relationship between the monarch and the people. Th e people was viewed as a passive object of royal actions. Calls for a more active engagement of the people in the united eff ort were removed from offi cial statements aft er the war. Despite this consensus in Parliament, the end of the 1740s saw some public debate of interest. Gregory Sharpe, for instance, sug- gested that the Whig oligarchy would be destroyed once the people decided to “establish a Democracy or popular Government in them- selves” and thereby produce fi rst anarchy and then the restoration

83 [Anon.], An Essay on Liberty and Independency: Being an Attempt to Prove, Th at the People under a Popular Form of Government, May be as Much Slaves, as Th ose Subject to the Arbitrary Will of One Man (London 1747), 20. 84 [True Scotchman and lover of his country], Hereditary Right not Indefeasible: or, Some Arguments Founded upon the Unalterable Laws of Society and Government, Proving that the Rights Claimed by the Jacobites, Can Never Belong to Any Prince or Succession of Princes (London 1747), 22. 85 Francis Hutcheson, A Short Introduction to Moral Philosophy, in Th ree Books; Containing the Elements of Ethicks and the Law of Nature . . . Translated from the Latin (Glasgow 1747), 298. Th e original version had been published in 1742. 114 chapter two of the monarchy.86 Robert Dodsley published a schoolbook with the frank intention of teaching everyone “of a Free People” the notion of every Englishman as “a secondary Legislator, as he gives his Consent by his Representative”.87 Dodsley’s description of democracy repeated traditional reservations but also mentioned some noteworthy positive features: Th e third original Form is called Democracy, which [. . .] signifi es the Government of the People; for under this Form every Citizen, when he has attained to proper Qualifi cations to recommend himself to the public Choice, is intitled by Virtue of that Choice to a Share in the Government. We need not wonder therefore, that this Form has always had many Advocates, that it has been presented in the fairest and most plausible Colours; and that it has been cried up as of all others the most favourable to Virtue, Merit, and Liberty. At fi rst Sight indeed it appears so to be, but a very little Consideration will shew us, that it must be subject to many and great Inconveniencies. While the Government is small and low, a Democratic State is generally in a happy and fl ourishing Conditions; that is to say, it is purest, and answers best the End of its Institution, by which it enlarges and dilates itself, arriving quickly at a high Degree of Prosperity; which from the Nature of its Constitution it is not able to bear; for as Aristocracies are commonly subject to Cabals, so Democracies are almost always disturbed with Factions; [. . .].88 Dodsley categorized the regimes of his day on the basis of the classical division. According to him, the Dutch Republic without a stadholder (until 1747) had been a combination of aristocracy and democracy. Pure democracies only existed in the free cities of Germany, while a mixed constitution of the Spartan and Roman type was to be found only in Sweden “where tho’ the Administration of Aff airs is in the King and Senate, yet the last Resort is in the Dyet; to which Deputies are admitted from the Clergy, the Citizens, and the People.” Th ere remained no doubt as to the desirability of such a mixed government in comparison with pure types; a happy combination of the advan- tages of all forms was the best. Th e victory of Sweden over the Danish

86 Gregory Sharpe, A Short Dissertation upon that Species of Misgovernment, Called an Oligarchy (London 1748), 17. 87 [Robert Dodsley], Th e Preceptor: Containing a General Course of Education. . . . (Dublin 1749), Vol. 1, xix. Th e book was reprinted fi ve times by 1775. 88 [Dodsley], Th e Preceptor. Second edition, (London 1754), vol. 2, 480; cf. another schoolbook defi nition, according to which “when the Representatives of the People rule, ’tis called a Republic; and if the People themselves rule, ’tis a Democracy.” Sam- uel Edwards, A New Compendium of Geograph . . . (Dublin 1765), 30. the westminster parliament and the people, – 115 and Polish domination in the sixteenth century and the Dutch Repub- lic aft er the restoration of stadholdership in 1672 and 1747, provided Dodsley with evidence of an inherent strength in mixed governments. Even so, there was no denying the inconveniences of constant strug- gles between the diff erent parts of the constitution in such regimes.89 Th e ideal solution was to be found in the British House of Commons, which had such power as was “all that ever was pretended to, in the very purest Democracies, and was even in them much more easily eluded or defeated”.90 Th e British system was simply better than any of the pure democracies. Th is may have been the language of some schoolbooks, but the mem- bers of parliament themselves did not yet use the concept of democracy to describe their activities. Royal Speeches and the Addresses of the two Houses also continued to depict a totally harmonious relationship between the King and his people, based on the notion of the monarchy as a guarantee of the happiness and prosperity of the people (XIV, 573–575, 608). A confl ict between the interests of the two remained unthinkable, and the Commons emphasized “the mutual and insepa- rable interest of your majesty, and your people” (XIV, 608). Now that peace had been restored, John Perceval (1711–1770), Lord Egmont, who worked as an adviser to Prince Frederick, ventured to question the credibility of the Address even in the eyes of “the most vulgar and ignorant part of the people” (XIV, 579). Th is opposition man wanted Parliament to take a tougher stand as the spokesman of the people, which made Pelham, the fi rst minister, summarize in ironical terms the current uses of the concept of the people in the Commons: [. . .] what is called “the people” is a sort of ghost or hobgoblin, some- times raised by the imagination of the person that is frightened; and, like other hobgoblins, it always says what the imagination of the frightened suggests, or the art of the frightener devises (XIV, 585).91

89 [Dodsley], Th e Preceptor, 1754, 481–483, 514. Dodsley probably, and quite cor- rectly, associated the Swedish Noble Estate with the Senate, thus not listing it with the other three estates. Interesting is also the defi nition of the Swedish Peasants as “the People”. 90 [Dodsley], Th e Preceptor, 1754, 499. 91 For Lord Barrington’s parallel accusation about the abuse of the concept of the people, see Gunn 1983, 80. 116 chapter two

Pelham’s own characterization of the people was moulded by his desire to retain the established order: Th e British people, he claimed, counted on Parliament and were never excessively subservient to either the ministry or the King (XIV, 585). Th e Jacobite opposition, represented by John Hynde Cotton, who had actively supported the Pretender during the rising, replied to Pel- ham by complaining that the current administration did not take the people and their calls for a reform of Parliament seriously: I am sorry [. . .] that any minister should have cause to compare the people to a hobgoblin, that can frighten none but fools: the time has been when the voice of the people was of some real importance, and when the voice of the people and the voice of the parliament was always the same: but now, I am certain it is otherwise; and I do not found this opinion from the people I converse with; I found it upon the written remonstrances of the people to their members (XIV, 595). Th e opposition was disappointed with its representation in Parliament and concluded that the voices of the people and Parliament diverged because of ministerial manipulation. Th is confrontation demonstrates how ‘the people’ continued to be a central concept of political contro- versy, the meaning and proper use of which the fi rst minister and an opposition members of parliament were openly debating in the cham- ber despite repeated expressions of offi cial consensus aft er 1745. Th e British debate about the people and politics was infl uenced by a major Continental author when the fi rst English translation of Mon- tesquieu’s De l’eprit des lois (1748) came out in 1750. While references to Montesquieu appeared in parliamentary debates only much later, its ideas would aff ect British conceptions of their constitution and, in the long run, their political language as well. Montesquieu gave consider- able recognition to republican forms of government in the past, defi n- ing republican government as one in which “the body or only a part of the people are possessed of the supreme power”.92 He viewed both democracy and aristocracy as republican, related forms of government. He argued that “when the body of the people in a republic are pos-

92 Montesquieu, Th e Spirit of Laws, 1750, Vol. 1, 11; cf. Wright 2002, 293, which uses a modern translation that connects the concepts ‘the people’ and ‘sovereign power’. In the original French version the term is la souveraine puissance. Montesquieu, Charles- Louis de Secondat, Oeuvres de M. de Montesquieu, Vol. 1, (London 1767), 10. the westminster parliament and the people, – 117 sessed of the supreme power, this is called a democracy”,93 connecting the concepts of ‘the people’, ‘the supreme power’ and ‘democracy’. In democracy, “the people should have the sole power to enact laws”.94 However, in the English translation, “the people” and “sovereignty” were associated only in the sentence: “In a democracy the people are in some respects the sovereign, and in others the subject.”95 Th is meant that “the people in whom the supreme power resides, ought to do of themselves whatever conveniently they can; and what they cannot well do, they must commit to the management of ministers” chosen by them.96 Th ese statements do not remove anti-democratic criticism from Montesquieu’s book. His conception of the common people remained aristocratic and paternalistic, repeating assumptions like that which claimed that the actions of the people were “always either too remiss or too violent”. In a democracy, “the lower sort of people” should therefore be directed by those of higher rank.97 In a popular govern- ment, furthermore, “the power ought not to fall into the hands of the vulgar.”98 A notable alternative to democracy and popular government continued to be an aristocratic system with a numerous nobility, so that the people had no power but “the democracy” was instead “in the body of the nobles”.99 Th is aristocratic argument well suited some

93 Montesquieu, Th e Spirit of Laws, 1750, 11, cited here from the fi rst English trans- lation, which was the version most likely to have been read by British parliamentar- ians; Maier 1972, 841; Dippel 1986, 61. 94 Montesquieu, Th e Spirit of Laws, 1750, 17. 95 Montesquieu, Th e Spirit of Laws, 1750, 12. In the original French, the term was le monarque, which shows that the concept of sovereign continued to be intimately linked with the person of the monarch in English. Montesquieu, Oeuvres de M. de Montesquieu, 11. Th e French concept of sovereignty seems to have been much easier to combine with the people as a synonym of the supreme power than was the case in the English language. Th e translation of Jean Jacques Burlamaqui’s text in 1752 contained the idea of shared sovereignty between the King and the people, and it presented Poland as a warning example of the anarchy of a popular government. J.J. Burlamaqui, Th e Principles of Politic Law: Being a Sequel to Th e Principles of Natural Law . . . (London 1752), 61–62, 73, 91. Th e concept of sovereignty entered English in a translation, but it was not yet regarded as a native one. Th e fi rst edition of Fenning’s dictionary still defi ned democracy as “a form of government, wherein the supreme power is lodged in the people”, limiting “sovereignty” to refer to ‘majesty’. Daniel Fen- ning, Th e Royal English Dictionary: or, a Treasury of the English Language . . . (London 1761). 96 Montesquieu, Th e Spirit of Laws, 1750, 12−13. 97 Montesquieu, Th e Spirit of Laws, 1750, 14, 17. 98 Montesquieu, Th e Spirit of Laws, 1750, 355. 99 Montesquieu, Th e Spirit of Laws, 1750, 18. 118 chapter two members of both the Swedish Noble Estate and the British House of Lords. Of signifi cance for future parliamentary debates was also Montes- quieu’s distinction between democracy and the liberty of the people, a point on which he diff ered from Aristotle.100 In his view, echoed by both British and Swedish speakers, true political liberty fl ourished in moderate governments only, not in aristocracy or democracy. While “in democracies the people seem to do what they please; [. . .] political liberty does not consist in an unrestrained freedom.”101 Montesquieu also held a traditional view of democracy in that he saw elected repre- sentatives and democracy as incompatible; representation was rather a feature of aristocracy.102 As for possible democratic states, Montesquieu could not view Republican Rome as a democracy.103 Th e British search for what he called “democracy” had also been not only unproductive but mistaken as well,104 a notion that Montesquieu’s Swedish audience readily repeated. Montesquieu’s association of the British constitution with “democracy” despite British denials of this is noteworthy.105 From an English point of view, democracy remained, in Samuel Johnson’s words, no more than “one of the three forms of govern- ment, that in which the sovereign power is lodged in the body of the

100 Cf. Hobbes’ citation of Aristotle arguing that “Th e Ground or Intention of a Democracy is Liberty” and that “no Man can partake of Liberty, but only in a Popular Commonwealth”, reprinted in a collection of Hobbes’ works in the same year 1750. Th omas Hobbes, Th e Moral and Political Works of Th omas Hobbes of Malmesbury. Never Before Collected Together. . . . (London 1750), 84. 101 Montesquieu, Th e Spirit of Laws, 1750, 213; Maier 1972, 842; Dippel 1986, 61. 102 Markoff 1999, 671. 103 Montesquieu 1750, Vol. 1, 239; Edmund Burke even questioned the extent to which Athens, Sparta or Rome had in reality been “free States, or popular Govern- ments” and rather characterized them as oppressive oligarchies. Edmund Burke, A Vindication of Natural Society . . . (London 1756), 65–66. 104 Dippel 1986, 62. 105 Conventional political wisdom was represented by Sir Walter Raleigh’s max- ims of state, reprinted in 1750–1751, which implied that England was a “Free State” and thus a “Popular State” but not necessarily a democracy. While in an aristocracy, “some small Part of the People have in them as a body Corporate, the Sovereignty and supreme Power of the whole State”, in a democracy “all the People have Power and Authority Sovereign.” Walter Raleigh, Th e Works of Sir Walter Ralegh, Kt. Political, Commercial, and Philosophical . . . (London 1751), Vol. 1, 2–3, 5, 41, 51; For William Temple, by contrast, “democracy” and “popular state” were exact synonyms, though England was by neither of them. Indeed, Temple rejected a popular state because of its inherent instability. William Temple, Th e Works of Sir William Temple . . . (Edinburgh 1754), vol. 2, 46, 52. the westminster parliament and the people, – 119 people.”106 As no one claimed that all sovereignty would have been possessed by the body of the people, it was diffi cult for the British to accept suggestions of their system as democracy. Th ey understood democracy as no more than an element of the mixed government and rarely suggested that Parliament was a democratic institution.107 However, Montesquieu may have aff ected their use of language in the long run, as his notions of democracy were oft en reproduced word for word in late-eighteenth-century reference works on politics,108 and they would also be later cited in parliamentary debates.

Consensual Conceptions of the People as Subjects during the Seven Years’ War

Most of the 1750s and early 1760s can be considered fairly unsurpris- ing from the point of view of parliamentary discussion on the consti- tutional role of the people. Aft er the crises of the 1740s were assuaged, the centre of political power shift ed from Parliament to the Court and the ministry. Aft er 1754, a further war with France and ministerial stability provided few possibilities for the free expression of views in Parliament.109 Th e Royal Speeches and parliamentary Addresses of the early 1750s remained, under Pelham’s direction, totally conventional. Very little was said about the people. Rather, international tensions brought the concept of the nation—its honour, security, interests and happiness—to the centre of ceremonial speaking (XV, 89), and domes- tic controversies were passed over in silence in the Addresses.110 Some particular debates show, however, that the popular dimension of the constitution continued to be highly esteemed among the British estab- lishment, although ill-considered references to the rioting mob contin- ued to appear as very suspect.111

106 Samuel Johnson, A Dictionary of the English Language . . . Vol. 1. (London 1756). 107 Markoff 1999, 671. 108 See [Anon.], Th e Politician’s Dictionary; or, a Summary of Political Knowl- edge . . . (London 1775), Vol. 1, 396–397. 109 Black 2001, 247, 249. 110 Holmes & Szechi 1993, 240. 111 Th e debate on the Jewish Naturalization Bill on 17 April 1753 has been omitted from this analysis because of its concentration on ethnic prejudices. However, the debate contained an indirect suggestion that the British form of government was a “sort of democratical government” as opposed to the absolute governments on the 120 chapter two

When the Newcastle ministry draft ed the Speech from the Th rone in November 1754, the preceding general election was mentioned as having aff orded “my people an opportunity of giving fresh proofs of their duty and aff ection to my person and government, in the choice of their representatives.” (XV, 330) Following an early-modern con- ception of the monarchy, Newcastle, who was anxious about royal support,112 presented the elections as no more than an expression of the loyalty of the people to the Crown; there was no question of an independent will of the people having been sought in them. Parlia- ment was described as “my parliament” cooperating for “my own, and my people’s happiness” (XV, 331). Both houses unanimously reinforced such notions. Th is absence of any expressed independent identity among the members of parliament reveals how well the King and the ministry were able to manipulate the representative institution in this period. However, some opposition views were recorded. Th omas Potter, a member of a party supporting the Prince of Wales, insisted that no approving Address should be pre- sented before the policy of the ministry towards the French in America had been properly examined (XV, 342). William Beckford, a fi nancial backer of the anti-ministerial journal Th e Protester, argued that the Commons would lose “its character among the people” if it merely accepted the ministerial formulations (XV, 353). On the government side, Henry Legge easily rejected these protests as unproductive in that they might give rise to division in the House “or among the people without doors” and, most worryingly, reveal the existence of disagree- ments among the British to foreign powers (XV, 346–347). In the face of a war in 1755, the interests of the national commu- nity rose to the centre of royal speaking (XV, 528). It was certainly no

Continent, which made it more diffi cult for the system to tolerate religious devia- tion (William Northey, XIV, 1371). Th ere was also a claim put forward that the Jews wished to deprive “the people of all power” in order to secure their position in a society where public opinion opposed all concessions to them; in other words, the toleration of Jews endangered the popular basis of the British government (Nicho- las Fazakerley, XIV, 1408). Furthermore, the opposition was accused of attempts to provoke “the democratical aff ections of the lowest orders of the people” against laws like the Naturalization Bill (Earl of Egmont, XIV, 1420). Th e opposition was, in the end, successful and forced the ministry to withdraw its unpopular proposal, arguing that the sentiments of the people and those of Parliament were diff erent. Colley 1981, 1–19; Wilson 1995, 199. 112 Black 2001, 247. the westminster parliament and the people, – 121 time to emphasize the political rights of the demos.113 A debate on a military reform in the Lords in March 1756 illustrates the prevailing ways of talking about democracy. Th e Lord Chancellor, Philip Yorke (1690–1764), the Earl of Hardwicke, an active politician despite his position as Speaker, argued that an increased infl uence of the Com- mons in the nomination of the land tax commissioners—to the detri- ment of the monarch and the Lords—was about to lead to an excessive growth of the democratic element in the constitution, thus threatening its balance. Instead, the monarchical and aristocratic elements should be strengthened: Th e scale of power, in this government, has long been growing heavier on the democratical side, I think this would throw a great deal of weight into it. What I contend for, is to preserve the limited monarchy entire; [. . .] (XV, 731). Many noblemen remained opposed to any increase in the popular or “democratic” element of the constitution and rejected reforms pointing in that direction, including the reorganization of the militia. Hardwicke, who had expressed his prejudices towards popular dis- turbances before and advised the Lords to treat the people like phy- sicians,114 specifi ed the potential risks of the proposal for the social order, describing how “none but the very lowest rank of our people” would be recruited and trained militarily, while arms might be made accessible to “the mob”. All this increased the risk of a mutiny. Greek and Roman precedents spoke rather in favour of an army consisting of propertied and truly free men (XV, 743–744). An alternative point of view defending a citizen militia was pre- sented by William, the Baron and Earl of Talbot, who saw the bill as one that the Commons as “the representatives of the people” had pre- pared so well that their judgement about the good of the people should be esteemed. Indeed, the political community as a whole was likely to benefi t from the strengthened virtue and martial spirit of both the lower and the higher ranks of the people that military training would produce. Rome, unsurprisingly, also provided an example of a martial

113 Th is debate on the Address of Th anks has, unlike most others, been contextual- ized in Jones 2006, 232–261. Jones focuses on the process as a struggle between New- castle, Henry Fox and Pitt the Elder within the ministry. It demonstrates the crucial role which the debates on the Address played in parliamentary politics as a vote of confi dence in the ministry. 114 Dickinson 1995, 156, 212. 122 chapter two spirit among “the body of the people” (XV, 746, 748–749). Talbot’s ideas were identical with those in much of the public discourse, in which the notions of an active, armed citizenry and national strength and prosperity were oft en associated in this period.115 Th e democratic or popular element of the constitution thus contin- ued to be simultaneously both suspected and admired by the Lords. Most noblemen did not want to arm the common people, while some viewed the civic activities of the people as the very foundation on which the strength of the national community rested. Th e Militia Act would be passed the following year, a major supporting argument then being that the defence of the nation and its constitution were to be placed in the hands of respectable classes of the people as opposed to the people as a whole.116 Th e start of the Seven Years’ War and the nomination of the Pitt- Devonshire ministry led to the use of slightly more varied language referring to the people in the Royal Speech of December 1756, the aim being to motivate the national community in the struggle against France, despite food riots and other domestic problems.117 Another explanation is that the nomination of a new ministry at about the same time was generally considered a consequence of the impact of the “Voice of the People”,118 and the ministers who draft ed the speech made use of this. Th e King now stated that he counted on “union and fi rmness in my aff ectionate people” and on “the spirit and zeal of my people” and assured the nation that he would regard equally “the just rights of my crown and people” when organizing the military forces (XV, 772, 775). A wartime consensus was easily achieved with the following speeches, too, in which the building up of the national morale played a major share (XV, 829), while setbacks at home and abroad were passed over in silence.119 Th e time of war made the Com- mons view themselves not so much as representatives of the people with potential grievances but rather as representatives of the King’s loyal subjects, denouncing “that spirit of disorder which has shewn itself amongst the lower people in some parts of the kingdom” (XV, 837–838).

115 Wilson 1995, 188, 200. 116 Gould 2000, 78, 83, 87. 117 Holmes & Szechi 1993, 241. 118 Gunn 1983, 276. 119 Holmes & Szechi 1993, 241. the westminster parliament and the people, – 123

In the public debate of the late 1750s, democracy was constantly viewed as degenerate, disorderly, revengeful and scandalous, “a state of government the most subject of all others to disunion and faction”, while “a due admixture of Monarchy, Aristocracy and Democracy” pro- vided the best form of government.120 In the North American colonies, however, it is possible to fi nd an occasional reference to democracy as an essential element of the British constitution. Th omas Frink pointed out in his anniversary sermon that in Britain—as in Athens, Sparta and Rome—there was “Democracy, that is, a popular State, wherein the common People rule by their Representatives” side by side with monarchy and aristocracy.121 Th is seemingly conventional description of the mixed constitution associated the concepts of democracy and representation in a description of the Commons at a quite early date. At the same time, as Kathleen Wilson has demonstrated, the concepts of the people and their rights continued to play a role in extra-parlia- mentary discourse irrespective of the war.122 In its Address of November 1758, the Commons referred to the military victories and assured the monarch that the mutual coopera- tion between him and his people would lead to “the continuance of the same truly national spirit” (XV, 931, 934). Th e Royal Speech of November 1759, for its part, refl ected the increased confi dence of the national community as a consequence of major naval victories over France.123 Language referring to the nation rather than to the people predominated.124 In 1760, however, a further transformation in the corpus of Royal Speeches occurred. George III, the new King, who was eager to gain infl uence even to the detriment of his ministers,125 deliberately extended the role of the monarch in politics with a speech to which Parliament responded with expressions of unwavering loyalty. While the nation was defi ned with attributes of greatness and glory and in

120 Edward Wortley Montagu, Refl ections on the Rise and Fall of the Antient Repub- licks. Adapted to the Present State of Great Britain (London 1759), 15, 18, 33, 87, 106, 357. 121 Th omas Frink, A King Reigning in Righteousness, and Princes Ruling in Judge- ment. A Sermon . . . (Boston 1758), 80. 122 Wilson 1995, 200. 123 In October, a reference to a “bloody and expensive war” in the King’s speech had been replaced with a “just and necessary” war in the Privy Council. Holmes & Szechi 1993, 242. 124 See also Ihalainen 2005, 390, 395, 402, 404−405, 409−411. 125 Christie 1982, 56. 124 chapter two a way that strengthened the unity of interests of the people and the monarchy, the relationship between the elements of the constitution appeared as unproblematic. Th e King represented himself as “promot- ing the welfare of a people” and thanked them for their “loyalty and warm aff ection to me”. Th e victories allowed him to promise “the true and lasting felicity of this great people” and to count on “zeal and harmony among my people” (XV, 982–985, 995). During a successful war and in the beginning of a new and probably long reign, no friction between the people and the monarch was to be mentioned in ceremo- nial statements, while unity and loyalty were emphasized. In rhetorical terms, all sovereignty had been given into the hands of the monarch, “a gracious and aff ectionate sovereign”, as he seemed to be serving his people so well. Th e national community could hardly have been defi ned in more favourable terms; it was “a dutiful and united nation” and “a free and happy people” (XV, 993–995). In the early 1760s, no sign of a schism between the monarchical and popular elements of the constitution was made visible. Aft er the general election of 1761, George III characterized Parlia- ment as conveying “the truest information of the sense of my people, by [. . .] their representatives” but made no further mention of the popular element of the constitution (XV, 1110), thus presenting the monarchy ever more clearly as the dominant element. Th e Commons tended to likewise remove all possibilities for opposition to monarchi- cal power by defi ning itself as “a happy proof of the zeal, the loyalty, and the aff ection of your people” (XV, 1118–1120). Th e rhetorical construction of a monarchy based on unanimous popular aff ection seemingly played down all tension between the elements of the consti- tution. Aft er the military successes of 1762,126 too, George III and his ministry viewed the people as faithful, and nothing more seemed to be expected from them in political terms (XV, 1233, 1235, 1238). No negotiation between the powers of the state was seen as necessary by either of the Houses. In offi cial terms, the British political community was completely united at the time of the conclusion of the Peace of Paris in 1763. As for the public debate, it remained as suspicious of excessive democ- racy as it had traditionally been, despite occasional statements on the positive eff ects of the democratic element. Oliver Goldsmith’s fi cti-

126 Holmes & Szechi 1993, 243. the westminster parliament and the people, – 125 tious Chinese philosopher in Th e Citizen of the World, for instance, explained the unique degree of freedom in England by “their enjoy- ing all the advantages of democracy” yet maintaining the prerogative of the monarchy. According to this account, the British people did not play any particular role in the legislative power in comparison with other European states. Goldsmith implied that the balance in the British constitution was so delicate that any development “towards a Democratic form” would decrease the amount of freedom enjoyed by the subjects.127 Two translations of classics that came out in the early 1760s remind us of the continuous easy access that the British had to anti-democratic ideas abhorring the political activities of the common people. H. Spens, the translator of Plato’s Republic (1763), concluded in his introduction: [. . .] in every Democracy the people are enemies of the good, whilst they caress cunning and self-designing men, who, to serve their own ends, sooth the passions of others, and give countenance and encouragement to popular vices and corruptions.128 Democracy appeared as “licentious”, “corrupted and depraved”, “a monster with innumerable heads”.129 Plato had early on taught that democracy “arises when the poor prevailing over the rich, kill some, and banish others, and share the places in the republic, and the magistracies equally among the remainder”, and that only tyranny would follow.130 Th e translator of Polybius (1764) applied his teach- ings to contemporary Britain, lamenting how “from the Revolution to the present time, the government has been strongly drawn towards democracy”, and warning about a future fall of the country. While the King and the people had traditionally controlled each other, so much power had been given to the people that excess liberty, partisanship and the general corruption of the people threatened to destroy the constitution, leading fi rst to popular licence and then to despotism.131 Polybius had already shown how “the people were all well pleased to

127 Oliver Goldsmith, Th e Citizen of the World; or Letters from a Chinese Philoso- pher, Residing in London . . . (London 1762), Vol. 1, 215, 217. 128 Plato, Th e Republic of Plato. In Ten Books. Translated from the Greek by H. Spens, D.D. With a Preliminary Discourse Concerning the Philosophy of the Ancients by the Translator . . . (Glasgow 1763), xi. 129 Plato, Th e Republic, 1763, xvi, xxxi. 130 Plato, Th e Republic, 1763, 335, 354. 131 Polybius, Two Extracts from the Sixth Book of the General history of Polybius. . . . Translated from the Greek. . . . By Mr. Hampton (London 1764), no page numbers. 126 chapter two maintain this popular state” with its equality and liberty but could not prevent it from degenerating into anarchy. Once the people took over “the intire sovereignty”, the result would be “a government adminis- trated by a blind and unskilful multitude” even if it was still called “a free and popular state”.132 Th e classical predictions for democracies were depressing, and no-one really yet questioned their validity. Nor was Enlightenment political philosophy straightforwardly pro-democratic either. When Jean-Jacques Rousseau’s most famous works were translated into Eng- lish in the early 1760s, they provided little that was new in debates on democracy and the supreme power of the people. Émile (1763) suggested that only in connection with the original formulation of the social compact “had the people [acted] collectively in quality of sovereign”.133 In democracy, “the supreme power” had committed “the charge of government to the whole body of the people, or to the majority of them, so that there may be more magistrates than private citizens.” Democracy might “include a whole people, or may restrain itself only to the half”.134 Generally speaking, it was a form of govern- ment suited only to small states.135 Th e Social Contract (1764) repeated many of these views, adding that democracy “is established [. . .] by the simple act of the general will”, and that “in a well founded democracy [government] should coincide with the public Will”.136 Rousseau con- tinued to denounce a truly democratic system in words that would be echoed by the critics of democracy in Westminster later on: [. . .] there never existed, and never will exist, a real democracy in the world. It is contrary to the natural order of things, that the majority of a people should be the governors, and the minority the governed. It is not to be conceived that a whole people should remain personally assembled to manage the aff airs of the public; and it is evident, that no sooner are deputies or representatives appointed, than the form of administration is changed.137

132 Polybius, Two Extracts, 1764, 9, 37. 133 Rousseau, Emilius and Sophia, Vol. 4, 247. 134 Rousseau, Emilius, 1763, 257. 135 Rousseau, Emilius, 1763, 258. 136 Jean-Jacques Rousseau, A Treatise on the Social Compact: or the Principles of Politic Law . . . (London 1764), 107, 109, 116, 173. 137 Rousseau, A Treatise on the Social Compact, 1764, 110. the westminster parliament and the people, – 127

Furthermore, Rousseau rejected the idea of representation of the peo- ple in the British fashion, maintaining that “the people” or “the sov- ereign cannot be represented” and pointing out that the ancients did not even know such a word. In Rousseau’s view, the people of England were free only during the election of the members of parliament.138 According to Rousseau, democracy was subject to constant change and the risk of civil war at any moment, and hence he saw it as a perfect form of government that suited only tiny and simple states, or even only “a nation of Gods”.139 Rousseau thus shared many of the tra- ditional doubts about democracy. He also represented ‘the sovereign power’ and ‘the people’ as separate concepts in much of his book. One of the few instances in which ‘the people’ had been both ‘the sover- eign’ and the magistrate was provided by the Roman Republic, which had for a time under the tribunes been “a true democracy”. However, when the Roman people had been “legally assembled as a sovereign body”, many problems had followed.140 Th ese adverse notions of democracy changed little in the British debate. At the same time, domestic debates on the political role of the people were being revived. When John Wilkes could not make his voice heard in Parliament, he turned to publicity to defend a populist anti-ministerial cause.141

Wilkes and America: Th e Increasing Relevance of ‘the People’ in Political Argumentation, 1763–1769

We have seen how the ministry and Parliament had followed a highly consensual line in their mutual ceremonial speeches during the Seven Years’ War. Once peace had been restored with the Treaty of Paris in February 1763, the atmosphere of the political debate changed abruptly. In Parliament, Pitt and Newcastle, former prime ministers, criticized the new Bute and Grenville ministry for the excessively mild peace terms it had imposed. Th e common people and the press, in turn, protested against a new cider tax so vehemently that Bute had to resign. Wilkes attacked the ministry so fi ercely that the government

138 Rousseau, A Treatise on the Social Compact, 1764, 163–165. 139 Rousseau, A Treatise on the Social Compact, 1764, 112–113. 140 Rousseau, A Treatise on the Social Compact, 1764, 147, 159. 141 Th omas 2004. 128 chapter two endeavoured to close down his journal. Meanwhile this populist was being supported by London crowds demonstrating in the name of “Wilkes and liberty”.142 Radicalism as such was nothing new, but a period of intensifi ed extra-parliamentary radicalism was about to begin. Th e rise of radi- calism was provoked by problems caused by economic change and numerous wars. It was also based on an already existing tradition of protest and on a developed network of associations and the press, particularly among the middling orders. A considerable proportion of the population had subsidized or participated in the Seven Years’ War, which had led to a broadening of the concept of citizenship and notions of the popular origin of power. Politicians ready to challenge the parliamentary elites were able to make use of this emerging wider concept of the people. Th e parliamentary elites, however, felt little acute need to actively appeal to the people at large at this stage.143 A more modern concept of the people may have been gradually emerg- ing aft er 1760, but the circumstances for its breakthrough did not yet exist. According to Denis Baranger, the modern concept, once it emerged, entailed the existence of the people, fi rst, as a political force in constitutional questions and, second, the notion of the people as the source of all legitimacy.144 Th e crisis of the 1760s was certainly aggravated by the actions of the new King, including a tendency in the Royal Speeches to concentrate exclusively on the role of the monarch as the centre of the political system. Th e King left the people no political role beyond expressions of loyalty when he argued: It will ever be my earnest wish and endeavour, to demonstrate to my people, by my action, the love which I bear them; and I doubt not of receiving from them the grateful and just returns of duty and aff ection (XV, 1335–1336). Th e pronoun “I” dominated the speeches, while the people appeared as no more than the King’s people, and the Houses of Parliament con- tented themselves with echoing these formulations. Th e Commons played down all constitutional friction by declaring in 1763 that “your

142 Holmes & Szechi 1993, 243; for a recent biography of Wilkes, see Th omas 1996. 143 Colley 1981, 16; Dickinson 1995, 222–224; Wilson 1995, 198, 207, 209. 144 Baranger 1999, 357, 360. the westminster parliament and the people, – 129 real interests and those of your people are inseparable” (XV, 1341, 1343–1345). Even if George III was not building an arbitrary monarchy, concern about the constitutional consequences of the policies of his ministries was rising among various opposition circles, including the aristo- cratic Rockingham Whigs and the populist Wilkites. Th e fi rst avoided appeals to the people, the latter built on them.145 Th e closing speech of April 1763 provoked Wilkes to write that previous ministries had been more cautious in their formulation of the speeches, remember- ing the role of Parliament as “the constitutional guardian of the liber- ties of the people” (cited in XV, 1331). Wilkes reminded the Grenville ministry of the prerogative which the people possessed, in addition to that of the King (XV, 1336), and presented a conspiracy theory according to which the new monarch was threatening the rights of the people.146 Such a challenge immediately led the majority of the Com- mons to denounce Wilkes’ North Briton No. 45, published on 23 April 1763, as alienating “the aff ections of the people” from the King in its criticism of the peace treaty (XV, 1359, 1393).147 Th is happened despite protests from Pitt the Elder, a major opposition leader, according to whom “the rights and interests of the people” would be jeopardized by the censorship of Wilkes (XV, 1363–1364, 1401). Th e latter became an object of illegal persecution and, in January 1764, he was expelled from the Commons.148 He fl ed to France, and the cause of the people seemed to fi nd no further spokesmen in Parliament at that time. In the following years, it was rather the relationship between the British Crown and the inhabitants of the North American colonies that produced some uses of language referring to the people by the opposition. Even the advocates of the colonial cause did not yet defend democracy, or “a government of all over all” but spoke in favour of representation derived from the notion that power, which had been placed “ultimately in the people” by God, needed for practical reasons to be transferred to “a few”.149 On the colonial side, we fi nd individual

145 Dickinson 1977, 206–207. 146 Dickinson 1995, 224. 147 Black 2001, 251. 148 Christie 1962, 12; Holmes & Szechi 1993, 243; Th omas 2004. 149 James Otis, Th e Right of the British Colonies Asserted and Proved [London 1764], 19. 130 chapter two voices defending “the Order of Democracy” side by side with that of monarchy and aristocracy.150 Much more infl uential than such ephemera was William Black- stone’s Commentaries on the Laws of England (1765), probably the most important contribution to constitutional theory in eighteenth-century Britain. Blackstone aimed at preserving the supposedly perfect British mixed constitution with mutual checks between its various elements: the King, the nobility, the people, which were taken as parallel to the classical models of monarchy, aristocracy and democracy. Blackstone defi ned this community as a whole, not individuals, as the source of sovereignty, and he placed all sovereignty in the British constitution in the hands of Parliament. He also emphasized the representatives’ inde- pendence of their electors.151 From the point of view of long-term con- ceptual change, it was signifi cant that he depicted a Commons, “freely chosen by the people among themselves” as “a kind of democracy”.152 According to him, in democracy, “the right of making laws resides in the people at large”. His concept of democracy had positive aspects as well: Even though “popular assemblies are frequently foolish in their contrivance, and weak in execution”, they aimed at doing “the thing that is right and just, and have always a degree of patriotism or pub- lic spirit”.153 Furthermore, Blackstone represented the elections as “the exercise of the democratical part of our constitution”. In other words, sovereignty was exercised and “the people’s will” was declared by the electors “in a democracy”.154 Blackstone’s representation of democracy as an integral and potentially positive element of the British consti- tution certainly aff ected the ways in which British politicians talked about it in the years to come. All this had little immediate infl uence on the Royal Speeches, the King continuing to emphasize his active role in January 1765 and referring to the need to “secure the rights, and promote the happiness of my people”, obviously with reference to American protests against

150 Daniel Dulany, Considerations on the Propriety of Imposing Taxes in the British Colonies . . . Th e second edition, (Annapolis 1765), 1, 5, 33. 151 Derry 1976, 18–19; Dickinson 1977, 147; Miller 1994, 246; Similar views on the King and Parliament as sovereign were held by Adam Smith. Goldsworthy 1999, 181–183, 201–202. 152 William Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of England, Vol. 1 (Oxford 1765), 51; Evans 2006, 6. 153 Blackstone, Commentaries, 1765, 49–50. 154 Blackstone, Commentaries, 1765, 164. the westminster parliament and the people, – 131 new taxes (XVI, 2, 4, 6). Th e Commons, by contrast, seemed to be talk- ing about the “rights” of the subjects at home, but remained unspecifi c in this (XVI, 5). In another Address, they emphasized the power of the King-in-Parliament over all parts of the Empire, promising “to exert our most zealous endeavours for [. . .] the true interest of your people, in all parts of your extended empire.” Th e majority chose to underline the unity of interests of the monarchical and popular elements of the constitution by stating that “Your Majesty’s happiness and that of his people are one” (XVI, 89). In January 1766, interestingly, the emphasis of the Royal Speech changed, under the direction of Charles Watson-Wentworth, the Mar- quis of Rockingham, to “your aff ection and concern for the welfare and prosperity of all my people”, the members thus being urged to support the monarchy (XVI, 92). Such formulations were aimed at strengthening conceptions of the King and Parliament as the possess- ors of the supreme power over all British subjects. During the Stamp Act crisis, the colonists suggested that the people were the origin of all power and that sovereignty was divided, while the British political establishment (including lawyers such as Blackstone) emphasized the sovereign status of Parliament.155 In offi cial rhetoric in London, the diff erent elements of the consti- tution, including “all your Majesty’s people”, remained united (XVI, 110–112). Only individual members like Pitt questioned the theory of the virtual representation of the colonies and emphasized the right of representation as a condition for taxation (XVI, 100, 104).156 Th e crisis resulted in the attribute “sovereign” being increasingly associated with the British legislature as a whole. Harry Dickinson has suggested, how- ever, that the American calls for representation actually inspired some British radicals to adopt a new concept of the people challenging the orthodox doctrine of parliamentary sovereignty. Th ey would, later on, apply the newly defi ned concept, which emphasized the accountability of Parliament to the people, in their calls for extended suff rage.157 Th e content of the British parliamentary debate was changing in other ways, too. In 1766, the dispute with America already led to some signifi cant discussions in the Lords. When the power of the King and

155 Dickinson 1976, 189, 201–204. 156 Goldsworthy 1999, 192. 157 Dickinson 1976, 204; Dickinson 1995, 225. 132 chapter two

Parliament to legislate over the whole Empire was being debated, George Lyttelton, now the Baron of Lyttelton, a veteran member and a close ally of Pitt, lectured the House on the principles of the constitu- tion, starting with “an original compact” in which the government had been given the power to decide on behalf of the people. Th is meant that the British system did not allow the people to freely oppose laws passed by the legislature. Such opposition would mean the dominance of the democratic element in government, which was unthinkable in a mixed constitution in which all supreme legislative power remained in the hands of Parliament (XVI, 166). Th e only express sympathizer of the colonial point of view was Charles Pratt, Earl Camden, also an ally of Pitt, who questioned the right of Parliament to pass the Stamp Act, pointing out that there were limits to what the legislature could do. “Th e sovereign authority, the omnipotence of the legislature” did not, according to Camden—who had defended individual liberties in the Wilkes case—extend itself to the private property of the subjects in the form of taxation without the subjects having the opportunity to consent through their representatives (XVI, 168). Th e notion of the sovereignty of parliament was clearly strengthening as a reaction to American discontent, but so were disagreements over the extent of sovereignty within Parliament.158 Th e Lord Chancellor, Robert Henley, the Earl of Northington, replied by refuting Camden’s views as unconstitutional and under- lining the universal need for subjects to obey parliamentary majority decisions instead: Every government can arbitrarily inpose [sic] laws on all its subjects; there must be a supreme dominion in every state; whether monarchical, aristocratical, democratical, or mixed. And all the subjects of each state are bound by the laws made by government (XVI, 170). Northington proceeded by suggesting the withdrawal of British pro- tection from the colonies if they did not prove their proper allegiance to the mother country. He pointed out, in highly ironical terms, that even such weak states as Genoa or “the kingdom or rather republic of Sweden” would be capable of taking over the American colonies if the colonists tried to survive independently of Britain (XVI, 171). Th e colonies would be nothing without the protection of the British

158 Dickinson 1977, 147, 215–216; Goldsworthy 1999, 193–194. the westminster parliament and the people, – 133 monarchy. Northington’s other point was that excessively republican constitutions gave rise to weak political communities. Sweden was not the primary object of his criticism, but, in his capacity as the Speaker of the British House of Lords, he pointed out that Sweden with its extraordinary form of government was far from an ideal polity; it rather provided a warning instance of weaknesses that the reduction of monarchical power was likely to give rise to. Th e majority of the Lords were of the opinion, articulated by David Murray, the Earl of Mansfi eld and Viscount Stormont, that the Brit- ish Parliament represented the Empire as a whole and had an equal authority over all its subjects irrespective of their voting rights. Rep- resentation by election was merely a royal favour, and the idea that “every subject must be represented by deputy, if he does not vote in parliament himself, is merely ideal” (XVI, 173). It is evident that the American complaints did not have an extensive eff ect on how the polit- ical role of the people was understood in the British Parliament.159 In the opening speech of November 1766, the ministry of William Pitt the Elder (the Earl of Chatham), lamented discontent at home and in America and suggested that some subjects had broken the unity of the people (XVI, 236). For both the Lords and the Commons, the people remained essentially the King’s people (XVI, 240–241), but the Commons also referred to “the future liberty [. . .] of your people” (XVI, 244). Th is emphasis on liberty can be interpreted in two ways: it reinforced the capability of the British monarchy to safeguard the liberty of its people, but it might also be an indirect expression of concern for the future liberty of the people in an era when accusations of tyrannical rule by the Crown were being made on both sides of the Atlantic. Th e current premier probably had nothing against such a choice of words. In the public debate, concern for the political role of the people was also being expressed much more outspokenly. For example, Marcham- ont Nedham’s republican writings, originally published in the early

159 Documents draft ed by colonial assemblies contain some quite diff erent concep- tualizations of the political role of the people, especially with regard to its representa- tion. Th e Virginians, for instance, argued that the liberties of the people which their forefathers had enjoyed in Britain had been transmitted to them as well, and that these liberties included the right for the representatives of the people to decide on taxation (XVI, 120). Th e same argument about the American people wanting representation of the colonies in Parliament as a condition of their consent to taxation was made by Benjamin Franklin when he was questioned on the issue. XVI, 146, 156, 158. 134 chapter two

1650s, were reprinted; they advanced a number of arguments empha- sizing “the excellency of a free-state or government by the people”, the principle that “the original and fountain of all just power and gov- ernment is in the people” and the necessity of placing “the supreme authority in the hands of the people’s representatives”.160 Simultaneously, speculations on the positive eff ects of democracy within the mixed government were emerging in political philosophy. Adam Ferguson wrote about general ideas of democracy and popular government: Candour, force, and elevation of mind, in short, are the props of democ- racy; and virtue is the principle of conduct required to its preservation. How beautiful a pre-eminence on the side of popular government! And how ardently should mankind wish for the form, if it tended to establish the principle, or were in every instance a sure indication of its presence!161 Th e concept of democracy seemed to be experiencing a slight re-evalu- ation, even though Ferguson, too, pointed out that not all the people acted “in their capacity of sovereign” in a democracy. He also added that popular governments oft en had aristocratic features and remained vulnerable to being corrupted into despotism.162 Th ere was no escaping the presumed fact that ordinary men were unable to rule without this giving rise to confusion, servility, corruption and factions and, fi nally, to the loss of their “sovereignty”.163 Ferguson seems to have been the fi rst English-speaking philosopher to combine the concepts of democ- racy, the citizen and sovereignty in this way, but he certainly did not recommend pure democracy or popular government for his own age or country. In his view, Rome’s mixed government had been inclined towards democracy, whereas in England monarchy was stronger, and this produced the best conceivable system.164

160 Marchamont Nedham, Th e Excellencie of a Free State (London 1767), v, x, 25, 34. Nedham described how Solon and the Romans had placed “both the exercise and interest of supremacy in the hands of the people” (xvi, 5). 161 Adam Ferguson, An Essay on the History of Civil Society (Edinburgh 1767), 100. 162 Ferguson, An Essay, 1767, 101–102, 110. 163 Ferguson, An Essay, 1767, 286–287; Th e idea of men being ready to give up their “sovereignty” in a democratic state can also be found in Th omas Leland’s transla- tion of Demosthenes, Th e Orations of Demosthenes, Delivered on Occasions of Public Deliberation . . . (London, 1771), 81. 164 Ferguson, An Essay, 1767, 252, 254. the westminster parliament and the people, – 135

In the Royal Speech of November 1767, drawn up under the direc- tion of Augustus Henry Fitzroy, the Duke of Graft on, the eff ects of the crisis of the preceding years can be seen more clearly than before. Th e ministry had been subject to some successful opposition manoeuvres, and the country had witnessed further food rioting.165 At a time of constitutional friction in the Empire and an economic crisis caused by the rise of corn prices, it was considered necessary to address not just the governing elite but also the totality of the King’s subjects outside Parliament, including the poor (XVI, 380–381, 383). Importantly, the response of the Commons did not concentrate so much on thanking the King for his services to his people as on defi n- ing the political role of Parliament itself. Th at role was presented as totally loyal to the monarch, the Commons promising to work “with a zeal and alacrity becoming the representatives of an aff ectionate and grateful people”. However, the House represented itself essentially as the representatives of the people, emphasizing “the indispensable duty we owe to those we represent” and expressing thereby a view of the source of their political power as independent of the monarch (XVI, 393). Th is may have been primarily a sign of the rising self-confi dence of Parliament with regard to the American question, with the principle of the representation of the people by Parliament clearly present.166 Th e Commons’ formulation may also have been addressed to the vot- ers in order to prepare them for the coming general election. In the debate on the Address, the young Edmund Burke was among those who openly suspected the administration of “spreading corruption through the people.” Burke denounced what he saw as the ministry appealing to the people by the means of the Royal Speech, attempting to make Parliament responsible for solving the food crisis (XVI, 387, 390–391).

165 Holmes & Szechi 1993, 244–245. 166 At about the same time, the concept ‘national representation’ also entered public discourse for the fi rst time, being used to emphasize the “supreme legislative capac- ity” and “sovereignty” of the British Parliament. [Anon.], Th e Constitutional Right of the Legislature of Great Britain. To tax British Colonies in America, Impartially States (London 1768), 12, 51. According to the author, in the British popular government: “Th e legislature, consisting of king, lords, and a representation of the people, or com- mons, constitute her supreme and absolute sovereignty.” (p. 41) Th e sovereignty was shared by all the elements of the constitution; see also Joseph Priestley, An Essay on a Course of Liberal Education for Civil and Active Life . . . (London 1768), 103. 136 chapter two

Th e character of the debate about the political role of the people was indeed changing more broadly in the late 1760s. Th e election campaign of spring 1768 became more colourful aft er Wilkes’ return from his four years of exile on the Continent. Wilkes had met Vol- taire and renewed his contacts with French radical intellectuals such as Baron D’Holbach, whom he had known since his studies at the University of Leiden. He now fought a successful election campaign for a seat in the populous constituency of Middlesex but, predictably, was prosecuted for his previous off ences. Wilkes made skilful use of the prosecution to gain popularity, suggesting that the parliamentary oligarchy was attempting to prevent the representation of the people in Parliament. His supporters turned to widespread rioting in London, which ended in the so-called St George’s Fields massacre with several fatal casualties. Th e Graft on ministry reacted with persecution aft er a further Wilkite election victory and repeated propaganda attacks on the government.167 Th e result of the controversy was a crisis that had both political and constitutional consequences. Wilkite protests appeared in courts, county petitions, parliamentary speaking, the press and demonstra- tions and riots, and they lasted until 1770. Th e Wilkite movement strengthened an already existing urban popular political culture which provided an alternative to parliamentary politics. It made eff ective use of publicity and encouraged the formation of associations. An anony- mous author suggested that the concept of the public had been rede- fi ned so that it stood for the mob. Some of the associations that were formed and the arguments that were used during the crisis would serve as a foundation for later political radicalism, involving more people in political activities that would, in the long run, have an infl uence on parliamentary politics and political discourse.168 According to Wilson, the Wilkite reformists, with their references to the right of resistance, already heightened ‘popular sovereignty’ into a central concept of British politics.169 Dickinson has suggested that the Wilkite movement occurred simultaneously with a radicalization of public discourse from the late 1760s onwards. Joseph Priestley, for instance, argued on the basis of natural rights theory in favour of the

167 Christie 1982, 75; Holmes and Szechi 1993, 245; Dickinson 1995, 225; Wilson 1995, 211; Th omas 2004. 168 Dickinson 1977, 210, 213; Gunn 1983, 81; Reid 1985, 139. 169 Wilson 1995, 216–217. the westminster parliament and the people, – 137 ultimate sovereign authority of the people and the right of resistance, describing the rulers as no more than “the servants of the people”. According to Dickinson, in Priestley’s understanding, the sovereign authority of the people was active in the sense that they had a right to freely reform a government.170 It is evident, however, that Priestley did not yet use any explicit concept of popular sovereignty.171 Linda Colley, by contrast, claims that Wilkes’ long-term infl uence was rather modest.172 Th e Wilkites certainly did not constitute a demo- cratic movement,173 even if commentaries on party-strife during elec- tions turned into openly anti-democratic criticism of them. Among the allegations was the following one, which lamented the fact that the fi erce campaigning had extended to the masses and given rise to disorder: Th e general election is now over; and it is speaking a melancholy truth to say, that the state of the elections was a state of democracy, through several parts of the kingdom.174 Th e Wilkites themselves, though including the middling and even lower orders in their concept of the people, did their best to distin- guish between “the people”, who they represented, and “the mob, who were to remain excluded even aft er a reform.175 Th e eff ects of the Wilkite aff air and the American crisis crept only gradually into the language of ceremonial speaking. When they met the new Parliament in November 1768, the ministry still followed the conventional formula by defi ning the occasion as an “opportunity which the late general election gives me [the King] of knowing from their representatives in parliament the more immediate sense of my people” (XVI, 466). Th e sovereign had reduced references to what he

170 Dickinson 1977, 198. Dickinson draws generalizing conclusions by combining references to a variety of authors who wrote in diff erent contexts, without always ana- lysing their original use of language. Th is method oft en hides the extent of the points of view and the scale of the conceptual change. Generalizing concepts of ‘democracy’ and ‘the sovereignty of the people’ are also used in Goodwin 1979, 56, when the views of the reformers are discussed. 171 See Joseph Priestley, An Essay on the First Principles of Government; and on the Nature of Political, Civil, and Religious Liberty (Dublin 1768), 24–25. 172 Colley 1981, 16. 173 Christie 1962, 2; Wilson 1995, 227. 174 [Anon.], A Perspective View of the Complexion of some late Elections, and of the Candidates (London 1768), 3–4. 175 Dickinson 1977, 212–213; Wilson 1995, 235. 138 chapter two had done and would do for his people, however, and instead recog- nized the ability of Parliament to act in cooperation with the King. However, the rights of the king’s people continued to be viewed only collectively and they were contrasted with their violations by outsiders, including some Americans (XVI, 466–467). Th ere were few in Parlia- ment who opposed such sentiments. Parliamentary debates of the expulsion of Wilkes from the Com- mons, which were opened soon aft erwards, also contain few references to the political role of the people. Wilkes was being accused—in Black- stone’s words—of having attempted “to prejudice the minds of the people against the administration of public justice” (XVI, 542–543).176 On 2 February 1769, however, George Grenville, an opponent of the expulsion, recognized Wilkes’ status as “an object of popular favour” capable of infl aming “the people without doors”. Grenville suggested that Wilkes’ popularity would soon wither away if he was just allowed to keep his seat in Parliament, while his expulsion would turn him into a victim and further increase his popularity (XVI, 567–569). On the following day, Wilkes was expelled from the House. And aft er each re-election that followed, he was always expelled again.177 By April 1769, several members of parliament would already be argu- ing that “the right of the people” had been violated by the nomination of Wilkes’ rival candidate to Parliament and that the repeated expul- sions of Wilkes had turned into “a dispute between the parliament and the people” (XVI, 584). Edmund Burke, a Rockingham Whig, accused the ministry of having made the Commons present Addresses that were “libels on the people” and having thereby created a schism not only between the Commons and the voters but also between the King and the people (XVI, 587). Other debaters insisted that “the Com- mons and the people are virtually the same” and “inseparably con- nected both in interest and in freedom”. It was hence very strange that the Commons should violate “the liberties of the people” in the way they had (XVI, 595). In the course of spring 1769, the Wilkes aff air thus started to pro- duce constitutional debates, including arguments emphasizing the pri- macy of the rights of the people. Th e public debate and crowd activity

176 Blackstone was preparing the last part of his Commentaries upon the Laws of England for publication in 1769. Holmes & Szechi 1993, 245. 177 Holmes & Szechi 1993, 245. the westminster parliament and the people, – 139 was changing the way in which at least some opposition members understood their role in relation to the people. For the rest of 1769, the opposition continued to organize widespread petitioning in favour of Wilkes and against the decisions of the Commons,178 which con- tributed to this change in parliamentary language. Pamphlets were published, including some that pointed out the original source of the authority of the Commons—the people. According to the anonymous author of one, the most valuable principle of the constitution contin- ued to be “that which vests in the people the power of chusing their own representatives in Parliament.” He added that “it is by them that the consent of the people is given”.179 Th e relationship not so much between the King and the people but rather that between the current Westminster Parliament and the people at large had been a topic of general dispute in and out of Parliament. Th is controversy was also observed with keen interest in countries outside Britain, including Sweden, as we shall soon see.

Redefi nitions of the Relationship between the People, Parliament and the Crown in the Aft ermath of the John Wilkes Case, 1770–1771

Th e relationship between Parliament and the people had become problematic in an unforeseen manner as a consequence of the recur- rent elections in Middlesex, in which John Wilkes repeatedly won the popular vote, only to have his entry to the House prevented each time by the Commons. Th is confrontation was hardly relieved by the appointment of Lord North as the Prime Minister on 25 January 1770, though the manipulation of Parliament was intensifi ed.180 Th e Royal Speech of 9 January 1770 retained its old tone, ignoring accusations that the administration was not demonstrating proper respect for the rights of the people. George III merely argued that he would maintain “the dignity and honour of my crown, together with the just rights and interests of my people”, and that he expected to receive the full backing of “my parliament, [. . .] in their zeal for the true interest of

178 Holmes & Szechi 1993, 245; Th omas 2004. 179 [English freeholder], Th e Sentiments of an English Freeholder, on the Late Deci- sion of the Middlesex Election (London 1769), 6–7. 180 Holmes & Szechi 1993, 245; Black 2001, 253. 140 chapter two my people” (XVI, 643–644). Parliament was still the King’s institution rather than the people’s. Th e Lords offi cially echoed these formulations, but in reality criti- cism was on the rise. Lord Chatham (William Pitt the Elder), with his authority as a former premier, challenged the request that the Lords should agree on the Address in order to pacify the people and demanded instead that the complaints of the people should be exam- ined. As the privileges of the Lords stood “upon the broad bottom of the people”, the peers should “watch over, and guard the people; for, when the people had lost their rights, those of the peerage would soon become insignifi cant.” (XVI, 651) If indeed it really was pronounced in the Lords in 1770,181 this was a radical statement from a former fi rst minister, echoing Wilkes’ words in 1763.182 Chatham went on to advise his fellow noblemen: Let us be cautious how we admit an idea, that our rights stand on a foot- ing diff erent from those of the people. Let us be cautious how we invade the liberties of our fellow-subjects, however mean, however remote; for [. . .] slavery [. . .] [is] a disease which spreads by contact, and soon reaches from the extremities to the heart (XVI, 651–652). No distinction between the people and the peers was to be made by the former premier, now frustrated in opposition. Chatham’s point was that the liberty of the subjects had been invaded, that the complaints of the people were justifi ed and that the Lords should have informed the King about the dissatisfi ed mood of the nation. Th is meant, above all, reconsidering the prosecution of Wilkes by the Commons (XVI, 652–653). Chatham’s suggestion was viewed as utterly dangerous by the Earl of Mansfi eld (XVI, 654), but Chatham went on to insist that the proceedings against Wilkes had been unconstitutional, that the “national rights contained in Magna Charta” concerned “the whole people”, and that the Lords should respect “the collective body of the people” even more than the Commons as “the representative”. Th e Lords should have “the English nation” on their side and act as “mediators between the King and people” (XVI, 661–663). Th e Wilkite language of popular politics had undeniably entered the British Lords. Th e elder Pitt was rather alone in his use of such language, but his

181 Th e source critical problems related to this debate are obvious, as Cobbett bases his report on the account of a politician who revised the notes as late as 1813. 182 See Dickinson 1977, 211. the westminster parliament and the people, – 141 style of argumentation was gaining ground. Th e Wilkite rhetoric was repeated in printed literature and found its way abroad, including all the way to the Swedish House of Nobilities. Nor was the Commons content with repeating old loyalist formulas. Aft er an extensive debate, they decided to send a clear message to the King, the government and the general public, expressing themselves in increasingly confi dent terms in the aft ermath of the Wilkes aff air: We will steadily perseverve [sic] in such principles as are most agree- able to the true spirit of this free constitution, and invariably pursue such measures as are most conducive to the real happiness of the people (XVI, 729). Th e House was speaking with a voice of its own, emphasizing its inter- pretation of “the true spirit of this free constitution” and its determi- nation to make decisions that would be for the best of “the people”, as the members of parliament understood it. In this formulation, the word “people” was used for the fi rst time in the history of the Addresses of Th anks by the Commons since the mid-1730s with the defi nitive article, without the usual references to “the King’s people”. “Th e people” undeniably stood for a collective political agent indepen- dent of the monarch but one constituted by Parliament rather than some extra-parliamentary people. Repeated claims in public discourse that the sense of the Commons and that of the people diverged had forced the lower house to defi ne itself more emphatically as the true representative of the people, understood as a collective. Th is message was still reinforced by repeating the conventional claim about the unique nature of the British constitution and by implying that Par- liament was working to ensure the future of the constitution (XVI, 730). By this time, even most of the parliamentary opposition were unhappy with Wilkite radicalism and rather advocated an interpreta- tion of themselves as “the people”.183 Contrary to what some speakers had suggested during the preced- ing session, the Commons Addresses were not mere meaningless rit- uals but could at times convey serious messages, even ones relating the existing constitutional frictions. Th e formulation of 1770 was not so much a turning point in the relationship between the monarchi- cal and popular elements of the British constitution as a statement

183 Wilson 1995, 217. 142 chapter two emphasizing the independent status of Parliament in relation to the people at large, and particularly to the Wilkites. At the same time, the confi dent formulation presented in the name of the people hid disagreements within the Commons. William Dowdeswell, a member wavering between Whig and Tory attitudes, took up the “violations of the people’s rights” by the government in various parts of the Empire and the neglect of all petitions of the people (XVI, 680). According to Velters Cornewall, a country Tory, “in an assembly of the people, regard is to be paid to the voice of the people” and to “popular discon- tents” no matter what their reason was (XVI, 684). Th e response of the Attorney General, Th omas de Grey (1748– 1818), to these speeches illustrates the belief of the majority of the members that the Commons retained an indisputable right to exclude Wilkes from the House on the basis of the denial of the imperative mandate. Th is was particularly so because the Commons constituted “the people”: Th is House, once chosen, is, to all legal and constitutional purposes, the people collectively, and to suppose their judicial proceedings, when cho- sen, to be cognizable by any number of the individuals who have chosen them, is to subvert our constitution from the root (XVI, 686). A further comment of De Grey reveals the social prejudices inherent in the attitudes of the parliamentary elite towards the Wilkite cause: the opposition outside Parliament consisted of no more than “a few despicable mechanics, headed by base-born people, booksellers, and broken tradesmen”. Th e signers of the petitions were “the scum of the earth, the refuse of the people, unworthy to enter the gates of his Majesty’s palace” (XVI, 696). No wonder De Grey’s speech was inter- rupted by John Glynn, a Unitarian member of the editorial board of Wilkes’ North Briton, who shouted that the claims constituted “an off ence against the people of this free kingdom”, as “[t]he privileges of this country do not depend upon birth and fortune” (XVI, 696). Th e language of the people challenging the establishment fl ourished among opposition speakers for the rest of the debate. George Sackville (Germain from 1770), an old offi cer who supported the nomination of North to the head of the ministry, emphasized in a very fervent speech the need to rephrase the Address as “the minds of the people are alarmed, and they have high expectations from the deliberations of this House.” (XVI, 686) Reconsidering the expulsion of Wilkes was the only method to “give the people satisfaction” and to show that the the westminster parliament and the people, – 143

Commons remained “the representatives of the people”. Th e Commons should denounce the ministerial formulation, which suggested that the King approved the manipulation of the election results in Middlesex as well as the neglect of popular petitions in favour of Wilkes in order to not off end the people (XVI, 687–688). In Sackville’s description of the state of aff airs, the people throughout the Empire were concerned that their liberties were in danger, expected action by their representa- tives and otherwise were prepared to withdraw their support from the House. In the worst scenario, the tragedy of St George’s Fields might be repeated. If the Commons did not aim at saving the constitution, “the representatives of the people” would turn into a “league against the people”, and the people might deny the authority of Parliament and allow themselves to be governed by an authoritarian ruler instead. Th is had, according to Sackville, already happened in the once free state of Denmark (XVI, 688–690).184 Charles Jenkinson, a servant of the court with a Tory background, overcame his usual timidity and questioned the idea that “the author- ity of this House was to depend on the voice of the people out of this House” (XVI, 690). Th e controversy over the relationship between Parliament and the people appeared to him to be a result of a Wil- kite faction abusing the thoughtless multitude. According to Jenkin- son, support for the Address did not mean voting “away the people’s rights”; opposition to the amendment should rather be seen as a defence of both the rights of the people and the honour of the mem- bers (XVI, 691–692). Two more opposition speeches followed, both of them question- ing the authority of the Commons to some degree. George Savile, a defender of the rights of the electors to freely choose their representa- tives, argued that while “the diminution of the authority of this House by the people” was lamentable, even worse was “the invasion of the people’s rights by the authority of this House” (XVI, 699). He repeated his last point despite having been repudiated by Sir Alexander Gilm- our (XVI, 700–701). Savile found a defender in the Wilkite Glynn, who demanded that the suggestions in the press about the rights of the people having been betrayed by the Commons should be taken seriously. Glynn maintained that the lower house had already lost “the

184 In Denmark, royal absolutism had been taken over by J.F. Struensee’s autocratic rule in 1770. 144 chapter two love and confi dence of the people” and was about to turn from “an assembly of free representatives of a free people, into a gang of slaves” (XVI, 701, 703). Th e debate became heated, and Jeremiah Dyson, a pedantic observer of parliamentary procedure and a consistent defender of the author- ity of Parliament, maintained that the claims of the opposition were unfounded. He saw no reason why the people should protest against Parliament; it was merely the opposition that desperately exploited “the mob” and “rabble” of the rioting “middling sorts” and the publi- cists of London for their sinister purposes. No confl ict between Parlia- ment and the people existed in the fi rst place: We have been told, [. . .] that we have lost the love and confi dence of the people, that an hon. gentleman who has reproached us with betraying our trust, has spoken the sentiments of the people, that we are at this moment in danger of being called to account by the people, that the people are ready to do themselves justice upon us, and that we should beware what we do, because the people, whom by one of the rhetorical fl ourishes, which are so useful on other occasions, he calls the Avenger, is at the door. Sir, it is hard to say whether this insult is more gross against this House or the people. Is the rabble that is now supposed to be gathered about the door, the people? Are the writers of news-papers, who wish for a prison or a pillory, that their libels may be thought more important, the people? Or do the petitions, about which so much has just been said, contain the sense of the people? Th e people are too great, too respectable a body to become the tool, the puppet of any faction; [. . .] (XVI 703–704). Dyson, as one of the voices of the majority, concluded that Parliament should not be aff ected by the opinions of the rabble if it did not want to see the entire system degenerate into a tyranny of the mob (XVI, 705). Th e mixed constitution should be actively protected from such degeneration, the assumption continuing to be that the parliamentary majority constituted the people. As the opposition did not give up their claims that the people as a collective was discontented with the administration (XVI, 705, 710), the Prime Minister insinuated that they were “alienating the aff ections of the people from their Sover- eign” (XVI, 717), i.e. behaving treasonously. Th e offi cial line remained unchanged: the administration was not violating “the rights of the people”, nor would it allow outsiders to violate the power of Parlia- ment (XVI, 719). Th e debates on the Address in spring 1770, in the aft ermath of the Wilkes controversy, thus led to extensive disagreements over the the westminster parliament and the people, – 145 proper political roles of the people on the one hand and Parliament on the other. A turning point in the parliamentary use of language referring to the people was clearly at hand. Th e debate, which had been initiated by Wilkite publications, was joined by parliamentarians outside the House as well. Edmund Burke, for instance, was already active at that time.185 Whereas the concept of the people was at the centre of this debate, that of democracy did not yet play any notewor- thy role in it. Th e main message of oppositional publications such as Junius’ letters in the Public Advertiser was that the Commons’ power was delegated by the people and that there were serious defects in the representation of the people in that House.186 Th e controversy of spring 1770 and the troubles of the rest of the year led to some revisions in the draft s of the Royal Speech and Addresses of the following November. Lord North chose to rephrase the description of the relationship between the monarchy and the people in some respects, particularly as he himself esteemed the Com- mons but was concerned about the questioning of the government’s authority in public discourse. Furthermore, even some of North’s sup- porters had referred to the voice of the people in favourable terms during the year.187 In a speech approved by North, the King responded to popular dis- content by repeating fi ve times the phrases “the honour of my crown” and “the just rights and interests of my people”. Th e addition of the attribute “just” before the rights of the King’s people may be seen as

185 Burke referred to democracy only twice in his pamphlet, denying the “demo- cratical” character of the Commons’ decision on the Middlesex election and arguing that the British constitution, though it was not based on the popular election of mag- istrates “provided [. . .] better for all the eff ects of it than by the method of suff rage in any democratic State whatsoever”. At the same time, he argued forcefully in favour of “that great and only foundation of Government, the confi dence of the people” and of the people being allowed to express their discontent in relation to their rulers even if “the generality of the people are fi ft y years, at least, behind-hand in their politicks”. Burke’s suggestion was that the dispositions of the House of Commons and the people at large did not currently meet, which was highly problematic as the forms of power “all originate from the people.” Th e essence of the Commons was, aft er all, to function as “a controul for the people”. Edmund Burke, Th ought on the Cause of the Present Discontents (London 1770), 5, 8, 14, 23, 29, 35; Th is book would be cited against Burke in a Commons debate over twenty years later. See pp. 402–403. 186 [Anon.], Th e State of the Nation, as Represented to a Certain Great Personage, by Junius and the Freeholder: and the Petitions of the Citizens of London . . . (London 1770), 1-2; [Junius], A Complete Collection of Junius’s Letters . . . (London 1770), 154–155. 187 Gunn 1983, 277. 146 chapter two a slight reformulation. To show that claims about the administration neglecting the interests of the people had no foundation, the King referred to “my people’s rights”, though still defi ning them collectively and limiting them to the context of foreign policy. Th e familiar defi ni- tion underscoring the indivisibility of the King and his people was also still there: “I have no interest, I can have none, distinct from that of my people” (XVI, 1032). Th is statement can be seen as a response to the questioning of the unity of interests of the Crown, Parliament and the people in preceding political discourse. Th e Commons replied with a highly consensual Address, according to which the House was determined to defend the cause of the King’s people. Th e Address was designed to appease the opposition and the public more generally by underlining the House’s conviction that the King “would never be induced, by a mistaken tenderness for the pres- ent ease of your people, to sacrifi ce their more essential and more lasting interests”. However, the Address extended the formulations of the Royal Speech when referring to the need to maintain “the luster of your crown” on the one hand and the need to preserve “undimin- ished the rights of your people” on the other (XVI, 1079, 1081). Th e message was that no royal intrusion on the rights of the people would ever take place. Th ese formulations had been strongly challenged during the debate. William Meredith, a Tory and previous Jacobite, carried on the old opposition attack against the ministry in the name of the people, sug- gesting that despite governmental claims of the continued confi dence of the people, “the people wish destruction to them and their mea- sures”. Meredith openly took issue with the misleading nature of the use of language referring to the people’s rights by the Crown: North’s ministry claimed that it was defending the rights of the nation against Spain while in reality it was seriously “violating the rights of the peo- ple at home”. A further suggestion was that without the removal of a threat to liberty at home (i.e. a reconsideration of the decision on the Middlesex election), there would be no certainty of the readiness of the people to fi ght for their liberties abroad either (XVI, 1038–1040).188

188 In the report of the London Museum, reprinted in Cobbett, the formulation is more moderate, referring only to the people being “at variance with them and their measures”. However, the basic argument about the ministry having violated the essen- tial rights of the kingdom, the people being therefore unwilling to fi ght and the Wilkes case calling for reconsideration was the same (XVI, 1057–1059). the westminster parliament and the people, – 147

Prime Minister North replied to this claim scornfully, attributing it to the opposition’s readiness to “abandon their lawful sovereign” (XVI, 1050, 1072). Th is whole exchange demonstrates the continuity of the confrontation between the government and opposition (which had been opened by the Wilkes aff air), expressed through language refer- ring to the people. Th ere remains no doubt that the Wilkite protests provided an impulse for a change towards new conceptions of the political role of the people. One particular debate contributed to the ongoing transition in the parliamentary concept of the people. On 25 March 1771, the Com- mons discussed the imprisonment of the Lord Mayor of London because of his failure to stop the printing of parliamentary debates as the House, on a motion of Colonel George Onslow, had ordered in February.189 Th e Wilkites were again actively challenging the secrecy of the Commons and, as a result of this episode, they managed to radi- cally cut down the censorship of parliamentary reporting. Reporting had expanded dramatically as a consequence of the Middlesex election, and the Wilkites wanted to ensure the access of “the people” to parlia- mentary proceedings in the future as well.190 Th e debate concerned the true defi nition of the rights of the people on the one hand and those of Parliament on the other. Interestingly, it also produced previously rare references to the existence of a democratic element in the British con- stitution. Th e extensive and at times radical use of language referring to the people on both sides followed to a great extent from the fact that Wilkite crowds were at times rioting in the very courtyard of Parlia- ment, demonstrating their support for those London offi cials who had protected the printers (XVII, 119, 155). Th e members of parliament were forced to defi ne their position on what the proper political role of the people was—and in more concrete terms than ever before. Th e most active accuser of the London offi cials was Welbore Ellis, a placeman who rejected all attempts to change the constitution. He interpreted the publication of the debates as a major breach of the privileges of the Commons, demanding that the practice should be prevented and the status of the Commons as the guardian of liberty reinforced (XVII, 121). Whenever the opposition tried to defend pub- lication, Ellis was there to repeat his arguments.

189 Bullard 2005, 314. 190 Th omas 2004. 148 chapter two

Savile opposed the motion to punish the London magistrates, sug- gesting that the Commons might not be “the true representatives of the people” in the fi rst place (XVII, 121). Alderman James Townsend, a Wilkite member, interpreted the case as one “between the people and their representatives” and expressed his concern that the privi- leges of the Commons left “the people scarcely the shadow of liberty”. Indeed, he argued, such censorship was just a further stage in gov- ernmental attempts “to root out the people’s liberties”. Th e privileges of the Commons should rather be seen as identical with those of the people. Townsend’s conclusion was that the Commons violated this principle in forbidding discussion of their debates outside its walls (XVII, 121–122). Th is opposition provoked Ellis to put his argument on the relative roles of Parliament and the people more vehemently. According to Ellis, the London magistrates aimed at destroying the whole institution of the Commons by violating its privileges. Th is was, indeed, more than an opposition attempt to abuse a mistaken notion of an “all-rul- ing supremacy in the people” and of a misleadingly broad concept of the people. Th e purpose seemed to be to destroy the balanced consti- tution by a redefi nition of the political role of the people. Ellis main- tained, by contrast, that the Commons alone—and not the populace at large, or even the voters—constituted the people of England (XVII, 125). His concept of the people remained highly exclusive, resembling that held by the parliamentary elite more broadly: [. . .] one of the most favourite principles of the present opposition is, that all authority is originally derived from the people, and that in exi- gencies of peculiar necessity, where the law has provided no remedy for unforeseen criminalities, that then the power of the people should interpose, and the safety of the state even justify occasional infractions upon the established ordinances of the kingdom. Th e opposition, how- ever, while it reasons in this manner, while it contends for this all-ruling supremacy in the people, never once refl ects, that it is actually enforcing the propriety of parliamentary privilege. Th is House, Sir, in its legis- lative capacity, constitutes the only people of England which the law acknowledges: [. . .] the moment they [our constituents] elect new repre- sentatives, these representatives, and not the constituents, again become the legal body of the people. To imagine any other people, either in a judicial, or an argumentative sense, is to lay the political axe immediately at the root of our constitution, it is to substitute anarchy in the room of order, [. . .] (XVII, 125). the westminster parliament and the people, – 149

Th e concept of the people appeared here as totally identical with mem- bership of the Commons; Ellis regarded it as unconstitutional to sug- gest that some other people outside the House existed, and even worse was any claim that the said people were entitled to intervene in poli- tics. Th e logic of the supreme authority of Parliament as represented here demolished all calls for active popular participation in decision- making. Ellis argued: As we are therefore the people of England, Sir, nothing is more absurd than to say we are trampling upon the rights of the nation, when we are merely supporting our own constitutional claims, and exercising those powers, which have been immemorially allowed us for the most salutary purposes (XVII, 126). Popular government in its British sense, as understood by Ellis, was the same thing as parliamentary rule conducted behind closed doors. What the City magistrates had done in allowing reports on debates to be published violated the privilege of the Commons and thereby bypassed “the whole body of the British people” as represented by Par- liament. Th is was so because the privilege of the House was originally meant “to make the scale of the people as important in the constitu- tion” as that of the King and the Lords and was inviolable without destroying the House as “the temple of freedom”. Publication would, according to Ellis, mean that anyone would be allowed to misrepresent the debates of the House in public (XVII, 126–128). Ellis’ motion that the Lord Mayor should be condemned for violat- ing the privilege of the Commons was adopted by the majority, but his claims were also disputed by many. Savile warned the members of parliament of making themselves “detestable to the nation” with the proposed measures (XVII, 130). Glynn saw the dispute, again, as one “between the people and their representatives”. According to him, the privileges of the Commons, originally awarded by the people, were now being perverted by the House (XVII, 131, 133). Th omas Town- shend (aft erwards Baron Sydney) was convinced that any repressive measures of the Commons would be resisted by the people anyway (XVII, 136). Th e speech of the Attorney General, Baron Edward Th urlow, well demonstrates how diff erently ‘the people’ could be viewed. Th e off ence of the London magistrates had been that they had expressly denied “the power of decision in the whole representation of the British peo- ple”, and even that of “the united majesty of the British people” (XVII, 150 chapter two

137–138). Th is formulation, provoked by the opposition defence of the political rights of the people outside Parliament, is unique for the period 1734–1771 in that the concept of the people was connected for the fi rst time with ‘majesty’, though, of course, the word referred to the institution of King-in-Parliament as the majesty which ruled over the British people. Any idea of the people alone as the majesty would still have been as inconceivable to Th urlow’s contemporaries as any notion of it as the sovereign. However, a recognition of the popular basis of parliamentary power was present in his ideas (XVII, 139). Once the ministry had defi ned the decisions of the majority of the Commons as identical with “the sense of the people”, John Dunning, an opponent of excessive monarchical power, pointed out that the people might resist the decisions of the Commons—even if made in the name of the good of the people—if they felt that the parliamen- tary measures demonstrated “a spirit of despotism”. Th e best solution would be to stop the censure of the actions of the London magistrates. Dunning also had an unusually radical constitutional point to make when viewing the people as “the original spring from which the three streams of government proceeded, and must in fact be paramount to all” (XVII, 140, 142). In such a view, the origin of all political power in the people was undeniable; the question was only how far the politi- cal participation of the people in decision-making could go. In this particular case, the opposition was campaigning for no more than the right of the general public to be informed about what was discussed in Parliament. However, the next step seemed obvious, leading to the questioning of the degree of representation which the current division of parliamentary seats provided: It is a plausible argument, that the voice of the nation is only to be heard in this House; but plausibility does not necessarily imply justice, nor does this House constitute a real representative of the kingdom. [. . .] when it is [. . .] recollected, that the inadequacy of parliamentary repre- sentation is a subject of universal complaint, there is but a slender basis for asserting that our voice is the voice of the kingdom, and that as such it should be decisive in every deliberation (XVII, 142–143). Th is statement implied that a parliamentary reform concerning the distribution of places was inevitable before the Commons would be able to claim that it alone expressed “the sense of the people” (XVII, 143). Th e debaters of March 1771 were divided into those who advocated the right of the people at large, outside Parliament, to have access to the westminster parliament and the people, – 151 political information and those who defended the exclusive privilege of Parliament as representing the people to discuss politics. Th eir dis- agreement thus arose out of two diff erent political concepts of the peo- ple, a division that became increasingly important in parliamentary debates as the century progressed. It is worth observing how in 1771 Charles James Fox, a man with an aristocratic background and an active member of parliament since 1768, fi ercely opposed what he considered a misleading theory of the “divided interests of the Commons and the people” as well as claims that “the voice of this House is not the voice of the people”. Fox con- sidered it unconstitutional to make the above-cited appeals to the peo- ple outside Parliament, as the members of parliament were and would remain “the only revealers of the national mind” and “the only judges of what ought to be the sentiments of the kingdom” (XVII, 145).191 He did, however, recognize that popular discontents oft en occurred when laws were passed in Parliament. He also denied the existence of two concepts of the people, arguing: “I will not diff er with the honourable gentleman about the idea he annexes to his term of “the people””. His argument was rather that the members of parliament were responsible for seeking the common good “notwithstanding the imaginary infal- libility of the people” (XVII, 145–146); in other words, because the people were bound to misunderstand the nature of political aff airs, it was necessary for the members of parliament to decide on their behalf, even against their express wishes. Fox evidently shared his conception of the people with much of the parliamentary elite. One explanation for his attitudes is that his seat had practically been bought by his father. Furthermore, Fox’s loyalty to his father Henry made him oppose the Rockingham Whigs, his father’s earlier political opponents, support the Graft on and North ministries and criticize Wilkite populism in the early 1770s. His anti-populist attitudes even made him a target of mob violence at that time.192 Fox would become a champion of the cause of the people outside Parlia- ment only aft er he campaigned for Middlesex around 1780. In 1771, Fox still considered it one of the fundamental duties of Parliament to defend the British mixed constitution against any popu- lar attempts to replace it with democracy. It was indeed Fox, familiar

191 For a similar instance, see Derry 1976, 17–18. 192 Mitchell 2004. 152 chapter two with the French Enlightenment criticism of pure democracy as well, who opposed excessive democracy as utterly dangerous to the British constitution during these debates. In 1771, democracy was, according to Fox, a phenomenon to be actively resisted by the Commons: [. . .] let us suppose that the people, instead of this mixed monarchy, which we celebrate equally the pride and envy of the universe, should instruct us, their representatives, to introduce a democratical form of government; should we act as good subjects to our king, or as faithful guardians to our country, if we complied with so dangerous an advice? [. . .] Shall we, then, do what we are sensible is wrong, because the people desire it? Shall we sacrifi ce our reason, our honour, and our conscience for fear of incurring the popular resentment, [. . .] (XVII, 146). Th e members of parliament, as representatives of the people, must be wiser than their electors and the people at large; they must protect the balance of the most ideal constitution of the whole universe, even against the people. For Fox, the people were incapable of ruling on their own, and democracy in its classical sense remained an abhorrent form of political anarchy, which meant that Parliament needed instead to play the key role in the mixed monarchy. Fox’s ‘people’ did not deserve any recognition as statesmen: I suspect their capacity to judge of their true happiness. I know they are generally credulous, and generally uninformed; captivated by appearances, while they neglect the most important essentials, [. . .] (XVII, 146). According to Fox, the people changed their minds arbitrarily and complained unnecessarily, being unable to appreciate the successes of Britain. Such an incompetence to judge the common good had almost destroyed the constitution aft er the Civil Wars, in a period of “unlim- ited indulgence of the popular wish”. Even the current composition of Parliament demonstrated how the people tended to re-elect their representatives despite their proven inability to advance the interest of the electors (XVII, 147–148). It was a totally ridiculous idea that the Commons should have no power to make decisions, whereas “the people, because the origin of all power” and “the fountain of author- ity” did not need to obey its decisions (XVII, 148). An extended inter- pretation of the popular origin of political power was unacceptable, as the entire system was based on the principle that power had been delegated to the Commons. the westminster parliament and the people, – 153

Fox was thus convinced that the Commons rather than “the people at large” constituted the appropriate body to decide what the common good was. Fox’s fi nal defi nition of the respective roles of the people and the Commons was an uncompromising one, probably because it had recently been reinforced by the hostility of the London crowds towards him in person. Fox’s conceptions of the people and democ- racy in 1771 and later on in the 1780s and 1790s are also illustrative of the profound conceptual change that the Age of Revolutions brought to the content of these concepts. In the 1790s, Fox would be the major advocate of popular power, the sovereignty of the people and democ- racy in the British House of Commons. In 1771, however, the power of Parliament in relation to the people was for him still absolute: I pay no regard whatever to the voice of the people: it is our duty to do what is proper, without considering what may be agreeable: their busi- ness is to chuse us; it is our business to act constitutionally, and to main- tain the independency of parliament: whether it is attacked by the people or by the crown, is a matter of little consequence; [. . .] (XVII, 149). While Edmund Burke would turn from being an advocate of the rights of the people in the 1770s and 1780s into an opponent of democracy in its French revolutionary form, Fox’s concepts of the people and democracy developed in quite the opposite direction aft er 1780. In 1771, Fox was still unyielding in his opposition to the mob asserting its infl uencer on parliamentary decisions. If Parliament were not alert, “the people will be their own agents, though they elect us to represent them in parliament” (XVII, 149).193 Such a popular political agency was unthinkable as the members of parliament were already the agents of the people. Fox further elaborated his uncompromising condem- nation of political activism of the Wilkite kind: “I stand up for the constitution, not for the people; if the people attempt to invade the constitution, they are enemies to the nation” (XVII, 149). In the heated atmosphere of 1771, it seemed entirely logical to Fox to view the people at large as potential enemies of the nation if they did not recognize the supremacy of Parliament with regard to the determination of the interests of the people. Parliament represented order, the people anarchy of the Wilkite kind. Th ere was, clearly, no straight development towards modern representative mass democracy even in the political thought of a man who would later be known as

193 Author’s emphasis. 154 chapter two the leading spokesman for the cause of the people. Fox’s illustrative speech also shows the logic of the language referring to the people as used by the political elites of representative institutions like the British Parliament and the Swedish Diet: the concept of the people was used to legitimate the participation of the elite in decision-making and the limits of the politically signifi cant people were defi ned very restric- tively: they did not really extend beyond the walls of the assemblies. By the early 1770s there were alternative understandings of ‘the people’, however. Colonel Barré repeated the point that the establish- ment defence of parliamentary privilege denied “the birthright of the people, who are ultimately paramount to all the three branches of the legislature.” For him, the Commons itself was enslaving the people and opening the way to anarchy (XVII, 151–152). William Meredith warned of a deepening discontent among the people as a consequence of the imprisonment of the Lord Mayor (XVII, 154). His prediction was realized: on the following day, 27 March 1771 a crowd rioted around the parliament building, with “the people out of doors” thus concretely participating in the political process (XVII, 155). Richard Whitworth, a further defender of the popular cause and opponent of extensive parliamentary privilege, characterized the confrontation between the Commons inside and the people outside as the deepest crisis which Parliament had ever encountered. He saw the Commons as actually being “at war against itself”, which might lead to a civil war if the scheme of censoring parliamentary reports was not rejected. Whitworth lamented how the people struggling for the laws of the land and their liberties at large, and the representatives of that same people, and from whom they derive their whole authority, contending for that assumed power of uncontrol- able, unlimited, indefi nite privilege and jurisdiction (XVII, 158, 160). Whitworth and the Wilkites lost the division but won the argument in the long run, and reporting on parliamentary debates soon became freer than ever before. Th e crisis also led to divided understandings of the political role of the people among the political elite. Th e diff ering defi nitions of the people would be used during the American War and the parliamentary reform movement of the 1780s. It is noteworthy, however, that the confrontation of 1771 did not yet bring about any breakthrough in references to democracy. A further important consequence of the controversy was that the publication of parliamentary debates became easier, as North’s ministry, despite its victory in the division, abandoned attempts to keep parlia- the westminster parliament and the people, – 155 mentary debates completely secret.194 It follows that the source basis for the later chapters on Britain is considerably more extensive than that on which this chapter was based. Th e public debate would also become increasingly interested in the proceedings of the Commons aft er 1771, which further strengthened its position at the centre of politics. Th e debates of the Lords would soon be reported more frequently as well, which contributed to the survival of the upper house as another, and oft en ideologically more advanced, forum of political debate. Th e British parliamentary debate on the political role of the people in the late 1760s and early 1770s was considerably more lively and radical than at any time since 1734. However, the radicalization of the debate on the proper place of the people was by no means unique in Europe at that time. Nor did north-western European political cul- tures function in a vacuum; on the contrary, members of their political elites actively followed developments abroad. We may now turn to simultaneous debates in a country from which records on parliamentary debates are even more extensive, which also had a relatively free public debate and which has been seen as having taken major steps towards modern democracy during the same period. In the British Parliament, the character of the estate-dominated pol- ity of Sweden, its threatened status and its fall were discussed at least a dozen times between 1734 and 1784. In 1752, William Beckford, a colonial merchant, still denied the relevance of comparisons between Britain and Sweden because freedom in Sweden was “of such a mod- ern date, that it cannot be brought as an example” (XIV, 1103). By 1766, however, the extraordinary nature of the Swedish regime was recognized by Lord Northington, the Speaker of the House of Lords, who referred to “the kingdom or rather republic of Sweden” (XVI, 171). It is, therefore, worth examining what the position of the people actually was in the understanding of the political establishment of such a “republic”. Likewise, it is interesting to see how the Swedish political elite viewed the British form of popular government, which many of them considered the closest point of comparison. It is time to make an excursion to the northeast to fi nd out about the state of Swedish “democracy” and, through a comparison, to obtain tools for a better understanding of the British eighteenth-century debate on the political role of the people as well.

194 Holmes & Szechi 1993, 246.

CHAPTER THREE

THE SWEDISH CASE: DID POPULAR SOVEREIGNTY AND REPRESENTATIVE DEMOCRACY EXIST IN SWEDEN BEFORE 1772?

Lord [. . .] do not let our blessed form of government fall into anarchical and lawless democracy [sjelfswåldig och laglös Democratie], which can only be cured by tyranny and sovereignty [Tyrannie och Souverainité].1 If that is to be called democracy, then according to the law democracy belongs to the Estates of the Realm in their plenary sessions, and in my thoughts I shall always remain committed to a democracy so constituted on the basis of our law.2 Th e Swedish Age of Liberty (1718–1772), an era when the royal pre- rogative was taken over by the Senate and the four-estate Diet, is a fascinating period from the point of view of the comparative history of popular sovereignty and democracy. Its late phase (1769–1772) pro- duced contradictory references to the concept of democracy like those cited above. Th e debate on democracy at the Swedish Diet, as recorded in its minutes, was more active than in the British Parliament during the same period. Members of the Diet could either pray to God to save their country from democracy or—in the midst of a heated debate on the form of government—suggest ironically that the current form of government actually contained a major element of democracy. Historians have written a lot about the breakthrough of the princi- ple of popular sovereignty and the rise of democratic debate and prac- tice in Sweden in the late Age of Liberty. Most of their conclusions have been reached by applying the generalizing concepts of popular

1 Fredrik Vilhelm Leijonancker, Fri Frågor, Til Et Fritt och Sjelft änkande Folk (Stockholm 1769), 8. Th e pamphlet ends with this prayer dated on 27 January 1769. Th e word sovereignty refers here conventionally to the absolute power of the sover- eign, a use which illustrates the logical impossibility of combining the concepts of the people and sovereignty. As Captain Leijonancker had served in the French navy, he may have been familiar with French political terminology relating to democracy and sovereignty. 2 Fredrik Gyllensvahn, Sveriges ridderskaps och adels riksdagsprotokoll från och med år 1719 (SRARP), 1769–1770 (Stockholm 1962–1964), Vol. II, 28 November 1769, 160. 158 chapter three sovereignty and democracy in their interpretation of the eighteenth- century political reality. However, little systematic analysis of the actual language which was used by contemporaries to describe the political role of the people has been carried out. In this chapter, I shall analyse the vocabulary by which the political role of the people and the form of government known since classical times as democracy were described by Swedish statesmen and journal- ists during the last years of the Age of Liberty. My goal is to elucidate to what extent the Swedish political elite (comprising the members of the Estates who actually attended the Diet and a number of political writers) understood their political community in a way that would legitimate the use of the terms ‘popular sovereignty’ and ‘representa- tive democracy’ by us historians to depict their political system. I ask to what extent it had become possible to recognize popular sovereignty and democracy as positive phenomena which could be seen as defi n- ing both the political conceptions of individual actors and the regime of the Age of Liberty as a whole. Th is leads us to the question of whether these concepts in their modern, positive and post-revolution- ary senses already existed in Sweden at the time of the royal coup of 1772, and whether Sweden thus experienced a modernization of atti- tudes to democracy that predated that of the rest of Europe. Alterna- tively, a comparative reading of the sources may reveal patterns of thought that were quite conventional among the political elites of the “free states” in Europe. Th e results of this analysis, while demonstrat- ing the important role that references to the people in politics played in Sweden, will challenge some previous interpretations of the late Age of Liberty as an era that witnessed considerable progress in democracy. I have chosen to focus on the last years of the Age of Liberty (1769– 1772) as they have traditionally been seen as a period when the politi- cal debate reached its most radical phase,3 producing arguments that have been regarded as anticipating those of the French Revolution. Quite extensive claims have been put forward about the radicalization of the Swedish political culture and about Sweden developing as a political community towards modern democracy based on the prin- ciple of popular sovereignty. Before historians can legitimately charac- terize the regime and the politicians of the Age of Liberty as democratic, they must fi rst demonstrate that the actors themselves understood their

3 Fahlbeck 1915, 330–331. the swedish diet, – 159 political system as democratic and identifi ed themselves as democrats in a positive sense. Th ey must demonstrate that the people of the age either supported the Athenian notion of direct democracy or had adopted a more modern concept of representative democracy. If nei- ther was the case, historians should avoid teleological interpretations and rather respect the ways in which the contemporaries conceptual- ized their politics in early modern and oft en quite classical terms. Th e main point of studying past political vocabularies is to try to under- stand the political thought of the political actors through an empirical analysis of their own language and not only through our unhistorical interpretation of their aims. In this chapter, I shall show that the Swedish political elite around 1770 still hardly possessed any clear understanding of ‘popular sover- eignty’ or ‘representative democracy’ in the senses that these concepts would take on more generally only aft er the French Revolution. Th is does not, however, mean a denial of the centrality of the concept ‘the people’ ( folket) in contemporary political debate; rather it entails pointing out that no modern conception of popular sovereignty or representative democracy had yet become possible in the mid- eighteenth-century Swedish understanding of politics. In Swedish dis- course, ‘sovereignty’ stood only for the kind of royal absolutism that the country had experienced before 1718 and which the political elite and even the monarchs themselves consistently denounced. If these speakers and writers had any ideas resembling what would later be called “popular sovereignty”, these had to be expressed in more tradi- tional parlance. It follows that the contemporary vocabulary by which the political role of the people could be discussed needs to be eluci- dated and the various meanings it was given reconstructed. Th is entails the elucidation, analysis and explanation of the meanings these key- words might receive through their use in particular political debates. An equally important question is whether the word ‘democracy’ (demokrati) occurred during the debates of the Estates, and if so what exact meanings did it carry? It is worth considering whether democracy was yet associated with representation at all. Could the members of the Diet attribute positive connotations to democracy by either associat- ing it with, or distinguishing it from, the long tradition of criticism of direct democracy? If we can fi nd a debate in which democracy based on representation as a potential form of government was discussed in favourable terms during the last years of the Age of Liberty, we shall 160 chapter three perhaps be able to talk about Sweden as the country where modern democracy fi rst saw the light of day. If not, we should be careful not to exaggerate the degree of modernity of the Swedish regime under the Estates.

Interpretations of the Age of Liberty as a Watershed in the Progress of Democracy

Aft er the collapse of absolute monarchy in 1718 during the last phase of the Great Northern War, Sweden had turned into a monarchy that was ruled by the Estates to an extent that was exceptional in the Europe of that time. Since the Middle Ages, the Swedish political system had been based on the Diet (Riksdag), which was composed of four estates—the Nobility, the Clergy, the Burghers and the Peasantry—who convened at least once every three years. Th e members of the three lower estates were partly chosen by various systems of election. Th e Peasant Estate, in particular, was relatively large, constituting in principle about a quarter of the population. However, the system appears anything but ‘representative’ or ‘democratic’ in the post-French-Revolution senses of these words, as the majority of the populace, including most of the lower orders and professionals who did not belong to any estate, con- tinued to be excluded from representation. Even so, the Swedish ver- sion of estate representation allowed relatively large groups of people to send their spokesmen to the Diet. At the Diet, each estate held its own meetings and had one vote in the legislative process. Deliberation took mainly place within individ- ual estates, while interaction between the estates was characterized rather by negotiation. Th ree estates were able to pass a law but the consensus of all four estates was needed to change the constitution. In practice, the Diet met more oft en than every three years, and when it did so, it could remain in session for over a year. Th e work the Diet carried out was of considerable importance: it held the supreme power in the realm, including legislative, supervisory and even a degree of executive power. Th e senators became increasingly answerable to the Diet for their political actions, and they were liable to be sacked through a judicial process—a procedure that historians have oft en depicted as an early form of parliamentarism.4 Th e Swedish form of

4 Gustafsson 1994, 48–49, 158; Nordin 2003, 60; Saastamoinen 2003, 49. the swedish diet, – 161 government was exceptional in that neither the monarch nor the min- istry played such a dominant role in legislation as they did in Britain, for example. In Sweden, it was fi rst and foremost the Estates’ trust that the Senate had to earn rather than the King’s.5 In such a context, the self-confi dence of the representative institution grew independently of the other organs of state, and this is refl ected in the arguments pre- sented in the Estates concerning the monarchy, the Senate and the people at large. A fi erce rivalry between two parties, the Hats and the Caps, divided mid-eighteenth-century Sweden. Th eir original goals were moulded by the new political constellation, but some of the characteristics of the factions that they were composed of remained unchanged: the Hat Party consisted of leading economic interests and the highest noble civil servants, who were strongly francophile in foreign policy and cul- ture more generally. And they continued to receive considerable fi nan- cial support from their French allies. Th e Caps, in contrast, had political and fi nancial connections with the British and Russian embas- sies, supported a more cautious foreign policy and were not quite as keen on economic subventions as the Hats. By the late 1760s, some proponents of the rights of the non-noble estates had also found a political home among the Caps.6 Th e Caps thus received most of their support from the lower orders, and consequently some of them enter- tained ideas that challenged certain features of the established social order, the privileged position of the Nobility in particular. By the 1760s, the Hat Party, too, had undergone some transformation. As the voice of many members of the Nobility, the Hats had originally been highly critical of a strong monarchy and campaigned in support of the political infl uence of the Nobility as embodying ‘the people’ who should rule the country. However, when the Hat Nobles encountered the challenge to their privileges from the Caps and the lower orders, many of them were ready to reconsider their position and to become supporters of a stronger monarchy under the new king, Gustavus III, who ascended to the throne in 1771. Harald Gustafsson has argued that the constitution of the Age of Liberty described above should not be seen as ‘democratic’—despite some elements of representation, the existence of rival parties and changes in the membership of the Senate depending on who were in

5 Metcalf 2003, 41–42. 6 Skuncke 1999, 285. 162 chapter three the majority in the Estates. In a number of ways, the Swedish regime remained traditional and oligarchic, and it ought, according to Gus- tafsson, to be characterized rather as an “autocracy of the estates” than a “representative democracy”. Th e system may have been idealized by some critics of the French regime, but many foreigners also saw it as a warning example. While the rule of the Estates and the lack of a strong monarchy made possible the birth of novel notions concerning who should possess the supreme power in society, the Swedish regime had not developed into anything like a modern parliamentary state by 1772. Th e limited degree of radicalism among the Estates is demon- strated by the readiness of nearly all their members to give up the existing form of government without any notable resistance as soon as the King proposed a new one in 1772.7 Scholars have also put forward more liberal interpretations of the Swedish Age of Liberty as a period of development towards modernity and democracy, suggesting that the parliamentary system provided an alternative to classical direct democracy and was progressing towards representative democracy. Th is interpretation has been defended ever since the 1910s when it came as a reaction to earlier critical scholarly views of the Age of Liberty. Another explanation for the strength of this understanding of mid-eighteenth-century Sweden as a democra- tizing political community may be that most Swedish studies on the Riksdag have focussed on the structures and functioning of the Diet in its heyday rather than on an analysis of the contemporary language of politics used in actual debates, let alone any study of the suppressed Diet in the era of Gustavian autocracy.8 Analytical concepts applied by historians rather than an empirical analysis of the language of the pri- mary sources have dominated the fi eld. Fredrik Lagerroth, for instance, wrote extensively about the organi- zation and working methods of the Riksdag. For him, it was evident that the Swedish form of government had been based on a “demo- cratic-monarchical ideal” ever since the Middle Ages and had pro- duced calls for “popular representation” since the seventeenth century. Lagerroth argued that the regime of the Age of Liberty was “a modern parliamentary regime” with a “four-chamber system” that was more advanced than the contemporary British one. Th e Swedish system was,

7 Gustafsson 1994, 50, 52, 134, 157. 8 Malmström 1877, which is a mere chronical of events, and Hildebrand 1896. the swedish diet, – 163

Lagerroth claimed, developing towards “the rule of the people”, “pop- ular sovereignty” and “democracy”. By the end of the age, he sug- gested, the three lowest estates of the Riksdag constituted nothing less than “a real representation of the people”. He concluded that “the democratic principle” of the political power being derived from the people aff ected the Swedish regime throughout the Age of Liberty.9 For a comparative study of language referring to the people, Lager- roth’s interpretation provides little as it builds on generalizing conclu- sions drawn in the spirit of general constitutional history rather than on any analysis of direct citations from original sources. Yet Lager- roth’s study opened a tradition of history writing within which the Swedish regime has been interpreted as the most advanced political culture in eighteenth-century Europe. Following Lagerroth, Sweden has been seen as a pioneer in constitutional development, as a country that anticipated both the philosophy of the Enlightenment and the French Revolution.10 While Lagerroth’s conclusions have been repeated in historical studies published in the early 2000s, the criticism which Lagerroth’s book received back in the 1910s has not always been taken into consideration. Even in 1915, his book was, in fact, seen as “unhis- torical” and as determined to present the Age of Liberty in excessively modern terms.11 Th e strongest evidence which Lagerroth presented to support his interpretation was a manuscript written around 1760 by Carl Fredrik Scheff er. Scheff er was a leading Hat politician, and he wrote the text to instruct the Crown Prince, whose governor he then was. In the manuscript, Scheff er formulated the most radical version of the ideol- ogy of the Hat party, which had been radicalized by the failed coup by

9 Lagerroth 1915, 322, 326, 690, 711; Lagerroth 1934, Vol. 5/1, 148, 179, 212; Lagerroth 1947. Hugo Valentin wrote about “the democracy of the House of the Nobility (riddarhusdemokrati)” with reference to the lower nobility in connection with the question of social divisions within the estate. Valentin 1915, 1. 10 Lagerroth 1915, 665, 733–735. 11 Fahlbeck 1915, 326–328, 330, 335; also Fahlbeck 1916. Th ough criticizing Lager- roth, Fahlbeck took as his starting point the assumptions that “the sovereignty and original right of the people” and “the republican parliamentary doctrine” constituted the offi cial foundation of the Swedish constitution in the Age of Liberty, with the Estates (or the people) possessing the highest power in the realm. Fahlbeck developed his argument on the basis of what he saw as the pioneering status of Sweden in the development of natural law, claiming that power had been transferred from “sovereign individuals” to “the new sovereign”, that is the Estates, which stood for the people. 164 chapter three

Gustavus’ parents in 1756. Scheff er wanted to teach the son that the Swedish people had preserved “unlimited power [. . .] for themselves or for their representatives, who are called the Estates of the Realm”. Fur- thermore, the Estates were “the representatives [representans] or pleni- potentiaries [ fullmägtige]” of the Swedish nation “as if the nation itself and the whole Swedish community as individuals had been gathered there”.12 Th e Estates were not merely a representative body to which the people had delegated their power, but they actually constituted the people or the nation. Th is meant that they should be seen as the pos- sessors of supreme power with no responsibility to their electors.13 Scheff er’s formulations need to be read carefully. He did not use the word ‘sovereignty’ to describe the status of the Estates although he did use related terms. It was still impossible to imagine a monarchical regime where ‘sovereignty’ referred to someone else than the mon- arch. Not even Montesquieu had yet written about ‘popular sover- eignty’ even though he recognized a form of government in which the supreme power belonged to the people. Scheff er solved the situation by referring to the power of the Estates as imperium.14 Th e Estates undoubtedly possessed the highest power, but that power was not yet called ‘sovereignty’. Scheff er was using the word ‘representatives’ as a synonym for the vernacular fullmägtige, but this term had not yet been generally adopted by the members of the Diet. Lagerroth’s thesis has been echoed by several historians in and out- side Scandinavia, in the latter case oft en by scholars with Scandinavian

12 Lagerroth, 1937, 188, 199. Th e members of the Nobility considered themselves to be representatives of their individual families. In the case of the other estates, it might be more correct to speak about the plenipotentiaries ( fullmäktige) of each estate than of ‘representatives’, particularly as the Estates were not seen so much as representa- tives but as the nation itself. Nurmiainen 2009; Fahlbeck has pointed out that the people could be described as the possessors of the highest power even though the power actually resided in the Estates. ‘Th e people’ would thus have been a euphemism for the Estates. Some politicians may also have used ‘the people’ to refer to the whole populace in their speeches, all of which only goes to illustrate the multiplicity of mean- ings attached to the concept. Fahlbeck 1915, 342–343. 13 Roberts 1986, 66–67; Wolff 2007b, 56–57; Wolff ’s conclusions can be read in English in Wolff 2008. 14 Wolff 2007a, 360–361; cf. Wolff 2007b, 57, in which Wolff suggests: “Th e nation, represented by the Estates, was [. . .] sovereign, but the people who elected them was not per se.” If someone else than the monarch could be viewed as ‘sovereign’ in Swe- den, it was the Diet, not the people; Scheff er’s statement has oft en been generalized into a universal defi nition of the political order of the Age of Liberty. Scheff er was no uncritical admirer of the rule of the Estates, however, as he had no trust in the capa- bilities of the people. By the 1760s, he was ready to extend the royal prerogative. the swedish diet, – 165 connections. In 1986, Michael Roberts, in his Th e Age of Liberty: Sweden 1719–1772, was mainly content to repeat what Lagerroth and other early twentieth-century Swedish historians had stated about the Estates-dominated political system. Aiming at making the Swedish case understandable to an Anglophone audience, Roberts used a pleth- ora of supporting literature but did not proceed to any analyses of parallel primary documents from England and Sweden.15 He con- cluded that the Swedish constitution made it possible for “the sover- eignty of the Estates” (Robert’s words) to develop, unlike in Britain, where the King could appoint and dismiss ministers, dissolve Parlia- ment and veto legislation.16 ‘Sovereignty’ is clearly used here as a synonym for the contemporary expression ‘supreme power’ (högsta makten). Th e existence of a weak monarchy did not, however, entail the existence of the power of the people. Roberts refers to a pamphlet published during the so-called “principalate” controversy in 1747 according to which the people had renounced their rights to the Estates and could never claim them back.17 According to the principle of government being based on the con- sent of the governed, Roberts sees eighteenth-century Sweden as com- parable only to Britain and the Dutch Republic. Indeed, he argues: “Th ere was no representative system in Europe which was so fi rmly based on a broad sample of the population”.18 Structural and func- tional descriptions of the system made him also conclude: “In some important respects Swedish parliamentarism in the Age of Liberty had progressed further than parliamentarism in Hanoverian England”, or for that matter in any other country.19 Michael F. Metcalf has likewise presented Sweden as “the most representative legislative body to appear anywhere prior to 1789” and “the most sophisticated national legislative body in terms of its procedures and checks and balances”.20 However, these are all only estimates of the way in which the Swedish

15 Roberts 1986, 59. 16 Roberts 1986, 62. 17 Roberts 1986, 66, 69. Th e term ‘principalate’ refers to the notion that the non- noble members of the Estates were responsible to their electors (principaler) also dur- ing the Diet and that their mandate could be cancelled at any time. An extensive account on the controversy can be found in Nurmiainen 2009. 18 Roberts 1986, 71, 217; a recent attempt to compare Britain and Sweden can be found in Turkka 2007, 9–21, 220–221. 19 Roberts 1986, 91, 212. 20 Metcalf 2003, 40, 48, 54; see also Metcalf 1985, 148. 166 chapter three representative system functioned, not the results of any analysis of the contemporary language of politics or of actual comparisons between the two countries, Britain and Sweden. Marie-Christine Skuncke has recently repeated the thesis that Swe- den possessed “a unique political system during its Age of Liberty” thanks to “the quadricameral parliament, or Riksdag”, which formed the centre of political power. According to Skuncke, the Riksdag con- stituted “a parliamentary system advanced for its time” based on an “exceptionally broad social representation” and “an advanced political party system”. Th e presence of the Peasants at the Diet distinguished it from most other European regimes and was admired by some French Enlightenment philosophers. Skuncke has recognized that the term ‘democracy’ is a modern one. Few contemporaries used ‘democracy’ as a positive expression. Nevertheless, Skuncke has pointed to the exis- tence of “the Swedish debate on democracy in the years 1766–1772” as “a modern democratic debate” in that it dealt with questions such as publicity and equality. She further argues that Anders Nordencrantz, one of the most innovative writers of the period, wanted to “democra- tize” the Riksdag.21 However, a preferable approach might be to focus on what the people of the age really said about democracy, avoiding formulations that could be understood unhistorically.22 Bo Lindberg has recently suggested that the classical concept of democracy actually constituted a major ideological challenge to early modern Swedish politicians in that it forced them to reconsider their political system.23 Democracy had traditionally been discussed in

21 Skuncke 2003, 260–262, see also 403 and Skuncke 1999, 283–285, 288–289. Th e only example of ‘democracy’ appearing as a positive concept originates from Johan Hartman Eberhart, who saw a contrast between Democratie and “the aristocratic party”. Even this seems to have been a conventional description of diff erent elements in the mixed constitution rather a defence of democracy in any modern sense. Th e verb ‘democratize’ appeared for the fi rst time only aft er the French Revolution, which means that it was conceptually impossible to ‘democratize’ institutions in the 1760s. See Dunn 2005, 16–17. 22 Cf. a related use of the modern and potentially misleading positive concept of democracy in Virrankoski 1995, 407, 423, 426, which characterizes Anders Chydenius as a “democratic” politician. 23 According to Lindberg, politeia and demokratein had not been clearly distin- guished by Aristotle, whose concept of ‘citizen’ also had a “democratic” content and hence could be read in radical and democratic senses by early modern theorists. By the time of Polybius, Lindberg argues, demokratein had appeared as a “neutral” name for the power of the people. Lindberg 2006, 15, 101, 195–196. Th is is a surprising interpretation given Polybius’ critical view of excessive democracy in Rome. However, the swedish diet, – 167 learned treatises published in Latin, not in the vernacular, and had not been considered applicable to Sweden. Th e use of the term became more frequent in the course of the Age of Liberty, at a time when the concept of ‘citizen’, gained, according to Lindberg, a “democratic” connotation and contemporaries began to view the era as “more dem- ocratic in the sense of equal”, even though no breakthrough of democ- racy was yet seen.24 In 1720, David Salvius defi ned democracy as a form of government in which a free common people (en frij menighet) “permitted certain deputies or magistrates to discharge those daily tasks of governance which cannot be postponed”.25 In 1728 Johan Her- mansson characterized Sweden as a monarchy that was “democrati- cally tempered”, because the King was elected. And writing in 1749, Johan Montin was already, according to Lindberg, “at an abstract and general historical level” an advocate of “representative democracy as opposed to direct” so that “the Estates represent the people and make decisions on their behalf ”.26 Of course, Montin did not use some mod- ern concept of “representative democracy”. He did not speak about “limited democracy” either but rather wrote in conventional terms about the role of the Estates within a mixed monarchy,27 which implies

Polybius did use ‘democracy’ to designate “the good polity”, while adopting ‘ochloc- racy’ as a name for the power of the mob. Maier 1972, 834. 24 Lindberg 2006, 114, 209–210. 25 [David Salvius], Påminnelser Angående Succesions-Rättigheten i Sweriges Rike, Samt Det å kallade Souvereine Wäldet, Upsatte i Januarii Månad 1719 (Stockholm 1720), paragraph 2. Salvius had also explicitly spoken about the “representatives” of these people. 26 Lindberg 2006, 210–211; cf. an opposite conclusion in Saastamoinen 2003, 49, and Velema 2002, 21, on the Dutch debate; Montesquieu, though calling a republic in which the people had sovereign power a democracy, had recently rejected the very idea of combining democracy and representation. Dippel 1986, 61; Maier 1972, 841, Markoff 1999, 671. 27 Montin did defi ne democracy in very positive terms in the particular context of the controversies of the 1740s, seeing it as an antidote to tyranny and aristocracy within a mixed government. He argued, aft er Montesquieu, that the form of govern- ment could be called a “democracy” when “an assembly of the Estates themselves possess the supreme rights”. Montin’s aim in using the term ‘democracy’ seems to have been to reject demands for a wrong kind of democracy of the multitude by defi n- ing the existing system as the right kind of democracy. In this he followed the classical critique of the power of the many in pointing to its impracticality in large societies where the people could not simply be assembled in one place. Th e power of the many was harmful to the understanding of the common people, which was incapable of correct judgement. Furthermore, even the best of democratic governments could end in the ruination of society as a result of disunity. What Montin argued was that supreme power should be delegated to qualifi ed members elected by each estate, with power invested in the meetings of these fullmägtige of the estates and not to the 168 chapter three that we should be cautious in any conclusions that we draw. Lindberg has also found an instance of democracy being used in 1751 in a polemical sense to counter claims that Sweden was an aristocracy. He suggests: “Th e tenor of the debate can undoubtedly be described as democratic in the sense of equality”. On the other hand, he concedes that radical writers never used the term to identify themselves with; rather they were attacked for advocating “democratic principles”. Th ere were statements in the 1760s claiming that democracy was such a bad form of government that it could not be changed for any worse one. Hence it is no surprise that the French ambassador described the domestic crisis in Sweden as having been caused by an epidemic of “the love of democracy”.28 None of these uses of the word ‘democracy’ constitutes evidence that the Swedish system was actively defi ned as democracy in a positive sense. Th e thesis of a development towards democracy in mid-eighteenth- century Sweden fi nds further support in Jonas Nordin’s suggestion that the word ‘democracy’ developed in this period from a denomina- tion of a form of government into an ideological concept which referred to the rights of the citizen.29 Peter Hallberg, for his part, has found in Swedish history writing “the invention of a democratic ideol- ogy” that refl ected the unique parliamentary system of the country.30 Th e rule of the Estates, social confrontations between them and the freedom of the press certainly created a suitable climate for radical ideas to emerge. In the late 1760s, the opportunity of the three lower estates to outvote the Nobility at the Diet also encouraged them to challenge the special status of the highest estate. Nordin has argued that the constitution was developing towards popular government ( folkstyre) in that it could only be changed aft er another election of representatives for the Diet. Th e relatively free

people as a whole. Johan Montin, Borgelig Regering, til des Uprinnelse och Art, Beskå- dad (Stockholm 1749), 69–73, 75, 77–80, 83–84. Th is is actually very much the language used to describe the British kind of parliamentary power within a mixed government expressed in Swedish terms, not a defence of some modern representative democracy. ‘Th e sovereignty of the Estates’ was not a possible expression in Sweden, where ‘sovereignty’ was widely rejected as politically incorrect because of its associa- tion with absolute royal power. Even in 1755–1756, the Estates were still not defi ned as sovereign but as the “holders of the power”. See Saastamoinen 2003, 37, and Ihalainen 2007 on Lindberg 2006. 28 Lindberg 2006, 213. 29 Nordin 2003, 64, 358. 30 Hallberg 2003, 279, 281. the swedish diet, – 169 public debate also enabled the expression of radical ideas among the lower orders. Nordin sees this radicalism as based on principles such as the will of the people ( folkviljan; it is unclear whether this concept can be found in the primary sources) restraining and steering legisla- tive and executive power, all citizens constituting the legislative body and being entitled to choose their representatives on equal terms, and noble privileges in legal matters and appointments to civil and military offi ces being abolished. Nordin’s interpretation of the goals of the lower orders sounds excessively modern, although he does point out that this was not yet “a modern conception of democracy”.31 Th ese ideas were held only among limited groups of writers. Th ey refl ect a radicalization in political discourse and an increasing ability of the non-noble estates to cooperate with each other.32 Nordin also points out that the goals of this lower-estate radicalism were mainly social and judicial rather than political: the non-noble estates fought for the same legal opportunities for offi ce as the Nobility possessed rather than for the extension of political representation outside the Estates.33 Th e Cap Party had made the civil service, monopolized as it was by the Nobility, an object of scrutiny since 1765, sometimes claim- ing that the power of the holders of offi ce originated from the people, that the duty of the state was to preserve the liberty of the people, and that the people should be able to supervise how their liberty was main- tained.34 Nordin suggests that this campaign, had it succeeded in abol- ishing the privileges of the Nobility, might have led to the system of representation in the Estates being questioned and to a reform extend- ing to a “bourgeois revolution” and to the creation of a modern par- liamentary system.35 It goes without saying that this is counter-factual history writing and goes far beyond what the people of the time them- selves said about democracy, sovereignty and representation. Scholars have claimed to have discovered much evidence of popular power and democracy, or at least of a search for these, in the late phase of the Swedish rule of the Estates. Th e existence of these tendencies, however, needs to be demonstrated through international compari- sons and empirical analyses of the language of politics of those times

31 Nordin 2003, 61, 64–65. 32 Nordin 2000, 424. 33 Nordin 2000, 402; Nordin 2003, 70. 34 Nordin 2000, 407, 419; cf. Cavallin 2003, 252; Winton 2006, 318–319, 332. 35 Nordin 2003, 71–72. 170 chapter three rather than by applying later concepts to the interpretation of sources from one country only. Historians should not overgeneralize from the fact that the entire epoch is conventionally called “Th e Age of Lib- erty”.36 We should also avoid calling the early modern four-estate Diet a quadricameral parliament. Th e Diet remained a deliberative assem- bly of the Estates, which was convened by the monarch in order to consult with his subjects, and it concentrated on maintaining the priv- ileges of the corporations represented in it. It was not a parliament consisting of free and equal citizens and meeting independently of the monarch. We should perhaps see the Swedish polity, in Charlotta Wolff ’s words, as “a republican monarchy” or even as an aristocratic republic and not as some sort of democracy.37 One special context of the debate of the late 1760s needs to be emphasized. Confrontations between the estates became more fi erce aft er the opportunities of the lower estates for advancement to the Nobility were curtailed in 1762. Th is restriction meant that well- educated men of high social standing among the clergy and the burghers could no longer expect to enter the highest offi ces, which were reserved solely for members of the Nobility. Nor was it even possible for all men of standing to send their plenipotentiaries to the Diet. Th e aff ected parties were able to express their discontent with the situation aft er the establishment of freedom of the press in 1766, which resulted in an increase in public political debate during the Diets of 1769–1770 and 1771–1772. Political newspapers and periodicals, pamphlets and offi cial documents were all printed and circulated in unprecedented numbers.38 We should thus primarily interpret the challenge to the Nobility and the government in the context of an estate society where access to the Nobility had been recently denied and the possibilities for

36 An alternative denomination for the period 1718–1772 in Swedish history would be “Th e Period of Estate Rule” (ständervälde). Th is name too can be misleading if it suggests that all the estates enjoyed equal possibilities for political infl uence. “Th e Age of Liberty” is used here because of its associations with the fi eld of the history of political ideas and because of its widespread use in previous research, rather than to emphasize the uniquely advanced character of the era in European history. ‘Liberty’ referred to the liberty of the Estates in the absence of strong monarchical power, a state comparable to that of the Roman Republic. See Carl Fredric Scheff er, Tal, Om Förbindelsen, Imellan Grund-Lagarnas Art och Folkets Sällhet, Som Aft er Dem Styras Skal; Hållit Uti Kongl. Vetenskaps Academien, Vid Praesidii Afl äggande, den 28 Octo- ber 1772 (Stockholm 1772), 7–9; Wolff 2007b, 35, 37; Wolff 2007a, 359. 37 Wolff 2007b, 35; Wolff 2007a, 367. 38 Skuncke 1999, 284; Skuncke 2003, 264, 286. the swedish diet, – 171 the expression of opinions opened up. Th e struggle for broader privi- leges for the lower estates was not a product of Enlightenment phi- losophy or comparable to the acts of defi ance of the French Revolution.39 Th e use of language referring to the people oft en emerged out of the particular goals of the participants in the confrontation. Th e speakers were aiming at strengthening their own privileges rather than advocat- ing radical ideas about the extension of political rights to the whole population. Th e debate took place in an estate society, not in a rapidly democratizing political community. To explore the validity of the thesis that the Swedish political culture was developing towards ‘representative democracy’ based on ‘popular sovereignty’, it is necessary to analyse the concepts that were used to describe the political role of the people in the debates of the Estates and in printed literature. Th e rise of such notions should be refl ected in the practical everyday language of politics. In the rest of this chapter, I shall analyse the relevant vocabulary used in the debates of the Diets of 1769–1770 and 1771–1772. My intention is not to “defi ne” the concepts in a normative manner for analytical purposes but to empirically elucidate the nature of the concepts used in contem- porary debates on the political role of the people. Th e Enlightenment and the French Revolution brought about changes in the meanings of political concepts, and consequently post-revolutionary concepts are not necessarily applicable to the pre-revolutionary period at all. Furthermore, ‘democracy’ has been such a contested concept since the French Revolution that no one defi nition for it has ever existed. To obtain an authentic understanding of past thinking, we need to recon- struct both the contemporary vocabulary by which themes related to what later was to be called ‘popular sovereignty’ and ‘representative democracy’ were discussed and the variety of meanings which its key concepts were given in various contexts. Th e specifi cally Swedish sources I have used for this purpose consist of all of the journals of the plenary debates of the Nobles—the largest, most powerful and potentially the most open to new ideas of the Estates thanks to the high degree of knowledge about European polit- ical theory among its members. I have contrasted those debates in

39 Cf. Lagerroth 1915, 665. Lagerroth went as far as to refer to the possibility that “the true representatives of the people” might have constituted a “national assembly” in Sweden by the early 1770s; Skuncke 1999, 292; Lindberg 2003, 20; Cavallin 2003, 252; Nordin 2006, 154; Wolff 2007b, 58. 172 chapter three which the political role of the people was discussed (or should have been discussed in view of the subject of the debate) with related debates in the important Secret Committee of the three highest estates and in the plenary debates of all the lower estates. I have also consulted the proceedings of two special joint committees in which constitutional questions were discussed: a joint committee of the Secret Committee, the Secret Deputation and the Deputation of Justice in October 1769 and a joint committee of the Secret Committee and the plenipotentia- ries of the Peasant Estate in the autumn of 1771. Th e former discussed proposed changes to the constitution, the latter dealt with the royal oath to be given at the accession of Gustavus III. Th e sample of public debate analysed side by side with the Riksdag debates consists of four kinds of printed item: (i) pamphlets in the title of which the word “people” ( folk, folket) appeared in a distinctly polit- ical sense; (ii) the leading political papers of the time; (iii) documents with titles which caused controversy at the Diet; and (iv) documents with titles which have been presented as radical in previous research. It is interesting to consider whether the key concepts were understood diff erently at the Diet and in the published literature.40 As Bo Lindberg has pointed out, the concept of the people ( folk) played a fairly marginal role in Swedish politics for much of the early modern period. Th e Roman concept of populus, which provided a precedent for some early modern political theorists, could be under- stood as incorporating both the rulers and the ruled. It referred to citizens who together constituted the people, enjoying liberty and actively taking part in public aff airs. In the early modern period, by contrast, the people was generally viewed as separate from the rulers and was hence seen as having no political role beyond the original creation of political power. In the seventeenth-century too, the Riksdag had been unwilling to identify itself with the people. Th e situation changed dramatically during the Age of Liberty when, according to Lindberg, a democratic understanding of ‘the people’ was emerging.41 Th e abolition of absolutism could be interpreted as the restoration of the right of the people to choose its form of government. Th e phil- osophical legitimacy for such thinking was to be found in John Locke’s Two Treatises. Locke’s book could be understood in a way that made

40 See Nordin 2000, 408; Cavallin 2003, 254. 41 Lindberg 2006, 124, 127. the swedish diet, – 173 it possible to uphold claims that the “supreme power” had always remained “in the hands of the people”.42 It is not certain, however, that Lockean notions of the political role of the people were generally held among the Swedish political elite, as the most radical interpretation of the power of the people would have violated the interests of those in power. According to Per Nilsén, Locke’s texts were used only ad hoc by the anti-absolutist elite who wanted to increase their power over that of the King. As soon as the noble elite had succeeded in this, they forgot their Lockean ideas.43 According to Lindberg, the classical phrase ‘free people’ was force- fully reintroduced in the course of the Age of Liberty, and the concept of the people was increasingly used in various political senses by the noble elite. Towards the end of the period, a further transformation took place, as the rulers and the ruled were “reunited” aft er the Roman fashion and “the Swedish people” established itself as a political agent. Th is happened as the concept of the people was widened to include the lower orders and the view that political power was given to the rulers by the people was increasingly articulated.44 Lindberg has placed the beginning of this transformation in the mid-1750s, when a confronta- tion between the monarchy and the Hat party saw the latter arguing that the highest legislative power belonged to the free Swedish people as represented at the Riksdag. In the most far-reaching defi nition for- mulated by Johan Browallius in the early 1750s, the Estates were the “authoritative executors of the rights of a free people, among whom the law alone is sovereign and absolute”.45 Here, however, it was not

42 Kari Saastamoinen has argued that in the Swedish translation of Locke’s famous work, the people ( folk) appeared as a political agent and sometimes also as the source of supreme political power. In the latter case, the will of the people could be under- stood as separate from the will of the legislature. Saastamoinen 2003, 50. 43 Nilsén 2001, 181. 44 Cf. Saastamoinen 2003, 50; Lindberg argues that during the confl ict over estate privileges, the concept of the people was extended to include many more members of the lower estates. Th is kind of rhetoric should perhaps rather be seen in the context of the Burghers and to a lesser extent the lower Clergy striving for the privileges which the Nobility enjoyed in the late 1760s. Th ese writings thus tended to view wider sec- tions of the entire population as ‘the people’ in opposition to the Nobility. Such rhet- oric did not mean that the writers were prepared to extend political rights to the Peasants, let alone to country people outside the Peasant Estate. 45 Lindberg 2006, 93. Th e statement was made in a memorandum of the Minor Secret Deputation of January 1752, in which it was concluded that legislative power in the Swedish constitution belonged to “the Estates of the Realm, and shall be executed by their popularitét” (p. 454). Here ‘popularitét’ obviously stood for the 174 chapter three the people but the law that appeared as a substitute for royal sover- eignty. In the 1760s, some tracts addressing “the Swedish people” sug- gested that the supreme power belonged to the Estates, who represented the people.46 Th ere were also oppositional publications in which a dis- tinction was drawn between the actions of the Estates and the senti- ments of the people. Th ese claims were rebuff ed by maintaining that the Estates defended the welfare of the entire people—‘the people’ standing not just for the members of the Estates but for every inhabit- ant of the realm.47 While the relative rise in the use of the concept ‘the people’ is evi- dent, there were few references to ‘the people’ in political theory. Folket mainly stood for the aristocracy in an early modern republican sense. Even so, Lindberg suggests that the Swedish political elite understood constitutional liberty as the right of the people to participate in deci- sion-making and that this conception was suffi ciently developed to justify the designation “popular sovereignty”. At the end of period, the idea of constitutional liberty was radicalized further. Th is happened as a consequence of several factors, including the long tradition of using phrases like “the free people” and “free nation”, the Estates-centred political system and ideas borrowed from Britain and elsewhere. Some writers then extended the concept of liberty to mean that the people were free to decide on their form of government. Even so, it remained evident that the rights of that free people were to be exercised by the Estates.48 While fi nding the relatively modern notions of popular sovereignty and representative democracy in eighteenth-century Swedish political language, Lindberg has also emphasized the continued relevance of classical political concepts and examples to the contemporary debate. Th e Swedish debate does not appear to have been as future-oriented as that which would be later waged in connection with the French Revolution. Lindberg’s study provides a good starting-point for the

majority. Th e document denied the legislative power of the King and argued that in a free people “only the law could be sovereign and absolute (Souverain och enwäldig)” (p. 457). Th is usage did not, however, associate the Estates directly with the concept of sovereignty. “Mindre sekreta deputationens betänkande om irriga begrepp rörande regeringsformen”, 17 January 1752, reprinted in Malmström 1899, vol. 4. 46 Lindberg 2006, 162–164. 47 Nordin 2000, 414–415. 48 Lindberg 2006, 186. the swedish diet, – 175 following analysis, which is based on the actual debates of the Estates. We fi rst shall consider how the Estates and the press presented the key concepts of the debate during the Diet of 1769–1770. Within the Noble Estate, this led to some far-reaching conclusions about the political role of the people but hardly yet to a recognition of an active sovereignty of the people or of democracy as a goal of the political community.

Th e Relationship between the Nobility, the Nation and the People at the Beginning of the Riksdag of 1769–1770

A serious constitutional crisis preceded the Diet of 1769–1770, and this was refl ected in government activities, party struggles and public debates. Th e King and the Hat-dominated higher administration had opposed the governing Cap party in a number of ways since the Diet of 1765–1766, when the Caps had succeeded in seizing power from the previously dominant Hats. Th e most extreme form of opposition to the Caps included a royal “strike” in 1768, to which the Caps responded by ordering a stamp with the royal signature, to be used in case King Adolphus Frederick refused to cooperate. Th e oppositional Hat party for its part—though previously critical of the monarchy—had started to conspire with the King to restore royal power and thereby its own pre-eminence. With the approach of a new session of the Diet, the power struggle produced an unprecedented public debate in the press, which had been released from pre-publication censorship just a couple of years previously. An entirely new type of public debate was emerging. Th e Hats, with Carl Christoff er Gjörwell at their head, began to create a medium for party propaganda. Th eir aim was to counter Cap propaganda, which was mainly published in the periodical Uplysning för Swenska Folket (Information for the Swedish People). Th e Cap organ took a critical stance towards the King, while the Hat publication Den politiske Aris- tarchus (Th e Political Aristarchus) defended him. Th e points of view of the parties had changed radically aft er the mid-1750s, when the Hats were still signifi cant opponents of the King. Th e political opinion of the voters had also changed dramatically since the Diet of 1765–1766. When the Estates met in Norrköping in April 1769, it soon became evident that the Hats held a majority, which enabled them to obtain all the posts of Speakers of the Estates and gain a majority in the important Secret Committee. No leading Cap 176 chapter three adherent succeeded in becoming a member of the Committee.49 Dur- ing the Diet, the Cap Senate was replaced by one consisting of the supporters of the allied Hat and Court parties.50 A party political change of power was taking place, and there was a revival of the old unanimity concerning the appropriate privileges for each estate. Th e estates may have been equal in their powers according to the constitution, but only one estate was truly infl uential. Th e Nobility remained the most self-confi dent, numerous and infl uential estate, and it fi ercely defended this status. Th e Nobles had most deeply adopted the idea that political power was based on the consent of the leading sub- jects. In 1769, the Nobility was still also the estate within which the political role of the people was most likely to be emphasized—primar- ily with reference to the Nobility and secondarily to the other estates. Th e majority of the population were included in the concept only in virtual terms. Noblemen were generally familiar with classical political thinking, with the Scandinavian language of freedom and with current political theory in France, Britain and elsewhere, particularly if they had recently travelled on the Continent. Th e Nobles constituted a debating organ in which all of these traditions of political speaking could interact, and it was they who defi ned the key political concepts of the time. Th ey remained unanimously critical of the concept of sovereignty, for instance, continuing to denounce the so-called “Age of Sovereignty” (souverainitetstiden),51 which had preceded the Age of Liberty and had seen the concentration of all power in the hands of an absolute monarch. At the same time, the Noble Estate repeatedly denounced ‘aristocracy’ as well. Both parties used this concept to crit- icize each other for attempts to create a despotic form of government based on a majority in the Senate.52 In 1769, ‘aristocracy’ was a favou- rite concept of the opposition Hats when they attacked the Cap Senate

49 Malmström 1877, Vol. 6, 112–113. 50 Lagerroth 1934, Vol. 6/2, 201. 51 ‘Souverainiteit’ as monarchical power had been the conventional usage at least since Salvius 1720; Ridderstolpe, SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 2 May 1769, 45; von Schönberg called the French and Prussian regimes “souveraine”. SRARP 1769−1770, Vol. I, 27 May 1769, 149. See also Olof von Nackreii’s distinction between “the most souveraine states” and the consideration of the will of the people among “a free people” like the Swedes. SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 15 September 1769, 354; Fredric Gripenstierna, SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 529; Christer Horn, SRARP 1771–1772, Vol. I, 17 October 1771, 434. 52 Wolff 2007a, 362–363. the swedish diet, – 177 for what they saw as attempts to create “an intended tyranny” in which the cooperation of the King would no longer be sought.53 Th is critical attitude of the Swedish political elite towards both sov- ereignty and aristocracy was easily transferred to that of the Gustavian regime, so that aft er his coup in August 1772 Gustavus III denounced “the so-called sovereignty” and “an aristocratic despotism” of the Estates.54 Th e latter, for their part, would then thank the King for having removed “the aristocratic power” by his coup.55 What these instances tell us is that ‘sovereignty’ stood merely for the monarch and that sovereign royal power was consistently denounced. It remained impossible for the Estates to declare themselves “sovereign” even though they did emphasize their role as the possessors of supreme or legislative power. And it would have been even less conceivable to speak about “the sovereignty of the people”.56 If ideas that would later be understood as standing for the sovereignty of the people occurred, they must have been expressed in other language. ‘Democracy’ did not belong to the everyday vocabulary of the Nobil- ity, but the word did appear during some debates in 1769 and 1770, when some noblemen advocated and others opposed a proposal to extend the role of the plenary sessions of the Diet and to include the Peasants in economic and foreign political decision-making. At the same time, we can fi nd numerous references to the rights of the people in the debates of the Nobility. Th e meaning of ‘the people’ remained vague, however: noblemen readily used the concept to vindicate their own status as legislators, but it is far from clear whether they would have included the other estates, let alone the population at large, in the concept. Th e self-evident assumption was that the Nobility held a key role within the constitution and, together with the other estates, com- municated the voice of the people to the executive power. Th e political

53 Gustav Adolph Gyllenborg spoke against aristocracy although he was later to defend the Senate. SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 1 May 1769, 38; cf. Sekreta utskottets protokollutdrag, SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 20 May 1769, 68; Lorentz Creutz, SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 23 May 1769, 83; Johan von Böhnen, SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 23 May 1769, 91; Samuel Ehrenmalm, SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 23 May 1769, 97; Schönberg, SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 23 May 1769, 108; Augustin Ehrensvärd, SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 27 May 1769, 156; Carl Ridderstolpe, SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. II, 15 November 1769, 73. 54 SRARP 1771–1772, Vol. III, 21 August 1772, 628, 632. 55 Bondeståndets riksdagsprotokoll (BdP), Sten Landahl (ed.) (Stockholm 1978), 26 August 1772, 507. 56 Roberts 1986, 67; Wolff 2007a, 361. 178 chapter three role of the rest of the people appeared as a passive one: the people remained the object of the actions of the executive power and the Estates rather than any kind of active political agent. Axel von Fersen, the Hat Speaker of the Noble Estate, made a speech at the opening of the Riksdag on 22 April 1769 that illustrates what was meant by the generally held principle of the people having a role in the political process. Fersen, as a nobleman, was unwilling to change the form of government to the extent that the Court wished, and thus he defi ned the members of the Estates as “a free, independent people” who were entitled to advise the executive power on aff airs of state. He eagerly defi ned the Nobility as the embodiment of that people by say- ing that “the gentle hearts of the Knights and Nobility cannot be closed to the voice of the people [ folckets röst]”.57 Th us the Noble Estate formed the core of the free people in a political sense even if they did not belong to the common people. On the other hand, they listened to the voice of the people at large when making decisions. Th ese two classical senses of the concept of the people would be used side by side and frequently confused in the debates of the Estates.58 Th ey might also be distinguished more clearly in cases where members of the Nobility spoke about “the common people” (allmogen, menigheten). Th e commoners (menige Allmogen) had recognized judicial rights, but they could not be regarded as politically active.59 Th e concept of the people ( folket) could likewise be used in a broad sense when it suited the purposes of the argument. Count Lorentz Vilhelm Creutz, for instance, challenged the Senate by asking: “Why have the lords of the Senate not wanted to pay attention to the cries of the people, [. . .] which has also found their ways to the throne”?60 Here the role of the people was limited to a petitionary one, but the concept of the people could still be used by the opposition to question the legitimacy of the current government.61 Creutz may have been an active supporter of the Hats in opposition to the Court in the 1750s, but by the late 1760s he was suggesting that the King heard the complaints of the people

57 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 22 April 1769, 4. 58 According to Charlotta Wolff , the concepts ‘the people’ and ‘nation’ had become synonymous as political actors and were both associated with liberty and rights by 1769. Wolff 2008, 67–68; cf. Wolff 2008, 69. 59 Se Gustaf Adolph Leijonmarck, SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 25 September 1769, 416–417. 60 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 23 May 1769, 83. 61 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 23 May 1769, 83–84; see also von Frese, 90. the swedish diet, – 179 better than the Caps, and that the Hats could help the King in solving the crisis and delivering the people from their distress. In the Secret Committee, the representatives of the three highest estates met to discuss constitutional issues. In May 1769, the predom- inantly Hat members of the Committee debated the measures taken by the Cap Senate. Mayor Mattias Kjörning, a supporter of the Court, argued that the Senate had violated the right of the citizens (Medbor- gars) to freely choose their deputies during the elections with the obvi- ous aim of changing the constitution into what he called “a harmful Dyarchie”. Th ese measures had made the offi cers of the state “odious in the eyes of the nation”.62 Colonel Fredric Horn (a Hat) likewise complained about the interventions of the Senate in “the free Riksdags- man elections of the nation”.63 Chamberlain John Jennings (a Hat) questioned the ability of the Cap members of the Senate to defend freedom and depicted them as “the purest aristocracy”. A further object of criticism was the harsh treatment of the King, recalling the anti-royalist measures of 1756, which “the nation had wished to forget for ever”.64 Th e concept of ‘the nation’ also occurred in Colonel Carl Fredrik Pechlin’s (Hat, later Cap) reference to the Swedish nation as loyal to their King, in lamentations about the disunity which the par- ties caused in the nation,65 and in Gabriel Lütkemann’s (a Hat clergy- man) emphasis on the need of the nation to defend its rights.66 Colonel Johan Diedric Duwall (Hat), who had schemed in secret with the Court and the French about the possibilities of changing the constitu- tion in order to make it more monarchical, accused the Senate of attempting to “create an aristocracy to the detriment of the nation”.67 Th is debate shows how the Hat party, aft er obtaining an overwhelming majority in the Secret Committee, defi ned the interests of the nation as the opposite of those of the ‘aristocracy’ of the governing Cap party. Speaking in the Secret Committee in the presence of the representa- tives of the Clergy and the Burghers, the Hat Noblemen seem to have eschewed attributing any far-reaching meanings to the concept of ‘the

62 Riksdagsarkivet (R) 3457, Secreta Utskottets Protokoll (SUP) 1769–1770, 6 May 1769, 42; Malmström 1877, Vol. 6, 115; Th e term dyarchie probably referred to joint rule by the monarchy and the aristocracy as opposed to the population at large. 63 R 3457 SUP 1769–1770, 6 May 1769, 46. 64 R 3457 SUP 1769–1770, 6 May 1769, 46. 65 R 3457 SUP 1769–1770, 6 May 1769, 45; 12 May 1769, 91, 103. 66 R 3457 SUP 1769–1770, 6 May 1769, 50. 67 R 3457 SUP 1769–1770, 12 May 1769, 104–105. 180 chapter three people’ and rather talked about ‘the nation’. Speakers from the two lower estates used the concept in essentially the same way. Th e context was diff erent when the Nobility debated the issue among themselves. Th e political role of the people was emphasized in much more outspoken terms as soon as no need for self-censorship was felt. Th e concept ‘the people’ was given a variety of meanings in the polit- ical argumentation of the rival parties. Some nobleman already saw the freedom of the press as a natural element of the Swedish constitution and viewed the consequences in quite positive terms. Leonhard Mag- nus Uggla, for instance, argued that the freedom of the press was a boon to a free people in that it informed the nation about the actions of the authorities and the members of the Estates.68 Th e publicity cre- ated by a free press thus enabled the people to better control what was going on in the administration and in the legislative assembly. Th is suited the Hats well in their campaign against the Caps. A further element in the Nobles’ understanding of the political role of the people concerned the responsibility of the executive power to the Estates. Whenever an argument on this subject was put forward, the phrase “a free people” was frequently used. Major Johan von Böh- nen depicted the policies of the Cap Senate as nothing less than crimes against the people. Th e Senate had violated “the rights of a free people who abhor slavery” and demonstrated “bold and illegal measures and stern hearts” towards a free people. Worst of all was the Senate’s sug- gestion that “liberty was in danger and the people were the biggest shame of the nation”—something that Böhnen considered utterly impossible in a state where the people was the most important defender of liberty and where the people and the nation were one and the same thing. Refl ecting on the current policies of the Hat and Court parties, Böhnen presented the King as the major champion of “liberty and the people” ( för frihet och folk).69 For party political reasons, and following their previous anti-monarchical ideology, the Hats gave the people a key role in their criticism of the Cap Senate. At the same time, they were approaching the Court in their arguments. Individual Caps endea- voured to defend the Senate by using similar references to the people, which shows the importance of the concept for both parties in the Noble Estate. Samuel Ehrenmalm, a Councillor of the Court of Appeal,

68 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 23 May 1769, 86–87. 69 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 23 May 1769, 91–92. the swedish diet, – 181 pointed to “the happiness of the right of a free people to give counsel on the common good of the realm during their joint meetings”.70 Here the advisory role of the people acting through the Estates was recog- nized by the government. Th is type of argumentation made the Estates—primarily the Noble Estate—appear identical with the people. Ehrenmalm also attempted to uphold faith in the continued support of the Estates for the Cap Senate. A more theoretical aspect emerged when the Historiographer of the Realm, Anders Schönberg (Hat), defi ned “the liberty of the Swedish people” as consisting of “that security which everyone should enjoy according to the law so that one citizen did not need to be afraid of another”. For Schönberg it was self-evident that the Estates were “the only and most certain defenders of liberty” in “a free nation”.71 Th e problem was that the Senate had not listened to the “complaint of the people” despite their responsibilities for its welfare.72 Schönberg, conversant with Anders Nordencrantz’s writings on England and probably with the Wilkes aff air in mind, took this as a warning example of what the consequences in Sweden and other “free regimes” could be.73 Schönberg’s points were echoed by Carl Magnus Sparrschiöld, who was unhappy with the way in which the Senate had failed to “defend the right and liberty of the people” and to “maintain the rights of the people”. As the Senate had paid no attention to “the cry of dis- tress of the nation”, the Swedes were currently no more than “a people sighing in the face of miseries”.74 Th e concepts ‘the people’ and ‘the nation’ were being employed here for obvious party-political ends. “A free people who love their rights and laws” was the ideological slogan of the Hat opposition in its attack on the Cap Senate. However, much of this language was common to both parties in the Noble Estate, as can be seen in some Cap contributions to the debate.75 Carl Johan Ridderstolpe, a Councillor of the Court of Appeal, and probably the best speaker in the Noble Estate, wished to see clearer appreciation of the offi ces of the senators “for the sake of the people” as their very purpose was indeed to secure “liberty and the rights of the people”.76

70 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 23 May 1769, 96–97. 71 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 23 May 1769, 108–109. 72 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 23 May 1769, 107. 73 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 23 May 1769, 109. 74 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 23 May 1769, 111, 113. 75 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 23 May 1769, 114, 116. 76 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 23 May 1769, 101, 103. 182 chapter three

Ridderstolpe’s defence of the Cap Senate was all the more noteworthy in that he had recently moved to the Cap side and started to play a major role in the formulation of its political arguments. Th e Senate was losing the debate, however, including the argument over how the rights of the people had been looked aft er. Th e Caps attempted to reply in a related debate. Th e speaker, Gustav Adolf Gyllenborg from the Collegium of Mining, argued that the Sen- ate had been forced to use a stamp to replace the royal signature. Th is action had saved the realm from following the way of Poland into total disintegration. Gyllenborg maintained that the stamp would never be used “without the voice of the nation”, as the Senate knew it so well. He referred to the nation as: [. . .] the informed, gentle but at the same time earnest Swedish people who also know the content and meaning of both the law and righteous- ness whenever they become irritated.77 Th e claim was that the Senate governed according to the voice of the people in all circumstances. Th is recognition of the popular legiti- macy and necessary control of government, expressed at a time of an approaching political catastrophe for the Cap Senate and aimed at the ears of the Noble Estate only, is important in that it refl ects a far-reaching conception of the people as a political agent controlling, advising and, if need be, petitioning the government. “Th e people”, of course, stood primarily for the majority of the Noble Estate. By this time, some noblemen were expressing concern over an undesirable extension of the political nation outside the Estates as a consequence of the freedom of the press. Eric Linderstedt, was worried about “an unsanctioned disease of censuring (tadelsiuka) the business of the Estates and the government that has appeared in the nation”.78 Linderstedt saw such political interest as inappropriate, considering that political power belonged to the Estates and the Senate only, not to the whole nation. Th e increasing public discussion showed that the concept of the nation was no longer being used merely to legitimate the established political order or to criticize those currently in power, but that the existence of a nation outside the Estates had to be recog- nized. In a more traditional understanding, the nation had been seen

77 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 27 May 1769, 143. 78 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 27 May 1769, 150. the swedish diet, – 183 as an object that could be saved by the Estates;79 now it could also be seen as constituting a potential threat to the Estates. With a free press, the nation was no longer so easy to defi ne and control by the core of the political elite. But how would the lower estates conceptualize the ongoing shift in the balance of power between the two parties? Would they interpret it through a concept of the voice of the people similar to that which is traceable in the debates of the Nobility? Th is was not the case in 1769: the lower estates had quite other interests and ways of conceptualizing politics. Th e Burgher Estate con- tinued to debate the specifi c interests of individual towns or of the estate as a whole and did not enter into any substantial debate on the nature of the political power and the role of the people. Only a few party members took up these questions. Mayor Johan Kock criticized the Senate for prosecuting an “aristocratic” way of governing and thereby neglecting “the liberties and rights of the nation”.80 Another critic, Mattias Kjörning, who had voiced his concern in the Secret Committee, maintained that the trust of the nation had been trans- ferred from the Senate to the Estates.”81 In other words, he claimed that the greater trust enjoyed by the Hats among the nation legiti- mated their political actions against the Senate at the Diet. While the Nobility and some burghers might refer to the political role of the people in debates over the confi dence enjoyed by the Sen- ate, the Clergy had little to say on the subject. Th e lack of engagement in political debate on the foundations of executive power refl ects the traditional role of the clergy as a social and ideological corporation defending the established order. Th e clergy constituted an important political force in that it stood for continuity in values, providing a basis for a restoration of older ways of thinking if need be.82 Clearly the Clergy were no pioneers in the radical language of politics.83 A similar dedication to inherited values is visible among the Peas- ants. While the Nobility talked about the people and the nation as the core of the political community, the Peasants rarely used these words. Th eir preferred concept was that of the common people (allmoge,

79 See SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 27 May 1769, 151. 80 R 1392 Borgarståndets protokoll (BrP) 1769–1770, 23 May 1769, 394–395. 81 R 1392 BrP 1769–1770, 25 May 1769, 458. 82 Ihalainen 2003, 406; Ihalainen 2005. 83 Cf. Winton 2006 and Ihalainen 2006, 824–825, 828. 184 chapter three menighet), a term that emphasized estate identifi cation and political passivity rather than activity. Lacking a generally applicable and polit- ically active concept of the people, the Peasants continued to view themselves as political objects rather than subjects. Th is traditional view of themselves was combined with sympathy for the monarchy. Lars Torbiörnsson, a servant of the Speaker of the Estate, expressed his gratitude for what the King had done “to save his people from oppres- sion” and “the populace and particularly the country people from calamities and miseries”.84 Th is was a peasant expression of Hat oppo- sition to the government: it was the King and not the Senate that was to be thanked. Th e argument reinforced inherited conceptions of the common people as the subjects of the ruler and as passive objects of whatever measures the King was pleased to take. It does suggest, however, that there was, in addition to offi cial communication between the estates, freer social interaction between the members of the diff er- ent estates in taverns and communication of information through the press.85 Fellow party members were told about debates in the other estates, and consequently the informed members of the Peasant Estate shared some topics of discourse and political concepts with the higher estates.

Th e Concept of the People in Printed Literature and the Reactions of the Estates to Publicity in the Autumn of 1769

Th e concept of the people re-emerged in the debates aft er the Estates started to review the consequences of freedom of the press in the autumn of 1769. A fl ood of pamphlets and periodicals were seen by the members as violating the rights of the Estates and the constitu- tion. Th e discussion focussed on two particular titles, the anonymously written En Patriots Tankar, Om Grundlagens nödvändiga förbättring (Th e Th oughts of a Patriot on the Necessary Improvement of the Constitution) and the previously mentioned Cap periodical Uplysning för Swenska Folket. In the former, Arvid Bernhard Virgin (Hat) had criticized some of the principles of the constitution, the Estates’ habit of changing their earlier decisions, and the policies of the Cap Sen- ate. His text started with a conventional description of the Swedes as

84 BdP 1769–1770, 23 May 1769, 60. 85 Sennefelt 2003, 415. the swedish diet, – 185

“a free people” and “a free nation” and continued with insinuations that the Caps had abused the system in ways that would lead to “the oppression of all the nation”. Virgin also suggested that the English case demonstrated how a monarch could successfully act as a counter- balance to Parliament. A warning counter-example was to be found in Poland, where the whole system was about to fall apart aft er a failure to reform the constitution by strengthening the monarchy.86 Such claims for a stronger monarchy had already been rebuff ed by Cap pamphleteers. Not all Hats, either, agreed with Virgin. Anders Schönberg had argued that it was unthinkable that the power of the King could be strengthened by imitating the English constitution. On the contrary, “a free people” must defend its liberty by retaining the Swedish constitution unchanged. Nevertheless, Schönberg recognized, with an explicit reference to the Wilkes case, that the English, too, were “a people enlightened by a general freedom of thought and one zealous about its freedom and security”.87 Most commentators did not make such concessions but denounced Virgin as “a patron of sover- eignty”88 and advised the Swedes not to imitate the false freedom of the English.89 Th e periodical Uplysning för Swenska Folket, which had appeared since the beginning of 1769, was one of the new political publications which emerged with the freedom of the press and the approaching meeting of the Diet. It is uncertain who actually authored this publica- tion. One suggested author is Esbjörn Christer Reuterholm, a Cap Senator, who would have presented the views of the Senate in it. Another suggestion is that a Cap called Johan Odelius was paid by the Danes for writing this propaganda.90 If we assume that it was written by a Cap, the political content of the periodical was not without

86 A. Wirgin, En Patriots Tankar, Om Grundlagens nödvändiga förbättring i det, som rör Fides Publica och des Befästande, s.l., s.a., 63–64, 69. Th e author was prose- cuted and paid a high fi ne for his publication. 87 [A. Schönberg], Anmärkningar, Wid En Ny Skrift , kallad: En Patriots Tankar . . . (Stockholm 1769), no page numbers; Wilkes was also presented as a defender of the rights of the nation in [Anon.], Wärkan Och Påfölgden Af Wåldsamheters Utöfwan Bland et Fritt Folk (Stockholm 1770), no page numbers. 88 [Anon.], Bref Til Politiske Eqvilibristen, Eller Hwar På en Patriots Tankar . . . (Stockholm 1769), no page numbers. 89 [Anon.], Mörker och Förwillelse För Swenska Folket, I Politiska Saker (Stockholm 1770), no page numbers. 90 Sveriges periodiska litteratur (SPL), Vol. 1:129, www.kb.se/Sverigesperiodiskalit- teratur/1/1_129.htm; Lagerroth 1915, 613. 186 chapter three contradictions. Th e author implied, for instance, that the wrong kind of policy by the Senate would see the Swedish people revert to a state of nature. Th e Estates remained, in his view, the only defender of “the rights of a free people”.91 He described the latter in totally positive terms, talking about “the honest Swedish people”, “the steadfast Swed- ish people” and “the Swedish people’s ancient devotion to virtue and honour”, while the Senate was portrayed as misleading the otherwise virtuous people.92 All this sounds very much like an opposition posi- tion: the author seems to have been using the concept of the people to attack the Cap Senate rather than to defend its position. Th e periodical was, in any case, seen as provocative and was repudiated by a number of pamphlets. Th e author was accused of misleading the common peo- ple and the nation as a whole.93 More particularly, the way in which the writer had “publicly spoken to the people on matters of govern- ment” was represented as an attempt to “implant the most dangerous false notions in the Swedish people”.94 Th e critics talked about the people in terms that were just as positive as those used in Uplysningen, but they urged the people not to be misled by the kind of propaganda that this publication had promulgated.95 In the Noble Estate, Hat speakers viewed the publications not as representations of “the voice of the people” but as attacks against the people. Colonel Carl Hierta (Hat) saw them as violations against reli- gion and the law and interpreted them as attempting to incite the people against the royal family.96 As the debate progressed, other peri- odicals also became objects of criticism by leading Hats. Fredric Horn took up one entitled Pratsiuka fritalaren (Th e Garrulous Free Speaker) and accused it of questioning the respectability of “the King, the Estates, the civil servants and the people”.97 Th is periodical had—

91 [Anon.], Uplysning För Swenska Folket Om Anledningen, Orsaken och Afsigterne Med Urtima Riksdagen 1769 (Stockholm & Götheborg 1769), 30, 73–74. It is question- able whether Reuterholm could have expressed such ideas as he had opposed the summoning of the extraordinary Diet. 92 [Anon.], Uplysning För Swenska Folket, 1769, 76–77. 93 [Anon.], En Swensk Patriots Bref. Til Författaren af Uplysningen för Swenska Folket . . . (Stockholm 1769), 3, 7. 94 [Anon.], Undersökning öfwer Den i en utkommande Wecko-Skrift lofwade Uplys- ning för Swenska Folket . . . (Stockholm 1769), 2, 28. 95 [Anon.], Undersökning öfwer, 1769, 3–4, 21, 29, 33–35. 96 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 15 August 1769, 271. 97 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 15 August 1769, 271. the swedish diet, – 187 despite its seeming defence of the principles of the constitution—been highly satirical about the higher orders and the Estates in general.98 While the Hat speakers complained about how these authors had written about the people, their real concern may have been that such propaganda broadened the concept of the people excessively and, in the long run, challenged the established order, including the privileged position of the Nobility. In the arguments of these speakers, the people appeared as a passive object of manipulation rather than an active par- ticipant in the political process. Jacob von Engeström (Hat) concluded that the freedom of the press had been grossly abused to the detriment of “the country and the people”. Th ere had been a lack of respect for “the high person of the King, the Estates of the Realm, the Swedish people, the collegiums and the authorities as well as the constitution of the realm”.99 Th ough suspicious of the ability of the people to han- dle this kind of political propaganda, Engeström here recognized “the Swedish people” (in a defi nitive form) as an inseparable part of the political and administrative system of the realm and as comparable in this respect with the King, the Diet and the government. Lieutenant Carl Nathanael Franckenheim claimed that these publications had originated from nothing if not from popular rage ( folckilska) expressed by attacking the king, the Senate and the Estates.100 Th e concept of the people had gained such a central role in the jus- tifi cation of the established system within the Noble Estate that a crit- icism of any aspect of the established system could be interpreted as an injury to the people. At the same time, there remained deep-rooted doubts as to the true ability of the lower orders of the people to under- stand political questions. ‘Th e people’ legitimated the use of power by the Estates, but the Nobles continued to view with suspicion any ideas about the public discussion somehow refl ecting the voice of the peo- ple. Th at voice was to be found in a Noble Estate with a Hat majority rather than in anonymous Cap publications. For instance, Rudman Bergenstråhle, a Councillor of the Court of Appeal, was unwilling to accord the people an active political role and repeated the traditional

98 Th e author represented himself as the advocate of all the Swedish “legislating” people and especially the lower orders as opposed to the Nobility. [J.G. Rothman], Philolalus Parrhesiastes, Eller Den Pratsjuke Fritalaren. En Wecko-Skrift . Första Flocken [Stockholm 1768], No. 21, 166–167. 99 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 18 August 1769, 289. 100 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 18 August 1769, 290. 188 chapter three formula according to which “a happy people feared God, loved their king, their fatherland and the laws”.101 Even if the liberty of the press as such was not questioned, the debate refl ects diff ering views as to the desirability of the freedom of the press awarded by the Cap Senate. Indeed, freedom in general was not always regarded as exclusively benefi cial, as the examples of England under Cromwell and Poland under its present constitution demonstrated for many.102 In the Burgher and Clerical Estates, the controversial publications did not provoke any substantial debate.103 Th e Hat members of the Peasant Estate, in contrast, used the opportunity to demonstrate their loyalty to the established political order by denouncing the publica- tions and echoing the party views expressed in the higher estates. Th ey also suggested that the common people could not be so easily misled as the higher estates seemed to believe. Lars Torbiörnsson (Hat) com- plained how some author had in an inappropriate manner “railed at the Swedish nation with harsh accusations when he calls people crim- inals and the like.”104 “Th e Swedish nation” appeared here as a highly respectable agent not to be denigrated by authors, particularly ones from a rival party. Gabriel Månsson denounced “unlimited royal power or so-called sovereignty” in a manner familiar from other con- texts, arguing that the accused author had violated the sacred funda- mental laws of the realm, and suggesting that his text was a mere libel against the nation and the Estates. Having read the news about the Wilkes aff air in England as reported by opposition writers there,

101 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 18 August 1769, 297. 102 Johan Albrekt Schönström and von Fersen, SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 18 August 1769, 306–307; von Böhnen argued a week later that the Swedes did not want to fall into anarchy “and become Poles”. SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 25 September 1769, 424; Carl von Qvanten published similar arguments on the weaknesses of the Polish and English republican constitutions in his Tankar om Regerings-Sättet; Med bifogade Anmärkningar öfwer Finance-Wärkets bidragande til Frihetens både säkerhet och bestånd (Stockholm 1769), 9–10; Comparisons between England, Poland and Sweden were also made during the Riksdag of 1771–1772: [Anon.], Refl exioner, Angående den Lagstift ande Magten i Engeland, med mera (Stockholm) [1771], complained about the anarchical situation that had destroyed the people not only in Poland but also in Sweden. In [Anon.], Afh andling om Engellands, och Polens Borgerliga Författningar: “Th e English free (Fri-Borgerliga)” constitution with its combination of monarchy, aristocracy and democracy was preferred to the aristocracy of Poland. According to Swänska Frihetens Företräde, Framför Engelska och Polska Regeringar (Stockholm 1771), 7, the Swedish constitution was better than either of the other two; See also Roberts 1986, 188, on the English constitution as an argument in Swedish debates. 103 R 703, Prästeståndets konceptprotokoll 1769–1770 (PrP), 15 to 18 August 1769. 104 BdP 1769–1770, 15 August 1769, 166. the swedish diet, – 189

Gabriel Månsson saw the author as advocating an English form of government where “parliamentary decisions (parlamenternas beslut)” would govern the country and even establish an autocracy.105 Here a respectable member of the Peasant Estate denied a parallel between the Swedish Estates and a “Parliament” of the English type, which he regarded with suspicion, believing that the English system was likely to lead to a victory of autocracy. Th e Swedish system appeared as quite unique in its degree of freedom, incomparable with any other and unchangeable. More generally speaking, ‘the people’, ‘sovereignty’ and ‘parliament’ were not yet concepts used by the Peasantry in discussing politics. Th e Peasant Estate regarded itself as part of the Swedish nation but did not expressly defi ne itself as belonging to the core of ‘the peo- ple’ in a political sense; the Peasant Estate primarily viewed itself as the spokesman of the common people. In the printed literature, the argument was sometimes advanced that the Estates, and thereby “the freedom-loving nation” at large, had reacted strongly to Virgin’s pamphlet. An anonymous author saw such reactions as natural among the Swedish people, who had from time immemorial loved freedom and been zealous about its sacred laws.106 Th e pamphlet vindicated the established system by references to the divine help which “the Swedish people” had enjoyed when defending their constitution. Th e constitution was understood as uniting “the Swedish people” in that it provided its most important temporal bless- ing. Even if there might exist diff ering views among the people, the form of government itself was to be regarded by “a wise people” as sacred and beyond criticism.107 While “the voice of the people” super- vised the maintenance of the established political system, the supreme power belonged to the Estates, in which “the Swedish people is col- lectively gathered through their plenipotentiaries [Fullmägtige]”.108 Th e Swedish system was not described as a ‘democracy’ here, but it was seen to contain a strong notion of the Estates as plenipotentiaries of the people.

105 BdP 1769–1770, 15 August 1769, 165; 26 August 1769, 180–181. 106 [Anon.], Nödig Granskning Af En så kallad Patriots Tankar Om Grundlagens Nödwändiga Förbättring (Stockholm 1769), 3. 107 [Anon.], Nödig Granskning, 1769, 4–5, 11. 108 [Anon.], Nödig Granskning, 1769, 6, 9–10. 190 chapter three

Th e Concept of the People in Debates on the Constitution

In late September 1769, the Estates began to debate a reform of the “fundamental laws” (the constitution). Th e debates were initiated by a Hat attempt to reduce the direct judicial powers of the Estates and to extend the royal prerogative instead, which shows that a consid- erable section of the party had become defenders of the monarchy. Th e debates concerned the creation of the post of Chancellor of Justice, the elections of the Senate, legislative measures for a change in the constitution and the reinforcement of the division of power.109 Th e plan proved unsuccessful, but it provoked the Noble Estate to dis- cuss the political role of the people extensively. Th e Burghers, too, were activated. Th e debates show how divergent were the Nobles’ conceptions of the proper degree of political activity among the people. Ehrenmalm, who had spoken positively about the involvement of the people in decision-making in the spring, now underlined the essential connec- tion between the law and “the welfare of the people”.110 Captain Per Lilliehorn (Hat) emphasized the role of the people in the Swedish form of government with the obvious purpose of criticizing the Cap govern- ment. According to Lilliehorn, “the law is made for the people and not the people for the law; when a new law is legislated by us, the people with good reason expect to benefi t from it”.111 Colonel Fredric Horn (Hat & Court) argued that “the existence and happiness of the nation is dependent on its laws, and therefore these should be suited to the true common good of the nation”. Th is meant that the laws should be benefi cial for the King, the Estates and the people at the same time. It had been so in Greece and Rome in the past, and so should it be in Sweden.112 Classical examples guided the speech of Carl Johan Ridderstolpe (Cap) as well. For this advocate of a moderate reform in the form of government, Sweden was a free nation comparable with “free Greece and Rome” where ‘the people’ had been entitled to decide on all

109 Oscarsson 2003, 422; Lagerroth 1934, Vol. 6/2, 202. 110 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 25 September 1769, 409. 111 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 25 September 1769, 412. 112 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 25 September 1769, 421–422. the swedish diet, – 191 changes in the law.113 Ridderstolpe defi ned the Chancellor of Justice in highly classical terms as a man who [. . .] can represent the voice of the people [folckets röst] before the King and the Senate and the Estates of the Realm and without fear or preju- dice and with an honest heart talk about the law and truth.114 Th e Chancellor of Justice would have been, following the Roman anal- ogy, a kind of people’s tribune who communicated the voice of the people to the decision-makers. “Th e voice of the people” here implied not merely something to be brought to the knowledge of the decision- makers but was apparently synonymous with the law and truth; this use gave the people (however defi ned) a fundamental political role in the system. Ridderstolpe’s formulation suggested that the Estates were not necessarily identical with the people in that they could be informed about the voice of the people by the said tribune. Even so, the Estates (and the Nobility in particular) were “the supreme power (högsta makten), the core of the nation, the most elect of the people (det utvaldaste folket)”. Th anks to their basic character, the Estates could never become despotic in the same way that individual rulers tended to. Th e nation could be counted on, Ridderstolpe suggested, and this was necessary, because “the spirit of the nation and law shall endure for as long as the nation itself if the nation is to retain its lib- erty and independence”.115 Ridderstolpe thus not only emphasized the role of the Estates—chosen from among the people—as the possessors of the supreme power in the realm, but he also expressed his belief in the ability of this nation to govern itself without the system falling into anarchy. Th is understanding of the popular foundation of estate- based government was not derived out of any explicit concept of the sovereignty of the people, but its implications regarding the political power of the Estates were far-reaching. Such a characterization of the proper roles of the Estates, the people and the proposed Chancellor of Justice provoked no immediate pro- tests. Anders Schönberg (Hat) supported the reform by talking about the Chancellor as the bastion of “the rights of the people ( folkets rätt)”

113 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 25 September 1769, 427. Th is supports Lindberg’s thesis on the revival of the Roman concept of the people. 114 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 25 September 1769, 428. 115 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 25 September 1769, 429. For Ridderstolpe, “sovereigns” were “lords and powerful princes” to whom the Estate rule provided an alternative. 192 chapter three between the sessions of the Riksdag. Th e Chancellor of Justice should then “enunciate the rights of the people (folckets rätt)” before the King and the Senate and otherwise protect those rights.116 Schönberg was referring here to the control of the legality of the government’s actions carried out by the Chancellor in the name of the people. Even if the Hat scheme was intended to lead to a stronger monarchy, it was advo- cated with repeated appeals to the rights of the people. Court Chancel- lor Sven Bunge (Hat) emphasized the need to distinguish between the powers of the people and those of the administrators:117 In free states, the government has always been divided between the peo- ple and those to whom the administration has been entrusted. Liberty is actually dependent on the fact that the people has resolved to retain for itself the legislative power, that is the right to make its own laws, and the direction of the executive power, or the right to apply the law that has been made. Here Bunge off ered a defi nition of liberty in a government with a popular basis. Th e people alone had the right to pass laws through a representative institution. Th ey had given the executive prerogative to elected persons, who could be changed. In the autumn of 1769, the Hat and Court parties were looking forward to such a change. An old dispute on the existence of a contract between “the ruler and the people” was also revived. Gustaf Gottfrid Reuterholm, a Cap law- yer, protested against such a notion, maintaining that the relationship between the ruler and the people was to be seen as a law which the Estates were free to change without violating “the balance which should exist between the ruler and the people”.118 In a “free nation”, this took place when “the Estates, which were going to pass the law, had previously listened to the voice of the people” and in a sense to “all the nation and each member (ledamot) in the realm”. In this way, they could preserve “the love of the people for the form of govern- ment”.119 In Reuterholm’s formulation, the position of the people also appeared to be dominant in relation to the monarch. Th e Estates were to listen to “the voice of the people” and thus represent it.

116 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 25 September 1769, 431. 117 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 25 September 1769, 432. 118 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 25 September 1769, 437; Th e idea of the constitution as a contract between the King and the people had existed at the beginning of the Age of Liberty. Fahlbeck 1915, 344. 119 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. I, 25 September 1769, 438. the swedish diet, – 193

Th e Hats mainly used references to the people in arguing their pol- icy in the House of the Nobility; the Burgher Estate was less keen on using such language. Th e concept of the nation made an appearance but only as a suitably vague reference to the political community. Mayor Hans Ungers referred to the need to seek the happiness and benefi t of the nation in establishing the new post of Chancellor of Justice.120 Mayor Georg Tollstorp (Cap) and Mayor Mattias Kjörning both described the future Chancellor as “the man of the nation”.121 Th e Clergy and the Peasantry did not refer to the nation or the people during their debates. It was thus solely the Nobles who appealed to the people in the constitutional debates during most of the autumn of 1769. At the same time, the debate in the press was lively. Folkets Röst (Th e Voice of the People), edited by Carl Estenberg, a Cap Councillor of the Court of Appeal, was among the most radical publications.122 Estenberg had been expelled from the House of the Nobility and was hence free to articulate whatever views he may have held.123 Th e very title of his paper sets out to popularize the vocabulary referring to the people. Th e basic assumptions of the author were that the Swedes were a free people and that the Estates were “the empowered plenipotentia- ries of the people (Magtägande Fullmägtige)”. Th e paper evidently aimed at presenting the measures of the Cap Senate in a positive light, one of the claims being that the courtiers always considered “the voice of the people” as identical with that of God, and another that the Riks- dag considered the good of the people the most important goal.124 Th e “fundamental laws” of Sweden were the best among all free states and the Swedish people the happiest on earth.125 With slight reforms the laws could be made even better. As the legislators had not suffi ciently considered the risks to liberty that either aristocracy, democracy or the despotism of the many (sjelfswåldet) might entail, a reform was needed to [. . .] strengthen the liberty of the realm, safety and security against aristocracy, democracy and despotism of the many as well as against

120 R 1393 BrP 1769–1770, 25 September 1769, 1696−1697, 1700. 121 R 1393 BrP 1769–1770, 25 September 1769, 1737, 1752. 122 SPL, Vol. I:141; Metcalf 1985, 153. 123 Nordin 2000, 416. 124 [Anon.], Folkets Röst, 1769, No. 1, 1–2; No. 2, 5, 7–8. 125 [Anon.], Folkets Röst, 1769, No. 10, 37. 194 chapter three

autocracy, as these are equally dangerous enemies of liberty. Th e experi- ence of all times affi rms that it has always been more unbearable for a people to be oppressed by many rather than by just one despot or tyrant.126 Th e Cap Senate was obviously not striving for anything resembling democracy in its later sense. It consistently denounced aristocracy as well. Later on, Estenberg made the same point by adding a denounce- ment of sovereignty: Aristocracy, democracy and other kinds of lawless despotic power and anarchy among the plenipotentiaries of the people are just as pernicious and dangerous to liberty and the people as unlimited autocracy or so- called sovereignty [Souverainiteten], and at times much worse; [. . .].127 Historians have also located suggestions for an extended participa- tion of the people in Estenberg’s paper. Th e suggestion that “all free- born respectable Swedish men who have reached maturity” should be allowed to participate in elections has been interpreted as a proposal for universal male suff rage.128 However, even if he was discussing the limits of the franchise, Estenberg was not making any ‘democratic’ initiative as he understood it. Even so, the ideas propagated by Folkets Röst were radical. Esten- berg’s idea of the participation of the people was considered exces- sively broad and likely to lead to a confusion and despotism of the many that were worse than under the Polish Diet. Estenberg’s people stood “not only for the noblemen, clergy, burghers and peasants but also for every inhabitant of the realm, irrespective of the estate, condi- tions or circumstances he came from.”129 It was simply not possible to allow all kinds of people who lacked knowledge and insight to par- ticipate in the work of the Riksdag. Nor was there any need for them to be involved as the four Estates already looked aft er the welfare of the people. Th e limits of the concept of the people had obviously become an object of debate outside the Estates. At the Diet, the reform of the constitution was next debated in a separate committee in which the Secret Committee and the Secret and

126 [Anon.], Folkets Röst, 1769, No. 11, 43. 127 [Anon.], Folkets Röst, 1769, No. 17, 68. 128 Lagerroth 1915, 695–696; Roberts 1986, 209; Skuncke 1999, 291; Nordin 2000, 414. 129 [Anon.], Bref Till Utgifwaren af Folkets Röst (Uppsala 1769), no page numbers. the swedish diet, – 195

Justice Deputations were jointly represented. Th e Secret Committee constituted an assembly where the representatives of the three highest estates discussed constitutional issues in terms set mainly by the noble Hat members. Schönberg was again the fi rst to point out that all power was to be used “for the welfare and security of the people” and hence the offi ce of the Chancellor of Justice was important for securing “the freedom, welfare and security of the people”.130 Mayor Johan Sundblad likewise reminded the committee that all offi ces existed for the people, not the people for the offi ces.131 Schönberg went on to deny the existence of a simple contract between the King and the people and emphasized the balances needed to prevent any form of government from degenerating into tyranny. If there was a contract between the King and the Estates, it must be conditional and was not to be con- fused with a very diff erent kind of contract originally made by the people and preserved in their laws: Th e making of the proposal by the Estates of the Realm would [. . .] dis- tinguish the rights of the people [ folkets rätt] and constitute a counter- balance to autocracy. Th e right of the King to choose out of three candidates demonstrates a balance with democracy. Not only His Royal Highness and his person but also the benefi t and welfare of the people would be taken into consideration.132 ‘Democracy’ was used here by a nobleman in a neutral sense, as an element of the mixed constitution. Carl Sparre’s way of talking about democracy suggests that monarchy and democracy could in principle be regarded as mutually counterbalancing elements in the constitution. Without such a balance, the welfare of the people was in danger of being destroyed. Th e classical term ‘democracy’ was used here instead of the more widely used vernacular term “the rights of the people”.133 More unconventional views were heard from Colonel Carl Fredrik Pechlin, previously a Hat but soon to become a Cap defender of the principle of the supreme power belonging to the Estates.134 Accord- ing to Pechlin, there could be no balance between monarchy and

130 R 3480 Protocoller, hållne vid 1769 års Riksdag uti Sammanträdet mellan Secrete Utskottet samt Secrete och Justitiae Deputationerne angående Lagarnes Verkställighet 1769 (PSUSJD), 5 October 1769, 43r–44v. 131 R 3480 PSUSJD, 5 October 1769, 54r. 132 R 3480 PSUSJD, 10 October 1769, 76v. 133 R 3480 PSUSJD, 10 October 1769, 77v–77r. 134 Fahlbeck 1915, 330. 196 chapter three democracy as the Estates were “the sole possessors of power”. No mutual contract between the monarch and the Estates existed, and the proposal for the appointment of a Chancellor was dangerous as it extended the royal prerogative, allowing the King to bypass the will of the Estates in nominating civil servants. Pechlin further reminded the committee that it was a major duty of the Senate to look aft er the rights and liberties of the people and to be responsible to the Estates in doing so.135 Th e more moderate John Jennings insisted that no-one had advo- cated the existence of a contract between the King and the people and repeated the conventional formula according to which the Swedish constitution comprised the King, the authority of the Senate and the liberties and rights of the Estates.136 County Governor Carl Rappe, a leader of the Hats, admired the balanced nature of this constitution in comparison with those of ancient Greece and Rome as well as with those of the contemporary Dutch Republic and Britain, all of which achieved a constitutional balance by diff erent means: in Sweden the balance was between the King, the Senate and the Estates, while in the Netherlands it existed between the provinces, and in Britain between the King, the Lords and the Commons.137 Pechlin interpreted the classical lessons diff erently. As the Athenian and Roman systems had collapsed because of a lack of suffi cient guar- antees of the mutual rights of the people, the monarchy and the empowered Estates, they provided no applicable models for Sweden. Pechlin saw the Swedish constitution as entirely unique in that the Estates did not consist of the whole body of the people (hela menigheten) but only of their elected deputies (deputerade). Developing a notion of what was later to be called representation, Pechlin insisted that the constitutional balance arose from the principle that “the people are empowered ( folket är magtägande), and that not always the same per-

135 R 3480 PSUSJD, 10 October 1769, 78v–79r. 136 R 3480 PSUSJD, 10 October 1769, 80v–80r. 137 R 3480 PSUSJD, 10 October 1769, 82r–83r; While referring to classical examples and considering the Dutch Republic and Britain as the most relevant contemporary examples, Rappe denounced Rousseau’s views on the social contract. Th e English con- stitution with its guarantee of the nation’s rights was represented as being equally worth preservation as the Swedish one by Israel Acrelius. R 3480 PSUSJD, 10 October 1769, 164r–165v. the swedish diet, – 197 sons come to the Riksdag”,138 i.e. the plenipotentiaries of the people changed frequently. Furthermore, he questioned the claims that the three powers of the state were equal. His point was that only the Estates (and the synonymously understood people) possessed power in the Swedish realm.139 Pechlin’s statement illustrates the degree of radicalism among some nobleman in the autumn of 1769. Th anks to such speeches in favour of an extreme form of the rule of the Estates, Pechlin found it easy to obtain funding from Russia, which wanted to keep the Swedish mon- archy weak. Recognizing his disagreement with the majority of the Hats, Pechlin decided to move over to the side of the Caps. Even Court Chancellor Bunge viewed the Estates as “the representa- tives of all the nation”, recalling the Hat formula used in the 1750s. Th e Estates, being both well informed and law-obeying, could not make any mistakes and, therefore, he claimed: “[. . .] they enjoy the trust of the nation to such a degree that their will expressed in legisla- tion expresses that of the whole nation.”140 Th is statement not only underlined the power of the Estates but also recognized the role of their members as the representatives of the nation. While not disput- ing Pechlin’s and Bunge’s interpretations, the other debaters did not go so far either in defending the absolute power of the Estates or in equating it with the people. Th is constitutional dispute at the Diet was closely interconnected with debates in the public sphere. A pamphlet entitled Upmuntran För Swea Folk (Encouragement for the Swedish People), for instance, was discussed in the Secret Committee on 28 October. Th e pamphlet had been addressed directly to “the Swedish people” as “a free nation” without delimiting the concept of the people in any way. Th e author had urged the people to take a more active role in issues debated by the Riksdag so that they might be aware of what was going on and also express their opinions: “Look into these topics, people of Sweden, and express your thoughts on them”.141 For some anonymous authors, the Swedish people and their ancient rights had by the autumn of 1769

138 R 3480 PSUSJD, 10 October 1769, 87v; cf. Fahlbeck 1915, 337, who has inter- preted this to mean that the Estates constituted an unlimited sovereign power as a kind of condensed people. 139 R 3480 PSUSJD, 17 October 1769, 177. 140 R 3480 PSUSJD, 17 October 1769, 166v. 141 [Anon.], Upmuntran För Swea Folk, Til Upmärksamhet I ett Högwigtigt Ämne (Stockholm 1769), no page numbers; R 3457 SUP 1769–1770, 28 October 1769, 874. 198 chapter three become the key concept in the political debate.142 Even if these publica- tions were mainly a form of propaganda in the power struggle between the parties in the Noble estate, they taught the political vocabulary referring to the people to the lower orders as well. At that juncture, Hat noblemen welcomed the extension of opposition appeals to the people to include the lower orders, something that the Caps had been doing for some time. Th is polemical and personal friction with the Caps induced at least one member of the Burgher Estate to use more radical language with reference to the people. In November 1769, Arvid Schauw, a mayor, businessman and leading Hat, deliberately challenged the Cap minis- try aft er being excluded from the Riksdag by them in 1765 and being denied access to the Estate by the Caps in 1769 on the grounds of his supposedly unorthodox religious views. Schauw was, indeed, a Wilkes- like fi gure who chose to use language referring to the people in order to win the argument for his party. He presented a memorandum defending the right of the people to hold free elections, something that the Burgher Estate unanimously approved even though the other members did not employ similar arguments on the popular origin of political power. Schauw’s opening speech is illustrative of an extreme formulation used to defi ne the fundamental rights and privileges of the people as well as of the notion that the sentiments of the people was expressed by the “representative” Estates. Th e Noble model of speaking about “rights and liberty” had evidently been adopted by some Burghers as well: [. . .] the constitution of the realm, maintained in the Form of Govern- ment and the Accession Charter and by the gathered plenipotentiaries of the four Representative Estates [Representive Ständers], constitute a major part of the rights and freedom of the Swedish people, [. . .] the assembled Estates of the Realm exercise these rights on behalf of the people [. . .] and have also been given the right to change [. . .] the funda- mental laws [. . .] the free Swedish people [. . .] wishing to have their rights and freedom retained have also allowed their Riksdagsmen to keep and preserve it and conversely not to endanger it. [. . .] the right of the people [Folckets rätt] is original and perpetual [originair och perpetual], but the measures of the executives contingent [casuel] and subject to those adjustments and changes which the main goal [the welfare and freedom of the people] demands.

142 [Anon.], Upmuntran För Swea Folk, 1769. the swedish diet, – 199

[. . .] everything should [. . .] be administrated so that, ne quid detri- menti kapiat res publica, and that the people’s, each individual citizen’s, right to enjoy the property, benefi t and rights which the laws accord to him [is guaranteed].143 Th is was a forceful non-noble argument in defence of the rights, privi- leges and liberties of the people as well as a recognition of the par- ticipation of the people in the original contract in the Lockean sense. Schauw also referred to the indirect political participation of the people through the authorization of the plenipotentiaries of the Estates. Th e delegates at the Diet represented their Estates rather than the people more generally, but they were understood as working on behalf of the people and expressing the wishes and interests of the people with regard to the preservation of their rights and privileges. Th e main goal of the Diet was, of course, to maintain its existing rights and not to extend them to new groups. Th e reference to the rights of the people as “original and perpetual” is intriguing. Lagerroth interpreted this as an expression of “a doctrine of popular sovereignty justifi ed by natural law”.144 Schauw did refer to the rights of the people, and he implied that all political authority was ultimately derived from the people. But at that time he could not have possibly talked about “popular sovereignty”. His view of the original emergence of civil society was commonplace in European political theory and had been present in Hat doctrine for some time. It was reinforced by works discussing Lockean political theory, like the one published by the Cap politician Anders Nordencrantz the following year, according to which: [. . .] Locke and other theoretical writers have been of the opinion that there always remains with the people “an original superior power to can- cel or change the legislature when they fi nd that it acts against the trust which has been given to it; so that when such a trust is abused, it is thereby forfeited and returns to those who gave it.”145

143 R 1393 BrP 1769–1770, 2 November 1769, 2245–2247, 2249–2251, 2253. Th e Latin quote: “the state should suff er no harm”. For “right and freedom” (rätt och frihet) as the ideological foundation of politics in this period, see Wolff 2007b, 34. 144 Lagerroth 1934, 6/2, 203; Ericsson 2003, 150. 145 Anders Nordencrantz, Undersökning om de rätta Orsakerne til den Blandning som skedt af Lagstift ande, Redofordrande och Redoskyldige Magternes Gjöromål . . . (Stockholm 1770), 47. 200 chapter three

Th is could mean an undesirable return to a state of nature, and hence Nordencrantz concluded that “the power of the Parliament is unlim- ited and incontestable”.146 Similar interpretations had been presented ever since the translation of Locke’s works in the 1720s. Schauw seems to have developed his thinking on the basis of Lockean ideas about the original power of the people and combined this with the tradition of the people sending plenipotentiaries to the Diet to defend their rights. According to his description, the people were not given any active role in everyday politics; decision-making would remain with the Estates. Not was Schauw referring to democracy, as he pointed out that in 1720 the Swedish people had already rejected “the inconvenience, disorder and peril which follows from democracy or a general popular government (Folk-Regering)”.147 Th e notion of “the original and perpetual right” of the people could be seen as a chal- lenge to certain decisions made in the 1740s according to which all power belonged to the Estates, who were not directly responsible to their electors. According to Erik Fahlbeck, such ideas were advocated by individual opposition politicians and only when they were in the minority. Th e offi cial doctrine consistently held that the highest power belonged to the Estates and not to the people.148 Schauw was not speaking in favour of democracy in some modern sense, and his defence of the people as the source of political authority was quite conventional. Th is seemed to be an isolated speech act; the other speakers did not endorse it, although only one openly criticized it. Even Schauw himself did not repeat his argument in any of his other thirteen speeches during the debate, which suggests that it was not his main point in the fi rst place. Schauw’s memorandum and speech thus by no means constitute representative examples of the character of the debate among the Swedish non-noble orders. Alterna- tively, of course, we could assume that Schauw had merely been expressing a theoretical principle which had few practical conse- quences, and which the other members consequently did not bother to take up.149

146 Anders Nordencrantz, Undersökning, 1770, 47; Only Nordencrantz, infl uenced by British philosophy, used the term ‘parliament’ in such a wide sense. 147 Cited in Fahlbeck 1916, 34. 148 Fahlbeck 1915, 338. 149 R 1393 BrP 1769–1770, 2 November 1769, 2258, 2266, 2287. the swedish diet, – 201

Th e Noble Estate had much more to say about the political role of the people. Ridderstolpe opened the debate by pointing out that the people ultimately possessed the supreme power in the realm. Indeed, “the supreme power of the nation” overshadowed even “His Royal Highness and the authority of the Senate”,150 which is a far-going interpretation expressing once again the dominant role of the Estates in the system. For Ridderstolpe, an extension of the royal prerogative was out of the question as the King could not have a prerogative “opposed to the nation, the power of which is the cornerstone of our entire constitution.”151 Th is was Noble republican language directed against the attempts by the Court to strengthen the monarchy. Th e spokesman of the Cap Senate consistently denied the possibility that the royal prerogative could be “a separate power opposed to that of the people, for whom the King rules”. Th e crowned head could not “wish something diff erent from the people, whose will he executes” or hold a position that was “in confl ict with the nation”.152 Th ere remained no doubt as to the supreme power of the people within the Cap ideology as represented by Ridderstolpe. Th e people stood here primarily for the majority of members of the House of the Nobility rather than for the people as a whole. Ridderstolpe had other ideas derived from the Nobles’ republican tradition of understanding the political role of the people. He restated his view that the Chancellor of Justice should act as a kind of tribune chosen by the Estates and indirectly by the people, listening to “the voice and needs of the people”, looking aft er “the welfare of the nation” and supervising the maintenance of “the freedom of the nation.”153 ‘Th e people’ was a highly positive concept for Ridderstolpe: the people was honourable, patriotic and virtuous.154 Ridderstolpe was defending the political power of the people, but he did so inside the House of the Nobility, in an attempt to save his minority party. Th e radicalization of the concept of the people in 1769 was fi rst and foremost a Noble phenomenon among both the Hats and the Caps, and it was advocated

150 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. II, 15 November 1769, 66; cf. Ridderstolpe’s changing argumentation during the following Riksdag. 151 SRARP 1769−1770, Vol. II, 15 November 1769, 69. 152 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. II, 15 November 1769, 71. Here we have an expression that comes quite close to the concept of ‘folkviljan’ (the will of the people) emphasized by Nordin 2003, 65. 153 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. II, 15 November 1769, 68. 154 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. II, 15 November 1769, 74. 202 chapter three by the leaders of both parties. It arose out of a variety of factors: the need to legitimate opposition to the Cap Senate, the need to justify changes in the constitution, a reaction against attempts to strengthen the monarchy and attempts to counter the rise of the Hats. Much of the radical language used to refer to the people was, at that stage, shared by both sides of the Nobility. A speech by Otto Henrik de Frese also illustrates the central status of references to the people in the rhetoric of the Nobility in 1769. Frese defi ned the main purpose of the constitution as being to ensure “the happiness of the nation and the people” and the duty of both the King and the “empowered” Estates as being to “maintain the freedom of the people”. For him, the Estates were almighty, being responsible to no higher power. Anyone who challenged the title of the Estates as “empowered” would, according to Frese, jeopardize the rights of the people.155 Th is language of the people legitimated the dominant status of the Estates in general and the Nobility in particular in relation to the King. In Frese’s view, the system had only been strengthened since the freedom of the press had made it easier to hear “the voice of the people”.156 Such a recognition of the value of active debate outside the Diet refl ects the optimistic attitudes of some Noble party politicians who believed that they had benefi ted from the new forms of political propaganda. By the time of the following Riksdag, attitudes towards free public debate would become much less favourable on all sides, particularly among the Nobility. A fi nal remark on Frese’s thinking is apposite. When comparing the Swedish constitution with others, Frese turned not to Athens but to Sparta as a model of a mixed constitution; it had, according to him, maintained its fl ourishing position for 800 years by preserving its laws.157 Not unlike some British comparisons, a Swedish nobleman was here expressing his admiration for the supposedly virtuous and militaristic Sparta as an example over the democratic and potentially anarchical Athenian political system. Th ere were also those who con- sidered the Swedish constitution better than any other, including the classical ones.158

155 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. II, 15 November 1769, 79–80, 84, 87. 156 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. II, 15 November 1769, 86. 157 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. II, 15 November 1769, 80. 158 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. II, 15 November 1769, 89. the swedish diet, – 203

Th e Noble Estate and the Meaning of ‘Democracy’ in the Autumn of 1769

In November 1769, the attempt to change the constitution generated some unusual disquisitions on the meaning of ‘democracy’ and on the possibility that the rule of the Estates might turn into democracy. However, it is doubtful whether these constituted any milestone on the road to democracy in a modern sense. Th e power of the people, as articulated by some noblemen, did not yet stand for democracy in any revolutionary sense. Th e exchange of views that followed was strictly restricted to the Noble Estate. It was provoked by Lars Herman Gyllenhaal’s memoran- dum proposing that some questions of fi nance and foreign policy could be discussed in the plenary sessions of the Estates, including the Peasant Estate, instead of being confi ned to the exclusive Secret Com- mittee.159 Th e reactions show where the limits of popular rule lay in the opinion of the majority of the Noble Estate. While the political role of the people and sometimes even the democratic element within the constitution had been viewed in positive terms, the inclusion of the representatives of the Peasantry in economic and strategic decision- making remained unthinkable for many noblemen. ‘Democracy’ now provided a concept by which such aspirations could be rejected. Th e extension of decision-making to plenary sessions was presented as an attack on the principles of the constitution and an attempt to reveal secrets of the realm to foreign powers. Councillor Christer Horn, an independent, considered it absurd to make questions of for- eign policy topics of public discussion among a perhaps less cautious and vacillating common people. According to him, Gyllenhaal’s pro- posal tended to “once and for all overthrow the form of government in a most dangerous manner and turn our government into a democ- racy”.160 In a democracy, “the Peasant Estate concerns itself with the aff airs of the cabinet, and the common people (menigheten) judge over the proposals of foreign courts”.161 Such an involvement of the com- moners and the Peasants in particular in decision-making sounded

159 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. II, 28 November 1769, 148–149. 160 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. II, 28 November 1769, 152. 161 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. II, 28 November 1769, 152. 204 chapter three very strange in the context of classical political thought and also in the international context of 1769. Th e majority agreed that the Peasants should stay excluded as no democracy was desired. In a similar vein to Horn, Count Lorentz Vil- helm Creutz argued: If the plenary sessions, as seems to be happening, begin little by little to move to what according to the law belongs to the King, the Senate and the Secret Committee, the form of government will be gradually trans- formed into a democracy.162 According to Creutz, the practices of exclusive decision-making should be retained; otherwise there was a real risk of democracy growing within the Riksdag. While many noblemen had underlined the polit- ical role of the people when vindicating the infl uence of their own estate and party in government, there were few defenders of what were seen as outright democratic practices, and it was suspected that they might be in the pay of foreign powers that wished to keep the Swed- ish monarchy weak and to prevent France from benefi ting from its Swedish alliance. Only two noblemen spoke on behalf of democracy in November 1769. Fredrik Gyllensvahn, a radical Cap, who must have been familiar with the language of politics of the Dutch Republic aft er serving its army, supported Gyllenhaal’s proposal for the extension of decision- making to plenary sessions. Gyllensvahn was known for his readiness to take matters to extremes, and this certainly decreased the credibility of this particular speech act. However, his speech demonstrates that the numerous vindications of the rights of the people could lead to a radicalization of the concept of democracy as well. He had previously defended majority decisions and responsible government, which sug- gests that he was intentionally arguing that the constitution allowed the plenary sessions to discuss whatever they liked. Referring to Horn’s and Creutz’s uses of the concept of democracy, he declared in pro- vocative terms: If that is to be called democracy, then according to the law democracy belongs to the Estates of the Realm in their plenary sessions, and I shall always remain in my thoughts committed to a so-constituted democracy based on our law.163

162 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. II, 28 November 1769, 155. 163 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. II, 28 November 1769, 160. the swedish diet, – 205

Th is description of democracy as a positively understood element of the constitution, arising out of arguments about the power of the Estates originating from the people, went further than any other in either the British Parliament or the Swedish Riksdag in the period studied here. Gyllensvahn’s speech act was a restatement of preceding claims that the proposed procedural change would lead to democracy and of more cautious references to a democratic element in the con- stitution. It did not defi ne the entire rule of the Estates as democ- racy. Even less was it a call for some kind of ‘democratization’ of the representative system. It was a defence of a proposed procedural change that would increase the infl uence of the existing lower estates, among whom, importantly, the Cap party continued to enjoy more support than among the Nobility. While earlier speakers based their arguments on the pejorative senses of the classical concept of democ- racy, Gyllensvahn turned to the theoretical tradition of mixed monar- chy within which limited democracy did have a legitimate place. Th e fact that such a defence of the democratic element was possible sug- gests that the concept had the potential to take on new meanings. A re-evaluation of the status of democracy within the classical model of a mixed constitution had thus become possible, albeit only in the minds of a few maverick noblemen. Th e opposing Hat argument came from Anders Schönberg. Accord- ing to him, no democracy of the suggested kind was needed as the members of the Secret Committee were already elected by the (three higher) estates and thereby “represented” (ræpresenterar / ræpresen- teras) them in the Diet.164 As the representation of the Estates was thus realized, there was no need for ideas such as the people as a whole being represented by the Estates. Th e representation of the Estates, not the people, remained the key idea of the Hat conception of the consti- tution. Th e concepts of “representative” estates and the “representa- tion” of the estates occurred in public debates as well.165 Only the most radical Cap echelons suggested that the members of the Riksdag should be seen as “representing the people itself ”.166 Th e other spokesman for the democratic element was Carl Fredrik Pechlin, a former Hat who was approaching the Cap party because of

164 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. II, 28 November 1769, 161. 165 [Anon.], Afh andling om Engellands, och Polens Borgerliga Författningar (Stock- holm 1771), no page numbers. 166 [Anon.], Folkets Röst, 1769, No. 16, 62. 206 chapter three the rising sympathy among the Hats for a strengthened monarchy. Th e ideological motivation for Pechlin’s speech is obvious: he had consis- tently opposed attempts to increase the royal prerogative though he had doubts about republican government as well. A further reason for his stance was a common one in the struggle between the Hats and Caps in the Age of Liberty: in November 1769 he had been bribed by Russian diplomats to join the Cap side.167 Ever since the 1740s, the Caps and the Russians had shared the goal of keeping the power of the Swedish King in check and maintaining the rule of the Estates along with their party divisions. Speaking to his fellow noblemen, many of whom doubted his polit- ical integrity, Pechlin saw nothing that would lead to democracy in the proposal that the plenary sessions should be better informed by the Secret Committee. In his view, the supreme power belonged to the plenary sessions of the Estates. While there had been a risk of the rise of direct democracy during a controversy on the responsibility of the members to their electors in the 1740s, there was no longer such a risk. Pechlin, despite his radical views, denied all intentions to introduce democracy, which indicates that democracy was neither a goal nor a term of self-identifi cation for even the most radical members of the Swedish political elite: Constitutions are oft en created with plans that depend on current condi- tions. Whether it be aristocracy or democracy, [. . .]. Th is is not about establishing democracy. As long as the informed Estates take care of the constitution, there will never be any democracy here. As far as I remem- ber, just once were we in danger of democracy, and that was when the question about principalate was put forward; [. . .].168 Pechlin’s point was, despite his support for Gyllenhaal, that the Swedish rule of the Estates was radically diff erent from democracy. Democracy in the classical sense in which he understood it would have entailed the direct engagement of the people at large in decision-mak- ing. While the Hats saw the inclusion of the Peasant Estate in the debates as the rise of this kind of democracy, some radical Caps will- ingly drew a distinction between democracy and the equal engagement

167 Roberts 1986, 175. 168 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. II, 28 November 1769, 173, 175; In the anonymous pamphlet Upmuntran För Swea Folk, which had been mentioned in the Secret Com- mittee a month earlier, Pechlin had been described as a defender of the freedom of the Swedish people and the rights of the nation. the swedish diet, – 207 of the Estates in the decision-making process. Both stances were moti- vated by strong party-political interests: the Hats wanted to keep the rule of “the people” in the hands of the higher Hat nobility in the Secret Committee, while some Caps wanted to reform this so that the non- noble estates with their Cap majorities would be involved in decision- making. However, Gyllensvahn was the only member who represented the latter alternative as “democracy”. Pechlin’s speech refl ected a conception of the Swedish form of government as a mixed government that included elements of aristoc- racy and democracy, which were viewed in terms not that diff erent from the established British notions. Th e purpose of the democratic element was to balance the aristocratic one; democracy was not a goal as such, although the democratic element needed to be slightly strengthened. Nor did the existence of such an element entail that the people at large should be allowed to live without the regulation of the powers that be: [. . .] our history books show that the realm has oft en been under monar- chical and aristocratic power; monarchy when the kings have ruled on their own; aristocracy when the power has been held by the Senate or the business magnates. Aristocracy can also exist if power remains in the Secret Committee and certain factions make themselves holders of the reins. If our constitution is a mixed one and consists of both aristocracy and democracy [componerat och aristocrati o democratisk [sic]], extremes on both sides would be avoided. Not too much power for the Senate, the Secret Committee or the business magnates, nor any licence to be lawless for the people.169 Pechlin concluded that Gyllenhaal’s memorandum did not aim at a democratic coup but was a well-intended attempt to maintain “the freedom the nation” and “the benefi t of the people” within a mixed government.170 It is tempting to read more into this speech than it really contained. Lagerroth saw Pechlin as an advocate of “the representative system” in which “the people were the possessors of power” and were represented by the Estates. Pechlin had pointed out in a committee debate that “the people are empowered” in being able to send diff erent persons to the Riksdag. Lagerroth interpreted this as a desire to limit the power

169 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. II, 28 November 1769, 173–174. 170 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. II, 28 November 1769, 174. 208 chapter three of the Riksdag in favour of the people.171 However, Pechlin did not argue for popular representation or representative democracy. Th e Noble Estate decided not to send the memorandum to the other estates,172 which blocked any possibility of further debates on democ- racy there. Th e motion itself was seen as so foolhardy that Gyllenhaal was prosecuted for having made an illegal proposal.173 In 1769 the advocates of a democratic element in the form of government still remained a clear minority within the Noble Estate. In the meantime, the public debate off ered some alternative per- spectives on the political role of the people. A pamphlet written by the Councillor for Commerce, Johan Fredrik Kryger, recognized the key role that the people played in the passing of laws but refrained from viewing this arrangement as democratic. Nor, according to Kryger, were all the inhabitants of the realm to be involved in the legislative process in the fi rst place. In Kryger’s formulations, infl uenced by Mon- tesquieu, persons authorized by the people, and not the populace at large, exercised the power of the people in a free state: [. . .] I call that state free in which the legislative power lies with the people. [. . .] A state can be free without being totally democratic. A peo- ple can commission one or more persons to take care of the executive power and still possess its freedom insofar as it can itself enact the laws according to which it wants to be governed and to supervise how they are administrated by those whose task it is the implementation of execu- tive power. [. . .] legislative power and the power to demand accountability lie with the people. Th ese can never, without all too great a disorder be exercised by the common people at large, but they have to take place through plenipotentiaries chosen specifi cally for that purpose. But [. . .] these [. . .] are chosen from among all the common people of the state; [. . .].174 Th e rest of the Riksdag in 1769–1770 saw no real debate on the politi- cal role of the people although proposals anticipating the rise of dis- putes over the privileges of the Estates were already being made. When a proposal for privileges for the Peasant Estate was put forward by Jonas Olofsson Norberg in January 1770, the emphasis was primarily

171 Lagerroth 1915, 622–623; Lagerroth 1934, 6/2, 204. 172 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. II, 28 November 1769, 179. Th e proposal received 335 votes for and 483 against. 173 SRARP 1769–1770, Vol. II, 2 December 1769, 184. 174 J.F. Kryger, Tankar om et Nationelt Intresse i Fria Stater och i synnerhet i Swer- ige (Stockholm 1769), 3, 7. Cf. Gjörwell’s writings during the following Riksdag. the swedish diet, – 209 on economic rights and not on extended political ones.175 Th e Peas- ants made no political use of references to the people to legitimate their demands but merely pointed out that “the liberties and rights of the Peasant Estate are as sacred as the other ones protected by the fundamental laws”.176 However, it is not out of the question that there was a gradually rising political consciousness among the Peasants. Th e activities of their plenipotentiaries at the Riksdag had increased politi- cal awareness and led to the publication of writings in which the mem- bers of the estate called for the representation of the Peasantry in the Secret Committee. First and foremost, however, they demanded equal treatment with the other estates in economic and judicial matters.177 Th e most extensive notions of the political rights of the people and of the existence of a democratic element within the constitution emerged among the Noble Estate at the Riksdag of 1769−1770. At the same time, the Nobles were the fi ercest opponents of democracy, being concerned to maintain rather than to reform a system that was so advantageous to them. Th e involvement of the Peasant Estate in deci- sions on the economy and foreign policy appeared to most noblemen, and Hats in particular, to be a type of democracy they did not want.

Increasing Contestability of the Concept ‘the People’ during the Riksdag of 1771–1772

Th e party-political situation changed quite dramatically between the Diets of 1769–1770 and 1771–1772.178 When the new Riksdag con- vened in spring 1771, the ruling Hat and Court parties had a majority only in the Noble Estate, while the Caps dominated all the three lower estates.179 Th e Caps of the lower estates had used the concept of the people sparingly when their party had been in power during the Diet

175 Th e proposal for privileges for the non-noble estates, including the Peasants, had initially been made by Alexander Kepplerus, who aimed at reforming rather than chal- lenging the estate system and wished primarily to promote the interests of his home town. Nurmiainen 2003, 413. See also Nordin 2000, 394, 401. 176 BdP 1769–1770, 18 January 1770, 473–474; 3 February 1770, 561–563. Privileges for the Peasant Estate had also been proposed during the Riksdag of 1765–1766, but no progress had been made on the issue. Nordin 2003, 62. 177 Claréus 2003, 407. 178 For the original Swedish citations in the rest of this chapter, see an earlier ver- sion which has been published in Ihalainen 2008a. 179 Lagerroth 1934, 6/2, 209. 210 chapter three of 1769–1770. Radical Cap speeches in favour of popular power and the democratic element of the constitution had remained exceptions in the House of the Nobility. And among the Burghers, a radical Hat leader had been the only outspoken proponent of the rights of the people. By 1771, however, the Cap opposition in the lower orders was making much wider use of references to the people, while the Hats and the Nobility more generally had become increasingly cautious in their use of the appeals to the people that had previously been characteristic of them. In the opening speeches at the Diet of 1771−1772, the concept of the people still retained its prominent place. King Gustavus III was well aware of the persuasive potential of words like “the people” and “citizen” for infl uencing the members of Riksdag and chose to describe himself as “the fi rst citizen (medborgare) in a free people”. He also said that it was his goal to rule over “a free people” so that the Swedes would become “the most fortunate people on earth”.180 Th e Speaker of the Noble Estate, Axel Gabriel Leijonhufwud, replied with the tradi- tional Noble rhetoric of references to the people, mentioning “the Swedish people” in general as well as “the Swedish people assembled at a general meeting of the realm”.181 Th e prevalent notion of the Nobility and the other Estates as constituting the politically active Swedish people and not merely representing it is visible in a formula- tion which stated that the Nobility “together with the rest of the Swed- ish people” met the King at the Diet.182 Th e Swedish people was symbolically present, and this constituted an opportunity for Leijon- hufwud to express established views about the role of the people in decision-making. In the public debate, too, the notion of the Estates as the delegates, the elected plenipotentiaries of the people, continued to occasionally appear. An important change in the content of the debate in the press was also taking place. As Marie-Christine Skuncke has demonstrated, Noble party leaders were beginning to lose their control over the press as writers from the commoner estates increasingly attacked their spe- cial privileges. Writings criticizing the Nobility appeared mostly in papers supported by the Cap Party, whose fi nancial sponsors were

180 Sveriges ridderskaps och adels riksdagsprotokoll från och med år 1719 (SRARP), 1771–1772 (Stockholm 1969), Vol. I, 25 June 1771, 25–26. 181 SRARP, Vol. I, 25 June 1771, 26–28; Lagerroth 1934, 6/2, 209. 182 SRARP, Vol. I, 25 June 1771, 28. the swedish diet, – 211 mainly from abroad, particularly Britain, Russia and Denmark. Publi- cations supporting the Court similarly continued to receive fi nancial backing from the French Embassy. Th e most heated issue of the Diet and the press debates was over the possibility of extending privileges to the non-noble estates. Newspapers such Dagligt Allehande (Daily Miscellaneous) would report regularly on debates in the Estates in the autumn of 1771 and spring of 1772.183 Th e use of references to the people in these publications was not strictly divided according to Cap and Hat lines of argumentation. Th e confrontation was one between estates rather than between parties. Carl Ingman, a leading publicist, described the constitution in con- ventional terms as one in which “the Swedish people” had deposited its freedom and security “in the hands of its plenipotentiaries (Fullmäk- tiges hander)” and placed the supreme power “in the hands of friends and fellow citizens”. Ingman, hired by a Hat leader and hence eager to defend the privileges of the Nobility, maintained that the constitution functioned so well that “the trust of the people” had never been betrayed.184 Ingman’s appeal to the members of the Diet illustrates the Nobles’ view of the political role of the people: Free Swedish men! You who, as the trusted ones of the people, have been raised from among your fellow citizens to be their highest judge, in whose hands we in good faith have laid our welfare and that of our children, it is your ears that should be open to the voice of the Swedish people, [. . .] you cannot abuse the rights of the entire nation [. . .].185 Ingman combined this Noble republican notion of the members of the Diet as the judges of the people with expressions of sympathy for the Court, admiring a monarch who was actively supported by the Swed- ish people and seeing the Estates as being “the plenipotentiaries of Sweden” who would be setting “the crown on the head of Gustavus on behalf of the Swedish people”:186 When speaking about the coronation, Ingman combined the terms ‘people’ and ‘representative’ in its for- eign forms (representative, representant), something that was seldom done at the actual Diet, where the vernacular term ( fullmäktig) was

183 Skuncke 2003, 418. 184 [Carl Ingman], Svenska Folkets Röst, Framburen Inför Rikets Församlade Ständer Vid Riksdagen 1771 (Stockholm 1771), 2. 185 [Ingman], Svenska Folkets Röst, 1771, 7. 186 [Ingman], Svenska Folkets Röst, 1771, 13–14. 212 chapter three favoured: “Be aware that the people who have made you their repre- sentatives pays most careful attention to all your steps, [. . .].”187 At the Diet, it was the Accession Charter together with the con- nected question of the privileges of the Estates that gave rise to the most extensive debates on the political role of the people. Th e formu- lation of the Charter became such an important question because it was considered comparable to the constitution, although it could be changed by the decision of three estates instead of the unanimity usu- ally required on privilege questions.188 Th e opportunity was used by the lower orders with Cap majorities to prosecute the question of privileges, which had been eff ectively opposed by the Noble Estate. Th ey saw a possibility to combine this question with the reformulation of the Charter of 1751. According to the suggested new formulation, the agreement of the King and three estates would be enough to enact changes in estate privileges. Likewise, state offi ces would also be opened to the members of the non-noble estates.189 In these circumstances, in which the special status of the Nobility was being openly challenged, the Cap opposition began to use words referring to the people more frequently, in radicalized senses, and also among the lower orders, which they dominated. In the course of autumn 1771, three proposals for according eco- nomic privileges to the three non-noble estates were made. In the Peasant Estate, the question of privileges was addressed as a conse- quence of the reintroduction of a proposal that had already been made at the end of the preceding Diet. Among the Burghers, Johan Sundblad proposed a formulation of privileges for his own estate. Henrik Albrekt Brandenburg repeated this proposal in early October. All the propos- als focused on equal judicial and economic rights and contained no claims for extended political rights. Th e Peasant Estate remained unwilling to open estate membership to those members of the rural population who did not yet belong to it. On the other hand, there were calls for widening the membership of the estates so that land-owning persons of standing could take part in elections, but they went unheard.190 Every estate continued to jealously defend its own inher-

187 [Ingman], Svenska Folkets Röst, 1771, 14. 188 Nordin 2003, 62. 189 Nordin 2000, 418. 190 Roberts 1986, 196–197; Nordin 2000, 402–403, 407, 414, 421, 426–427; cf. Lager- roth 1915, 671–674. the swedish diet, – 213 ited rights against all outsiders and only attempted to widen them. Only those who already belonged to one of the estates could apply for new privileges.191 In 1769 the concepts of the nation and the people had been used for party-political ends by some noblemen and a solitary Hat leader in the Burgher Estate. Th ey had articulated fairly conventional notions that political power originated in the people. In 1771, however, these ideas were being used by quite diff erent groups and for diff erent purposes. At a time when the position of the Nobles was being questioned by suggestions that privileges should be extended to the lower orders, it was mainly the Burghers and the Clergy who used this language, and they did so increasingly as the confl ict on privileges grew more heated. Th e Secret Committee was in charge of preparing the proposal for the Accession Charter. Th e composition of the Committee was unusual in that members of the Peasant Estate were also invited to join the planning sessions. Th e extended Committee of fi ft y noblemen, 25 cler- gymen, 25 burghers and the delegates of the Peasant Estate thus con- stituted a unique forum in mid-eighteenth-century Europe: in 1771 and 1772 members of all four estates of the realm met and debated constitutional questions in Sweden. When the question of the Accession Charter was fi rst taken up in the Secret Committee, Anders Ekman (a Cap burgher) suggested an amendment according to which the King would state that he received his post not only from God but “from the hand of the Highest and the hand of the people or nation ( folckets eller nationens)”.192 Th e people were thus represented as an equal bestower of political power side by side with God, in a law that formed part of the constitution. Ekman also emphasized that the hereditary position of the King was derived from the free election of the Estates. Th e proposal was supported by [Caspar] Wikman, a member of the Clergy, which suggests that it was in agreement with prevalent notions about the character of the mon- archy and with Lutheran political ideas.193 It was also in accordance with the medieval tradition of elective monarchy. Th e reason for the emphasis on the concept of the people by the Burghers and Clergy

191 Roberts 1986, 207–209. 192 R 3570 Secreta Utskottets Beredrings Protocoller och Handlingar Rörande Svea Konunga Försäkran (SUBP), 25 September 1771, 57. 193 R 3570 SUBP, 25 September 1771, 57. 214 chapter three may not only have been a desire to revise the formulation of the Charter but also to advertise the approach which those groups had adopted in the controversy on privileges. At about this time, the Cap majorities of the two estates were forming an alliance over the privi- lege question. Some members of the Committee referred to the people mainly in speeches defending free elections, which they felt had been disrupted by the interventions of the executive power. Th ey wished to see the right to free elections written down in the Accession Charter. Israel Melin (a Cap clergyman) criticized all government infl uence on elec- tions as something that violated the very essence of the freedom of the people.194 Th e press had also written about the manipulation of the elections, higher civil servants and the Senate being accused of having “encroached upon the rights of the people” and attempting to silence “the voice of the nation”. As a consequence, it had become diffi cult for the nation “to see itself represented (presenterad, sic) by those who had not been chosen by it but by the authorities”.195 In another pamphlet, a quotation from the proceedings of the Secret Committee during the previous Riksdag was used to complain about how the nation “does not see itself represented by those it has itself chosen”. Here a clear contrast was made between the Hat Senate and the nation.196 Th is also provides us with an instance of the combination of ‘the nation’ and ‘representation’, an association of terms that the Estates themselves eschewed. Th e author lamented the fact that the people was prevented from choosing its representatives for the Diet freely. He saw it as a particular problem that “the common people [Små-Folket]” did not really know their rights.197 On 30 September, the Burgher Estate became active in the Secret Committee, bringing the dispute over privileges to the fore. Johan Lorentz Munthe (Cap) argued that the people had a right to demand a newly draft ed Accession Charter that contained a promise to rule according to the constitution, which should never be changed.198 Th e old rights of the people should be reinforced in a manner that would

194 R 3570 SUBP, 25 September 1771, 68. 195 [Anon.], Tankar Om De Ämbetsmän, som wid förfl utne Riksdagsmans-Wal, gjordt inbrott i Folkens Rätt och Wal-Frihet (Stockholm 1771), no page numbers. 196 [Pileus Invariatus], Folkets Rätt, At Obehindrat Wälja Riksdagsmän, Såsom En wäsentelig del af Nationens Frihet (Stockholm 1771), 6–7. 197 Folkets Rätt 1771, 3, 5. 198 R 3570 SUBP, 30 September 1771, 88. the swedish diet, – 215 make the political role of the people indisputable. Samuel Corin stated: “Properly speaking, the Accession Charter should contain the high commitments of the King to the people”.199 Th e popular basis of the royal prerogative was being emphasized by the Burghers, not by the Nobility as in 1769. Such views were not unanimously held in the Committee. Accord- ing to Johan Christoff er Hasencampf, a reference to “the commitments of the King to the people” would become a new element in the consti- tution. He doubted whether the Charter could be viewed as “a contract between the King and the people”, since such a contract should be drawn up by the two sides in cooperation. Th is would go too far as the Swedish people was already an exception among peoples with elective monarchies in that the King agreed to the existence of an Accession Charter.200 Th ere were other opponents among the Nobility, including Chamberlain Fredric Ulric von Essen (Cap). Von Essen, who had entered into an agreement with the King about retaining the constitu- tion and sympathized with the claims of the lower estates, could not accept the view that the Charter was a kind of contract between the King and the people.201 Carl Johan Ridderstolpe, a leading Cap, defended the status of the Accession Charter as a fundamental law. In his view, it constituted a joint act in which the nation and the people participated together with the monarch: [. . .] on the part of the King it would be the highest act ensuring the safety of the nation: and it comprises a fundamental [byggeligt] promise [. . .] about the freedom and security of the people.202 Th is was a moderate way of saying that political power was originally derived from the people, something that a considerable proportion of the political elite could accept. However, the focus of the speech was consistently on the necessity of securing the existing privileges. Another debate in the Committee is noteworthy for its comparisons between the Swedish and other past and contemporary republican regimes. Th e parallels reveal that the real point of dispute was not so much between the King and the people but between the Nobility and

199 R 3570 SUBP, 30 September 1771, 90. 200 R 3570 SUBP, 30 September 1771, 92–93; On the controversial background of the contract theory, see Roberts 1986, 64–65. 201 R 3570 SUBP, 30 September 1771, 95. 202 R 3570 SUBP, 30 September 1771, 95–97. 216 chapter three the other estates, the latter wishing to cut down the favoured status of the Nobility by extending their own privileges. Th e Burghers and some Clerics were active in the campaign, but the Peasants held their peace. Even some Cap noblemen expressed their sympathies for the demands of the lower estates. Clas Frietzcky (Cap) considered it necessary for the Nobility to make concessions in the confl ict, his concern for strengthening the royal power overshadowing his worries about noble privileges.203 Frietzcky was convinced that a real spirit of liberty and love of the constitution could only be achieved “when a free, equally empowered people see themselves as equally entitled” to the benefi ts of society.204 Among the Burghers, Olof Raméen pointed to the Nobility’s monopoly on offi ce, which the lower estates wished to abolish. Raméen used references to the people here, insinuating that the nobles were not actually part of the nation or the people. It must have sounded highly provocative in the ears of the noble members to hear Raméen maintain that there was “great alarm in the nation” over the question of privileges and that it was absolutely essential that the people be “satisfi ed in this issue to some degree”.205 Th e wishes of the nation and the people were presented as being distinctly contrary to the noble privileges. Th is was essentially a restricted defi nition of a central polit- ical concept used in an attempt to gain an advantage in the dispute over privileges. Th e Nobility, who had traditionally constituted the most eminent section of the people, was being eff ectively excluded from that people. As Jonas Nordin has pointed out, this exclusion of the Nobility was a conscious tactic adopted by the lower estates.206 Th e views of the lower clergy were summarized by Israel Melin. Th e problem was that while the relationship between the people and the King was in order, the relationships between the diff erent estates were not: “Th e Swedish people would be secured in its freedom in relation to the throne”. On the other hand, there was not as yet any guarantee regarding “the balance which should exist between the estates”.207 Th is was a further contribution to the process of the radicalization of the concept of the people in the privilege controversy. To leave no doubt

203 Nordin 2003, 63. 204 R 3570 SUBP, 1 October 1771, 126. 205 R 3570 SUBP, 1 October 1771, 128. 206 Nordin 2000, 407. 207 R 3570 SUBP, 1 October 1771, 129. the swedish diet, – 217 as to the seriousness of the confrontation, Melin compared contempo- rary Sweden with the Roman Republic, suggesting that similar rights to offi ces and equality in decision-making between the Estates were necessary to achieve a balanced constitution: [. . .] the Roman patricians enjoyed the respect of the people as long as they did not usurp the rights of the people. When the plebeians could take the highest offi ces, and when decisions made by their comitia tributa became as valid as decisions in their comitia centuriata, the Roman freedom and the right of the people was settled for the fi rst time.208 Th is simultaneous reference to the two classical senses of the concept of the people, the common people on the one hand and the people as the political community on the other, tended once again to exclude the Nobility from a people that was interpreted as consisting of the three lower estates only. With a further related parallel drawn between Sweden and republican Florence, Melin warned the Nobles about the consequences of their unwillingness to proceed in the privi- lege question: Th e nobility in Florence attacked the common people [menigheten], but thereby decreased their power, their own security and their prestige and never regained the trust of the public.209 Although Melin was talking on a rather general level, he was advocat- ing the equal distribution of privileges amongst the existing Estates, not a political reform entailing a wider representation of the people in the Diet. Th e Nobility had previously used the concept of the people both in its disputes with the King and in its internal party strife. Th e radical- ization of the arguments of the lower estates in the course of autumn 1771 changed their argumentation considerably, not only in the joint committees but also in the plenary sessions of the estate. Th e Cap leader Ridderstolpe, who had previously been ready to make conces- sions to the lower estates for tactical reasons, reacted by rejecting all comparisons between the Roman and Polish Republics and “our free community”. Th e only things that really connected Rome and Sweden in the circumstances of 1771 were the party strife and the impossible demands of the plebeians. In Rome, these had led to the fall of the

208 R 3570 SUBP, 1 October 1771, 130. 209 R 3570 SUBP, 1 October 1771, 130. 218 chapter three

Republic, and the implication was that the same might happen in Swe- den.210 Fredric Horn, an old opponent of democratic schemes, also opposed the goals of the lower estates as threatening the status of the Nobility. According to him, Roman history proved that “once tribuni plebis ruled like tyrants they also received the fate of tyrants”.211 No wonder Horn would soon ally himself with the King. Comparisons between the Roman division into patricians and ple- beians on the one hand and the Swedish Nobility and the commoner estates (odalstånden, as they were called at that time) on the other were frequent in the public debate as well. Th e Nobility might be regarded as representing aristocracy and the commoners democracy in this context. One argument was that a balance between these with- out a strong monarchy as a mediator had caused the fall of the repub- lican form of government in Rome and might destroy liberty in Sweden as well.212 For the Nobility, it seemed diffi cult to accept the idea of a necessary balance between aristocracy and democracy. As Captain Pfeif put it, the Accession Charter was fi rst about the King’s “commit- ment to the realm and then about the rights of the nation”,213 it was not about privileges. Once the discussions in the Secret Committee seemed to be challenging the privileges of their Estate, individual noblemen ceased to champion the rights of the people as visibly as before. Th e negative reaction on the part of the Nobility induced some members of the lower estates to imply that it was not total equality they were aiming at. Th is indicates that the concept of the people had not been used to extend democracy in a classical sense or to underline some active sovereignty of the people in a more modern sense but primarily to achieve equal possibilities for clerics and burghers in the competition for the key posts in the realm. Th is was an entirely under- standable goal in an estate society in which social mobility was cur- tailed by the diff erent privileges accorded to each estate. Johan Sundblad (Cap) pointed out that it was not a democratic scheme he was advocat-

210 R 3570 SUBP, 1 October 1771, 133. 211 R 3570 SUBP, 1 October 1771, 135. 212 [Anon.], Refl exioner angående Romerska Republiquens olyckelige tilstånd, eft er Konunga-Magtens afskaff ande (Stockholm 1771), no page numbers. 213 R 3570 SUBP, 1 October 1771, 143. Th ere were three captains called Pfeif attending the Noble Estate in 1771. It has not been possible to identify this particular speaker. the swedish diet, – 219 ing. Such an attempt, according to him, had already been condemned by Plato as leading to the despotism of the many.214 Th e debate in the Secret Committee had been radicalized, but it still concerned privileges rather than the form of government as such. Th e proposal of the Committee was—in accordance with the wishes of the lower estates—that the King should follow the will of the majority of the Estates and that appointments to offi ces should only be based on merit and no longer on noble status.215 Th e concept of democracy had not been used once during the debates of the Committee. References to the nation and the people had, in contrast, appeared quite fre- quently. As the Burghers had been most active in introducing radical defi nitions of the rights of the people into the joint debate, it is now worth considering the arguments they used in their plenary sessions. Th e question of privileges was fi rst addressed in the Burgher Estate on 12 October, when Sundblad made his proposal and linked the question to the decision on the Accession Charter. Th e proposal focussed one-sidedly on the interests of the Burgher Estate. It was fol- lowed by a long debate dealing with a variety of economic problems and purely individual interests which might or might not have had something to do with the formulation of the charter. Th e confl ict with the Noble Estate was hidden behind the traditional rhetoric of consen- sus. Replying to a delegation from the Noble Estate, the Burghers argued that they wanted to avoid all changes in the constitution and merely “to maintain the balance between the equally empowered estates”.216 Apparently, the redefi nition of the estates’ privileges would take place within the framework of the existing constitution. Rather surprisingly, references to the nation and the people played only a marginal role in the debates of the Estate. Not even Arvid Schauw (Hat), the spokesman for the political rights of the people two years previously, had anything to say about it.217 Inside the Estate, the privilege question was not seen as related to the political rights of the people or to the advancement of democracy. When Henrik Albrekt Brandenburg presented his proposal for privileges for the commoner

214 “He did not suff er from any Platonic ideas in favour of achieving equality between all people, or of abolishing all borders between [. . .] estates, between the higher and the lower, which would end in suff erance.” R 3570 SUBP, 1 October 1771, 139; See Nordin 2000, 422. 215 Roberts 1986, 201. 216 R 1410 BrP 1771–1772, 17 October 1771, 2468. 217 Cf. Lagerroth 1915, 672. 220 chapter three estates, the people were mentioned only once, when the defence of the people was defi ned as one of the duties of the authorities.218 Only in speeches given to the other estates in the Secret Committee did the Burghers exploit the concept in order to advance the privilege issue. Th ey certainly did not entertain plans to extend the political nation to include all the subjects. While some Clerics supported the Burghers in the Secret Commit- tee, that Estate mostly refrained from talking about the political role of the people in their own sessions. Israel Melin spoke about “the pre- vious security of the Swedish people in relation to the throne”, which should be supplemented with protection for the people from the power of the authorities.219 Uno Brander also spoke briefl y about the need to protect the rights of the nation.220 Th e special privileges of the clergy received considerable attention, but little was said about the political rights of the people. Rather like many of the debates in the press, the Clergy primarily concentrated on the extension of the privileges of their own social or political corporation.221 Th is was a social debate within and between elite groups, not a radical debate aiming at a polit- ical reform, let alone a revolution.222

Th e Concept of Democracy in the Rhetoric of the Deadlocked Parties

Th e constitutional crisis made the Nobility change their political argu- mentation. Th e radicalization of the concept of the people which the Noble members of the Secret Committee had witnessed and the rest of the members of the estate read in the press led to references to the nation and the people playing a much more limited role in Noble debates than during the preceding Diet. Pamphlets were circulated suggesting that it was unacceptable “in a free community to raise aristocratic and almost half-barbaric dividing walls between equally

218 Henrik Albrekt Brandenburg, Swenska Odal-Folkets Rätt, Sammandragen i Proj- ect til et Dem gemensamt tilhörigt Privilegium, Wid Riksdagen År 1771 (Stockholm 1771), 389, 398. 219 R 704 PrP 1771–1772, 12 October 1771, 859. 220 R 704 PrP, 12 October 1771, 859. R 704 PrP, 29 January 1772, 1270. 221 Skuncke 1999, 291. 222 Cf. Lagerroth 1915, 637, 652; For a related conclusion, see Roberts 1986, 210. the swedish diet, – 221 empowered estates”.223 Th e Nobility was the obvious object of this criticism, while the King was readily presented as the defender of “the liberty of the entire nation”.224 In this atmosphere, the Nobility used the word ‘democracy’ in its classical Aristotelian sense in expressing concern for the rising demands of the commoner estates. Democracy was defi ned once again as a threat to the political order, not a valued element of the constitution and even less a positive future prospect. Baron Lars Kagg, a sympa- thizer of the Court and opponent of the proposed Charter, opened the debate by emphasizing diff erences in the language by which various forms of government were described: Monarchies, aristocracies and democracies, so diff erent in their essential characteristics, are all based on laws that diff er from each other as much as the words by which the forms of government are described.225 A special strength of the Swedish form of government was, according to Kagg, that it avoided most of the problems which the simple clas- sical forms involved.226 Kagg did not develop this point into a defence of the democratic element within a mixed constitution, however. Nor were references to “the rights of the free people”, so popular among the Nobles at preceding Diets, widely used in this context.227 Councillor Fredric Horn, who had opposed the claims of the com- moner estates in the Secret Committee, did not hesitate to argue that a democratic coup was being prepared. In his view, the political power of the Swedish Estates was already more extensive than in any other country with a mixed constitution. Th e Nobility had tradition- ally played a prominent role among the Estates, and the calls for priv- ileges by the other estates was leading to dangerous changes in the relative strength of the estates: Now the supreme power seems to be moving to the other three estates, and then we are in danger of becoming a complete democracy, so popular

223 [Anon.], Medborgelighetens [sic] och Enighetens Echo, Wid Genomläsandet af Protocollerne och Projecterade Swea Konunga-Försäkran (Stockholm 1771), no page numbers. 224 [Anon.], Medborgelighetens [sic] och Enighetens Echo, 1771. 225 SRARP, Vol. I, 17 October 1771, 403. 226 SRARP, Vol. I, 17 October 1771, 404. 227 See Carl Magnus Sparrschöld, SRARP, Vol. I, 17 October 1771, 406, 408. 222 chapter three

[populaire] that nothing like it would exist in any other republic in the entire world.228 Sweden was viewed here as a republic in a broad classical sense, which meant that there was a popular and even democratic element in its constitution but certainly not direct democracy. Th e danger was that Sweden was about to turn into a real democracy just as foreign dip- lomats were currently reporting to their courts.229 In Horn’s under- standing, demands for social equality and for privileges were leading to the rise of a democratic form of government. In his view, civilized states could not achieve such a “complete equality amongst subjects” as the commoner estates were calling for.230 Th is concern was shared by many speakers, but few chose to describe the development as the rise of democracy. Peter Th am, a court offi cial with a Cap background, however, did join Horn, stating: “Such adjustments and additions to the constitution will fi nally lead to democracy”.231 Th ere were also members such as Colonel Clas Cederström who referred to the Accession Charter as a contract between the King and the people. While such a contract could in principle be altered, Cederström could not accept a change that would lead to a decrease in the privileges of the Nobility.232 Most speakers ruled out all changes, either presenting the Charter as a fundamental law which both the monarch and the people should observe233 or questioning the existence of a pact between the King and the people in the fi rst place.234 Th e basic character of the constitution could thus still be viewed in a vari- ety of ways. Per Lilliehorn, a supporter of stronger royal power, used the concept of the people most extensively, drawing a parallel between

228 SRARP, Vol. I, 17 October 1771, 434–435; cf. the statement of the British Speaker of the House of Lords referring to Sweden as a republic in 1766. 229 See, for example, the reports of the French ambassador on the danger of Sweden becoming “purement démocratique” (2 August 1771) and about “l’amour de la démocra- tie” being “la maladie épidémique de cette nation” (12 September 1771), cited in Skuncke 2003, 274. Hat Nobles, concerned about what some of them viewed as the rise of democracy threatening other elements of the constitution, had certainly informed their French allies about these developments. Such diplomatic reports do not, of course, provide evidence of positive interpretations of ‘democracy’ among the Swedish political elite. 230 SRARP I, 17 October 1771, 435. 231 SRARP I, 17 October 1771, 440. 232 SRARP I, 17 October 1771, 442–443. 233 Per Lilliehorn, SRARP I, 17 October 1771, 444. 234 Hasenkamf, SRARP, Vol. I, 17 October 1771, 447. the swedish diet, – 223

Sweden and other free nations such as Greece, Rome and Poland.235 He also opposed all changes to the Charter and the privileges of the Estates, which should be maintained in order to guarantee the liberty of the people. Th e Nobility as a whole decided to inform the other estates about their understanding of the proposal for the Accession Charter as a violation against the constitution and the established priv- ileges of the Estates and hence as impossible for the Riksdag to adopt. In their view, the Charter of 1751 should be kept unchanged.236 Related discussions about the political position of the people within the constitution also appeared in the press. Gjörwell (Hat) published an essay reviewing Montesquieu’s notions of popular government (Folk-Regering, Folk-wälde) and democracy. Applying Montesquieu’s defi nition of democracy as a republic in which the supreme power belonged to the people to the Swedish context, he argued: A state can be free without being totally democratic. Th e people can retain their freedom even if they delegate the administration to one or several persons provided that they themselves ratify the laws and see to it that these are properly administered.237 Th e Swedish people had such a role both in the legislative process and in the control of government. While there were democratic features in a classical sense in the Swedish system, it was certainly not con- sidered to be a democracy either in a classical or in some innovative modern sense. For Gjörwell, democracy was a system in which the people would vote on issues in large meetings and in this way become rulers engaged in the active use of power. Th is popular form of gov- ernment had its strengths as shown by the fact that both Athens and Rome had been able to achieve “things worthy of wonder”.238 At the same time, it had caused major problems, as the people were capable

235 “Mr Lilliehorn recalled the history of the Roman people, how they retained their laws for so long until they lost all rights to pass their laws any longer. Aristocrats rose, the greed to rule made them violate laws and continually make new ones until they fi nally took the mantle of a ruler on their shoulders and their will became the law of the people. New accession oaths in connection with every change of King in Poland has brought that realm to the situation in which we fi nd it today; [. . .] Among the Greeks emerged areopager [judges deciding on life and death] who worked for so long under the guise of defending freedom until the law disappeared along with the free- dom of Greece.” SRARP, Vol. I, 23 October 1771, 493. 236 Lagerroth 1915, 657. 237 [Anon.], Politiske Refl exioner 7, 29 October (Stockholm 1771), 5. Gjörwell was the author at least of the fi rst edition of this periodical. 238 [Anon.], Politiske Refl exioner 7, 29 October 1771, 51–52. 224 chapter three only of choosing and supervising the administration but not of ruling themselves. Th e reason was that “the people either has too much or too little power”. In democracy and in “popular rule” (Folk-wäldet), it had also been necessary to divide the people into classes before the system could function.239 Th at is, a division of the people into electors and administrators as well as into estates had been imperative even in classical democracies and mixed constitutions. Furthermore, Gjörwell claimed, democracy or popular government was unlikely to function in Sweden as it called for virtues which were lacking in the Swedes, who paid so much attention to manufactures, trade, fi nances and luxury. Th e seventeenth-century English Com- monwealth had already demonstrated that complete democracy was impossible. Th e Cromwellian attempt had proved to be no more than “the fruitless eff ort of the English people to establish democracy”. Because of a similar lack of virtue, the English had been forced to reintroduce their old, far superior constitution.240 Montesquieu’s polit- ical theory, instances from the classical and modern past, and the state of Swedish political debate all suggested to Gjörwell that the prospects for democracy in Sweden were poor. It was a much better option to retain the established constitution. Aft er the Nobility had approached the Burgher Estate to communi- cate their views on the Accession Charter, the Caps began to increas- ingly refer to the people in their political argumentation. When the delegation of the Nobility had left the hall, Anders Ekman (Cap) stood up to put forward views which he had already expressed in the Secret Committee, maintaining that “the freedom and security of the nation” was the object of the reformed Charter. More particularly, the right to be chosen for state positions belonged also to “the non-noble part of the nation”, who also constituted “a free and thoughtful people”.241 Johan Henrik Hochschild (Cap) from Stockholm supported Ekman by underlining the power of the Estates to choose any policy as long as it did not jeopardize “the liberty of the nation” or the privileges of indi- vidual estates.242 Hochschild adopted a more radical approach, sug-

239 [Anon.], Politiske Refl exioner 7, 29 October 1771, 53. 240 “Th e people in their dismay looked for democracy and found it nowhere. Finally, aft er many commotions, scandals and crises, they had to retain the same form of government which they had rejected.” [Anon.], Politiske Refl exioner 7, 29 October 1771, 55–56. 241 R 1410 BrP, 2 November 1771, 2510–2511, 2513. 242 R 1410 BrP, 2 November 1771, 2519. the swedish diet, – 225 gesting that “the mischief of the Knights and Nobility in this matter should be revealed to the nation”;243 in other words, an appeal to pub- lic opinion should be made to counter the Nobles’ unwillingness to accord privileges to the commoners. A similar kind of appeal to the people outside the Riksdag is visible in Frans Cervin’s (Cap) advice that the Burghers should take the issue further to prevent “the nation” from becoming frustrated: “If the Estate still postpones its [. . .] answer, we shall have the voice of the nation against us.”244 Th e pressure from the Nobility thus made the Cap party adopt a more outspoken use of references to the people and the nation within the Burgher Estate. On 6 November, the estate approved a statement according to which the question of the Charter and privileges was highly signifi cant “for the free Swedish people”, the Charter being seen as containing “the most precious property of the Swedish people” and as ensuring “the preservation of the rights and security of the people”. Th e view of the Cap majority was that the proposed formulation of the Charter would add to the “strength of the form of government, the prestige of the realm and the security of the people”.245 Th e concept of the people was used here to legitimate calls for widened privileges for the Burgher Estate and thereby also for the other commoner estates. In another reply to the Noble Estate, the Burghers agreed on a formu- lation emphasizing the law-abiding nature of the people on the one hand and “the trust of the people” as the basis of all administration on the other.246 In November 1771, the Cap majority of the Burgher Estate thus used a positively defi ned vocabulary referring to the people in a campaign to strengthen the social position of their corporation. Th e Noble Estate could not arrive at any consensus on how to pro- ceed, although the proposal continued to be viewed as constituting a serious violation of the established order. Concern was expressed over the inability of the Estates to agree on the Charter becoming a threat to the people as a whole.247 Fredric Horn suggested that the ongoing dispute among the people on the proper interpretation of the

243 R 1410 BrP, 2 November 1771, 2529. 244 R 1410 BrP, 2 November 1771, 2529. 245 R 1410 BrP, 6 November 1771, 2543, 2546–2547; cf. an extract of the proceed- ings of the Clerical Estate referring to “the unconditional right of the free and inde- pendent Swedish people” and that of those empowered by the people ( folkets fullmäktige). Cited in Lagerroth 1915, 658. 246 R 1410 BrP, 27 November 1771, 2706, 2719. 247 de Fritzkij, SRARP, Vol. I, 20 November 1771, 608, 610. 226 chapter three constitution might aff ect the way in which the nation viewed the Nobility,248 the minority status of the Estate within the national com- munity being thus recognized. Both the people and the monarch were viewed positively, the former appearing as free and law-abiding,249 the latter as gracious and loving towards his people.250 Captain Fredrik Vilhelm Leijonancker, who in 1769 had prayed to God to protect Swe- den from democracy, emphasized the high degree of loyalty which the Swedish people exhibited for their King.251 Voices emerged suggesting that a royal intervention in favour of the Nobility might be needed to resolve the crisis.252 Horn, one of the most dedicated supporters of King Gustavus, repeated his point that the passage of the suggested privileges with a majority of the three lower estates would lead not only to the nobles losing their status but also to the rise of a democratic tyranny. In his view, “a popular government” could “never be based on equality” without soon degenerating into a tyranny.253 It was unrealistic to achieve equality, and any attempts to move in that direction would not only bring democracy but also endanger the existence of any kind of government. Th ough highly critical of equality and democracy, Horn did continue to recognize the popular basis of the Swedish government provided that the system was regulated by a strong nobility. His choice was easy when the time of the royal coup came in August 1772, and he took an active part in it.

Th e Political Role of the People in the Accession Charter and the Nomination of Senators

Th e stalemate of November 1771 was followed by three months of silence over the privilege issue in the plenary sessions of the Estates. Th e commoner estates chose to abandon a debate which they found fruitless and decided to prosecute the issue further on the basis of their majority regardless of the Nobles’ opposition. A royal intervention also followed, the King warning the Estates that he would personally

248 Fredric Horn, SRARP, Vol. I, 20 November 1771, 614, 30 November 1771, 680–681. 249 Uggla, SRARP, Vol. I, 30 November 1771, 665. 250 Liljehorn, SRARP, Vol. I, 30 November 1771, 670. 251 SRARP, Vol. I, 30 November 1771, 676. 252 Fredric Horn, SRARP, Vol. I, 30 November 1771, 680–681. 253 SRARP, Vol. I, 30 November 1771, 660. the swedish diet, – 227 take royal measures in case no solution was found by the Estates, but there was no consequent breakthrough in the deadlock.254 At the same time, the demands of the commoner estates were almost daily debated in the press by both Cap and Court organs.255 It was evident that the Nobility was about to lose its monopoly of the civil service, but the estate contained to campaign against such a prospect. Some two hun- dred noblemen, mostly offi cers and young Hats, formed an organiza- tion to defend noble privileges and later on to support a restitution of the monarchy. In the meantime, the more moderate noblemen of both parties became concerned about the future of their precious constitu- tion and viewed a compromise with the lower orders as the only way to save it.256 Once the debates on privileges were resumed in February 1772, the Noble Estate was even more divided than in the previous autumn. Th e increasingly critical nature of the confrontation was refl ected in the use of references to the people. Now that the special status of the Estate was at stake, many noblemen regarded a return to traditional monarchy as the only way to defend their cause.257 Many members of the Clergy and Peasantry readily adopted traditional ways of speaking about the people, which questions suggestions that the commoner estates were unanimous and demonstrates the persuasive force of the traditional language of politics.258 Not even the Burgher Estate put for- ward the kind of challenging proposals that had been heard in the previous November. Th e radicalization of the public debate and the threat of a further royal intervention had obviously caused a tradition- alist reaction amongst the members of all estates. Th e debates of the Secret Committee demonstrate this reactionary tendency in the language of politics most forcibly. Rather than empha- sizing the liberties of the people, the Noble members adopted an approach that was based on the traditional idea of teaching obedient subjects in an organically understood society. Th e obvious goal was to persuade the commoner estates to readopt traditional ways of think- ing and speaking and renounce their attack on the established order.

254 Lagerroth 1915, 662–665; Roberts 1986, 201–202. 255 Skuncke 1999, 286; Skuncke 2003, 418. 256 Roberts 1986, 202. 257 Nordin 2003, 63. 258 Cf. Lagerroth’s interpretation of the lower estates as the true representatives of the people in Lagerroth 1915, 665. 228 chapter three

Illustrative of this approach is Per Lilliehorn’s argumentation, which maintained that the Nobles, too, “must have the voice of the people on their side when they, holding a law book in their hands, are defending their rights”.259 Here a nobleman who was sympathetic towards a stron- ger monarchy resorted to religious arguments in a speech that resem- bled an open prayer in order to touch the feelings of his audience: May Providence, which decides on the fates of peoples and countries, allow the spirit of unity to prevail amongst us so that this blessing would stay with us and those misfortunes be avoided which threaten a divided people!260 Fersen, one of the most prominent noblemen of the realm, also spoke about the need to save the fatherland by calming the confrontations with divine assistance.261 Even Carl Johan Ridderstolpe, who had defended the political role of the people only half a year previously, spoke like a Lutheran bishop. According to him, “the voice of the people” should been heard, but it was even more important to follow “the voice of God and conscience”. According to him, no power could prevent him “from thinking according to the law of God and nature, according to reason and conscience”. Th e highest goal was to save the fatherland by bringing the dispute over privileges to an end.262 It is noteworthy that Ridderstolpe now distinguished between the voice of the people and that of God in campaigning for the preservation of at least some of the special status of his estate. In these circumstances, the rhetoric of language referring to the people in the spirit of Noble republicanism had become obsolete. All these noblemen hoped that the Clergy and the Peasantry and hopefully the more traditionally oriented Burghers would be silenced with this Lutheran language of loyalty. And the reactions of the lower estates show that it was indeed highly eff ective among these sections of the Swedish political elite. Aft er a large number of the Noble had readopted this kind of biblical view of the people, it would be easy for Gustavus III and his clerical propagandists to develop these reaction-

259 R 3570 SUBP, 11 February 1772, 206. 260 R 3570 SUBP, 11 February 1772, 206. 261 R 3570 SUBP, 11 February 1772, 215. 262 R 3570 SUBP, 11 February 1772, 211; Th ere do not seem to have been claims that the voice of the people was that of God, which was quite popular in Britain about this time. the swedish diet, – 229 ary concepts further in the aft ermath of the royal coup some six months later.263 Th e real masters of the language of obedience were to be found among the Lutheran bishops. While Jakob Serenius, a leading Cap politician, had emphasized the political role of the people in his Riks- dag sermon in 1765, by 1772 he was referring to the common Lutheran values of the political community in order to defend the constitution against political and social innovations. Serenius warned his fellow politicians of the danger of the Swedes being separated from God by their animosities and losing their happy constitution as a conse- quence.264 Independently of their party sympathies, the leading clerics were opening a way for a traditionalist reaction that would bring the constitution of the Age of Liberty to an end. Th e message was readily received at least among the members of the Peasant Estate, supporters of both the Lutheran Church and tradi- tional monarchy. Th e speech of Nils Svensson is an apt demonstration of their reactions. He did his best to convince the higher orders that the calls for privileges for the Peasant Estate were in no way meant to challenge the established order. He did refer to the rights of the people in general and the common people in particular, but he called for the maintenance of the established order and denied all accusations of the Peasantry being responsible for the crisis. He represented himself as a loyal spokesman of the simple people. At the same time, however, he made use of the only weapon that his estate had at its disposal: the threat that if the traditional rights of the people were not observed, there might emerge rising discontent, particularly at a time when a famine was raging in the realm and little had been done by the Riksdag to relieve it.265 His speech shows how the political ideology of the Peas- ant Estate continued to be based on the ancient principle of justice. It emphasized the observation of the mutual obligations of the Crown and the subjects. Evidently, this principle was defended more vigor- ously by the members of the Peasant Estate at the Riksdag in the

263 See Ihalainen 2005, 170–173. 264 R 3570 SUBP, 11 February 1772, 213–214; Ihalainen 2003, 81. 265 “[. . .] well, the whole nation has to be shown that we have no share in this. [. . .] Th e guilt does not lie with us. I pray for God’s and the people’s sake that we think about the simple country people who support those empowered by them so that they might defend their rights. [When there is] a famine in a country, it is advisable to pay attention to the rights of the people according to the law.” R 3570 SUBP, 11 February 1772, 220. 230 chapter three radical years of the late “Age of Liberty”.266 In order to gain entry to the political discourse of the higher orders and to have their points taken seriously, the members of the Peasant Estate not only repeated references to the divine order and the law but also used some words and phrases referring to the people and the nation. Unsurprisingly, Svensson’s speech was ignored by the higher estates. Despite all the rhetoric about equally empowered estates, the Peasants were not yet considered full members of the Swedish political com- munity. Indeed, not even the Peasants themselves actively demanded inclusion. In their own plenary debates, they mainly continued to speak about “the old freedom of the common people”, emphasizing the judicial rights of their estate rather than political rights.267 When the other commoner estates campaigned for extended privileges by the means of words, the Peasants remained uninvolved. Th e interests of the individual members focused rather on various specifi c questions addressed in petitions from diff erent parts of the realm.268 Th e Noble Estate also discussed privileges in February 1772. Opin- ions were divided: young offi cers were ready to fi ght for their privi- leges, but many nobles wanted to see a compromise. Classical parallels with the political position of the people that were drawn during the debates reveal some interesting features of the nobles’ understanding of the constitutional crisis. Captain Fredrik Otto Billberg started the discussion by drawing a parallel between social confrontations in the Roman Republic and in contemporary Sweden: Roman history teaches us that the fi rst division there concerned the dis- tribution of the lands of the Republic. Th ereaft er arose a dispute between patricians and plebeians, the nobility and the people, over infl uence on the aff airs of the government. Th is led to the formation of triumvirates and fi nally to the fall of the Republic. Our situation is not that much diff erent from the latter case.269 Th is description embodied a recognition of the existence of deep divisions between the Swedish Nobility and the people. Th e Nobility could even be understood as an antithesis of the people, just as some

266 Claréus 2003, 407–408. 267 Bondeståndets riksdagsprotokoll (BdP), Vol. 12, 1771–1772 (Stockholm 1978), 4 September 1771, 593, 603. 268 BdP, 4 September 1771, 112–113; 12 October 1771, 156; 26 October 1771, 169; 30 October 1771, 173. 269 SRARP, Vol. II, 22 February 1772, 176. the swedish diet, – 231

Burgher politicians had been suggesting. Th e redefi nition of the con- cept of the people to exclude the Nobility thus seems to have been recognized by noblemen who were ready to make concessions to the lower orders in order to avoid an escalation of the crisis and the poten- tial fall of the entire political order. Another warning example could be found in the democracy of Ath- ens. In Lilliehorn’s description, the current political disputes made Sweden comparable with the most famous instance of democracy his- tory could provide. Th e parallel also suggested a speedy fall of the Swedish system if the noble privileges were not protected: “Athens fell only when certain bold men among the people were compelled to renounce their rights as citizens in order to save themselves.”270 Lilliehorn’s obvious point was that the Nobility should continue to oppose changes in the mutual power relations of the estates; he pre- sented the nobles as defenders of both their due rights and the form of government in general. He was using a rhetoric based on the ideal of a republic ruled by the nobles, in which they continued to be seen as the core of the people. It was easy for Court Chancellor Sven Bunge (Hat) to support such an interpretation of the liberties of the Nobility and the nation as inseparable.271 Lilliehorn returned to his defi nition of the Nobility as the core of the people in another speech, arguing that changes in the Charter were unthinkable as the document consti- tuted “a golden band linking the rights of the King and the people”. Th e rights of the Nobility and the people appeared identical to such an extent that he spoke about “our and the people’s rights” and consid- ered it unthinkable that he for instance should have gained his posi- tion “at the cost of the people”.272 Th ere was also a group of prominent noblemen in both parties— such as Fersen, Ridderstolpe, Pechlin, Essen and Jennings—who were looking for a compromise among the Estates.273 While the fi rst two had used Lutheran rhetoric in the Secret Committee, they looked for a compromise in the conventional rhetoric of the rights of the people when speaking to their peers. Alex von Fersen (Hat) represented the Accession Charter as an “act of state preserving the law and the

270 SRARP, Vol. II, 22 February 1772, 198. 271 SRARP, Vol. II, 22 February 1772, 200. 272 SRARP, Vol. II, 24 February 1772, 270–271, 281. 273 Lagerroth 1915, 670. 232 chapter three people’s liberties and rights based on it”.274 Carl Johan Ridderstolpe (Cap) likewise spoke about the need to uphold “the advantage of the people” by passing the Charter.275 Carl Fredrik Pechlin (Cap), as a known opponent of the royal prerogative, a radical politician and hence a major distributor of Russian bribes within his party, was more outspoken in his call for concessions over the nobles’ privileges so that the people would be united and their liberty secured in the face of the risk of royal power being restored.276 Most speakers rejected such suggestions. Gustav Adolf Leijonmarck (Hat) regarded it as essential to maintain the noble privileges. Any compromise would “terminate our form of government, and we would have neither aristocracy nor democracy nor any kind of law”.277 Lei- jonmarck did not recognize aristocracy and democracy as natural and balancing elements in the Swedish constitution, instead, he described the prospective anarchy that awaited the country. ‘Aristocracy’ was the term that had been used to attack noble opponents for their attempts to monopolize power; now the lower estates were accused of trying to introduce ‘democracy’. Leijonmarck, as a supporter of a stronger mon- archy, rejected both alternatives. Despite comparisons with other mixed monarchies, it seems to have remained diffi cult for many noble- men to recognize the simultaneous existence of the three elements within the Swedish constitution. Warnings about the advent of democracy as a consequence of the proposed Charter were repeated. Gustaf Mauritz Posse maintained that the Charter should refer to the need of all the four estates to decide together about privileges. Th e suggestion that three estates could outvote the fourth meant nothing less than the victory of democracy of the most undesirable kind. Revealingly, he considered it necessary to retain the principle of unanimous decisions among the Estates as being “such an invaluable and wonderful defence of liberty against democratic power”.278 Th is young nobleman continued to view ‘lib- erty’—the most highly esteemed concept of the Sweden of his day— and ‘democracy’ as symmetrical opposites. Th e Swedish Nobility wanted no democracy in any classical or modern sense and indeed saw

274 SRARP, Vol. II, 22 February 1772, 180. 275 SRARP, Vol. II, 22 February 1772, 190. 276 SRARP, Vol. II, 22 February 1772, 187. 277 SRARP, Vol. II, 22 February 1772, 207. 278 SRARP, Vol. II, 24 February 1772, 268. the swedish diet, – 233 themselves as defenders of liberty against democracy. Th e other estates did not seriously discuss the possibility of strengthening democracy at all. A further interesting feature, which we have already encountered in the Nobles’ debates of 1769 but in a more positive sense, is the infl u- ence of rising publicity on the concepts of the people and nation. By February 1772, some noblemen pointed out that an vague wider nation existed outside the House of the Nobility and the Riksdag and followed the actions of the various estates. Lilliehorn described “how the whole of the nation” and “the whole of the Swedish people” was reading reports of Riksdag debates.279 Even the Nobility might appeal to the nation for support in their confl ict with the commoner estates. Some believed that “an enlightened nation” would understand that the Nobles had justice on their side.280 At the same time, there was aware- ness of the press being used to rouse the people against the Nobility. Billberg advised his peers to take measures that would restore the respected image of the Nobility among the people.281 He recognized the potential of the people as a reading public, did not deny that there existed a division between the Nobility and the people which had been propagated by the lower orders, and probably supported concessions on the privilege question. By February 1772, the majority of the House of the Nobility was ready to open the higher civil service posts to non-noble subjects, hop- ing that this would constitute a suffi cient compromise.282 However, the crisis, during which the concept of the people had become contested to an unprecedented extent, was not yet over. A further heated debate was opened when the actions of the Senate began to be discussed in April 1772. Th e Cap opposition focused mainly on nominations to offi ces, the control of the freedom of the press and attempts to infl u- ence the elections for the Riksdag.283 Th e widespread criticism resulted in the dismissal of altogether seven Hat senators by a majority decision of the three Cap-dominated commoner estates.284 During the debate, even the Cap majorities of the Clerical and Peasant Estates, which had

279 SRARP, Vol. II, 24 February 1772, 282. 280 Carl Jacob von Quanten, SRARP, Vol. II, 22 February 1772, 182. 281 SRARP, Vol. II, 24 February 1772, 294. 282 Roberts 1986, 203; Skuncke 2003, 281. 283 Lagerroth 1915, 676. 284 Roberts 1986, 203. 234 chapter three previously been very cautious in their use of references to the people and the nation, became activated. Th e concept of the people was thus now being used by all the estates to legitimate their political demands. Th e Clergy focused on questions of censorship. In this context, Carl Kröger, a talented speaker, who liked to engage in disputation, argued with uncommon explicitness that “the voice of the nation corre- sponded word for word with that of the deputies of the nation [Nations röst likde Nations Deputerade lika som orden i munnen]” whenever the latter acted “on behalf of the nation”.285 Th is formulation approaches the later concept of national representation to such an extent that Lennart Linnarson has interpreted it as an expression of “the demo- cratic parliamentarism of the Swedish eighteenth century”.286 How- ever, it may be anachronistic to call this way of thinking democratic, and we should rather see Kröger’s formulation as a radicalization of previous statements made about the Cap majority presenting the voice of the nation which had gone unheard by the Hat Senate. Kröger added references to “the rights of the people” and to “the rights of the citizen” in criticizing the bribery which the Senate had employed to infl uence election results. Government infl uence had endangered the liberty of the nation to elect their delegates to the Riksdag. Kröger’s complaints against the Hat Senate were fi erce in the context of Riksdag debates, though moderate in comparison with the public debate of the day: [. . .] with such measures, the Senate of the Realm has shown that it does not act as plenipotentiaries of the Estates or the people, and the confi - dence of the Realm in the Senate should no longer be continued, [. . .] such omissions of civic duties [medborgerligheten] have shocked the nation, and it is absolutely necessary for the plenipotentiaries of the people at the Riksdag to interpret this matter in a way that will earn them the aff ection [. . .] which the nation feels for them.287 Kröger was drawing strong associations between the Estates and the people and clearly presented the members of the Riksdag as plenipo- tentiaries of the people. His criticism of the Senate was based on the belief that the current administration did not serve the interests of the

285 R 705 PrP, 11 April 1772, 1733. 286 Linnarsson 1943, 339; cf. Lagerroth 1915. 287 R 705 PrP, 11 April 1772, 1734. the swedish diet, – 235 nation and that the nation had the power to change the administra- tion through their plenipotentiaries. Kröger’s statement was unusual in the corpus studied here. Th e fact that it was made in an assembly of Lutheran clergymen, and that it did not give rise to counter-arguments denying the principle of representation does suggest that these notions were held quite generally among the Swedish political elite. By April 1772, the concept of the confi dence of the people could thus be used by an opposition clergyman in a call for a change of government. However, the Clerical defenders of the Senate considered it neces- sary to reject Kröger’s interpretation of the opinions of the nation. According to Peter Wetterberg, “the whole Swedish nation” continued to be “satisfi ed with their patriotic and zealous [. . .] government”.288 In his defence of the Hat ministry, he turned to traditional calls for “mutual civic [medborgerlig] and Christian love and trust” and empha- sized the obedience which the Swedish nation should show under such a happy government.289 Th e statement only made the opposition Caps repeat their accusations, Dean Olof Lindbom questioning “the confi - dence of the nation” towards a Senate which had “treated the rights of the nation and the people [Nations och Folkets rätt] with such indif- ference”.290 For Lindbom, too, the members of the Riksdag were “pleni- potentiaries of the people” defending the security and welfare of the nation.291 Th is was a unique debate in the Clerical Estate and shows the degree to which language referring to the people had been adopted by both parties even among the conservatively inclined clergymen. Th e previously passive Peasant Estate also referred to the people in their debates in April 1772. Th e old peasant custom of speaking about the rights of the common people thus seems to have been supple- mented by the radicalized political vocabularies of the higher orders. Once some members of the Clergy had started to make radical claims by using the concept of the people, it was only a question of time before the members of the Peasant Estate did so as well. Th e fact that party affi liations crossed estate borders and that printed polemical political writings were available to all certainly played a role in the dissemination of the political use of this and related concepts. A fur- ther explanation is that members of the Peasant Estate were for the

288 R 705 PrP, 11 April 1772, 1744. 289 R 705 PrP, 11 April 1772, 1745. 290 R 705 PrP, 11 April 1772, 1754. 291 R 705 PrP, 11 April 1772, 1755, 1759. 236 chapter three fi rst time allowed to take part in the meetings of the Secret Committee and were thus better informed about the current state of debate among the higher orders.292 Hence Gabriel Månsson would wonder “with how little tenderness for the people and respect for the law the important offi ces of the Senate have been administrated between the Riksdags”.293 Gabriel Heikkilä reminded his fellow peasants that “the rights of the realm and the people together with the form of government” consti- tuted the law of the realm. Th is meant that any transgression of the law was a violation of “the rights of the people” as well.294 Heikkilä, a bilingual blacksmith from Vehmaa and supporter of the Caps, was the only peasant from Finland to contribute to the discussion on the polit- ical role of the people in the period studied here. Th e statement of this respected spokesman for Finnish interests and the Finnish language295 demonstrates the degree to which the plenipotentiaries of the common people in the eastern, more peripheral, provinces of the Swedish realm had also adopted the old Scandinavian notion of the rights of the peo- ple as the foundation of all government. It also supports Charlotta Wolff ’s interpretation that the concept of rights had indeed been extended to include all the inhabitants of the realm.296 We can add two further instances of peasants who used references to the people, this time speaking for the western provinces of Sweden. According to Eric Mårtensson, the Senate could no longer enjoy the confi dence of the Estates once it had acted “against the law and the liberties and rights of the people prescribed there”.297 Lars Svensson stated that the duty of the Senate was to “look aft er the rights of the people”.298 All of these instances show that by April 1772 the members of the Peasant Estate had adopted a vocabulary referring to the people that carried meanings of political signifi cance. Political connections at the Diet supported this strengthening and radicalization of old ways of speaking, and the acute famine in the country provided a context in which the Peasantry articulated their grievances more outspokenly than before.

292 Roberts 1986, 203. 293 BdP, 11 April 1772, 314. 294 BdP, 11 April 1772, 315. 295 Paloposki 1961, 265, 316, 318, 378, 433. 296 Wolff 2007b, 58. 297 BdP, 11 April 1772, 317. 298 BpP, 11 April 1772, 317. the swedish diet, – 237

For the Noble opposition, talking about the welfare and rights of the people as the basis of government was nothing new. Th e supporters of the Senate had also learned to make use of appeals to patriotism to gather support for the senators of their party. Th e latter group, given the continuous majority of the Hats in the Estate, was more numerous in April 1772. Major-General Christer Horn argued that the nation, which he described with attributes such as “free”, “regulated by law”, “informed” and “king-loving”, would never accept the dismissal of the current Senate for what it had done. According to him, “the appeal of the calm people” had been abused by the opposition with its demands that people who were not entitled to participate in decision-making would determine the policies to be followed.299 Carl Sparre, one of the Hat leaders, recognized the right of the nation to be informed about how the aff airs of the realm were being handled but rejected the criti- cisms of the Senate as unfounded.300 Two candidates for the new Sen- ate, Court Chancellor Sven Bunge and Carl Eric Wadenstierna, argued that the previous Senate had earned “the gratitude and acknowledge- ments of the entire nation”.301 Th e Cap opposition, in contrast, was cautious in its appeals to the nation. Carl Johan Ridderstolpe merely pointed out: “Th e people can demand more from those men in whose hands they have placed their highest trust.” Th e dismissal of all the senators would, however, only increase “bitterness in the nation”.302 Excessive confrontations were to be avoided. Even a party-man like Fredrik Gyllensvahn called for “unity in the nation” at a time when the Nobility was being attacked. He mitigated his call for the dismissal of some senators by suggesting conventionally that “an appeased nation” should through the Estates give pensions to those who had to go.303 Horn and Ridderstolpe would continue to be the most prominent speakers in the House of the Nobility. While Horn conceded that “the liberty of the people” was to be exercised through elections to the Riks- dag, he considered it necessary for civil servants to control how the voice of the people was registered because of the tendency of the pop- ulace to be so easily misled by men who propagated republican and downright anti-monarchical ideas. As an instance, Horn referred to

299 SRARP, Vol. II, 15 April 1772, 493–494; 25 April 1772, 544. 300 SRARP, Vol. II, 25 April 1772, 549. 301 SRARP, Vol. II, 25 April 1772, 497, 532. 302 SRARP, Vol. II, 25 April 1772, 513. 303 SRARP, Vol. II, 25 April 1772, 539–540. 238 chapter three propaganda published aft er the royal coup of 1756 which had attempted to promote and install “popular government” (populaire regeringssättet; det populaire regimentet; en populair regering).304 It remains unclear whether Horn saw Sweden as such a popular government as he further added: Th ere is no doubt that it is highly dangerous in a popular government for writings to be circulated which lead to insurrections and rebellions in the country.305 He was certainly worried about what he saw as a tendency of popular element of the government to rise concomitantly with the publication of radical ideas, which he had not anticipated when supporting the freedom of the press in 1766. Th e debates ended on 20 May when Ridderstolpe, among others, was elected a senator with support from the Caps, albeit against his own wishes. Th e Cap majority of the Clerical Estate underlined the trust which “the nation” felt towards the leader of their party.306 In one of his speeches, Ridderstolpe had himself recently stated: “It is our duty to go where the nation commands us to go.”307 Here he presented the sentiments of the people as the grounds for nomination to the Senate. As Clas Frietzcky, a Cap with republican notions, pointed out, the trust and wishes of both the King and the nation mattered in the nominations.308 Carl Jacob von Quanten even saw here “a new way [. . .] to receive mandates from [the] people, who really possesses them”.309 Th is is a noteworthy formulation in that it did not stand merely for the original role of the people as a party in the social con- tract but recognized the active delegation of power by the people to the government. Von Quanten also referred to the novel character of the procedure, something that must have made the Hats ever more concerned about the rise of popular government and readier to move to the side of the King. To be sure, not even von Quanten spoke in favour of democracy; indeed he consistently denounced both autoc- racy (envälde) and the power of the many (mångvälde) in a country

304 SRARP, Vol. II, 25 April 1772, 556, 559–560. 305 SRARP, Vol. II, 25 April 1772, 561. 306 SRARP, Vol. III, 20 May 1772, 77. 307 SRARP, Vol. III, 11 May 1772, 31. 308 SRARP, Vol. III, 20 May 1772, 82. 309 SRARP, Vol. III, 20 May 1772, 81. the swedish diet, – 239 with “a free people”.310 Decisions by the majority of the Estates were to be legitimated with reference to a mandate derived from the people, but the system remained essentially the rule of the Estates, not of the people at large. Even such a formulation was too much for the King and his noble supporters; and they would soon take the matter into their own hands.

Th e Concept of the People at the Time of the Coronation and the Royal Coup of 1772

Th e last occasion for the expression of ideas on the political role of the people in the Age of Liberty was provided by the approaching coro- nation of Gustavus III, for which a ceremony needed to be planned. In discussing the rituals and words to be used in the ceremony, the four estates came to comment on the political role of the people, each in its own particular way. Th ese comments show that not only party affi liations but also identifi cation with a particular estate continued to mould understandings of what the people was and how its say should be refl ected in government. Th e Peasants wished to use the occasion to gain privileges for the common people, but they did not choose to employ references to the people to justify their aims. Th ese concepts only came up in those debates when members expressed concern over attempts by the higher estates to increase the responsibilities of the common people in the proposed formulations of oaths. Th is concern made Gabriel Månsson and Johan Andersson argue that such violations of the rights of the commoners were unacceptable for “people in a free nation”.311 Not even the Burghers defended the privileges of the lower orders with references to the people. Neither were they willing to revise the oaths of 1751; in other words, no major change in the understanding of the political role of the people had taken place among them despite occa- sional references to the popular basis of government during the privi- lege disputes. Th e Burghers rather chose to join the Clergy in opposing a proposal from the Nobility that one of the senators would join the Archbishop in setting the crown on the head of the king.312 Bearing

310 SRARP, Vol. III, 20 May 1772, 81. 311 BdP, 11 April 1772, 349. 312 R 1410 BrP, 11 May 1772; 20 May 1772, 3928; 1 May 1772, 3961. 240 chapter three in mind their disputes with the Hat nobility, the Cap majority of the Burgher Estate found it unacceptable that a representative of the Nobility should play such a prominent role in an act of state. Th e Lutheran religious ceremony was suffi cient in their eyes. Th e position of the Nobility was put by Sven Bunge when he sug- gested that the change was needed to demonstrate that the Clergy was no longer the fi rst estate. Th e ceremony as such was unimportant in so far as the King would be recognized by his people.313 Bunge’s view refl ects secularization in the defi nition of the political power of the King among the Nobility as well as a reference to its popular legiti- macy as understood by the Nobles. Likewise, argued Bunge, the pur- pose of the oaths of the Estates was basically to “bind together the rights and responsibilities of the King and the people towards each other”.314 Th e diff erences of opinion regarding the coronation refl ected the diff ering concepts of the people that were still held by each estate. While the Nobility was willing to increase the symbolic role of ‘the people’ in the coronation and to augment the secular character of the act so that one of their members would participate in it as a represen- tative of the most important group of that people, the commoner estates rejected this as a mistaken form of symbolism of the rule of the people. Instead, they concentrated on the defence of the privileges of their own estates with arguments that did not make appeal to the pop- ular origin of political power. For them, the old notions of the relative roles of God, the King and the people in the coronation act were suf- fi cient. Many of them would actually welcome a stronger monarch who promised to uphold the privileges of all the estates. Th ey had certainly not been advocates of democracy in any modern sense in the fi rst place. At the time of the disputes over the oaths, there was rising dissatis- faction with the Diet throughout the realm for its inability to fi nd solu- tions to acute problems. Th e failure of the Estates to do anything about the famine in particular was leading to the loss of their legitimacy in the eyes of the public. By August, the King and his supporters had resolved to take over. Th ey were able to do so without encountering much opposition; there were only a handful of radical politicians like

313 SRARP, Vol. III, 20 May 1772, 93. 314 SRARP, Vol. III, 25 May 1772, 143. the swedish diet, – 241

Carl Fredrik Pechlin who protested against the coup. Much of the population agreed that the rule of the Estates should be replaced by a strong monarchy, and this was done without much diffi culty. Th e lack of opposition strongly suggests that neither the Swedish political elite nor the people at large had been using their references to the people in some pre-revolutionary modern ‘democratic’ sense. Even those French philosophers who had once admired the liberty of the Swedish constitution were sympathetic to the coup and to the francophile Gustavus III,315 which questions the sincerity of their previous admira- tion for the Swedish constitution. Th eir fl attering statements about the political order of an allied country may have been no more than compliments or an indirect way of criticizing the political order in France. Sweden had not become a ‘democracy’, and it was not admired as such. Th e success of Gustavus III depended on a number of factors, one of them being his command of rhetoric, by means of which he was able to persuade the Estates to cooperate. When speaking to them in connection with the coup, he delineated a widely approved redefi ni- tion of the concepts of the people and the nation. He presented the Swedish (political) nation as divided into two parties resembling two separate “peoples” ( folkslag) who had made “the people” ( folket) and “the populace” (menighet) victims of their never-ending strife. “Th e people” was “starving”, while “the nation” had seen its plenipotentia- ries abusing the people. Th e solution which the autocratic monarch off ered was to rule instead over “one free people” united by the King.316 In his defi nition, he questioned the legitimacy of the members of the Estates to be true plenipotentiaries of the nation and raised himself into the position of defender of the people—even a representative of the people. Th is interpretation seems to have been quite widely accepted, at least at the beginning of his reign. Th e transition to auto- cratic rule was easy because of the depth of the crisis of the estate system. It was also facilitated by previous appeals to the King both in the press and at the Diet, urging him to unite the divided Swedish people.317 Th e Lutheran clergy would also do their share in reintroduc- ing a political language that supported a strong monarchy.

315 Roberts 1986, 203–206, 211. 316 SRARP, Vol. III, 21 August 1772, 627, 629, 632; For background, see Alm 2002. 317 Johan Fredric Quist, Tal om Svenska Folkets Glädje och Hopp vid Konung Gustav IIIs Höga Kröning, Den 29 Maji 1772. Underdånigast hållt På Kongl. Trivial-Scholan i Örebro, Hyllnings-dagen (Örebro 1772), 17. 242 chapter three

Th is was the strategy of many leading noblemen as well. Carl Fredrik Scheff er, whom we met when reviewing the strongest arguments in favour of the rise of “popular sovereignty” in the Age of Liberty, had by the autumn of 1772 become a prominent spokesman for the new monarchical order. Speaking before the King and the Academy of Sciences in October 1772, the former tutor of Prince Gustavus had forgotten most of the advice he had given to his pupil some twelve years earlier on the supreme power belonging to the Estates as the plenipotentiaries of the people. Scheff er advised the King to assume power from the Estates, which had become excessively Cap-oriented, anti-aristocratic and popular. Aft er the coup, he helped Gustavus to draft a new constitution. In his speech in October, Scheff er interpreted all classical examples of popular government in highly pejorative terms, describing how the unrestrained rule of the people in Greece had ended in “the most atro- cious despotism of the many”. In Rome as well, under what Scheff er called its “Age of Liberty”, the Senate had disdained the people, and the latter had neglected all their duties in relation to the Senate. As a consequence, the people had been divided into two peoples ( folkslag) incapable of achieving unity and happiness.318 With these parallels, which actually stood for the rule of the Estates in the Swedish Age of Liberty, Scheff er and the Swedish elite whom he was addressing rejected the Athenian model of democracy and Roman republicanism and the unfortunate applications of these during the previous consti- tution of Sweden. By contrast, under Gustavus, the Swedish people was described as capable of achieving “this real and salutary liberty which is indispensable for the happiness of a people”. Indeed, the Swedes would be freer than any nation at any time in history. It fol- lowed that the Swedish people under the rule of Gustavus would become more fortunate than the Athenians had ever been under their despotism of the many.319 Th e King and the noble elite had made cer- tain that Sweden would never become a democracy, which appeared in their rhetoric as the absolute opposite of liberty.

318 Carl Fredric Scheff er, Tal, Om Förbindelsen, Imellan Grund-Lagarnas Art och Folkets Sällhet, Som Aft er Dem Styras Skal; Hållit Uti Kongl. Vetenskaps Academien, Vid Praesidii Afl äggande, den 28 October 1772 (Stockholm 1772), 7–9. 319 Scheff er, Tal, 1772, 23–25, 30. the swedish diet, – 243

Th e Academy of Sciences joined Scheff er’s interpretation by offi - cially declaring the Gustavian regime the source of the highest happi- ness the people could imagine: Th anks to an improved constitution, a more solid foundation has now been laid for the lasting happiness of the people, honest liberty secured, and the security of each individual restored.320 With these words, not only the form of government but also the politi- cal role of the people had been successfully redefi ned. In reality, of course, both political liberty in the old sense and the estate radicalism of the late Age of Liberty had come to an end.321 Th e turn had been so dramatic that it has proved diffi cult for many historians to accept it. Th e building of Swedish and Finnish democracy was to start (again) only much later in quite diff erent circumstances.

320 Scheff er, Tal, 1772, 32. 321 Roberts 1986, 207.

CHAPTER FOUR

THE REEVALUATION OF THE REPRESENTATION OF THE PEOPLE AND DEMOCRACY IN WESTMINSTER, 17721789

Th e Swedish coup of 1772 did not go unnoticed in the British Par- liament. Gustavus III’s seizure of power caused Th omas Townshend, Baron Bayning, to assert that the Swedish King had “cut the throat of Swedish liberty” (XVIII, 831), implying that the same might happen under any free government. Charles Lennox, the Duke of Richmond and Lennox, similarly suggested—with reference to North’s policies threatening the liberty of the people—that Britain, like Sweden, was ripe for “a total loss of liberty” (XVIII, 1378). John Wilkes also took the loss of liberty by the Swedes as a warning example to the British: Th e kingdom of Sweden, by its constitution one of the freest monarchies in the world, has recently fallen under the galling yoke of despotism by the treachery and perjury of its king (XIX, 1007). Depending on their conceptions of the state of the British constitu- tion during the American War of Independence and the activities of the parliamentary reform movement—and thus depending on their position as either supporters or opponents of the ministry—the mem- bers of parliament would either see the Swedish manner of depriving the monarchy of power in the Age of Liberty as a major mistake, or lament how the Swedes had in 1772 chosen “one instead of many rep- resentatives”.1 Th e Swedish case was thus considered relevant in the British parliamentary discourse on constitutional liberty, though it was mainly used as a warning instance by both sides in their arguments.

1 Sir Nathaniel William Wraxall, XXI, 1272; Richard Brinsley Sheridan, XIX, 1311; Archibald Campbell Fraser, XXIV, 391; Wraxall had visited the Scandinavian coun- tries and became involved in an attempted murder of the Queen of Denmark, sister of George III; Fraser’s reference to Sweden is probably explained by his background as a diplomat who had previously negotiated with the Danes. 246 chapter four

Th e American Crisis, Representation and the British People, 1772–1780

Th e Speech from the Th rone in January 1772 was remarkable in the corpus of ceremonial speaking in the British Parliament. As Chapter Two demonstrated, the Commons had adopted a clearer position as the spokesmen for the people in the late 1760s and in the very begin- ning of the 1770s. In the aft ermath of the Wilkes aff air, the ministry had also made some concessions towards a clearer recognition of the political role of the people. In spring 1771, the political roles of the people on the one hand and Parliament on the other had been sharply distinguished by both the Wilkite opposition and the defenders of the privileges of the Commons. It is thus noteworthy that George III, when speaking in January 1772, said nothing about his people; in other words, the ministry deliberatively ignored the concept. Th e King referred to the welfare of his people only aft er the Lords had closed their Address with that phrase. Th e Commons did not mention the people either, while the King answered by referring to his happy people under his government (XVII, 237). In terms of ceremonial speaking, the British political elite had been reunited in its conceptions of the relationship between the King and his people and remained so when facing food riots and American opposition to revenue offi cers.2 In the November Speech from the Th rone, George III referred to his people three times, albeit in an entirely conventional manner (XVII, 517–519). His words were echoed by the two houses. Th e English discourse on popular government was partly nurtured by French political philosophy, particularly in the early 1770s. Radi- cal Enlightenment conceptions of a sovereign people were creeping into the British language of politics through translations. Rousseau’s works were translated, and they suggested that the people had origi- nally had sovereignty over themselves and had never surrendered all of it to councillors. Democracy, too, could simply be seen as a state “where the people are sovereign”.3 Jean Paul Marat, also originally from Geneva, published his Chains of Slavery in Newcastle and gained recognition despite his radical ideas on popular government. Marat

2 Holmes & Szechi 1993, 246. 3 Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Th e Miscellaneous Works of J.J. Rousseau . . . (Edinburgh 1774), Vol. 3, 193, 196. Th e original title is Letters Written from the Mountains. democracy in westminster, – 247 rejected claims that democratic government would be more unsettled than monarchic or aristocratic and maintained that factions, seditions and rebellions arose “less from a popular constitution than from its corruption”. Marat argued likewise that popular risings advanced the cause of liberty and that popular government was unlikely to make any people suff er. According to him: “In a well constituted government, the people at large is the real sovereign, to them belongs supreme power.”4 While a Swiss émigré was putting forward such radicalized notions of democracy and the sovereignty of the people, in mainstream Anglo- phone opposition discourse Lockean language referring to the people and their “right to resume their original liberty” and to establish a new legislature was reviving in this period as a consequence of North’s fi s- cal policies in the American colonies.5 In the later eighteenth century, a number of thinkers built on increasingly radical interpretations of Lockean ideas about natural rights.6 Th e classical tradition of scepticism towards democracy had certainly not disappeared. Henry Home, Lord Kames, for instance, argued that democracy was “rash, violent, and fl uctuating”, the most turbulent and hence the worst of all governments. A combination of the people and sovereignty would lead to catastrophic consequences, with mob rule: Th e people, in whom resides the sovereign power, are insolent in pros- perity, timid in adversity, cruel in anger, blind and prodigal in aff ection, and incapable of embracing steadily a prudent measure.7 Kames’ conclusion was that “democracy will never be recommended by any enlightened politician, as a good form of government”.8 Th e constitutional debate of the Age of Enlightenment did not mean the victory of democracy, but its French, Swiss and Scottish dimensions provided some new interpretations of popular government, democracy and the sovereignty of the people in the English language as well.

4 Jean Paul Marat, Chains of Slavery. A Work Wherein the Clandestine and Villain- ous Attempts of Princes to Ruin Liberty are Pointed Out . . . (London 1774), 107–109, 197. 5 [Anon.], Th e London Magazine. Or, Gentleman’s Monthly Intelligencer (London) [1774], 188. Th e article consists mainly of a long quotation from Locke. 6 Dickinson 1995, 179. 7 Henry Home, Lord Kames, Sketches of the History of Man . . . (Edinburgh 1774), Vol. 1, 393–394. 8 Home, Sketches, 1774, Vol. 1, 403. 248 chapter four

Th ese interpretations had not yet been adopted in British high poli- tics. In the Royal Speech of January 1774, the people remained the objects of the patriarchal care of the King and Parliament (XVII, 937, 940). During that year, the relative weight of the opposition increased when Fox resigned from the ministry. Parliamentary legislation on trade, colonial administration and toleration for Catholics increased tension in America, but in Britain these measures strengthened sup- port for the government in general elections.9 When Parliament was opened in November, a challenge to its supreme authority was already undeniable. Th e King thus advised Parliament: Let my people, in every part of my dominions, be taught by your exam- ple, to have a due reverence for the laws, and a just sense of the blessings, of our excellent constitution (XVIII, 34). Th e formulation denied possibilities for opposition in the name of the people, either in Britain or in America. Both houses responded by expressing their determination to defend “the supreme authority” of Parliament.10 By the time of the next Speech from the Th rone in October 1775, the war in America had broken out despite attempts at reconciliation. Th is increased divisions in domestic politics and deeply infl uenced British political culture, including conceptions of Parliament as the holder of absolute sovereign power yet as a far from a representative institution.11 Th e American struggle in the name of the interests of the people provoked public debate on the political power of the people and democracy. In anti-American loyalist polemic, oft en sponsored by the North ministry and distributed free of charge,12 the colonists, and implicitly their British supporters, were criticized for aiming at “a democratical tyranny” or “democracy” in the sense of mob vio- lence. Blackstone’s Commentaries, which had otherwise given a rather positive sense to “democracy”, was used to reject demands that power should be given back to the people.13 Th e sympathizers of the Ameri-

9 Holmes & Szechi 1993, 246. 10 Holmes & Szechi 1993, 246. 11 Brewer 1980, 361–362; Wilson 1995, 237–238, 244, 249; Bradley 2007, 96, 102. 12 Wilson 1995, 241. 13 Dickinson 1998a, 92. democracy in westminster, – 249 can cause, by contrast, sometimes appealed to Montesquieu in calling for representation of the people as a pre-condition for taxation.14 Two political tracts—by James Burgh, and Jean Louis Delolme— illustrate the state of the theoretical debate in Britain and in Europe more generally at the time of the outbreak of the American War of Independence. Burgh presented an uncompromising interpretation on the popular origin of all political power. According to him, “all lawful authority, legislative, and executive, originates from the people. Power in the people is like light in the sun, native, original, inherent and unlimited by any thing human.” Th is meant that the power of the governors was “only borrowed, delegated, and limited by the intention of the people”. Th e people, in turn, were “answerable only to God”, as they were “the fountain of power” as well as “the object of govern- ment” and “the last resource”.15 While the exact concept ‘the sover- eignty of the people’ was not yet available to Burgh, he did write about “the majesty of the people”, following an old Roman expression.16 Burgh also possessed a developed concept of ‘government by repre- sentation’, which meant “parliamentary government” without “regular appeal to the people”. He maintained that representation produced the same good eff ects in government “as if every inhabitant of the country were to deliberate and vote in person.”17 While this concep- tion was based mainly on the British tradition, Burgh also regarded a wide range of regimes as mixed parliamentary governments, including those of Sparta, Athens and Rome in the past and the Dutch Republic, Britain and Sweden in the eighteenth century. Th e Dutch case was not clear, however: even though power should have belonged to the peo- ple, it was not extended to the middling sorts. In Britain, he argued, “the people are swallowed up in king, lords, and commons”,18 which did not sound like a particularly fl attering expression either. In 1775, the Swedish case could be left without further comment. Burgh was unhappy with the degree of popular representation in Britain. To make his point, he quoted (inaccurately) Walpole’s warn- ing of 1734 concerning the rise of “democratical” government if

14 [Anon.], Tyranny Unmasked. An Answer to a Late Pamphlet, Entitled Taxation no Tyranny (London 1775), 66. 15 James Burgh, Political Disquisitions: or, an Enquiry into Public Errors, Defects, and Abuses . . . (London 1774–1775), Vol. 1, 3–4. 16 Burgh, Political Disquisitions, 1774, Vol. 1, 4. 17 Burgh, Political Disquisitions, 1774, Vol. 1, 4. 18 Burgh, Political Disquisitions, 1774, Vol. 1, 8–9, 12, 16, 71. 250 chapter four parliaments were shortened.19 While Burgh considered parliamentary privilege to be as extensive as “the people’s power”, he maintained— with an obvious reference to the Wilkes case—that the people had retained rights, including the right to choose their representatives, which Parliament should never violate.20 Burgh’s treatise was evidently critical of the established system. Margaret Canovan has even seen it as an example of a “forward-looking, activist conception of popular sovereignty” which consisted of the people’s right to change the con- stitution as it pleased, the constant presence of the people’s deputies in the Commons and suff rage extended to all men.21 Delolme’s book on the English constitution, by contrast, supported the notion that in Britain “the People’s Power” was “completely del- egated to their Representatives”,22 i.e. that no active sovereignty of the people existed and that the constitution was essentially representative as opposed to popular.23 Th is view, formulated by an exile from Geneva, was later cited by some British parliamentary speakers to defend the established British system of representation against alternative mod- els. Delolme wrote about “the superior excellence of a Government in which the People only act through Representatives, that is, by means of an assembly”. Indeed, Delolme argued, “such a Constitution is the only one that is capable of the immense advantage, [. . .] of putting into the hands of the People the moving springs of the Legislative author- ity”.24 Th e distinction that he drew between representative and demo- cratic government was also important: A representative Constitution places the remedy in the hands of those who feel the disorder; but a popular Constitution places the remedy in the hands of those who cause the disorder; and it is necessarily produc- tive, in the event, of the misfortune, [. . .].25 Delolme’s judgement of pure democracy was an uncompromising one: the Greek democracies had only caused irregularity and cruelty, while Roman eff orts to create the equality needed in democratic govern-

19 Burgh, Political Disquisitions, 1774, Vol. 1, 113. 20 Burgh, Political Disquisitions, 1774, Vol. 1, 221. Th is was clearly a condemnation of the exclusion of Wilkes from the Commons. 21 Canovan 2005, 25–26. 22 Jean Louis Delolme, Th e Constitution of England, or an Account of the English Government . . . (London 1775), 249. 23 Lieberman 2006, 340. 24 Delolme, Th e Constitution of England, 1775, 253. 25 Delolme, Th e Constitution of England, 1775, 254. democracy in westminster, – 251 ment had failed miserably. Likewise, the English seventeenth-century attempt to build “democracy” had been totally in vain.26 Moreover, in comparing the British and Swedish constitutions, he denounced democracy as “a disguised, and the worst of Aristocracies.”27 In some respects, Delolme expanded the meaning of ‘democracy’: Unlike most other authors, he considered practices such as trial by jury and the liberty of the press—the placing of judicial and censo- rial power in the people—as phenomena that actually made Britain “a much more Democratical State than any other”.28 Th is view made democracy a wider phenomenon than the form of government alone. Democracy was not merely about formal decision-making; it was also about what would today be called “the political culture”, and in that sense the British system deserved to be called democratic. Fur- thermore, the English form of government, which Delolme so much admired, contained an essential democratic element, though not nec- essarily one in Parliament.29 Delolme’s anglophile advice was to retain the representative system unchanged. His views may have contributed to parliamentary speakers such as Burke associating democracy with both free trials and publicity in the mid-1780s. Th e British constitution was thus both admired and criticized, in Britain and abroad. In the circumstances of war in America and the intense public debate on constitutional issues, North’s ministry chose to use of inclusive concept ‘the King’s people’ in describing the state of aff airs in ceremonial speaking. Th e Americans, by contrast, were an “unhappy people” and a “deluded multitude” infl amed by the mis- representations of their leaders. As for the King’s relationship to his dutiful subjects, they “can have no cause in which I am not equally interested” (XVIII, 695–697). Th e Lords ostentatiously emphasized “the sovereign authority of the British legislature” and “the authority of the supreme legislature” over all the British Empire, viewing the “sovereignty of the legislature” as something that belonged jointly to the King and Parliament (XVIII, 707, 709, 713–714). Th e Commons spent days debating the proper policy on America but fi nally only added to the formulations heard in the King’s speech a declaration

26 Delolme, Th e Constitution of England, 1775, 60, 92, 375. 27 Jean Louis Delolme, A Parallel between the English Constitution and the Former Government of Sweden . . . (London 1772), 30. 28 Delolme, Th e Constitution of England, 1775, 408. 29 Delolme, Th e Constitution of England, 1775, 424; Lieberman 2006, 340. 252 chapter four that the British constitution provided “the freest and happiest condi- tion of any civil society in the known world” (XVIII, 796). Th e King was viewed as “the father of his people” whose rights and interests were identical with those of his people (XVIII, 797–798). In the British political culture, also the sympathizers of the Ameri- cans were allowed to speak. George Johnstone, the Governor of West Florida, lamented the lack of a parliamentary institution “to balance between the people and the crown” in America; therefore the people there were forced to defend the rights of their assemblies to express “the general sense of the people”. His suggestion was that instead of acting as “the guardians of the people’s rights and privileges”, the Com- mons were sacrifi cing these rights in America (XVIII, 745–746, 756). Temple Simon Luttrell, too, opposed an approving reply to the Royal Speech. In his view, “as representatives of the community in general” and as “the deputies of the people”, they simply could not approve it. Luttrell viewed the rebellion as understandable in that the original rights of the people had been violated (XVIII, 758). He thus did not rule out active popular resistance to a ruler, building on the tradition according to which resistance to arbitrary power by the people was a natural right.30 Th ere were not many constitutional debates in Parliament during the early phase of the war. In March 1776, however, Wilkes, who had fi nally become the member of parliament for Middlesex two years pre- viously, took the initiative by moving for parliamentary reform. Th e motion was supposed to answer long-standing calls for the removal of electoral corruption, the redistribution of seats and more frequent elections.31 No-one seconded the motion of the radical populist; indeed it the Prime Minister refuted it mockingly, and it was rejected without a division (XVIII, 1297–1298).32 Wilkes’ motion was probably addressed to the reading public of the “middling sorts” rather than to the Commons, particularly as he knew that he had no party to support him. It initiated a long series of related opposition motions regarding the abolition of rotten boroughs, an increase in the representation of the growing cities, the shortening of the length of parliaments, the extension of suff rage, and so on. Th ese

30 Dickinson 1995, 164. 31 Dickinson 1995, 176. 32 For Wilkes’ proposal in a long-term history of attempts to reform Parliament, see Cannon 1994, 67. democracy in westminster, – 253 proposals, which were particularly numerous in the early 1780s and again in the 1790s, and the debates that followed them made frequent use of language referring to the people. Th e argumentative structure of Wilkes’ original speech already reveals the centrality of the concepts of the people and representation. Th e speech opened with an expression of admiration for the classical models of Greece and Rome: “Th e most natural and perfect idea of a free government is [. . .] that of the people themselves assembling to determine by what laws they chuse to be governed, [. . .]” (XVIII, 1287). Th en domestic history was invoked: the ancestors of the British had improved the classical system intended for small states by introducing “the representation of the many by a few, as answering more fully the true ends of government” (XVIII, 1287). Representation appeared here as a British innovation distinguishing its constitution from the Roman form of popular government, which had rather been based on disorderly public assemblies. Wilkes’ defi nition of the English version of representation was: Every Englishman is supposed to be present in parliament, either in per- son, or by a deputy chosen by himself, and therefore the resolution of parliament is taken [. . .] to give to the public the consent and approba- tion of every free agent of the community (XVIII, 1288). While “the sense of the people” had been traditionally revealed by the representatives of “the great council of the nation”, in 1776, “the senti- ments of the people” could no longer be seen in parliamentary resolu- tions because of the degenerated composition of Parliament. Th erefore, it was essential “to restore to the people their clear rights, their original share in the legislature” (XVIII, 1288, 1290–1291). Wilkes put himself on highly sensitive ground by suggesting that the war with America was being fought “contrary to the sense of the nation” and that the opinions of the majority in Parliament were “directly counter to the sense of the nation.” A further provocation was hidden in the claim that a reformed Parliament would “speak the free, unbiased sense of the body of the English people” as opposed to the current “aristocrati- cal tyranny” (XVIII, 1293–1295). Th e leading radical further main- tained that the people was “the original fountain of power” and that the Commons was “only a delegated power from the people at large” (XVIII, 1296–1297). Th ese were maxims that found no supporters in the circumstances of 1776. Th e stakes were too high as a result of the war, the challenge to the established form of representation was exces- sively grave, and in the eyes of his colleagues Wilkes himself possessed no convincing ethos. 254 chapter four

Th e debate on ‘the people’ and the constitution was left for free authors to carry further. Th e crisis can be seen in the introduction of some novel expressions in printed literature about this time. Th e exact phrase “the sovereignty of the people”, for instance, fi rst appeared in the English language in print in an explicitly political sense when Edward Gibbon (1776) used it to describe what the monuments of Athens and Rome had been intended to represent. He also defi ned “a democratical government”, in quite conventional terms, as one in which “the citizens exercise the powers of sovereignty”. Th is con- tinued until the multitude took over and “all the inconveniences of a wild democracy” followed in the cycle of forms of government.33 Likewise in 1776, a translation of Guillaume-Th omas-François Raynal characterized the Swedish constitution of the Age of Liberty, with its popular control over a very limited monarchy, as “the greatest act of sovereignty a people can exercise”. Th is implied that in Sweden the sovereignty of the people had been eff ectively implemented but had been lost with the royal coup of 1772. Such a statement in hindsight of course provides no proof that the Swedes themselves understood their system in identical terms. As for the British mixed constitution, it was in principle a good and balanced one according to Raynal, who argued that the monarchy eff ectively checked “the tendency of the govern- ment to democracy” by the means of bribery there.34 Whereas the notion of the sovereignty of the people had become available by 1776, democracy was defi nitely not yet seen as a goal. An anonymous pamphlet entitled Plain Truth, published together with Th omas Paine’s Common Sense, presented democracy, in accordance with Montesquieu’s and Hume’s ideas, as a degenerated form of gov- ernment. In principle, democracy was “extremely plausible and indeed fl attering to the pride of mankind” but still “there never existed, nor ever will exist a real democracy in the world.”35 Th e problem with the Americans was that they were attempting to create “an indepen- dent, arbitrary, democratical government” and thus endangering the

33 Edward Gibbon, Th e History of the Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire (Lon- don 1776), Vol. 1, 34, 47, 68. 34 Abbé Raynal, A Philosophical and Political History of the Settlements and Trade of the Europeans in the East and West Indies. . . . Translated . . . by J. Justamond, Vol. 2 (Dublin 1776), 31; Vol. 4, (London 1776), 413–414. 35 Th omas Paine, Common Sense; Addressed to the Inhabitants of America . . . A new edition, [London] 1776, 2, 5. democracy in westminster, – 255 good eff ects of the British constitution.36 John Cartwright, a gentle- man reformist, remained equally conventional in maintaining that the “pure democratical” form of government was impractical for large communities, even if he argued for “rights of sovereignty” in the peo- ple, defended the independence of Parliament in relation to executive power, and proposed an extended suff rage.37 Pamphlets published in America, by contrast, argued more openly for popular government, the people being seen as the best governors in all branches of power.38 Th is debate, which extended itself to Brit- ain, combined older concepts in a creative manner. We can fi nd, for instance, a defi nition of “popular government, sometimes termed democracy, republic or common wealth” as “that plan of civil society, wherein the community at large takes the care of its own welfare, and manages its concerns by representatives elected by the people out of their own body”.39 In such a defi nition, democracy no longer sounded quite as bad as classical conceptions of it suggested. It was indirectly connected with the concept of representation, too, which was still rare at that time. A more extensive discussion on democracy was to be found in Jeremy Bentham’s critical review—almost a parody—of William Blackstone’s Commentaries. Bentham’s point was that Blackstone had misunderstood democracy in defi ning it as “the government of all” on the one hand and calling the Commons “a kind of democracy” and the democratical branch of the constitution on the other.40 Blackstone’s attempted redefi nition of the Commons as democracy was thus still being disputed a decade aft er the publication of his book. In his pro-colonial Observations on Civil Liberty, Richard Price wid- ened the constitutional debate towards notions that Harry Dickinson has been ready to call a “doctrine of popular sovereignty” that chal- lenged Parliament.41 Price saw the people as the body of independent

36 Paine, Common Sense, 1776, 37. 37 John Cartwright, Take Your Choice! . . . (London 1776), 5; Christie 1962, 62–63; Miller 1994, 355. 38 [Anon.], Th e People the Best Governors: or A Plan of Government Founded on the Just Principles of Natural Freedom [United States 1776], 4, 13. 39 An anonymous address to the people of Pennsylvania reproduced in Th e Remem- brancer, or Impartial Repository of Public Events . . . (London) [1775–1784], 124. 40 Jeremy Bentham, A Fragment on Government; Being an Examination of what is Delivered, on the Subject of Government in General, in the Introduction to Sir William Blackstone’s Commentaries . . . (London 1776), 89–90, 93, 105, 111. 41 Dickinson 1977, 222. 256 chapter four agents and governors as their servants.42 He argued that the power of the people was above that of Parliament, maintaining that all free civil government “is the creature of the people”, “originates with them” and “is conducted under their direction” for the sole purpose of execut- ing “the will of the people” (still a rare phrase in political discourse). Th e people could choose any form of government, but freedom always required their share in, and control over, government through a rep- resentative assembly, as the people simply could not have too much power. Power delegated to Parliament, by contrast, always remained limited. Indeed, “omnipotence”, insofar as it existed, “must be lodged where all legislative authority originates; that is, in the People.”43 Th is claim was adopted by Wilkes, who used it in Parliament in the fol- lowing year, arguing that government was merely “a trust from the people” and that hence any idea of “the omnipotence of parliament” was mistaken.44 Challenges to the notion of the sovereignty of parlia- ment were coming increasingly to the fore. In 1779 Price formulated his key maxim in the statement “the sov- ereignty in every country belongs to the people”.45 Such references to the people were striking, the point being that power would be returned to the omnipotent people if the King-in-Parliament could not guaran- tee the natural rights and liberties of the subjects.46 Few other authors had previously spoken so explicitly about Parliament as the executor of the will of the people. However, Price presented this argument with- out any reference to “democracy”. Th e reactions to these claims were numerous and revealing. Many denied Price’s claim that “all power rests and centers in the people” and emphasized instead the wisdom of the few or of just one in gov- ernance in comparison with the rule of the multitude.47 In particu-

42 Hampsher-Monk 2006, 670. 43 Richard Price, Observations on the Nature of Civil Liberty, the Principles of Gov- ernment, and the Justice and Policy of the War with America . . . Th e second edition, (London 1776), 6, 11–12, 15, 87. 44 Dickinson 1977, 216–217. 45 Richard Price, A Sermon, Delivered to a Congregation of Protestant Dissenters, at Hackney, on the 10th of February Last, Being the Day Appointed for a General Fast, Th e second edition (London 1779), 21. 46 Dickinson 1995, 172. 47 [Author of the Political Looking Glass], Th e Duty of the King and Subject, on the Principles of Civil Liberty . . . (London 1776), 8; John Shebbeare, An Essay on the Origin, Progress and Establishment of National Society; in which the Principles of Gov- ernment . . . Contained in Dr. Price’s Observations, &c. are fully Examined and fully democracy in westminster, – 257 lar, Price’s idea of the “omnipotence of an illiterate multitude” was rejected, and doubts were expressed concerning the skills of the people at large as rulers. Th e decisions of a majority of members of parlia- ment were rather seen as representing “vox populi”, as the House had been chosen with “the voluntary election of a whole people”.48 ‘Democracy’, too, was turning into a concept of dispute. Even if Price had said hardly anything about democracy, his opponents used the concept in their responses, arguing: “We have no instance of any government of a long duration, in a pure democratic state.”49 Henry Goodricke deliberately interpreted Price’s tract as an extremist advo- cacy of democracy, replacing the term “civil liberty” in the original text with “a pure democracy” and rejecting the claims that followed. Goodricke instead defended other forms of government based on pop- ular consent and cited Algernon Sidney, John Locke, Joseph Priest- ley,50 Jean-Jacques Burlamaqui and Francis Hutcheson as critics of pure democracy. His conclusions were that popular states could not function as a result of excessive liberty and that it was a grave mis- take to entrust political power into the hands of the people at large. Goodricke’s advice probably sounded agreeable to the British parlia- mentary elite: it was advisable “to avoid the evils of Democracy by excluding the great body of the state” and to have, instead, a Parlia- ment “nearly connected and related to the people in general”.51 Publications such as Paine’s Common Sense, Cartwright’s Take Your Choice!, Bentham’s Fragment of Government or Price’s Observations on Civil Liberty—or even the US Declaration of Independence in July 1776—did not immediately aff ect the content of speeches in Westmin- ster. Th is was the case despite the members’ awareness of the radical claim that the policies of the North ministry were only enabled by the corrupted nature of Parliament, which no longer communicated the wishes of the people to the Crown.52 Th e Speech from the Th rone

Refuted . . . (London 1776), 32, 35. Shebbeare was paid by the ministry. Wilson 1995, 241. 48 [Anon.], Remarks on Dr. Price’s Observations . . . (London 1776), 3–4, 7, 26. 49 [Anon.], Experience Preferable to Th eory. An Answer to Dr. Price’s Observa- tions . . . (London 1776), 8. 50 Priestley had argued in connection with the Wilkes crisis that popular power was originally given by the people. Gunn 1983, 82. 51 Henry Goodricke, Observations on Dr. Price’s Th eory and Principles of Civil Lib- erty and Government . . . (York 1776), 91, 97–99, 106, 108–109, 113, 115–116; cf. 98 and Price, Observations, 1776, 4. 52 Wilson 1995, 248. 258 chapter four in October lamented the mistakes of the King’s “unhappy people” in America in rejecting his mild government (XVIII, 1366–1367). In the Lords, some government supporters claimed that the rebellion had been fomented by the opposition in Britain, whereas Charles Wat- son Wentworth, the Marquis of Rockingham, and the Duke of Rich- mond, leaders of the Rockinghamite opposition, condemned the Royal Speech for misrepresenting the state of the people under the current ministry (XVIII, 1369).53 Richmond found an analogy in the fall of the Swedish free government in 1772. All liberty had been lost in a cor- rupt system as the consequence of a royal coup, and the same might happen in Britain: [. . .] from a total disregard which prevailed among public men, to the interests of the nation, and the innumerable modes of corruption, long established, with the new ones daily devised and discovered, he was in his conscience satisfi ed, that nothing but the personal virtue of the sov- ereign prevented this country from a total loss of liberty. Like Sweden, it was ripe for the event; [. . .] (XVIII, 1378). Th e American war brought premonitions of a constitutional crisis and made some opposition members look for parallels elsewhere. Rich- mond, as a former offi cer and diplomat with experience on the Con- tinent, was reasonably well informed about developments in Sweden. He may also have been infl uenced by Paine’s Common Sense, pub- lished in January 1776, which had presented Sweden and Denmark as recent examples of the sudden restoration of monarchical power in previously free states.54 Th e Rockinghamites failed to get the Commons’ Address amended as well. John Cavendish’s proposed alternative Address was critical of the conduct of the crisis by the ministry and opposed to the war as violating “the freedom of his Majesty’s people”. Its express goal was to restore to Parliament “the confi dence of all [the King’s] people” (XVIII, 1400–1401). Wilkes went as far as to admire the American Declaration of Independence for allowing “the people” to decide (XVIII, 1405). Since the offi cial Address made no complaints, the King responded in an authoritarian fashion by promising to defend the interests of his subjects (XVIII, 1431). As their protests seemed to have no eff ect on

53 Lowe 2004. 54 Derry 1976, 175, 177. democracy in westminster, – 259 the policy of the ministry, many members of the opposition quitted Parliament soon aft er its opening.55 Th e ministry continued along the same path in subsequent Speeches from the Th rone: Together with the parliamentary majority, it saw the war as the defence of the sovereignty of the King and the authority of Parliament against rebels aiming at the creation of a popular state. Nor was the public debate quite as radical as in 1776, containing as it did arguments critical of excessive popular involvement in politics. George Chalmers, for instance, argued in response to Willoughby Bertie, the 4th Earl of Abingdon, who had suggested that the authority of Parlia- ment was delegated from the people, that, as “no such aggregate body as the people is known as a part of government”, it was unthinkable that “the supremacy of the people” could coexist.56 When the mon- arch continued to contrast the “unhappy multitude” of America with his “faithful people” in Britain in his speech (XIX, 355), not even the opposition to the war, led by Chatham (Pitt the Elder) and Rocking- ham,57 made any signifi cant use of the concept of the people in its criticism. Richmond did express his concern for Britain losing its sta- tus as “a free people” as a result of the growth of the royal prerogative (XIX, 397, 411), and Captain John Luttrell viewed the speech as part of a project transferring “the supreme sovereignty”58 from the legislature to the ministry (XIX, 436–438), but this was regarded as no more than opposition grumbling. Th e loss of the Battle of Saratoga and the subsequent debate on a motion of adjournment in December 1777 demonstrates the tendency of defeats in the war to strengthen arguments based on the politi- cal role of the people among the opposition. In the Lords, Chatham opposed the adjournment by appealing to the role of the Lords as “the great hereditary council of the nation”, responsible for maintaining a balance “between the crown and the people”. In this case, according to the elder Pitt, both seemed to have been misled when the ministry had taken the country to war (XIX, 597–598). Th e government avoided getting involved in this kind of constitutional debate, whereas amongst

55 Holmes & Szechi 1993, 247. 56 George Chalmers, Second Th oughts: or, Observations upon Lord Abingdon’s Th oughts on the Letter of Edmund Burke, Esq. To the Sheriff s of Bristol (London 1777), 60, 62. 57 Holmes & Szechi 1993, 247. 58 Th is is an interesting double expression combining the concepts of the supreme power and sovereignty. 260 chapter four the Rockingham Whigs there was a willingness to take the argument further. William Petty, the Earl of Shelburne (later Marquess of Lans- downe), defended the right of the opposition to be taken into con- sideration as potential future ministers despite their protests against the war. Shelburne’s views mattered, as he was a former Secretary of State. In 1777, he was a leading opposition fi gure, and he maintained contact with moderate radicals in London. In just fi ve years time, he would become prime minister. Shelburne based his interpretation on Britain as “a popular government” in which “the nation at large” had a say and “public opinion” both inside and outside Parliament mat- tered (XIX, 610). Th ere had been relatively few explicit defi nitions of the British sys- tem as “popular government” in Parliament aft er the early 1740s; now the concept was back in the limelight. Th is debate on popular govern- ment in 1777 remained a single episode, to be sure, but it demon- strates the argumentative potential of language referring to the people and the public in a time of crisis, particularly when coming from such an infl uential fi gure. In 1778, an anonymous author argued that the British form of gov- ernment had a strong popular element in the Commons, “the virtual Representative of all the Commons of the British Empire.”59 A govern- ment propagandist argued that “the authority of the people of England is absorbed in the parliament—that the vox populi is only to be heard in the senate”. Th e obvious conclusion was that even though govern- ment “originated from the body of a free people”, in everyday politics “the collective body have not even the shadow of power”.60 It was irre- sponsible to attempt to exceed “the bounds of the people’s power” as the people constituted merely one of the several agents in the system, and one that should remain passive: Popular declaimers tell us, that “the Crown encroaches on the rights of the people,” and yet, with the same breath, they absurdly maintain that the people at large (aft er delegating their whole constitutional power, and divesting themselves of every degree of authority in the community) can reassume it as oft en as they please; nay, what is still more prepos- terous, that they have a natural and unquestionable right, not only to

59 [Anon.], An Appeal to Reason and Justice, in Behalf of the British Constitu- tion . . . (London 1778), 17, 54–55. 60 [Friend to the Public], Th e Delusive and Dangerous Principles of the Minority, Exposed and Refuted . . . (London 1778), 41, 43, 48. democracy in westminster, – 261

decide upon the conduct of their own share of legislation, but also to decide upon that of the other two estates, or component parts of the constitution; and to become party, judge and jury in the management of the whole authority of the nation.61 Th e fashionable concept of “the Majesty of the people”, propagated by the Americans and the opposition, was for this writer an absurd and meaningless expression derived from the writings of seventeenth- century republicans: Where is the Majesty of the people, where the vox populi aft er they have constitutionally, and during a time, irrecoverably delegated the whole of their power in the constitution to representatives of their own choice, without the smallest legal reservation?62 In November 1778 the declaration of war by France made the Ameri- can confl ict seem increasingly threatening for the nation. Instead of simply strengthening patriotism, the entry of France and other Con- tinental powers into the war increased criticism of the policies of the ministry.63 In this situation, in his next Royal Speech George III adopted a new tone in appealing to “the national honour and security” in order to motivate his subjects to fi ght in “the active and enterprising spirit of my people” (XIX, 1278). Such an emphasis on national feel- ings was readily accepted by the Lords, who continued the emphasis on the nation by referring to “the spirited perseverance of the British nation”, to “the national honour”, to “the yet undaunted spirit of the nation” and to the “national force” (XIX, 1320). In an atmosphere of national calamity, the more democratic aspects of language referring to the people seemed to have been left aside and the role of the mon- archy in saving the people—or rather the nation—emphasized. As a reaction to this, William Hervey, Marquis of Bristol, insisted that, as “the guardians of the people”, the Lords should fi rst demand an account of the war policies and formulate an Address in which “the voice and suff erings of the people” were present (XIX, 1286–1287). Th e Commons was slightly more conformist, echoing the rhetoric of “the active spirit of the nation” (XIX, 1377). Even Fox, despite being a francophile, appealed to “the national spirit” against the French (XIX, 1330). On the other hand references to the people were used by Wilkes,

61 Th e Delusive and Dangerous Principles, 1778, 55–57. 62 Th e Delusive and Dangerous Principles, 1778, 57–58. 63 Wilson 1995, 252–254. 262 chapter four according to whom: “Th e people [. . .] alone can constitute a House of Commons.” And, furthermore: “Th ere is a higher tribunal [than par- liament], that of the people, our constituents, ever ready to do justice to the oppressed and injured.” Th e populist Wilkes was quite ready to declare: “Th e people have no confi dence in administration. Th ey are detested by the nation, and therefore continued in power” (XIX, 1335, 1340, 1346). Only Governor Johnstone, a voice of the colonists, sec- onded Wilkes in this conclusion (XIX, 1356). Th e result was, however, that the opposition remained unable to eff ectively challenge North’s ministry despite its use of language referring to the people. During the course of 1779, Fox became more outspoken in his criticism of the war and found considerable backing for this in the Commons. Spain entered the war, and the ministry began to show some signs of disintegration.64 Th is year would also become a turning point in the debate when Christopher Wyvill launched his nationwide Yorkshire Association movement in late December. Th e movement criticized not only the American war and taxation but also the state of representation, calling for the redistribution of parliamentary seats and speaking boldly in the name of the people. Th e criticism was echoed by radical groups in London. A central argument of the movement was that the war had led to the monarchy invading the sphere of the Com- mons by means of corruption. Even though many of the Rockingham Whigs who were active in the movement were not ready for a reform in representation, the movement grew quickly. Its extra-parliamentary agitation decreased suddenly, however, aft er the Gordon Riots of 2–9 June 1780, when an anti-Catholic demonstration of 60,000 people led to several hundred casualties. Many considered the riots a practical example of the dangers of popular associations and popular anarchy.65 However, extra-parliamentary opposition, which was even ready to challenge the authority of Parliament, certainly did not cease with the riots. In the parliamentary elections of 1780 support for the govern- ment also declined.66 Th e Association Movement would aff ect the use of language refer- ring to the people in Parliament as well. Th omas Wycliff e’s treatise On Government, fi rst published in 1779, represents an extreme case of a

64 Holmes & Szechi 1993, 248. 65 Derry 1976, 187; Dickinson 1977, 219; Gunn 1983, 83–84; Perry 1990, 106; Dick- inson 1995, 128, 143, 151; Gould 2000, 164–165. 66 Gunn 1983, 83; Wilson 1995, 265. democracy in westminster, – 263 defence of the cause of the people. According to Wycliff e, the justifi ca- tion for the supreme power of the people was derived from the divine will as expressed in the Bible: “St. Paul has ordered all governors to be subject to the people; it is therefore, a Divine command, that [. . .] every governor shall acknowledge the supremacy of the people.” It fol- lowed that: “the supreme power of a state is in the people, and that the subordinate power of a state is in the governors, who are delegated by the people”. Th e people were “the original senators” and “an original subject of a state, whose prerogative is therefore the supreme power of the state”. Th e people had appointed the King, the Lords and the Commons as their delegated governors; they had “no authority inde- pendent of the people”. Th e unavoidable conclusion was that the King could no longer be called a sovereign either because “it is the people alone who are supreme in power, and who have no superior”. For Wycliff e, as for Price, “the will of the people” was what the governors should be guided by even if it diff ered from that of the King. Th e prob- lem with the current system was obvious: “Th e supposed sovereignty of the parliament” had replaced “the real sovereignty of the people”. A reform had become essential as it was demanded by such a number of petitioners that they could without doubt be regarded as ‘the people’. Th ey were, indeed, so numerous that Parliament had no right to resist this “supreme power of the people” without violating “the rights and sovereignty of the people”.67 In Wycliff e’s text, the sovereignty of the people was no longer a mere theoretical notion but a concept used to justify concrete political demands. Democracy was not Wycliff e’s goal, but “the sovereignty of the people” was the starting point of his programme. At least from the edition of 1786 onwards, this concept provided a real alternative for defi nitions of the basis of the British government. Th e claim was so radical, however, that its incorporation in the language of parliamen- tary speaking would take several years, even in radical circles. In ceremonial speaking, the concept of the people remained incor- porated in a language through which a stronger national community was constructed. Under attack from a French-led alliance, “the char- acter of my brave people” could not but give rise to a “national spirit”,

67 Th omas Wycliff e, On Government; Addressed to the Public . . . (Liverpool 1786) (1779), 45–46, 49, 68–69, 71, 73, 78–79, 83–85, 102, 104, 110–111; for the extent of petitioning, see Bradley 1986. 264 chapter four

George III argued (XX, 1021). As Chesterfi eld put it in the Lords, the speech was designed “to rouse the people” and “to stimulate parlia- ment, and through them the nation at large, to the most vigorous exertions” (XX, 1022). Even those lords who supported an alternative Address used language referring to the people only rarely to challenge the government. In the Commons, Prime Minister North, known for his spontaneity, recognized that the ministry was dependent on the majority in Parliament rather than public opinion: “God forbid, [. . .], that there should be a voice in the nation, stronger than that of parlia- ment” (XX, 1109). Fox, by contrast, already insinuated in a speech in 1779 that the peo- ple outside Parliament “were beginning to murmur, and their patience was not unlimited”, and suggested that demands for a change of min- istry were likely (XX, 1124–1125). Th is speech echoed Fox’s references to a possible popular uprising in his extra-parliamentary speeches and demonstrates a major change in his attitude to the people. Fox had now become an opponent of North’s ministry and even of the King himself. He was campaigning to win the most populous contested con- stituency of Westminster and speaking to large meetings outside Par- liament there. Fox’s actions constituted a rather opportunistic attempt to rally popular support in order to overcome the North ministry, make peace and launch a constitutional reform: he did not care that his stance was inconsistent with his previous views or with the very diff erent goals of the Westminster radicals, which including annual parliaments, secret polling, a redistribution of seats and an extended suff rage. Th e alliance made Fox, without a doubt, “the Man of the People”, creating connections between the parliamentary and London oppositions. Fox would maintain these links until the 1790s, but he remained a reformer working within the parliamentary system.68 By spring 1780, Parliament had also become a forum for reform debates. Arguments warning of excessive power on the part of the people were opposed there as we can see in the debate on Burke’s bill for abolishing the Board of Trade on 13 March 1780. Th is bill was part of a campaign for economic reform, which was connected with calls for parliamentary reform, an enterprise obstructed by North through

68 Christie 1962, 82–83, 99; Derry 1976, 188; Dickinson 1977, 219; Mitchell 1992, 34; Wilson 1995, 260; Corfi eld, Green & Harvey 2001, 159–160. democracy in westminster, – 265 the skilful manipulation of Parliament.69 Th e rise of the reform move- ment, in which Fox was involved, was, in any case, leading to the advent of a new concept of democracy in Parliament, partly as a result of Fox’s activities. Th e fi rst to address the question of the political role of the peo- ple was Th omas Samuel Jolliff e, who commented on Fox’s preceding defence of the petitions of the people (XXI, 248). William Adam, a close associate of North and a man who had wounded Fox in a duel just a few months earlier, carried the argument further, opposing the idea that Parliament should act according to the supposed demands of the people as expressed in petitions. According to Adam, it was unthinkable to “give up the deliberative power of parliament” in that way (XXI, 255) as only Parliament had the right to engage itself in decision-making. Representation was the essence of the parliamentary system: We were sent here by our constituents to judge for them, to think for them, and to determine for them, not to obey implicitly the dictates of their will. If we did, we lost and forgot the very essence of what a House of Commons was (XXI, 255–256). Th ese were logical sentiments, coming as they did from a representa- tive of a pocket borough. Adam presented direct democracy as potentially the most threaten- ing prospect if Parliament complied with the demands presented in the name of the people. Th e people outside Parliament constituted a potential threat to the established political order: Suppose the people were to tell us, this mixed government, the admira- tion of all foreign nations, and the happiness of this, is not suffi cient for our liberty, we want a democracy, that liberty may be extended. Would this House agree to their request, and alter the government of this country, because the prayers of their petitions contained such a request? (XXI, 256). Adam saw aristocracy rather than the monarchy or “the democracy” or “people”, as benefi ting from the bill (XXI, 256). Th e infl uence of the aristocracy should not grow disproportionately in relation to either the monarchy or democracy:

69 Christie 1962, 95–98; Holmes & Szechi 1993, 248; Wilson 1995, 259. 266 chapter four

[. . .] a combination of rich and powerful nobility, might, upon the reduc- tion of the necessary prerogatives of the crown, destroy and trample upon the democratical parts of the constitution (XXI, 256). Adam wanted no pure democracy, but he wished to secure the demo- cratic element of the balanced constitution, together with the mon- archy and aristocracy. His readiness to defend the monarchy against any reduction of the royal prerogative also reveals rather conventional reasoning. According to his calculations, the revenues on which Par- liament decided had grown tenfold by comparison with the royal ones since the Revolution of 1688, which had “rendered the people more independent” (XXI, 252–254). Leaving the Board of Trade as it was would, according to Adam, maintain the constitutional balance. Th e other debaters saw no reason to challenge Adam’s interpreta- tion of the balance of the British constitution. Richard Rigby, who generally supported North and opposed parliamentary reform, called for respect for the voice of the people as expressed in petitions. Fox, by contrast, emphasized the right of the representatives of the people to control any monarchical measures that confl icted with “the voice of the people” (XXI, 258). Democracy had re-entered parliamentary debates, and it reappeared a number of times in the course of the 1780s. Th is happened soon aft er the launch of the parliamentary reform movement. While the minis- try was able to prevent the reform, North regarded the spirit of the Commons as so threatening that he tried to resign, but this was not accepted by the monarch.70 On John Dunning’s initiative, according to which “the infl uence of the crown had increased to a degree dangerous to the liberties of the people” (XXI, 350), the opposition got a resolu- tion passed lamenting the growth of monarchical infl uence and calling for the strengthening of the Commons. Th is defeat was probably the most serious one for any eighteenth-century ministry.71 On 2 June, the same day when the Gordon Riots broke out, the Duke of Richmond, a supporter of the radical reformist John Cartwright, made another attempt to introduce a bill for a parliamentary reform in the Lords. Th e bill was so radical—it included the removal of property qualifi cations for candidates, universal suff rage for men and payment for members—and so badly timed that it was rejected without any

70 Holmes & Szechi 1993, 249. 71 Derry 1976, 188; Perry 1990, 107; Wilson 1995, 259. democracy in westminster, – 267 noteworthy debate on the issue. Viscount Stormont merely presented Montesquieu’s admiration of the British constitution as a major argu- ment against any change in it (XXI, 686, 688).72 Th e above-mentioned riots quickly cut support for the Association Movement. Th is did not, however, remove the fact that the concept of the people had become contested in a new way, both in and outside Parliament.73 Th e public debate around democracy was quite intense and far from positive aft er the June riots. “Democracy” was becoming a more rel- evant political term in any case, particularly as it was already generally understood as a synonym for popular government. In some defi ni- tions, the concept of the sovereignty of the people was also being con- nected with ‘democracy’ by 1780.74 Even the idea of democracy by representation might occur as a hypothetical possibility, as in Th omas Mortimer’s handbook, according to which in democracy, [. . .] the supreme, legislative and executive power is lodged in the hands of the people; that is to say, in the majority. For where the majority of the people, either by themselves, or those they depute to represent them, have the whole power of the community, and can employ it in making and executing laws; in this case, the form of government is a perfect democracy.75 Mortimer summarized much of the preceding debate, recognizing both the good and bad sides of democracy. According to him, “Democracy, or popular government, at fi rst sight, bids the fairest for the prefer- ence, as approaching the nearest to the state of nature, freed from its inconveniences.”76 Mortimer’s positive and negative sides of democ- racy were similar to those presented by Montesquieu: while demo- cratic societies should be virtuous, they tended to be disturbed by “the slow, irresolute and discortant deliberations and councils of great

72 Dickinson 1977, 220. 73 Wilson 1995, 261; Gould 2000, 174, 176. 74 According to Th omas Sheridan, in democracy “the sovereign power is lodged in the body of the people.” Th e meaning of “democracy” also appears to have been becoming gradually “modernised” in the sense that “democratical” stood for anything related to “popular government” or indeed for anything “popular”. Given this gener- alization of the concept, it is no wonder that opposition parliamentarians would also adopt the term in the following year. Th omas Sheridan, A General Dictionary of the English Language . . . (London 1780); see also William Fry, A New Vocabulary of the most Diffi cult Words in the English Language . . . (London 1784), 66. 75 Th omas Mortimer, Th e Elements of Commerce, Politics and Finances . . . (London 1780), 253. 76 Mortimer, Th e Elements of Commerce, 1780, 257. 268 chapter four assemblies”, to be tumultuous and licentious, and to fi nally degenerate into anarchy.77 A translation of a recent book by Delolme also rein- forced such commonplace prejudices about democracy and presented popular government as the rule of the commons.78 More radical voices were heard in the public discourse in 1780. An anonymous pamphleteer challenged the supreme power of Parlia- ment by pointing out that the members failed to recognize the classi- cal maxim that “the voice of the people is the voice of God”. Struggles for the rights of the people in Britain since the Revolution of 1688 had repeatedly demonstrated that this was indeed the case.79 Th is seemingly conventional claim embodied the radicalization of the old saying for the purposes of the Association Movement. Th e author attacked Black- stone, in particular, for having “carried the notion of a sovereignty in England independent of the people as far as it will bear”.80 Both the notion of parliamentary sovereignty, strengthened by the Wilkes aff air and the American war, and Blackstone’s suggestion that the Commons constituted a democracy, were thus questioned. Th e author further argued that the democratic part of the mixed constitution was under- developed even though the people had never given away their original “right of supremacy”, as described by Locke.81 A reform was needed to put a stop to the corruption of the representatives of the people82 who were, indeed, in Cartwright’s words, “a mock representation of the people”.83 Locke was also the authority for John Joshua Proby, the Earl of Carysfort. He argued that England had originally been “a pure Democracy; that is, all matters of general importance were decided in an assembly of the whole people”.84 Irony was also employed to fur- ther the cause of the people: Th omas Tyers published a fake dialogue

77 Mortimer, Th e Elements of Commerce, 1780, 258–260. 78 Jean Louis Delolme, An Essay on Constitutional Liberty: Wherein the Necessity of Frequent Elections of Parliament is Shewn to be Superseded by the Unity of the Execu- tive Power (London 1780), 13. 79 [Gentleman of the Middle Temple], Th e Out-of-Door Parliament (London 1780), 10–11, 13. 80 Delolme, An Essay, 1780, 24. 81 Delolme, An Essay, 1780, 25–26. 82 Delolme, An Essay, 1780, 68. 83 John Cartwright, Th e People’s Barrier Against Undue Infl uence and Corrup- tion . . . (London 1780), xxi. 84 John Joshua Proby, Earl of Carysfort, Copy of a Letter from . . . Lord Carysfort, to the Huntingdonshire Committee . . . [London 1780], 4–5. democracy in westminster, – 269 in which Walpole defi ned England as “a popular government”,85 thus distorting the ideas expressed by Walpole in 1734. Th e Gordon Riots and opposition gains in the September general election—although there were few victories for the advocates of a par- liamentary reform—scared the executive power to such an extent that references to the people were cut down for the opening of the session in October 1780.86 If the riots were what popular politics produced, appeals to the people were best avoided. Opposition to the war in Par- liament had also decreased aft er the riots and a victory in the Battle of Charlestown in June. Th is may have led to wrong conclusions by the ministers, however: Th e divergence of views between the ministry and the people at large were not removed. Calls for a parliamentary reform were rather increasing.87 In Parliament, the Earl of Abingdon, a Rockinghamite who con- stantly criticized North’s policies and advocated parliamentary reform, was the only lord to protest against the concessionary line of the House. In an eccentric speech, he called for “a new declaration of the rights of the people” now that a combination of the legislative and executive powers was aiming at despotism (XXI, 816). Th ere were few opposi- tion voices in the Commons as well. Richard Fitzpatrick, a Foxite who admired the American struggle for liberty, questioned the royal claim that the elections had conveyed “the sense of the people” as they had not been entirely free (XXI, 823–824). Fox, now an member of par- liament for Westminster, likewise maintained that the elections had not communicated the true “sense of the people” because of ministe- rial manipulation (XXI, 831–832). In just a few months time, a more extensive discussion on the political role of the people would follow in Parliament.

Enter Pitt and Fox: Democracy of the Pure Swedish and Mixed British Types Debated in the Early 1780s

Aft er 1781 the concept of democracy began to feature in British parlia- mentary debates with rising frequency. Th is was not so much a direct adaptation of the idea from America—still an enemy polity which did

85 Th omas Tyers, Political Conferences Between Several Great Men, in the Last and Present Century . . . London, 1780, 72. 86 Christie 1962, 120; Holmes & Szechi 1993, 249; Th omas 2004. 87 Wilson 1995, 259–260. 270 chapter four not use that concept to defi ne itself and the leaders of which explicitly rejected democracy.88 It rather followed from the deepening consti- tutional crisis in the British political community, with the monarchy and ministry being accused of having obtained excessive infl uence at all levels. A reform of parliamentary representation to counter such a development was called for. As John Derry has pointed out, the American crisis did not create radical thought in Britain or determine the ideas of the reformers. Wilkite populism, for instance, had been unconnected with colonial controversies on taxation and representa- tion. Th e calls for reform also arose out of economic and local prob- lems and from various notions about the privileges of Parliament and the principles of representation. Th e American war merely strength- ened the expression of such existing grievances. Th e defeat in the war added to this by demonstrating to many Whigs—quite wrongly—that the monarchical infl uence in the British system was to blame for all the problems.89 Harry Dickinson, by contrast, suggests that the American exam- ple did cause the radicals to call for representation for all tax-paying subjects. Notions of sovereignty were also redefi ned as soon as the Americans adopted the concept ‘the sovereign people’. According to Dickinson, the British radicals borrowed this concept for themselves, moving from an emphasis on inherited rights to one on natural rights, the extreme case being Price’s suggestion that “omnipotence [lies] in the people”.90 Even though the American example was signifi cant to some extent,91 we should consider the role that British authors and

88 Perry 1990, x; Ball 2003, xix. 89 Derry 1976, 188, 201; Cf. extolling interpretations by historians and politicians of the American Revolution as the herald of “government of the people, by the people and for the people” which provided a universal model of representative government. Newman 2006, 73–75. See also Dickinson 1998a, 64. 90 Dickinson 1998b, 19–20; Dickinson 1998a, 90. Dickinson’s interpretation clearly distances itself from contemporary language use here and leads him to character- ise the American Revolution as “a move towards democracy”; Th ere were, of course, those who remained sceptical of American notions of “the Majesty of the People” and the sovereignty of the people. See Th omas Pownall, A Memorial Addresses to the Sov- ereigns of America (London 1783), 85; Even de Mably had doubts as to the lasting of the “rights of sovereignty [. . .] to the people” and appreciated “the narrowest limits to Democracy”. Abbé de Mably, Observations on the Government and Laws of the United States of America . . . [London/Amsterdam] (1784), 93–94; Goodwin 1979, 58. 91 By 1783, Adam Ferguson would write about the Roman people as “sovereigns of the commonwealth”. Adam Ferguson, Th e History of the Progress and Termination of the Roman Republic (London 1783), Vol. 3, 430. democracy in westminster, – 271 debating politicians played in redefi ning the concept of sovereignty in the late phase of the American war. We should likewise note the major contribution they made in giving the concept of democracy new meanings in this period. By 1781 democracy was no longer seen merely as a denomination for a purely theoretical form of government but as a possible direc- tion of future development within the mixed government. Th e basic connotation of “democracy” remained rather pejorative, but the con- cept was used in a way that recognized the possibility of the British system developing (or degenerating) into democracy. Th is can be seen in the debates of 1781, which concerned the regulation of the civil list revenue, the annual budget awarded to the monarch, and was related to Burke’s and Dunning’s attempt in 1780 to introduce an economic reform. Th e proposal aimed at limiting the infl uence of the Crown by cutting the budget, i.e. by using the strongest means in the hands of Parliament to aff ect government policies. Th e measure was aimed at decreasing the infl uence of the ministry by abolishing offi ces distrib- uted as pecuniary perks to government supporters. Th omas de Grey, a government offi cial and Baron Walsingham from 1781, disputed claims that the infl uence of the Crown threatened the liberties of the people. Quite the contrary, any decrease in the power of the King was likely to hurt the national community as a whole (PR, II, 4, 6). Sir John Townshend responded by presenting the bill, which was designed to lessen the burden of the people in a state of national crisis by bringing the sovereign and his people together. He recommended that the members of parliament view the proposal as “representatives of the people”, demonstrating that they had not turned from being “the constitutional guardians of the people” into “their worst enemies”. Th e alternative policy would be “pernicious when they stood between the crown and the people, hiding and encouraging the attacks on the constitution”. Th e Commons should act as a national assembly remov- ing causes for popular licence of the type of the Gordon Riots (PR, II, 7, 9, 11). Th omas Powys, a country member and fi erce debater, also raised the opinion of the people into a justifi cation for the bill (PR, II, 13–14). Aft er this, the debate took on a comparative international dimension when Robert, the Earl of Nugent, referred to Poland and Venice as warning examples of pernicious constitutions in which the power of the monarch had been played down and was subjected to the control of the estates. According to Nugent, it was essential to achieve a balance that “secured the crown in its legal rights, and the people 272 chapter four in their freedom and immunities”, something that the proposed bill could not off er (PR, II, 15). Th e contribution of William Pitt the Younger is of the utmost inter- est. He had entered Parliament only a month earlier, at the age of 21, and had immediately demonstrated excellent qualities as a speaker.92 He had joined the opposition to North and was now supporting the motion to cut the civil list. For Pitt, the Commons were “his Majesty’s public counsellors” who should both support the popularity of the King and respond to the wishes of the people. By accepting the bill, they would exercise their duty “to guard the lives, the liberties, and the properties of the people” and be “the faithful representatives of the people”. Pitt insisted that the Commons should listen to the petitions of the people, particularly when that could be done without decreasing the glory of the Crown; indeed, the measure would support “the com- mon dignity of crown and people” (PR, II, 18–19, 21). In the speeches that followed, the concept of democracy, in the classical sense, played a crucial role only as an element in the mixed constitution. Archibald Macdonald argued: “Democracy was as much to be avoided as monarchy, or as aristocracy” (XXI, 1269). Th is later opponent of parliamentary reform considered that it was “criminal” on the part of the Commons to favour either the Crown or the people and to violate a contract between the monarch and the Commons (PR, II, 25–26). While there was no-one in favour of increasing democracy, the democratic element of the constitution was taken up by the oppo- nents of the reform. Th ey, too, recognized that there was a degree of democracy in the British constitution. Th e relative weight of this element was also becoming an object of serious debate in Parliament, as can be seen in Nathaniel Wraxall’s elaboration of Earl of Nugent’s and Archibald Macdonald’s arguments. Wraxall pointed out further warning examples of the rise of a mistaken type of democracy at the cost of monarchy in ancient and contempo- rary history. For him, the most relevant contemporary instances were the Dutch Republic and Sweden. Wraxall was certainly well informed in this respect as he was a professional travel writer who had visited both countries. As for the proposed reform, he had serious doubts. For him, the British constitution was a better form of government than any other, including all model forms of government that history

92 For background, see Hague 2004, 63–68. democracy in westminster, – 273 could provide. Republics, in particular, were to be avoided. Th e ideal- istic comments of anglophile authors on the Continent, in particular, showed that the British constitution was the best imaginable: He then drew a picture of the constitution of this country, and was warm in its eulogium. He declared it to be more perfect than the constitution of Rome, of Athens, or of Sparta; in short, than that of any republic either of antiquity or of modern Europe; its perfection he said, lay in the nice preponderance between its three branches, in that wonderfully cor- rect equipoise which balanced the power of the three distinct but relative states of King, lords, and commons; nor need there be a greater proof of its excellence and its perfection, than the admiration, the esteem, and the applause with which it had been spoken of by the wisest men of all countries! (PR, II, 27). In 1688, according to Wraxall, “the liberties of the people were accu- rately defi ned”, as the Revolution had brought a remedy from the Dutch Republic in the person of William III. Wraxall recognized the connection between the two ‘free’ peoples, despite the ongoing fourth Anglo-Dutch war, but the English form of government was by defi - nition a better one and the English “a yet freer people” (PR, II, 27). Even William, despite his role as “the guardian of the liberties of the people”, had not given up all of the royal prerogative (PR, II, 27). Th e combination of guaranteed liberties for the people and a suf- fi cient prerogative for the ruler thus constituted the basis of the suc- cess stories of the Dutch and the British. Th e grave weakness of the Swedish regime of the Age of Liberty, by contrast, had been the lack of true kingship; this state of aff airs had led to the degeneration of the people’s liberty and might well do so in Britain as well. Wraxall presented the Swedish case as a demonstration of how excessive power in the hands of the people had led to a total decay of the political community. While the Swedish monarchy had been excessively domi- nant in the seventeenth century, the extremes of the so-called Age of Liberty, when politics had been run by the people, had produced nothing but misery. From the perspective of 1781, Sweden appeared as a warning instance of a popular government of a very bad kind, as a regime that the British should avoid to the very end. Th e picture of Sweden was, without a doubt, distorted for the sake of argument. Wraxall had travelled there in 1774–1775, and the Swedish Gustavian interpretation of the preceding regime may also have had an impact on his views. Sweden was used by him as a counter-argument against the extension of the popular element in the British constitution. Th e 274 chapter four essential message was that the loss of economic, military and foreign political power, the lowering of public morale and the rise in corrup- tion, mutual denigration, ineffi ciency and the economic stagnation typical of Sweden were to be avoided: During all that period, the strong features of Sweden were faction, venal- ity, vilifi cation, and poverty; loss of glory, strength, and respect. Th e navy reduced to seven ships, the people enervated and spiritless, the govern- ment without system or public glory; till at length the nation was sunk into contempt, despised by every other European power, and the Swedes almost annihilated as a people. All these calamities, and all this disgrace had been entailed on Sweden, in consequence of the people, in the year 1718, having, when they felt sore from the oppression and rigour of the reign of Charles the Twelft h, madly precipitated into the opposite extreme, and robbed the crown of all its natural, just, and constitutional infl uence (PR, II, 27–28). Wraxall saw ‘the people’ rather than ‘the Estates’ as the rulers in the Age of Liberty. Th is shows that the language by which the use of power of the Riksdag had been legitimated could be easily used in other coun- tries as well. In 1781, Sweden provided a threatening scenario of the wrong kind of popular rule, even of democracy, though Wraxall did not characterize the Swedish system with that word; he just repeated his warning of “the great danger of popular inroad and democratic violence” (XXI, 1273) in Britain, referring to the Gordon Riots (PR, II, 29). No reform in the direction of democracy where the people had the last say was desirable in Britain. John Courtenay, a later radical who now supported North in order to retain his seat, claimed that the British constitution made it easy for the opposition to overthrow the government by inciting “the ter- rors of the people” (PR, II, 35). Sir Francis Basset (1757–1835), for his part, rejected claims that the petitions presented to Parliament “expressed the sense of the people” by appealing to formalities: the meetings in which the petitions were formulated had been convened at short notice, had been signed “by people who had no right to sign them” and could hence not be considered as binding on the county at large. Self-declared “friends and assertors of the rights and of the liberties of the people” had merely presented unfounded claims (PR, II, 43). Th e “sense of the people” was to be measured in the Commons, the elected organ: From that House, [. . .], the sense of the people could only properly be collected; for was it to be supposed that their constituents would send those there, whom they did not know to be of the same sentiments with democracy in westminster, – 275

themselves? Th e late elections had shewn whom the people look upon to be the real supporters of them and their rights, [. . .] (PR, II, 44). Th e third speaker to make democracy a subject of discussion was Wil- liam Dolben, a moderate Tory representing Oxford University. He argued that all three elements of the British constitution, including democracy, should be reformed simultaneously (PR, II, 46). Th e oppo- nents of the bill, using the concept of democracy in their arguments, were able to postpone the bill. However, the political rights of the peo- ple were soon to be debated again, and in a way that demonstrated a clearer revaluation of the concept of democracy. Th e choice of words in the February debates had probably been aff ected by the activities of the Westminster Association as well. Together with the provincial Associations, it was collecting signatures for petitions for parliamentary reform and better popular representa- tion. Th ese were presented to the Commons and debated there on 8 May 1781,93 when George Savile put forward a motion for dimin- ishing the infl uence of the Crown. Some interesting statements on the political role of the people were made on both sides. Savile had already been infuriated by the Wilkes case and had later campaigned for shorter parliaments in cooperation with Christopher Wyvill. Now he saw it as “a mockery of the people” if the petitions were not taken into consideration. Indeed, “this would be the last petition that would be presented to that House from the people” if it did not have the eff ect it should (PR, III, 216). Th is statement hinted at the possibility of extra-parliamentary action of the kind seen in the Gordon Riots. Henry Duncombe added that the petition “spoke also the general sense of the people without doors” (PR, III, 217). Th e government counter-argument was that the thirty-two signatures of the petition could certainly not communicate “the sentiments of all the people of England,” particularly as individual freeholders were not “the people of England’s representatives” (PR, III, 218). Horace Mann appealed to the principle of parliamentary representation, so that “every scheme for reformation should originate in that House, which contained the only true delegates of the people” (PR, III, 219). A fresh argument was presented by Courtenay, who divided the peo- ple outside Parliament into two categories: those deserving all respect, and to those not worthy of political consideration. He pointed out that

93 Holmes & Szechi 1993, 249. 276 chapter four the government and opposition actually held diff erent ideas of ‘the people’, the government referring to the respectable middle classes, the opposition to the rabble at large (PR, III, 228). For Courtenay, a defender of democracy some ten years later, “the great and respectable body of the people were those of the middle rank”. He even waxed poetical, declaring that these men were [. . .] the true props; they were the stay; they were the sheet anchor of the constitution! In that invaluable body of men resides the true spirit, the virtue, the nerve, the active energy, of Britain! (PR, III, 228). Defending the North ministry in 1781, Courtenay saw the already enfranchised echelons of society as the true people whose voice was to be heard. As for the rest of the people, the opposition was manipu- lating them for their own purposes: [. . .] there existed another class of the people; men composed of the prof- ligate, the idle, and the abandoned, who were ever ready to break out into acts of riot and outrage, and who were easily worked up into fac- tion, or infl amed into sedition, by the popular breath of every turbulent demagogue, [. . .] (PR, III, 229). All of these images were familiar from the Gordon Riots. Courtenay then turned to irony to silence the opposition, mocking the Common Council of London for exaggerating the principle that “all power origi- nated from the people” with their attempts to shorten Parliaments so that they would become “directed by every popular blast, and turn, [. . .] by the breath of the people” (PR, III, 230).94 Amongst the many replies to Courtenay, noteworthy is John Har- rison’s complaint about [. . .] the constant language of one side of the House, [. . .] to represent the petitions of the people in the most contemptuous light, as the voice of an ignorant and deluded multitude, led away by the factious and dis- contented spirit of their superiors (PR, III, 234). Accusations of republicanism were another method used to play down popular petitions. Harrison95 regarded these as expressing a subservi- ent attitude towards the ministry that was totally inappropriate for

94 Courtenay’s speech needs to be contrasted with his changed views during the French Revolution. His opposition to the extension of popular government did not prevent him from being converted into a supporter of democracy later on. 95 No further information on the speaker has been found. democracy in westminster, – 277

“any popular assembly”. It was also dangerous in that the ministry needed “confi dence in the people” in a time of war (PR, III, 235–236). Fox developed Harrison’s argument, condemning belittling attitudes towards petitioners. He reformulated Courtenay’s claim that “in every government of a mixed or popular form, the middle rank of people were [. . .] the true echo of the nation” and rejected it, seeing instead “the sense of the people, or great body of the nation” as “the true cri- terion by which public opinion could be fairly determined” (PR, III, 251–252). Identifying himself with the people, Fox took his election campaign in Westminster as evidence of how “he, or rather the people, triumphed over every obstacle and every combination that was formed against him”. He also extended the concept of the people by defi ning it as “the people properly so called”, not “the middle class, but [. . .] the people at large, coming with all descriptions” (PR, III, 253). Fox’s popularity among the crowds even encouraged him to make use of the threat of new rioting. According to him, “the people [. . .] began to recollect and recover their senses” and might once again run to the streets if the administration did not respect their wishes (PR, III, 256). By February 1781, Fox had really become a man of the people in his political language, defi ning those who endorsed his opposition to North as “the champions of the people and the supporters of the popular cause” (PR, III, 261). Th e administration replied in the words of the Solicitor General, James Mansfi eld, who provided an offi cial defi nition of parliamen- tary sovereignty, suggesting that it was just as unconstitutional for the Commons to deny the right of the people to be represented as for the people to “compel their representatives to act against their judge- ment”. Th e people did have their constitutional rights but even more important were the rights of the Commons, the infl uence of which was ultimately derived from the people: [. . .] the sovereign power of the legislature was to be maintained; that House had its constitutional rights as well as the people, whose repre- sentatives they were, and for whose behoof they acted as trustees; [. . .] (PR, III, 265). From the point of view of the ministry, the petitions subordinated Parliament to the people, which was absurd (PR, III, 269). Likewise any association between sovereignty and the people was missing. Th e opposition lost this case against Crown infl uence, but further debate on the politically active people and democracy was coming. 278 chapter four

Th e Lords’ debates of 1781 reveal further meanings associated with the concept of democracy at a moment when a revaluation of its mean- ing was about to emerge in Parliament. Th e Earl of Abingdon used the word as a synonym for the common people in general and as the opposite of ‘aristocracy’, dividing the people thus into “the little” and “the great” (PR, IV, 300). Th is eccentric nobleman, inclined towards radical politics, probably drew the distinction because the concepts were more current than previously. Within a few years, ‘aristocracy’ and ‘democracy’ would more generally be viewed as opposites rather than complementary elements in an estate society. In 1781, this exten- sion of the meaning of ‘democracy’ may have been a revision intended for the ears of the nobles only. Other lords rather viewed democracy as an element of parliamentary sovereignty. According to William Henry Lyttelton, Baron of West- cote (1776) and Baron Lyttelton (1794), the British mixed government was “composed of three elements, the monarchical, aristocratical, and democratical, which, when knit and united together, formed the sov- ereign power” (PR, III, 521).Westcote also associated ‘the nation’ and ‘sovereignty’ in a new manner in emphasizing the need to maintain “the inalienable and indubitable rights of the sovereign power of the King, the Parliament, and the nation” (PR, III, 523). Th e nation alone was not sovereign, but together with the monarch and Parliament it was. Th e concept of national sovereignty, as we know, would become more generally current only with the French Revolution. In the Commons, at least one Lockean statement on the popular basis of all government emerged during 1781. During the debate on Fox’s motion to conclude peace with America—a logical context for appeals to the political role of the people—Charles Turner, one of the opponents of the war, provocatively argued: Th e King, Ministers, nay the very Parliament itself, were constituted for the benefi t of the people over whom they were placed, not for the aggrandizement of their governors. When, therefore, people talked of power, and of resistance to it, &c. they must mean right, for there was no legal or constitutional power which was not founded in right; nor any right which was not ultimately for the benefi t and advantage of those who by compact, or common consent, created that right in persons of their governors, as sanctioned, explained, or marked out by the essential forms of the constitution (PR, III, 548). In this type of instance, we can recognize the infl uence of American language referring to the rights of the people. Considered together, democracy in westminster, – 279 these instances from the debates of 1781 show that the time for a change in the parliamentary understanding of the concept of the peo- ple, visible to some extent in public debates since the late 1760s, was at hand. A major historical event would bring the change about. It was news of the lost Battle of Yorktown in November 1781 that functioned as the catalyst for conceptual change in the political lan- guage of the British Parliament. Aft er the battle, not even the political establishment believed in a military victory in America any more.96 Th e way in which the ministry defi ned the constitutional relationship between the King and the people changed suddenly in an attempted response to the growing crisis of confi dence. More importantly, the opposition adopted ever more radical language in presenting an alter- native to the policy of the ministry, turning to the concept of democ- racy and revaluating it in a way that made it increasingly relevant for the ongoing constitutional debate. At the opening of the parliamentary session on 29 November 1781, four days aft er the news of the surrender of Cornwallis’ army to the Americans reached London, George III for the fi rst time plainly declared himself to be acting according to “the trust committed to the sovereign of a free people” (XXII, 635). Such a combination of the three concepts (‘sovereign’, ‘free’ and ‘people’) was new in the context of ceremonial speaking. Sovereignty still remained with the King, but the constitutional position of the Commons as the representatives of “a free people” to whom the monarch was ultimately responsible was recognized more clearly than before. Th is attempted redefi nition took place at a time when it had become clear that Britain would have to recognize the independence of the United States, a country which had declared itself to be fi ghting for the cause of the people. North’s obvi- ous strategy in including the formulation in the Royal Speech was to combine the interests of the monarch and the people, as usual, but in a new manner by making the King view himself as a “sovereign” of “a free people”. In such a formulation, the people were no longer presented as the King’s people but as a free people, independent even of the monarchy. A long-term analysis of the corpus suggests that a revision was being attempted here, and a close reading of the following debates shows that this was indeed the case: the same formulation was used

96 Black 2001, 253. 280 chapter four immediately in the debates of the two houses. Th omas Pitt, North’s fi erce opponent, deliberately challenged it. In proposing that the sup- plies for the army be postponed, thus endangering the continuity of the struggle in America, he repeated the defi nition of George III as “the sovereign of a free people” (XXII, 752). Th is phrase had never previously been used in recorded parliamentary debates but appeared now several times within a few days. Th e recognition of the people as free—and thus as a potential political agent—by the North ministry was a response to the lost war in America as well as to long-standing grievances over the neglect of “the sense of the people” by the government. We should not, of course, overestimate the change that the formulation brought about: its introduction and Th omas Pitt’s response did not entail its immedi- ate acceptance. Furthermore, this choice of words may have been no more than a temporary attempt to calm the parliamentary establish- ment at a critical moment when unity was needed but the existence of divisions was undeniable. Nor was the formulation necessarily ‘democratic’ in the sense of weakening the position of the Crown in relation to the people. It is, indeed, comparable to formulations that Gustavus III of Sweden used in his speeches from the throne before and aft er his royal coup in 1772. Gustavus presented himself as a “citizen” and king of “a free people”—not as a “sovereign”, which would have been considered an excessively direct reference to royal power in Sweden. Frederick II of Prussia was also inclined to use this kind of language. In other words, similar rhetorical modifi cations of the monarchy had been made previously and by monarchs who had no intention of limiting their constitutional role but rather out of the need to appease a potentially discontented political elite. Apart from this modifi cation, the rest of the speech by George III was entirely conventional, the King combin- ing “the honour of my crown, and the permanent interest and security of my people” and expressing his trust in “the faculties and resources of my people” (XXII, 835, 837). Th e question that follows is whether North’s modifi cation of the status of the monarchy was suffi cient. Th e Lords responded—aft er a debate, a division and a protest by the opposition against the continu- ation of the war—by acknowledging the monarch’s work for “the real welfare of your people” (XXII, 838). Baron Walsingham, a supporter of North, picked up the phrase “the sovereign of a free people” and democracy in westminster, – 281 extended the trust of the people to include the Lords as well, using it to argue against a premature peace settlement (XXII, 641). Th e Duke of Richmond, the leader of the protestors in the Lords, contested George III’s formulation, demanding that the House should instead “stand up as assertors of the rights of the people”. Unhappy with the views expressed from the throne, he insisted that the real defence of the rights of the people required a new policy on the war and a par- liamentary reform. Only these would restore the original spirit of the constitution (XXII, 650–651). In the Commons, both sides accused each other of abusing the people in a time of war. Charles George Perceval, who proposed the Address of Th anks, insinuated that the supporters of the American cause had misleadingly claimed that they had the people’s backing (XXII, 680). Perceval’s formulation for the Address shows, however, a consciousness of the need to negotiate between the executive and the people as represented by Parliament. Th e Commons fi rst welcomed the royal recognition of the freedom of the people, stating, with the deference befi tting subjects: [. . .] we receive with the strongest emotions of duty and gratitude your Majesty’s gracious and endearing declaration, that you should answer the trust committed to the sovereign of a free people (XXII, 682). Th e commitment of the Commons both as subjects of the King and as representatives of the people was emphasized, and the interests of the two presented as totally united (XXII, 682). At the end of the Address, however, Perceval added a further modifi cation in comparison with the King’s speech. Th e fact that the Address referred to the political role of the people was apparently part of a further attempt by North to promote the cause of continuing the war. Perceval’s suggestion was that popular government supported the national morale and that the current confl ict would be solved “by a vigorous, animated, and united exertion of the resources and faculties of the nation, and of the spirit of a free people” (XXII, 683). With this formulation, North and Perceval were speaking directly to the people, appealing to their national feelings. Th e reactions of the opposition show that the chosen strategy failed to convince some sections of the political establishment. Even so, the ministry was uncompromising in its nationalistic defi nitions of a war- faring political community. It once more reinforced the proposed 282 chapter four redefi nition of the political role of the people by making the King thank the Commons for their spirit and fi rmness as “the representa- tives of a brave and free people” (XXII, 751). Th e American war and domestic discontent were turning the Commons from mere represen- tatives of the King’s people to those of “a brave and free people”, but it is important to notice that this redefi nition was carried out by the representatives of the Crown and under exceptional pressure. Th e dispute that ensued produced further conceptual revisions. Fox, an opposition Whig whose self-confi dence had been strengthened by his popularity among the voters of Westminster, regarded all the state- ments of the ministry as totally inappropriate for the occasion. Accord- ing to him, the ministry had abused its power to dictate the message delivered by the King before “the representatives of the people of Eng- land”. Ignoring references to a free people, Fox, a consistent opponent of the policies on America and a politician with no need to seek royal favour, viewed the speech as one of a despotic monarch unable to rec- ognize his failures or to sympathize with “the sorrows of his people”. To respond to “the general opinion”, the King should have said that he had been misled by his ministers, but, instead, the speech dem- onstrated to “an injured and undone people” what they could expect from their government. It was not the ministry but the opposition that had been presented as “accountable to the people for the measures of government” (XXII, 689–692). Turning to the old argument of the country opposition, Fox complained how the infl uence of the Crown in Parliament enabled the ministry to neglect “the voice of the people”. For Fox, this voice was identical with reason (XXII, 705). Th e ministerial choice of words obviously acted as a catalyst for the radicalization of language referring to the people in the Commons. Burke carried on the opposition onslaught, presenting the defi nition of the King as “the sovereign of a free people” and the promise to preserve the combined rights of the Crown and people as ministe- rial abuse of language designed to justify the continuation of the war (XXII, 719–729). Indeed, for this Rockingham Whig, the speech was “a fresh attempt to impose, to delude, and to draw on the people” (XXII, 722). It demonstrated that the ministry did not really care about “the wishes and the inclinations of the people”, a people that—according to Burke’s provocative counter-defi nition—was “a free, a great, and a suff ering people”. As for appeals to the spirit of the nation, they were useless in that all such spirit had been extinguished by the unfortunate war (XXII, 727). democracy in westminster, – 283

Th e fi erceness of Fox’s and Burke’s reactions shows how delicate the constitutional situation was, and how risky the attempted ministerial redefi nition of the relative roles of the monarchy and the people was. Th e attempt was a serious one, but the speakers failed to convince the protesting Whig opposition. It was, in any case, a deliberate major speech act that made the relationship between the executive power and the people a constant subject of parliamentary discourse and initiated the rise of a new language of democracy. Two more speeches in the debate illustrate the existence of a con- ceptual confrontation that could no longer be hidden. On the gov- ernment side, Richard Rigby interpreted the language referring to the people used by the opposition as unconstitutional, since Parlia- ment remained the only forum for the expression of what the people wanted. Th e alternative that the opposition was off ering had been seen in the Gordon Riots: What! Was not the sense of the nation to be collected in that House? Such applications to the people were unconstitutional, if not illegal; they led to disaster, public tumult, and outrage. He was always against them; [. . .] for the great constituent body of the people, having delegated their voice to their representatives, their representatives only could pronounce it; [. . .] (XXII, 728). Th e parliamentary majority continued to defi ne ‘the people’ in a way that emphasized Parliament as the sole interpreter of “the sense of the people”. Aft er Richard Brinsley Sheridan, another Foxite, challenged the notion of the Commons as representing “all the sense of the coun- try” (XXII, 729), Rigby reconsidered his point, addressing not just his colleagues but also the audience in the Strangers’ Gallery, where a commotion was going on. Aware of the risk of jeopardizing the goals of the ministry by associating all public opinion with the violence of rioters, and attempting to bring calm to the chamber, he recognized the existence of “the sense of the people” outside Parliament as well: [. . .] he would not have it go forth, at a time when there was so full a gallery, that he had spoken contemptuously of the rights of the people; he had objected only to the diffi culty of gathering their sentiments in a peaceable manner (XXII, 729). Th is was a reminder of the links between parliamentary debates and the public sphere. Care also had to be taken on the government side to avoid any unnecessary confrontation with public opinion. No unap- preciative views of the people at large could be expressed. 284 chapter four

Th e opposition’s criticism continued even aft er the Address had been formally approved. According to Th omas Pitt, the inconsistency between the content of the Address and the true opinion of the Com- mons constituted an insult to the people. Th e Commons should have more clearly demonstrated equal loyalty “to the sovereign and people”, even if that meant challenging the ministry (XXII, 732). John Courte- nay responded by urging Parliament and the people to continue with their support in the common struggle. Th is eloquent speaker attempted to raise the spirits of the chamber by describing how “the sacred and applauding voice of the people will sanctify their sovereign’s choice” as far as the conduct of the war was concerned (XXII, 751). Once again the ministerial side endeavoured to silence opposition by elevating the voice of the people into a position that had seldom been heard from that direction before; in other words, by means of formulations that were characteristic of the opposition. However, the voice of the people, as seen by the government, remained identical with the policy of the King’s ministry.97 While the meaning of ‘the people’ had been the topic of the debates of 29 November 1781, the following day brought with it a new intro- duction of the concept of democracy to British parliamentary debates. Th e young William Pitt, a rising member of the opposition, moved for delaying the supplies, thereby using the most powerful weapon that Parliament possessed to challenge the government. Pitt continued the debate on the Royal Speech, considering the Address of the Com- mons, which merely repeated the formulations of the Royal Speech, to be “degrading to the parliament of a free people” in a situation where the ministers had used the speech to “tell the people that they meant to persevere” (XXII, 752). While Addresses echoing the Speech from the Th rone had been the rule, this no longer suffi ced in the eyes of the opposition, who were increasingly confi dent in their application of the concept of the people to criticize the policies of the ministry. In this formulation, Pitt already substituted the phrase ‘the parliament of a free people’ for ‘the sovereign of a free people’, thus indicating what he regarded as the true centre of political power. Th e American war was leading to the increasingly frequent use of the concept of democracy and also to its gradual revaluation. Even if

97 Courtenay became famous for his use of irony in debates, but it is hardly likely that irony was used in this context. democracy in westminster, – 285 neither the American rebels nor their British sympathizers were cam- paigning in favour of an extension of democracy, their emphasis on the popular element in decision-making and calls for a reform in the system of representation promoted the tendency to view democracy in a more positive light. In Pitt’s speech of 30 November 1781, democracy was no longer just an unavoidable theoretical element of the mixed constitution but an element that needed to be actively defended by the opposition. For the fi rst time in the history of recorded parliamentary debates, Pitt challenged the administration by using the concept, sug- gesting that the policies of the ministry were endangering not only the constitution in general but democracy in particular. “Democracy” appeared here in an explicitly positive sense, as a phenomenon to be championed. Pitt argued that the British political system would not be the same without democracy and that the tendency of the administra- tion to undermine both monarchy and democracy by corruption had degraded the credibility of the nation in the eyes of foreign powers: [. . .] our government was no longer what it used to be—a government lodged both in the king and his people: it was now, by means of corrup- tion, vested only in the servants of the crown; and therefore the nature of our government, which formerly derived so much lustre from its democ- racy, being changed, [. . .] (XXII, 753). Th e suggestion that corruption had endangered the constitutional bal- ance was an old one, but the inseparable role which Pitt gave democ- racy in the British system was new in the parliamentary context. Pitt argued that there had indeed been a considerable degree of democ- racy in Britain, a democracy that had been admired both at home and abroad. It was this democracy that was in danger in the crisis of 1781. It was unfounded for the government side to suggest that democ- racy was threatening the balance of the mixed constitution. Rather, democracy was being attacked by the current ministry and needed to be strengthened so that it could once again act as a counterbalance to the Crown. Building on previous suggestions for an economic reform by the opposition, Pitt insisted that nothing should be given “by the people to the crown” until the balance between the elements of the constitution was restored (XXII, 753). Even though calls for an economic reform had been repeated by the opposition every now and then, the association of the demands with the cause of democracy was a new one. Th is redefi nition of the character of the economic reform, and the simultaneous redefi nition 286 chapter four of democracy, came from a young politician who had just recently studied history and classical and Lockean political philosophy at Cam- bridge University. From his father, Chatham, Pitt had inherited an interest in parliamentary reform and perhaps also a readiness to use language referring to the people as a tool in opposition politics. Once he entered the Commons, he brought with him old ideas of reform and the advancement of the popular cause as well as a readiness to use language creatively for political purposes. We should not let Pitt’s later fame as the embodiment of conservatism hide his ability for political revision and innovation, including the introduction of a revaluated concept of democracy into parliamentary debate in 1781.98 In this speech act, Pitt was supported by Fox. According to the lat- ter, he “had undoubtedly hit upon the best means of procuring to the people that change of measures upon which their political salva- tion depended”. Fox developed Pitt’s claim that democracy was being ruined, defending, for the fi rst time, democracy as the popular element of the mixed constitution (XXII, 754). While Fox had been suspicious of excessive popular involvement in the early 1770s, his experiences in campaigning for the Westminster seat had turned him into a spokes- man of the people. Such a seemingly total change of attitude towards the people, and the popularity of this aristocrat among the public, made many contemporaries wonder. Yet Fox seems to have transformed his political language success- fully.99 Aft er Pitt’s initiative, he was ready to use the concept of democ- racy for the same opposition cause, though probably meaning no more by it than that the role of the Commons in the political process should be strengthened in relation to the royal prerogative. In Fox’s words, the Commons constituted the democratic element in a constitution endangered by monarchical innovation: Ministers had basely advised their master to rule by the silent means of intrigue, instead of reigning in the hearts of his people: they had destroyed the democracy of the constitution, and all was now swallowed up in the monarchy: [. . .] (XXII, 754).

98 Cf. Mori’s suggestion that the Younger Pitt had few innovative ideas or projects. Mori 1997, 17, 19, 21; Mori 2000, 5–6. 99 Stanley Ayling has also emphasised the rare occurrences of the concept of the people in Parliament, the Wilkes controversies of 1763 and 1768–1769 having been the only exceptions to the rule thus far. Th e Association Movement obviously moti- vated the increase in the use of the concept, and Fox found it a tool to oppose the King and North’s ministry. Ayling 1991, 75, 79. democracy in westminster, – 287

Fox’s suggestion was that the democratic element of the constitution had already been destroyed, which meant that the essence of the con- stitution had disappeared even if its outer forms seemed untouched (XXII, 754). Th e evident implication of Pitt’s and Fox’s speeches was that democracy was indispensable in Britain, needed to be defended, and was being defended by the Whig opposition. Such a revaluation of ‘democracy’—making the safeguarding of democracy a goal of poli- tics—contributed signifi cantly to the rise of an increasingly positive understanding of the concept in the course of the 1780s. Th e lengthy debates on parliamentary reform in the 1780s were thus preceded by a clearer recognition of the necessity of protecting the democratic element in the mixed constitution. In the 1790s, in diff erent circum- stances, Pitt and Fox disagreed on a number of practical political ques- tions but continued to view ‘democracy’ in the basically positive sense which they had jointly given it from the early 1780s onwards. It is clear that the defence of democracy in the early 1780s arose out of opposition Whig claims that the British monarchy was developing towards tyranny. Members of the opposition willingly used any argu- ment that supported this claim. In this context, they proved them- selves to be just as conceptually innovative as the North ministry when the latter attempted to introduce a conceptual change at the opening of the session of 1781. In a time of acute crisis, a ministerial conceptual modifi cation was countered with a revision by the opposition. How would North, the man responsible for the choice of words in the King’s speech, respond to the challenge by the opposition? He passed over the concept of democracy completely and had little to say about the people. He warned against tampering with the formulation of the Address; such an act would only demonstrate to the country’s enemies that there were divisions between the King and Parliament, which was unthinkable at a time when reasonable terms of peace were being sought. It was likewise nonsensical to appeal to voters in those circumstances to determine “the sense of the people” (XXII, 760). Pitt, the original mover, was given the last speech, which he used to draw a conceptual distinction between “the King” and “the Crown”, exploiting a slip of the tongue by North who had said “the King” when he meant “the Crown”. Th e use of a reference to the sovereign was not only considered inappropriate for the House100 but was also

100 Bentham, An Essay on Political Tactics, 1838−43, 135−136. 288 chapter four seen as revealing North’s excessively close cooperation with George III. According to Pitt, no disunity between Parliament and the King’s person existed, while opposition between Parliament and the Crown as “the executive power of government” was a self-evident part of the constitution. Th is was, indeed, an essential feature of parliamentary government: “[I]t is because these powers are not one, it is because they are disunited, that this government has obtained the admiration and envy of every other nation” (XXII, 761). In Pitt’s notion of the constitution, the Commons had a key political role in that it commu- nicated “the sense of the people” to the knowledge of the rulers and made decisions on behalf of the people on all resources originating from it and being used for its benefi t (XXII, 764). Th is was, of course, still a minority view. Pitt and Fox lost the divi- sion but won the argument—from the aft erwise perspective of an historian—in that they had introduced into parliamentary debates words referring to the people and democracy—and used them in more dynamic senses than ever before. Disagreements on how to conclude the unhappy war in America thus contributed to the radicalization of the British constitutional debate. Approximately two months later, on 23 January 1782, a further con- frontation between Fox and North on the political role of the people took place. Fox initiated the verbal duel by calling for an inquiry into the actions of the Admiralty, using language referring to the people in his challenge to North: [. . .] in every government, there must be a confi dence reposed in the servants of the Crown by the people; or else the business of the state can never be carried on with any degree of success: and though the people should be whimsical and capricious in their dislike of any minister, yet it never could be consonant to sound policy to keep him in offi ce against the opinion and wishes of the people (PR, V, 251). Fox was using the supposedly uniform opinion of the people as a way to legitimate his questioning of the confi dence enjoyed by a leading minister. Th e “free people” was once again the agent, now calling for the dismissal of the minister responsible for the Admiralty (PR, V, 252). North conceded that an inquiry into the management of the Admi- ralty was possible but rejected any suggestion that ‘the people’ was entitled to sack ministers. Such an active appeal to the people would go far beyond the original institution of government by the people: His Lordship answered several of Mr. Fox’s arguments, particularly those on the people’s power of removal of a minister, and the propriety democracy in westminster, – 289

of such a step, without assigning any reason for the measure. Th at was a doctrine, his Lordship said, to which he could not subscribe, and more especially in the extent that the honourable gentleman had carried his idea to (PR, V, 256–257). Prime Minister North thus recognized no power in the people to nom- inate and dismiss ministers. While this particular debate did not proceed further, language refer- ring to the people was increasingly used by both the government and the opposition in the following years, not least because of a mixture of mutually competing coalitions that followed. North resigned in March 1782, but returned to offi ce in April 1783 for the rest of that year, cooperating with his previous critic Fox. Soon most of the competing groups were using language referring to the people to legitimate their claims.

Prospects for a Parliamentary Reform and the People’s Ministry, 1782–1783

North’s resignation led to the nomination of Rockingham and Shel- burne as prime ministers in circumstances where the King considered abdication and the general public rejoiced in a seeming victory when the ministry was made accountable, ultimately to the people. Th e new Rockinghamite ministry was ready to recognize American indepen- dence.101 Th e main disagreements in 1782 concerned the ways to solve the crisis caused by the American war. Grievances concerning the state of the representative system also gave rise to debates in which the con- cepts of the people and democracy made an appearance. Th ese debates were initiated by William Pitt, now the Leader of the House, who on 7 May 1782 moved for examining the possibility of a parliamentary reform. He put forward a motion of a kind never attempted by a government spokesman before without ensuring the support of the fi rst minister. Th e motion made him a leader of the reform movement in the Commons for years to come, but his strategy failed to win a majority.102 It did receive considerable backing in 1782,

101 Holmes & Szechi 1993, 250; Wilson 1995, 267–268; Black 2001, 253. 102 Christie 1962, 145; Perry 1990, 112. 290 chapter four however, and led to related motions being introduced during the fol- lowing years.103 Pitt supported a moderate reform proposed by Christopher Wyvill’s Yorkshire Association rather than the further-reaching one champi- oned by Fox and some London radicals. He was obviously conversant with the radical writings of Richmond and Cartwright, among others, and was closer to their views in 1782 than he was later.104 He would hardly have gone as far as John Joshua Proby, the Earl of Carysfort, however, according to whom the people could “exercise sovereignty [. . .] either in a general assembly of the whole, or by their represen- tatives”.105 Carysfort further argued that popular government had prevailed among all the nations from whom the British derived their origin.106 A more moderate reformer suggested that the people’s or “national Representation” in Parliament [. . .] forms the popular check or balance in the State, and according as it is naturally and with considerable equality preserved, or as it loses its spring from the general mass of the people, becomes the source of every evil.107 Th is anonymous author lamented the loss of “the democratic virtue” or “that distinctive spirit, which characterized the popular infl uence” in the electoral system of the day.108 Many other views on reform were expressed in the public debate of the time.

103 Pitt’s motion was preceded by Wilkes’ successful motion for expunging the reso- lution relating to his expulsion aft er the Middlesex election in 1769 from the Journals of the Commons. Wilkes appealed to the new Rockinghamite ministry as “the friends and favourites of the people” and to “their former upright conduct in the cause of the people”. He defended the bravery of the people in petitioning against abuses in parliamentary elections, presented the Middlesex case as the clearest expression of “the voice of the people” and saw the proposed change as “justice done to a people” (XXII, 1409). Despite Fox’s opposition on the basis of the need to retain parliamentary privilege, Wilkes managed to win the division (XXII, 1410–1411); Wilson 1995, 268. 104 Pitt had met Wyvill at Richmond’s house in April and been asked by the two men to take the initiative in proposing the reform. Christie 1962, 145–146; Cannon 1994, 72; Ehrman & Smith 2004. 105 John Joshua Proby, the Earl of Carysfort, Th oughts on the Constitution, with a View to the Proposed Reform in the Representation of the People, and Duration of Parliaments (London 1783), 29. 106 Proby, Th oughts on the Constitution, 1783, 29. 107 [Anon.], Anglia Rediviva: No Defence of the Aristocratic Party, but the King and People, Mutually Restored to Th eir Constitutional Action . . . (London 1782), 8–9. 108 [Anon.], Anglia Rediviva, 1782, 27. democracy in westminster, – 291

Even if the original idea was not his, Pitt’s role as the initiator of the debate on reform was signifi cant. His proposal built on his experience in opposition to North, debates on the shortcomings of the represen- tative and economic systems, and the favourable circumstances which the forming of the ministry by politicians with a record of speaking in the name of the people had created. Th e people wanted reform: “Th e voice of the people had happily prevailed, and we were now blessed with a ministry, whose wishes went along with those of the people.” Th e nation counted on these “friends of freedom” as it knew that they “respected the voice of the people” (XXII, 1416–1417, 1422). Further- more, Pitt characterized the entire constitution as based on popular participation: in the British government, “the people were entitled to hold so distinguished a share [. . .] by the means of representation”. Th e problem with the system was that the representatives had “ceased, in a great degree, to be connected with the people”, becoming dependent on the monarchy or aristocracy instead (XXII, 1417). Even though democracy was not the concept with which to advocate such an his- toric reform, the message of the motion was unmistakable: democracy had suff ered from the corruption of the representative system, and a restoration of the initial principle of the constitution was needed. It was intended that this should take place through a parliamentary reform reintroducing “a more near relation between the representa- tives and the people” and aiming at an “equal representation of the people” (XXII, 1421). Th e door for constitutional innovation was opened, though excessive conceptual revisions played no role in this proposal. Th ere was no doubt as to the novelty of the proposal. Th omas Pitt, William’s cousin, immediately warned about the disastrous conse- quences of the proposed kind of reform. In his view, the rise of an excessive form of democracy was the danger: Th e reform would “let loose the imaginations of the public” and provoke “the passions of the multitude”. According to Th omas Pitt, the notion of equal representa- tion was unconstitutional, and he rejected the “wild and extravagant ideas” circulating in the public sphere and viewed the idea of univer- sal consent for laws as a product of speculative theorists. In parlia- mentary history he found that the knights had originally constituted “a complete representation of the people”, a function that they still exercised no matter how they were elected (XXII, 1423–1429). His cousin’s reform scheme, by contrast, was destructive of the political 292 chapter four signifi cance of Parliament in that it replaced a proper aristocratic infl uence in the Commons with the infl uence of everybody: Let us take care, that by innovation purely democratical, and which shall remove from us that infl uence to which we owe so much of our impor- tance, we do not reduce ourselves back again to that state, when the great infl uence of all may crush us under its feet (XXII, 1427). Much of this view is explained by the fact that Th omas Pitt had been elected from a borough which he himself owned. He was not, there- fore, necessarily “one of the representatives of the people of England” (XXII, 1436). Not denying his own interest, he maintained that the principle of equal representation had never been applied to any free government. Th e very idea appeared to him to be “the most extrava- gant, the most impracticable, the most visionary and absurd” (XXII, 1425–1426). Extending democracy through representation was not an option for Th omas Pitt. Th e arguments against the bill can be summarized as follows: Archibald Macdonald maintained that all parts of Britain were already represented. Looking at other countries, it was a common case that the numbers of the inhabitants and their representatives did not cor- respond: “[W]itness Holland, where Amsterdam sent no more del- egates than the smallest province, yet no complaint was made of any unfair representation” (XXII, 1429). John Rolle saw a philosophical conspiracy behind the reform scheme, having Enlightenment phi- losophy in mind. In his view, “a set of speculative men” had “stirred the people up to ask for something which they never before thought of ” (XXII, 1431). A third type of counter-argument was presented by Richard Rigby, who maintained that the associations that were cam- paigning for reform provided no proper way of sounding “the sense of the people”. Rather, the Commons should be trusted on this matter (XXII, 1436). Th ere were also forceful arguments in favour of the proposal. Charles Turner argued that the American war had demonstrated how “the House of Commons at present were not the representatives of the people” as they could not hear “the voice of the people” (XXII, 1431). Fox, now the Foreign Secretary, was unhappy with the “virtual representation” and denied correspondence between “the voice of the people” and the votes of the Commons. Aft er a year’s campaigning for a reform, he considered May 1782 the right moment to pass one before “the people would in the end assert their own rights” (XXII, democracy in westminster, – 293

1432–1433).109 Pitt, Fox and the other advocates of the reform received 141 votes as opposed to 161, partly because of absence on the govern- ment side.110 Th is was no triumph for representation or democracy, but an atmosphere enabling a further redefi nition of the concepts had certainly been created as a result of Pitt’s motion.111 Th e rest of 1782 was a time of constant political ferment. Legislation excluding some government offi cials from the Commons and support- ing economic reform was passed, but the sudden death of Rocking- ham led to a split in the administration. Th e public debate saw the appearance of numerous conventional if not downright reactionary contributions. Joseph Cawthorne, for instance, even though he saw government as “created by the people”, left no doubt as to the role of Parliament: “[T]he authority of the People of England is totally absorbed in the Parliament [. . .] the Vox Populi is only to be heard in the Senate.”112 Participation of “the People, or the collective body” in politics as well as “the Majesty of the people” remained out of the question, as the people tended to be “such free-thinkers in politics as well as religion”.113 Francis Basset warned about new applications of the maxim Vox populi, vox Dei which he considered to be likely

109 Steinmetz 1993, 86, sees this as an unrealistic proposition in the fi rst place. Yet Fox carried on the campaign outside Parliament, speaking about the power of the people to control the Crown through the Commons and about its remaining power to censure the actions of the representatives. He also hoped that “the voice of the People” would be heard in further petitions for parliamentary reform. Charles James Fox, Th e Speech of . . . Charles James Fox, at a General Meeting of the Electors of Westminster, Assembled in Westminster-Hall, July 17, 1782 . . . (London) [1782], 12–13. 110 Christie 1962, 147. 111 Reactions against democracy followed, in any case. Only a week later, the con- cept of democracy was used in a highly pejorative sense in the Lords, recalling the danger of the anarchy of the masses. Th e Marquis of Graham proposed that a new kind of militia should be created in Scotland to ensure the safety of the nation. For Graham, the creation of a citizen militia would be a “constitutional” measure that would place “arms in the hands of the middle class of the community, who had little to gain, and much to lose by troubles and commotions”. Th e idea behind this pro- posal was that the middling classes “would be a shield to the constitution against the turbulent grasp of democracy or the encroachments of the Crown” (PRVII, 162–163), that is, they would constitute a balancing force between the monarchy and the popular element, adding to the balancing eff ect of the aristocracy. Only a few Lords supported the proposal, and some opposed it as leading to slavery. Sir C. Turner, PR, VII, 164. 112 Joseph Cawthorne, A Constitutional Defence of Government (London 1782), 7, 9, 18. 113 Cawthorne, A Constitutional Defence, 1782, 19–20, 27; For the meanings of the phrase “freethinkers in politics”, see Ihalainen 1999. 294 chapter four to lead to a devilish mob rule and the loss of all liberties.114 Finally, Josiah Tucker attacked Lockean claims that the people was the foun- tain of power. For him, “a democratic Government is despotic in its very Nature” and indeed a “many headed Monster”.115 Th e approach of the opening of the session in December 1782 off ered the unpopular Shelburne ministry an opportunity to carry on the redefi nition of the political role of the people attempted by North a year before. Th e context for a new attempt was provided by the signing of the far-from-satisfactory peace preliminaries with America. Aft er the debates on parliamentary reform in spring, it also seemed req- uisite to give some recognition to the people in the political process, particularly as the Prime Minister himself was sympathetic to reform. Shelburne’s task was all the more demanding in that the combined opposition of North and Fox was waiting for a chance to undermine any proposed reformulation. In his speech, George III addressed Parliament, without hesitation, as the representatives of his people. He underlined the importance of their opinions and emphasized their duties as subjects and decision- makers on behalf of his people. Th e monarch seemed open to hearing “the sense of my parliament and my people” (XXIII, 205). But then followed a fateful turn in royal rhetoric as the King stated: “I have sacrifi ced every consideration of my own, to the wishes and opinion of my people” (XXIII, 207). To counterbalance this provocative sug- gestion, the monarch recognized the contribution of the people in the war eff ort more clearly than in any previous Speech from the Th rone. Th e King referred to “the entire confi dence which subsists between me and my people”, pointing out that “the signal spirit and bravery of my people” had been demonstrated, and asserted that he would also con- tinue to trust “the spirit of my people” in the future (XXIII, 207–208). A long list of proposals closed with an appeal to the members of par- liament both in the name of the King’s people and the monarch him- self: “My people expect these qualifi cations of you; and I call for them” (XXIII, 210). All in all, in comparison with previous Royal Speeches the content had been largely renewed, and in ways that turned out to be highly controversial. Shelburne obviously misinterpreted the pre-

114 Francis Basset, Baron Basset of Stratton, Th oughts on Equal Representation (Lon- don 1783), 19, 21. 115 Josiah Tucker, Four Letters on Important National Subjects, Addresses to . . . the Earl of Shelburne . . . Th e second edition, (London) [1783], 75, 98. democracy in westminster, – 295 vailing feelings in Parliament and handled the speech in a way that cost him royal confi dence. As the head of the executive power, he was making concessions in response to parliamentary pressure and the change of ministry, but the opposition saw the case diff erently. Th e Lords acknowledged the concessions “to the wishes and opin- ions of your people” and “attention to the true interests of your peo- ple” (XXIII, 220). Only Richmond called for a reform of “a mock of representation”, referring to the Commons (XXIII, 220). In the Com- mons, the response was mixed. Th e Address, draft ed by Philip Yorke, did not acknowledge or elaborate on the concessions regarding the political role of the people; it was simply supportive of the monar- chy. In reality, the members were in strong disagreement about the Royal Speech. Burke considered it one of “hypocrisy, self-commenda- tion, contradiction, and folly”. He saw the suggestion that the views of the monarch and those of the people diff ered as an unconstitutional attempt by the ministry to retain its popularity. Even worse was the demand of obedience at the end of the speech. According to Burke, it questioned the supervisory role of the people over the actions of the administration. Instead of acknowledging the proposed formula- tion, the members should remember “the duty which they owed to the people of England, to declare that they would never submit to be slan- dered or tutored by the King’s ministers”. It was, according to Burke, “from the people of England that they were to receive rebuke as well as counsel” (XXIII, 268, 271–272). Th e Commons should be seen explic- itly as the representatives of the people, functioning independently of the executive power, including the King. Fox shared Burke’s views with regard to the inappropriate content of the Royal Speech. Th e gravest mistake of the government was its tendency to undermine the constitutional role of the people: He saw the minister’s intention: he meant to wound the liberties of the people, by rendering that House odious, thereby to strengthen the power of the crown; a design as alarming as it was insidious, and he had long considered this to be the plan of the present minister (XXIII, 276). Particularly threatening was the attempt to transfer the controlling power over the ministry from Parliament to the Crown and to make the ministry control Parliament instead: [. . .] the command of disinterestedness was a miserable attempt to gain popularity, and was, of all other ideas that could be possibly imag- ined, the most preposterous, and thrown out for the most preposterous 296 chapter four

purpose, to invite the people to fl y to the Treasury and the crown, as an asylum from corruption; thereby meaning to insinuate to the people, that they could and ought to have no confi dence in their representatives, and that they must seek for protection in the crown. Th is was what he termed the most insidious attack that could be formed, [. . .], against the constitution, [. . .] (XXIII, 277). Th e solution to this constitutional crisis lay in the people; they would reject the ministerial trick against the Commons: [. . .] he had a confi dence in the good sense and energy of the people of England, that they would never be brought hastily to entertain suspi- cions of that House; and when they did, that they would not fl y to the crown for deliverance (XXIII, 277–278). Not unlike Burke, Fox presented the people as a political agent that was independent of both the ministry and the Crown and trusted in its representatives in the Commons. As a consequence of attempts to get out of the American war and fi erce rivalry between Whig factions, language referring to the peo- ple was being used in new ways by both the ministry and its oppo- nents. While the Shelburne ministry had interpreted the situation as demanding concessions and expressed this view in language referring to the people, the foremost opposition speakers rejected their attempts, attributing sinister motives to them, as they themselves carried on using and developing the same language. Th e constitutional crisis of 1782 initiated a period of transformation in that the use of language referring to the people became even more frequent and the meaning of the concept of democracy was revaluated. Th e debates of the following years on peace with America, parliamen- tary reform and the organization of the government of the East India Company provided further opportunities for revised uses of these con- cepts. In spring 1783, the Shelburne ministry, which had failed to fi nd support for the peace preliminaries, was replaced, despite royal oppo- sition, by a coalition of William Henry Cavendish Bentinck, the Duke of Portland (a Rockingham Whig), Fox and North.116 During the negotiations for the new ministry in March, the Foxites made abundant use of references to the people. Daniel Parker Coke, a supporter of the Association Movement, conceded that Parliament, in proposing a new ministry, was entering the sphere of the royal

116 Holmes & Szechi 1993, 250. democracy in westminster, – 297 prerogative. However, it was precisely the duty of the Commons to communicate the wishes of the people to the ruler and to fi nd “an administration entitled to the confi dence of the people”: [. . .] it became the duty of Parliament to interfere, and to apply to the Sovereign for redress. It was the public call of the people by its repre- sentative body, and he hoped it would not only meet the compliance of the Sovereign, but that it would have the unanimous concurrence of the House (PR, IX, 513). Charles Howard, the Earl of Surrey (a Foxite), spoke on similar lines concerning the political role of the people. While the King was to be respected as the sovereign, “there was also a high respect due to the people”. Both sides could be served if the Commons underlined “the hearty support, confi dence, and good wishes of his people”. Using the potential unrest of the people as a threat, Surrey suggested that if the Commons did not put pressure on the monarch to form a new ministry, “the people would in a manner still more exceptionable” (PR, IX, 514). Th e picture which Surrey painted recalled the rise of the colo- nists against their mother country a decade earlier and the Association Movement of 1780. Th e established order would no longer be safe if popular assemblies took the initiative instead of the Commons: [. . .] the people would not merely assemble to have a more equal repre- sentation, but would assemble in all parts of the kingdom, and insist on knowing where the blame lay, that no administration could be fi xed on, whose wisdom could relieve their distresses (PR, IX, 539). Th is reference to the Association Movement was evidently part of the strategy of the Foxites to strengthen their position in the forma- tion of the new administration and to advance the cause of parlia- mentary reform. It may also refl ect a genuine fear of the mob, arising from Surrey’s own observations of mob rage during the anti-Catholic Gordon Riots, which had in fact made him, previously a Catholic, con- vert to the Church of England. Th e alternative view was that “the sense of the people” had already been taken into consideration in the plans for a new administration. John Buller referred to the controversial Royal Speech as demonstra- tion of the readiness of the King to renounce his views in order “to comply with the wishes of his people” (PR, IX, 514). James Martin opposed the inclusion of the Foxites in the ministry, maintaining that the people were merely being manipulated in order to obtain their support for it (PR, IX, 515). Macdonald made an anti-democratic 298 chapter four statement, warning of an over-representation of the popular element in the constitution. He considered “the democracy more to be feared than the regal power” (PR, IX, 524, 527–528), “the democracy” refer- ring here to the domination of the Commons. Th e conclusion was that democracy needed to be kept in check by letting the King decide who formed the new ministry. Two more speeches by key debaters demonstrate how the concept of the people was used to argue both for and against the nomination of a particular kind of ministry in 1783. Fox himself carried on his exegesis of the Speech from the Th rone, concentrating to a great extent on the meaning of ‘the people’. Since the speech had suggested that the King knew the sentiments of the people better than their representatives, Fox claimed that the Commons was entitled to address the King in connection with the nomination of the ministry, stating: “Th e people expect an Administration they can confi de in, and to you they call for it.” A change of government was needed because the current advisors were rather acting “in opposition to the wishes of his people and to the sense of his Parliament” (PR, IX, 518, 520). Fox’s defence of the right of his party to be included in the ministry was uncompromising. It had to happen because “the people demanded it, and the kingdom wanted it; therefore it should have [the King’s] concurrence” (PR, IX, 530). Fox’s radical conclusion was that the actions of the monarch should be determined by the will of the people in the nomination of a ministry. William Pitt, who had not accepted the post of the Prime Minister off ered to him in February, was rather more suspicious than the Foxite appeals about what the people wanted. He had doubts as to how “the confi dence of the people” was to be measured impartially: [. . .] who were to be the judges of the particular men who had the confi - dence of the people, and how that matter was to be decided. At present there did not appear any criterion by which such an opinion could be formed (PR, IX, 535–536). Appeals to the opinion of the people were thus being used both to justify and to question the legitimacy of the proposed new ministry. Th e temporary solution to the government crisis took the form of an alliance between Fox and North, something that was widely despised outside Parliament.117 Aft er the cooperation between Pitt and Fox

117 Wilson 1995, 268. democracy in westminster, – 299 ended, rival political groups adopted language referring to the people to justify their diff erent political programmes, which led to the further application of these terms in a variety of debates between the ministry and the opposition. Before that, however, Pitt made use of the exceptional situation in which the self-proclaimed friends of the people had seemed to be dom- inant in the ministry, and introduced a bill for parliamentary reform on 7 May 1783. Th e proposal was a much more moderate one than that of 1782, corresponding with the aims of the Yorkshire Association rather than those of any radical thinkers. Pitt’s speech was received very favourably, but the motion itself failed as a result of the change of power from Shelburne to the Fox-North coalition.118 Pitt seriously miscalculated the support for his bill, although it did result in a debate in which the concept of people was used in highly favourable senses. Pitt’s initial suggestion was that recent developments had caused such deviation from the original constitution that a reform restoring the Commons into “the guardians of the people’s freedom” was indispens- able (XXIII, 828, 830). Unlike some radicals, Pitt did not speak for universal suff rage but for a slightly modifi ed concept of virtual rep- resentation: [. . .] his idea of representation was this, that the members once chosen, and returned to parliament, were, in eff ect, the representatives of the people at large, as well of those who did not vote at all, or who, having voted, gave their votes against them, [. . .] (XIII, 831). Th omas Powys turned out to be again the leading opponent of the motion. Th e moment was wrong, and it remained impossible to know what the people at large really wanted. Furthermore, while “the sense of the people” was to be respected, it had to be rejected when it turned out to be unreasonable (XXIII, 836). Th omas Pitt, too, opposed the motion, maintaining that the people at large wanted no such innova- tion. He regretted the way in which some members were ready “to throw all possible weight into the scale of the people” (XXIII, 842). Th ere was no guarantee of the support of the ministry either. North consistently associated ‘the people’ with Parliament, maintaining that the American war had been “the war of the people”, fought to defend “the just rights of parliament, or in other words, of the people of Great Britain” (XXIII 849). North, coming from a safe pocket borough

118 Christie 1762, 176, 179–180. 300 chapter four owned by his family, found no evidence whatsoever that the people were calling for a reform. Given that so few petitions with so few sig- natures had been received, the “real sense of the mass of the people” was not accessible through such documents (XXIII, 850–852). North’s uncompromising defi nition of the concept of representation excluded constitutional reforms, as all power was, and remained, in the hands of the King-in-Parliament: We are not the deputies, but the representatives of the people. We are not to refer to them before we determine. We stand here as they would stand; to use our own discretion, without seeking any other guidance under heaven (XXIII, 853). Th e representative system was perfect as it stood, and there was no need to make the members into deputies by adding to the amount of popular infl uence in Parliament. Parliament deliberated and decided, and outsiders had no right to intervene in politics. Welbore Ellis, a doctor of civil law and North’s former minister, further proposed an exclusive notion of representation, pointing out: [. . .] representation, as now insisted on, was a word unknown to our ancestors, who never either argued or wrote upon it with any view to the sort of construction that it had now obtained (XXIII, 865). ‘Representation’ could still be seen as an innovation foreign to the orig- inal form of the British constitution. Ellis thus rejected the common argument that representation was the quintessential idea of the British constitution since time immemorial. In addition to Ellis’ knowledge of the law, there is also a more mundane human explanation for his interpretation of representation: Ellis himself had sat in the House for fi ft y-two years without ever having had to contest an election. Th e defenders of Pitt’s bill were suddenly a minority. Fox made an attempt to change the situation by taking the fl oor, despite his position as Foreign Secretary. He spoke openly for the renovation of the con- stitution; the war in America had revealed that the Commons “did not speak the wishes of the people quick enough”. Th ereaft er, fortunately, “the republicanism of the people” had taken over the royal preroga- tive. Even if no universal suff rage was thinkable, Fox spoke in favour of a moderate reform. According to him “the best government [was] where the people had the greatest share in it” (XXIII, 862–864). Th is indicated how far Fox had gone in his adoption of language referring to the people since 1780. He was speaking openly in favour a popular democracy in westminster, – 301 government based on an extended suff rage and dared to pronounce the despised word “republicanism” in the Commons. A rather more analytical speech on parliamentary reform was made by Captain John Luttrell. Luttrell, speaking with the authority of a naval hero, saw a risk of “a most dangerous aristocracy” developing if the representation of counties and boroughs were extended through a partial reform. An elected aristocracy, contending for power with the Crown, was likely to sacrifi ce “the most valuable rights of the people”. A much broader reform was needed if the rights claimed by the people were derived “from the original institution of representation” (XXIII, 865–867). Reviewing Continental writers on the British constitution as well as medieval constitutional sources, Luttrell interpreted them, unlike Ellis, as supporting an extensive reform: [. . .] the people by their proxies constituted an important collateral branch of the government more than 500 years ago, [. . .]; so that it should seem to a complete or perfect representation they were originally entitled, and therefore, if any parliamentary reform was to be made in the plenitude of justice and in the spirit of our constitution, it ought to extend to an equal representation of the whole kingdom (XXIII, 868). Th is was the theoretical case for reform. In practice, however, Luttrell found such a reform “diffi cult, inexpedient, impolitic, and perhaps impracticable”. As a consequence, he considered the established form of representation to be as good as any suggested. Th ough excluding an extensive reform in the end, Luttrell did see a possibility for intro- ducing what he regarded as an entirely new democratic element of Parliament: He said, that with respect to introducing the democratical part of the legislature, whether the change of circumstance in the continual fl ux of human aff airs rendered prudent and necessary, whether from the good intention of establishing a more permanent common interest between the representative and his immediate constituent, or from what other cause it arose, there were various and discordant opinions about, nor was it material to the present purpose; [. . .] (XXIII, 869). Luttrell viewed representation and the existence of a democratic ele- ment in the constitution as positive phenomena. He speculated on the possibility of some kind of combination of representation and democ- racy: the purpose of the democratic element would be to ensure that the representatives shared the interests of their electors. Even so Lut- trell, too, rejected the possibility of a purely democratic reform. He 302 chapter four rather recommended that the Commons curtail the growth of aris- tocracy, as that could endanger both the position of the Crown and the people (XXIII, 870). Th e result of the debate of May 1783 was no reform, either aristocratic or democratic, but the discussion went on; it had already given birth to the speculative idea of a more democratic legislative assembly. Th e conclusion of the American war and the recognition of the independence of the United States in September 1783 removed the last barriers to a free constitutional debate in Britain. Discussion was also provoked by a widespread dissatisfaction with the Fox-North ministry. Th e advocates of reform, in particular, viewed the alliance as mere opportunism,119 and this reaction became a further force motivating the use of language referring to the people. At the opening of Parliament in November, the ministry decided to avoid appeals to the people, despite Fox’s previous rhetoric and fame as a man of the people, and reintroduced traditional formula- tions emphasizing “the strength of the nation” instead (XXIII, 1124– 1125). While no major confrontation between the ministry and the Commons was seen then, Pitt and his allies challenged the ministry on Fox’s India Bill just two weeks later. Th e controversy concerned the organization of the administration of the East India Company, the strongest of all British trading organizations, ruling an entire subcon- tinent. Fox’s position as a spokesman of “the people”, and the equal willingness of the Pittite opposition to use language referring to the people, gave rise to debates in which the concept featured promi- nently. References to ‘popular government’ and ‘democracy’ were also frequent whenever the constitutional role of the people was touched upon, the opposition claiming that the proposed administrative model endangered the sensitive constitutional balance. Fox’s defence of his bill was based on a far-reaching references to popular government and publicity, which provoked further modifi - cations in language by his fellow members in a number of debates. Indeed, Burke used similar formulations in a related debate three years later. Fox argued: “It was the character of despotic governments to be dark; of popular governments to have publicity; and he averred that it was their beauty and basis.” He then proceeded to propose that the commissioners supervising the Company were to be members of par-

119 Christie 1962, 192; Gunn 1983, 85; Corfi eld, Green & Harvey 2001, 160. democracy in westminster, – 303 liament responsible to the Commons. In his model, the people would control a key fi nancial institution, as befi tted a popular government (XXIII, 1277–1278). For some opposition members, these were excessively radical sug- gestions, sounding like democracy and the surrender of sovereignty over India to a few men chosen by the Commons. However, some Rockingham Whigs welcomed the proposal, including the young James Erskine, later the Earl of Rosslyn, who endorsed the view that Parliament should exercise sovereignty over India. In his speech, the phrase “the sovereignty of parliament”, which has been seen as the key doctrine of the British constitution in the eighteenth century, was pronounced for the fi rst time in the surviving parliamentary records (XXIII, 1293, 1295).120 A young man, like Pitt in 1781, was here giving direct expression to an initially judicial notion that had been apparent in political debate for quite some time. Th e bill made its way through the Commons to the Lords, but the majority of the speakers, mostly Pittites, opposed it in both Houses. In the Commons, [George] Hardinge interpreted the bill as increasing royal infl uence at the cost of the people (XXIII, 1259). William Plumer represented the bill as a source of further corruption, endangering “the general privileges of the nation” (XXIII, 1260). For Archibald Mac- donald, likewise, the bill was a trap “for the liberties of the nation” (XXIII, 1298). Th omas Powys insinuated that the scheme was no more than an attempt to make Fox independent of both the monarch and the people because he was no longer such a favourite of the people as previously (XXIII, 1310). As a member of a committee investigating Indian aff airs, and hav- ing participated in the formulation of the East India settlement, Burke had considerable expertise on the subject. Even if he had originally opposed the introduction of British institutions to India, his concern over corruption in the Company made him fear parallel develop- ments in Britain and support the reform suggested by Fox.121 Above all, he did not want any constitutional innovations to be introduced to

120 For the background to this important debate, see Dickinson, 1976, 189–210, and Dickinson 1998a, 65, 81; Keith Perry has simplifi ed the ideological division between the British and the Americans in the mid-eighteenth century by arguing: “As Brit- ish thought and practice moved towards the concept of parliamentary sovereignty colonial ideas were far closer to an idea of the sovereignty of the people.” Perry 1990, 17–19. 121 Langford 2004. 304 chapter four

Britain via India. Th ough he considered neither democracy nor aris- tocracy as an element of government to be undesirable per se, any attempt to increase the power of either of these elements—even in the government of a distant colony—was unacceptable. No reform towards a popular government was needed; neither was there any risk of a growth in the Crown’s infl uence (XXIII, 1376–1377). Th e fate of the democratic element of the constitution if the bill was passed was seen in other ways, too. John Ord opposed the bill because it “gave such a weight to the prerogative, as might in the end overbalance the democratical part of the constitution”. In other words, the democratic element (the Commons) had to be defended “because the moment the balance of the constitution was lost, our lib- erties were extinct” (XXIII, 1394–1395). Ord considered that the bill tended to increase the feared patronage and would only strengthen the position of the ministry. Th is kind of defence of popular government gave ‘democracy’ a more positive sense. Fox responded by accusing the opposition of mischievous attempts to alarm both the Crown and the people over the bill. Trying himself to make the best possible use of language referring to the people, he suggested that, when he had been part of the opposition, the opposition had enjoyed popular sup- port but that this was not the case with the current opposition (XXIII, 1427). Fox was right about all sides becoming alarmed. Both the King and much of the public debate rejected the bill as an extension of ministe- rial patronage, and the Lords was forced to repudiate Fox, which led to the fall of the ministry. Pitt, who had advised the monarch to publish his views, was nominated Prime Minister in a minority government. Th is incident also revealed major diff erences in constitutional con- ceptions.122 Th ere were few defenders of the democratic element of the constitution in the Lords debate, in which the eff ects of the royal intervention could be distinctly heard. Edward, the Baron of Th urlow, Lord Chancellor and the King’s loyal servant, argued instead that the bill tended to destroy the liberties of the people by giving excessive power to Fox (XXIV, 125). Th e Earl of Abingdon, a major critic of the Fox-North administration, wanted to see the Lords assume their role as “the mediator between the king and people” in this issue, holding a balance between the two parts of the constitution (XXIV, 136). As

122 Holmes & Szechi 1993, 250; Dickinson 1989, 2; Black 2001, 254. democracy in westminster, – 305 an opponent of excessive notions of parliamentary authority, he ques- tioned Fox’s credibility as the self-declared “Minister of the People”, suggesting that Fox was merely abusing rhetorical references to the people as an excuse to neglect royal views. Fox was no more than [. . .] the minister [. . .] of a corrupt majority of the House of Commons, where the people now are, as he says; but not the minister of the people, as when mounted on his stages at Covent-garden and Westminster-hall (XXVI, 137).123 Th e increasing common claim of the extra-parliamentary opposition that the majority of the Commons did not actually constitute ‘the peo- ple’, abundantly exploited by Fox previously, was used here against the Foxites. Th e continuity of Fox’s popularity was likewise questioned. If Fox’s attempt was not prevented, he would make himself into “a middle power between the king and people” and destroy both the royal prerogative and the rights and liberties of the people (XXIV, 137–138). Abingdon also misrepresented Burke’s Th oughts on the pres- ent Discontents—published in an entirely diff erent context in 1770—to demonstrate the claim that the ultimate goal of the administration was to establish an aristocracy subverting both the King and the people (XXIV, 139). Th e result was thus a conspiracy theory in which a politi- cal opponent was accused of creating an aristocracy. Th e Duke of Richmond, a member of the anti-Fox alliance and a future minister, likewise found a “dangerous innovation” in the bill. He viewed the bill as an attempt to introduce a false democratic system of government.124 According to this nobleman, who had studied in Holland, the example of the Dutch Republic showed that democracy should not be allowed to interfere with executive power. Th e ongo- ing war with the Republic gave relevance to the reference to suspect Dutch republicanism in this context, particularly as the Patriot move- ment was making progress there. Dutch “democracy” was something that a British nobleman did not want to see either at home or in the colonies (XXIV, 184). Th is statement also puts Richmond’s public calls

123 Polling in the Westminster elections took place in Covent Garden, and Fox made his speeches in Westminster Hall. Corfi eld, Freen & Harvey 2001, 163. 124 Richmond had published his ideas on manhood suff rage and annual parlia- ments—controversial even among the Rockinghamites—in a pamphlet Letter to Colo- nel Sharman earlier that year. Lowe 2004; He does not seem to have spoken so eagerly about the rights of the people once he entered Pitt’s ministry aft er the fall of Fox and North. 306 chapter four for reform based on universal representation, universal suff rage and annual parliaments in perspective:125 “democracy” was not a term that this radical used to defi ne his goals. In the face of a humiliating defeat, Fox further irritated his political opponents by describing himself as “the minister of a great and free people”. Anticipating his dismissal, he promised to quit offi ce before “the voice of the nation” demanded it. “I ever stood, and wish only and always to stand on public ground,” he said and argued further: “Th e people of England have made me what I am; it was at their instance I have been called to a station in their service” (XXIV, 213–214, 220– 221). Fox remained, in his own words, a minister of the people, but his rhetoric had lost its ability to persuade. Nor did his parliamentary majority count once the royal will was against him. At that time, Fox was alone in acting so conspicuously in the name of the people, but his pioneering style was followed by future ministers in their attempts to legitimate their policies.

Further Debates on Parliamentary Reform, 1784–1785

Th e nomination of Pitt as Prime Minister opened a period of over twenty years of fi erce but respectful verbal duelling between the prime minister and Fox, the leading speaker of the opposition in the House of Commons. It created the setting depicted on the front cover of this book in the context of 1793. Th e debating style of the two diff ered in many ways: Pitt counted on the well-ordered presentation of argu- ments, Fox was ready to challenge every detail of his opponents’ argu- ments. Both were spontaneous in presenting ideas, but Pitt was much more circumspect in his statements than Fox.126 From our point of view, it is interesting that the Foxite opposition challenged Pitt’s ministry with language referring to the people from the very beginning. Th is kind of language had, aft er all, been employed by both men ever since 1780. In January 1784, the Foxites moved that a committee be nominated to investigate the state of the nation under Pitt’s minority government. In the ensuing debate, both the minis- try and the opposition legitimated their stances with references to the popular support they enjoyed.

125 Christie 1962, 186. 126 Christie 1982, 181–183. democracy in westminster, – 307

Erskine127 pointed out that all privileges, including monarchical pre- rogatives, were “but trusts for the people”. Th e will of the majority of the Commons had been ignored: “Th e voice of the people’s rep- resentatives in that House had been recently, repeatedly, and loudly lift ed against them” (XXIV, 273). Th is kind of policy had deprived the system of the “vital spirit of popular government”. Erskine was also highly suspicious of the ability of Pitt’s ministry to secure the support of the majority of the people in new elections (XXIV, 275, 282). Sir William Pulteney, an independent politician, maintained that “when- ever it was suspected the House of Commons did not speak language referring to the people, it ought to be dissolved” (XXIV, 289). Th e frustration of the Foxite majority with the prevailing situation led to some quite radical defi nitions of the political role of the people. Henry Dundas, a lawyer, reformulated North’s words, declaring that “the King without the support of his people was nobody; with it he was a great Prince” (XXIV, 514). General Henry Seymour Conway defi ned the Commons, rather optimistically, as the safeguard of the constitutional rights of the people: Th e spirit of the representatives of the people alone seems to ride with the dangers which threaten their privileges. It is now that the House of Commons answers the end of its institution, and proves, not in specula- tion but in practice, the glorious palladium of our rights. Nor is this the fi rst time that the people and constitution of England have found a safe and permanent asylum in the magnanimity and patriotism of the Com- mons (PR, XII, 516). Several appeals to the support of the people enjoyed by the Foxites were needed before Pitt responded. Pitt recognized the principle that ministers were servants of the interests of the people but he made no concessions over the popular legitimacy of the power of his cabinet. No matter what the opposition might claim, the actions of the minis- try were based on the confi dence of the people rather than that of the throne alone (PR, XII, 536). Th e assumption and rhetoric claiming that political power was derived from the people had already reached such a venerable position in British political culture that Pitt’s government needed to resort to it, despite its minority position. Pitt took a risk by

127 Either James or Th omas Erskine may have been in question as both supported Fox. 308 chapter four counting on popular support for him against Fox and North—a risk that paid off . Another attempt against Pitt’s ministry led to a further exchange of opinions on the political role of the people. Pitt found a defender in Cecil Wray, who claimed that the voice of the Commons indeed dif- fered from that of the people. As “the voice of the House of Commons was no longer the voice of the people of England”, the House must be dissolved (PR, XIII, 31). Fox wanted no dissolution but a change of ministry and parliamentary reform. His defi ned the Commons as “the only constitutional asylum of genuine liberty, [. . .] even in this land of liberty”. More particularly, in the Commons, “the people of Eng- land assembled by their delegates and claimed an independence and a weight in the government, which they did in no other kingdom in the world” (PR, XIII, 36). As for Pitt’s ministry, it was acting “against the interest and inclination of the people, whose power in the scale of the constitution was being thus annihilated” (PR, XIII, 44). On 11 February, when the composition of the ministry was once again being debated, the Commons was viewed as the democratic element in the constitution in a manner originally suggested by Blackstone. Pitt himself spoke with considerable reverence about the Commons and the people, recognizing the signifi cance of the views of the people despite his minority position. Th e suggestion was that new elections would reveal the real “sense of the people”: [. . .] he ought to look for the confi dence of his Sovereign, and for the confi dence of that House; he would go farther, he ought to look for the confi dence of the House of Lords and of the people (PR, XIII, 98). Pitt continued by stating that “the confi dence of that House was abso- lutely necessary, and that an Administration could not last that did not possess it” (PR, XIII, 98). Nevertheless, he insisted that it was his duty to serve the King and people until the election irrespective of the opinion of the majority of the Commons (PR, XIII, 99). He knew that the opposition was unable to agree on an alternative coalition, that popular addresses supported the right of the King to nominate him as his minister, and that he would be campaigning in the coming elec- tions with royal funds.128

128 Gunn 1983, 85; Black 2001, 254. democracy in westminster, – 309

Pitt’s remarks caused Pulteney to emphasize the identity of the voice of the Commons and that of the people. Th is opposition man claimed “the House of Commons, or at least a small majority of it, when not supported by the people, to be no formidable body at all” (PR, XIII, 104). Charles Stanhope, later Viscount Mahon, a supporter of Pitt, maintained that it was, in principle, downright “criminal [. . .] to oppose the wishes of the House” but that this was a special case. Stanhope declared that he [. . .] was so great a friend to the democracy of this government, that except for the purpose of saving the constitution, he would not suff er prerogative to stand in the way of the just rights of that House (XXIV, 593). Here “democracy”, used in a positive sense, stood for the Commons. Stanhope, who had participated in local politics during his stay in Geneva, was one of the young guard who entertained new ideas, sup- porting parliamentary reform, and who were capable of expressing them in debates.129 However, in Stanhope’s description, the monarch also had his rights, and any attempt by the Commons to nominate ministers would violate the constitution. Democracy was to stay in its confi ned sphere in the constitution (XXIV, 593–594). Democracy could thus be highly esteemed in rhetorical terms while in fact it was being subordinated to the royal prerogative. In any case, “democracy” was now being used more frequently and in more favourable senses than previously. It was considered an element of the constitution that by the mid-1780s could be referred to by almost any parliamentary speaker, and in most cases, in a neutral or positive sense. On 1 March, when Fox attacked Pitt’s ministry again, the latter replied by looking for a conventional compromise in the defi nition of the British form of government. Th e Prime Minister argued that the British constitution was neither a pure monarchy nor a pure democracy but an ideal combination of these two elements. What is noteworthy is Pitt’s readiness to simplify the description into two elements instead of three. Th e omission of aristocracy increased the relevance of democ- racy, which nevertheless remained strictly limited by monarchy. Th e arguments of the two sides deserve some more attention.

129 Christie 1962, 92. 310 chapter four

Fox started by emphasizing an interconnection between the fates of the constitution, the people of England and the Commons in a situa- tion in which the King favoured a ministry that was not supported by the majority of the representatives of the people. Th e implication was that “the people of England” had not received “such an infl uence in government as the constitution has assigned them” and, consequently, that the Commons should defend the popular cause more vigorously. Th e justifi cation for such a defence was clear: measures had to be taken because “the people were the great source of all power” and the Commons “undoubtedly were competent to protect the rights of the people”. Th e members were “stationed as centinels by the people” and “the friends of the people”, and they were also accountable to the people for their actions. Th e uniform message of the Commons should be: “We wish to increase the weight of the people in the constitu- tion,” that is to strengthen control over the administration, to call for the responsibility of the ministry to the Commons, and to dismiss a ministry which had failed to earn “the confi dence of the representa- tives of the people” (XXIV, 687–688, 690–691, 700). Fox’s position as a frustrated opposition leader confronting a minority government nominated by the King, who despised the Foxites, thus produced a radicalized version of the doctrine of political power originating in the people. In Fox’s words, the parliamentary majority was now defending the cause of the people. William Gerard Hamilton responded to these grave accusations. In a political culture in which the people had generally come to be seen as the source of all legitimate power, Hamilton was forced to deny claims that Pitt’s ministry had failed to respond to “the sense of the nation”. Th e government’s interpretation of the situation was quite the opposite of these claims, and the ministry was seen as staying in power with the support of “the people at large”. Another argument was the right of the King to nominate “his own ministers” indepen- dently of the Commons. Th is system constituted “a limited monarchy and a good king” and was an alternative to “a dangerous democracy or a tyrannical republic” (XXIV, 700–701). Hamilton’s reply shows how democracy could, despite its revaluation in the preceding years, still be viewed as a threatening future prospect. Some of the Pittites were also distancing themselves from calls for an extended power of the people, which is what they took “democracy” to mean, and defending the monarchical element instead. Democracy was thus viewed here not only as a necessary element of the constitution but also as the oppo- democracy in westminster, – 311 site of a limited monarchy. Th e association between “democracy” and “republic” referred simultaneously to the English seventeenth-century republican Commonwealth and to the emerging form of government in America. Democracy was, perhaps, being increasingly regarded as more than a mere element of the mixed constitution—in fact, it began to be seen as an alternative to it. William Wilberforce, Pitt’s close friend who was at that time actively engaged in the Yorkshire Association movement and extra- parliamentary opposition,130 set out to distinguish between popular and parliamentary support for the government. In doing so, he used a strategy which the opposition had previously favoured. It was now indeed the government side that suggested a diff erence between “the interest of the people” and that of the Commons. Pitt’s ministry “had the confi dence of the people, although they wanted the support of that House”, as was demonstrated by the popular addresses pouring into London from various parts of the country. Th rough these addresses, Prime Minister Pitt could turn “implicitly to the voice of the people” and bypass Parliament. As far as the Foxite opposition was concerned, Wilberforce presented it as a mere parliamentary party that was acting against the interests of the people (XXIV, 703–704). Aft er Fox’s and Wilberforce’s speeches, the people were represented as the self-evident source of legitimate power by both the opposition and the ministry. Th e disagreement was over whether the views of the Foxite majority in the Commons and those of the people at large corresponded or not. Pitt had a clear conception of the state of aff airs, and he presented his views by using constitutional terminology. He emphasized his respect for the privileges of Parliament but also saw it as his duty to uphold the royal prerogative. While the Commons had the right to advise the monarch, it was, according to him, unconstitu- tional to demand that the ministers need enjoy the confi dence of the Commons alone. Th e King should remain free to decide on the compo- sition of the ministry independently of the Commons. Like Hamilton, he made the concepts ‘democracy’ and ‘republic’ near synonyms and counter-concepts to limited monarchy. Democracy was now not merely a harmless and potentially benefi cial element of the system, as in his description of it in 1781, but as classical philosophy had taught, an undesirable constitutional alternative in any pure form. Pitt’s rise

130 Christie 1962, 201–202. 312 chapter four to power made him moderate his language referring to democracy and distinguish its mistaken forms more clearly (XXIV, 708–710): Th e constitution of this country is its glory; but in what a nice adjust- ment does its excellence consist! Equally free from the distractions of democracy, and the tyranny of monarchy, its happiness is to be found in its mixture of parts. It was this mixed government which the prudence of our ancestors devised, and which it will be our wisdom inviolably to support. Th ey experienced all the vicissitudes and distractions of a republic. Th ey felt all the vassalage and despotism of a simple monar- chy. Th ey abandoned both, and by blending each together, extracted a system which has been the envy and admiration of the world (XXIV, 710–711). Neither monarchical despotism nor a democratic republic was think- able in the British constitution, which was a product of the historical experiences of both. Th ough Pitt was defi ning the kind of democracy he did not want, his rejection of democracy as being a source of anar- chy was a relatively moderate one in comparison with that of classical philosophy. He did not, for example, openly accuse the opposition of advocating democracy in any pejorative sense. Th e implication was that a degree of democracy was needed as a counterbalance to monar- chy so that an ideal limited monarchy could be achieved. Th e Foxite opposition made yet another attack against the minis- try in connection with Alderman Sawbridge’s motion for a debate on parliamentary reform. Sir Watkin Lewes, a founding member of the Society for Constitutional Information, which advocated a more radi- cal version of reform,131 argued that reform was needed aft er the Com- mons had failed to follow the sentiments of the people as expressed in their petitions (XXIV, 759). Th omas Powys insisted, instead, that the shared interests of the Commons and the people were demonstrated by their latest Address to the King. Th is Address, Powys claimed, con- stituted “a solemn pledge on the part of that House, that it could have no interest but those of the people” (XXIV, 760). Fox did not miss a chance to criticize the Pitt ministry for its contradictory arguments regarding the correspondence between the views of the people and those of the majority of the Commons. Together with the ministry’s apparent unwillingness to advance the cause of reform, these could be

131 Wilson 1995, 260. democracy in westminster, – 313 interpreted as signs that the administration, which had just won an election, was already disdaining the people: [. . .] if they would assert that the present House did not speak the sense of the people, and at the same time refused to assist in forming a bet- ter, it certainly was fair to argue that they did not wish the sense of the people should be collected, or heard in any House of Commons; [. . .] (XXIV, 761). Fox’s suggestion that Pitt was unwilling to countenance a reform was a downright insult to Pitt, who had already proposed reform on two occasions. Th is episode did not take the reform any further, but it demonstrates the high stakes with which language referring to the people was being used by both sides in spring 1784, at a time when a general election was approaching. During the election campaign itself, Pitt received considerable support as the advocate of the cause of the people, thanks to his challenging the Fox-North coalition. Much of his success is also explained by generous fi nancing from the Crown. Whatever the means may have been, Pitt could, aft er the election, more legitimately present himself as a minister who had the support of the people.132 By 19 May, at the opening of a new Parliament, the situation had changed dramatically. Parliament had been dissolved three years before its normal term, and the elections had created a majority for the previously weak Pitt government. In the Speech from the Th rone, the situation in domestic politics was presented as one of complete calm aft er “recurring [. . .] to the sense of my people” in the elections (XXIV, 804).133 Aft er the constitutional confrontations of the preced- ing months, the speech was dominated by eff orts to persuade Parlia- ment to engage in mutual cooperation with the Crown: You will fi nd me always desirous to concur with you in such measures as may be of lasting benefi t to my people: I have no wish but to consult their prosperity, by a constant attention to every object of national con- cern, by a uniform adherence to the true principles of our free constitu- tion, and by supporting and maintaining, in their just balance, the rights and privileges of every branch of the legislature (XXIV, 805).

132 Gunn 1983, 85–86; Wilson 1995, 268. 133 Even the petitioners for parliamentary reform continued in addressing the King to use the form “your people” rather than simply “the people”. Proceedings of the General Meeting of the Freeholders of the County of York, held at the Castle of York, March 25, 1784 (York 1784), 4. 314 chapter four

Th e supporters of the reform obviously took this as a promise by the ministry to take the reform further. Th ey recalled the formulation ten years later, reminding Pitt of the still unfi nished project (XXX, 803). Th e speeches made in the Lords were particularly supportive of the alliance of George III and Pitt, seeing their measures as an appeal “to the voice of the people” (XXIV, 806–807). In such descriptions, of course, “the people” essentially remained the object of royal action, not an independent political agent. In the Commons, as expected, interpretations about whether or not the elections had communicated the wishes of the people were mixed. John James Hamilton (later the Marquis of Abercorn) argued that the elections had carried “the senti- ments of the people” to the throne and proposed an Address in which the King was thanked for his “wisdom and goodness in recurring, at so important a moment, to the sense of your people” (XXIV, 829, 831). Th e Earl of Surrey disputed such claims, doubting whether “the genu- ine sense of the people” had been received in elections in which the people had been involved only nominally and which had not resulted from “the people’s free choice” (XXIV, 832–833). John Hussey, the Baron of Delaval, a convert to Pitt’s side, declared the election an expression of widespread support for the Prime Minister against Fox: Th e right hon. gentleman had been borne into that House through the portal, in the face of open day, on the shoulders of the people. His constituents at Berwick, and the constituents of the whole House, had declared their confi dence in his characters; [. . .] (XXIV, 835). Th e Pittite majority thus eff ectively interpreted the election results as an expression of the will of the people. It was left for the reformists to remind them that the election system by no means guaranteed a bal- anced representation of the people. Sawbridge’s further reform proposal in June, a deliberate attempt to demonstrate that Pitt was incapable of introducing one,134 produced some debate on the nature of democracy as well. Th e motion put Pitt in a diffi cult position in that he was in principle in favour of “an equal representation of the people” but considered it necessary to postpone the bill until the next session (XXIV, 976). Ian Christie has found evi- dence to suggest that Pitt was quite honest in his desire for reform but did not want to be forced to propose bill.135 Fox exploited the

134 Christie 1962, 204. 135 Christie 1962, 205–206. democracy in westminster, – 315 opportunity to put pressure on the ministry, demanding that the new Parliament demonstrate to the people its readiness to respond to “the feelings and wishes of the great body of the people”. He insisted the ministry could no longer disregard the unanimous will of the people (XXIV, 977–979). Th e majority of the Commons still had their doubts about a reform, the usual suggestion being that there was not suffi cient evidence that the people wished to see one. North, in a famous speech, labelled the calls for reform a dangerous democratic innovation. Any change in the current system of representation was, according to him, a risky experiment not deserving the name of “parliamentary reform”. Th ere was no evidence that the people were calling for a reform, and even if there were, the duty of the Commons was to oppose such improper wishes and thereby also demonstrate their independence of the voters. According to North, the members did not represent a particular prov- ince, as in the Dutch States General, but the whole kingdom, and the interests of the kingdom did not require a reform (XXIV, 987–989). North went even further, arguing that the popular element was already so strong that its infl uence exceeded what the ancient constitution had guaranteed to the people. If some original state of representation were restored, it would actually decrease the relative power of the people, North maintained: Good God! Did gentlemen consider what they said when they talked of renovation, and coupled with it the idea of a more pure representation in parliament, with a view to give the people a larger share of power? Th e people had more legislative power now than they ever had. Th e argument held by those who were the most zealous advocates for what was called a reform, was, that they wanted to check the infl uence of the crown and the infl uence of the aristocracy, and to give more infl uence to the democracy. And yet these very gentlemen talked of renovating the constitution, and recurring to fi rst principles. [. . .] In ancient times the people had no share at all in the legislature; [. . .] (XXIV, 990). For North, the idea of reform endangered the unique British consti- tution and, besides, tended to “lessen the power and infl uence of the democracy” contrary to what the reformers seemed to be suggesting (XXIV, 991). North thus turned his reactionary argument into a seem- ing defence of the popular element in the constitution. He did not question the potentially good eff ects of democracy, but neither did he want to see any extension of it. While no-one explicitly advocated the extension of the power and infl uence of democracy in the debate of June 1784, there were 316 chapter four spokesmen for popular power who turned to diff erent terminology to make related points. Beaufoy maintained that the people did wish for a reform, the evidence being found in “the language of the most popular candidates in all the popular elections”. In other words, the contested elections in the London area showed that a parliamentary reform was “that which the people have most at heart.” If the current Commons was as popular as described by North, it was a proper time for reform and the extension of political freedom. By approving a reform, the members would act as proper agents of the people,136 Beaufoy implied. According to him, it was a sacred maxim of the constitution that “the House of Commons shall be appointed by the people”. As this had not been the practice, the system of representation needed to be reformed. A reform would provide an antidote to the increasing power of the Crown and an eff ective defence of “the people’s freedom” as well (XXIV, 993–995, 997). Th e subordinate nature of the representatives in relation to the peo- ple was a repeated grievance among the radical advocates of reform. James Martin, for instance, lamented that the Commons had “for- gotten the relation they bore to the people, of whom they were the creatures” (XXIV, 998). Even Pitt, though opposing ideas of universal representation realized through universal suff rage, recommended a reform as a way to “have the sense of the people correctly spoken in the House of Commons” (XXIV, 999). Th e Prime Minister evidently held to his policy in connection with the reform. In later debates in 1784, the meaning of ‘democracy’ was discussed a few more times. Even though criticism of extended democracy did not cease, the debates on Pitt’s India Bill in July contained an argument defending democracy as the popular element of the constitution. Th is statement did not lead to any broader contestation about the meaning of the concept. Even so, the more frequent use of the term in debates on the constitutional position of the people provided possibilities for a redefi nition of the concept, including the advent of positive connota- tions associated with it. In introducing the bill, Pitt denounced Fox’s bill of 1783 as danger- ous to British liberties and presented his alternative as an opportunity

136 Th e phrase “the agents or representatives of the people” had appeared in Th o- mas Rutherforth’s Institutes of Natural Law . . . Second edition, (Cambridge 1779), Vol. 2, 401. Th e phrase was recalled in the debates of the mid-1790s as well. democracy in westminster, – 317 to “reconcile and secure the interests of the people of this country, of the people of India, and of the British constitution” (XXIV, 1086). He recognized that the Commons and the people tended to become jeal- ous of their interests whenever infl uence was discussed. He also repre- sented himself as the interpreter of the opinion of the people, claiming that the people were on his side and that their attitudes should direct the decision of the Commons as well: [. . .] he trusted that the sense plainly and incontrovertibly declared to be entertained upon the subject by the majority of the people of Eng- land, would prove to be the sense of the majority of that House (XXIV, 1087). Pitt’s way of speaking was unusual for a prime minister: he was attempt- ing to persuade the Commons in the name of the people to approve the piece of legislation he was proposing. Th is implied that, aft er an election victory, the people had become the legitimate authority in decision-making. Pitt also came to defi ne the nature of the responsi- bility of the ministry, albeit in a way that rejected the notion that all power was always derived from the people as represented in the Com- mons. Recalling his argument in an earlier debate, he maintained that government should possess “a suffi cient share of the confi dence of the sovereign, of parliament, and of the people at large” (XXIV, 1092). In a mixed government, these were three distinct political forces which all needed to be taken into account. In the case of the India Bill, this meant that the Commons would not have such a prominent role in controlling the East India Company as Fox had proposed. Power was rather to be placed in the hands of the executives in India. Th e delayed response of the Foxites was given by Philip Francis, an Irish cleric, who had worked in India.137 Francis used the opportunity to attack the ministry for having jeopardized democracy with its pro- posal, thus belying its claims to defend the popular cause, and for fail- ing to respond to charges that it did not enjoy the confi dence of the majority of the people as represented in the Commons. Reviewing the speeches and writings of the Pittites in highly ironical terms, he stated that “the sense of the nation had been unanimously declared, and [. . .] the united voice of the nation could not be resisted”. Furthermore, the Prime Minister presented himself as having “come into power,

137 Cobbett let Francis correct his speeches for publication, which is, of course, no guarantee of their accuracy. Black 2004, 159. 318 chapter four at the front door of the House, and on the shoulders of the people” (XXIV, 1120). Francis attempted to demonstrate that such a picture was a dramatic departure from reality. He took decisions concern- ing the elections in Westminster138 and the clauses of the India Bill, which did not include the principle of trial by jury, as evidence of an anti-democratic tendency in the government. Pitt had, according to Francis, abandoned democracy: Th e very fi rst act of this popular administration, of a minister who came into power on the shoulders of the people, attacked the democracy of the country, and annihilated the fi rst of all the popular powers of the con- stitution. Th e decision of the question upon the Westminster election, [. . .], carried you fi nally and inevitably to this conclusion; that the people of Great Britain might be governed by the laws to which they had not consented, and might be taxed by a House of Commons in which they were not represented. [. . .] Th e second measure of this popular adminis- tration, he insisted, attacked the trial by jury, and threatened to abolish it. Such were the instant operations of that very power which pretended to be derived from the confi dence of the people (XXIV, 1120–1121). Francis’ choice of words was ironical: the ministry did not in reality enjoy the support of the people. Noteworthy is also the extension of the concept of democracy to concern not only free elections with a popular vote but also the realization of the judicial process in the spirit of the common law. Th e area of reference of the concept was evidently broadening. In his answer, Pitt ignored claims concerning the legitimacy of his ministry in the eyes of the people and the constitutional role of the people in general. Endeavouring to reply to irony with irony, he depicted Francis’ speech as no more than a communication of “local information to the House” (XXIV, 1121). Th e Baron of Delaval, who had ostentatiously changed sides from the Foxites to the Pittites, responded, arguing that Pitt’s actions in Parliament were always based on “the real sense of the people” whereas the Foxites were unable to submit themselves “to the sense of the people” (XXIV, 1142). Th e administration remained fi rm and insisted that the majority of the people was on its side, making use of the election result as evidence of Pitt being the people’s minister.

138 Th is was a Pittite attempt to remove Fox from his seat in Westminster. Christie 1962, 214. democracy in westminster, – 319

Francis’ point is noteworthy in that he, as a self-declared defender of the political rights of the people, spoke openly about “the democ- racy of the country” as a self-evident phenomenon and one in need of strong defence. Francis used the concept of democracy in a very positive sense in defending “the popular powers of the constitution”. To be sure, “democracy” continued to stand for the popular element in both the political and judicial branches of the mixed constitution. It was not yet viewed as a name for an alternative, preferable, form of government that should be introduced. For Francis, and probably for the Foxites more generally, democracy meant the right of some subjects to vote in elections for their representatives and to participate in the judicial process through juries. Such a revaluation made democ- racy increasingly an inalienable part of the British constitution in its diff erent dimensions. It also meant that democracy was presented as being in need of active defence. Democracy was not yet any program- matic concept, however: when Francis prepared another speech for the India debates, he chose to not talk about democracy but instead lamented the way in which “the temper and character of the nation” had changed so that neither the Commons nor the people at large were ready to protest against attempts to abolish trial by jury. He appealed to “the sense of the nation” to prevent violations of the rights of the English people (XXIV, 1179, 1181). At the opening of the session in January 1785, Pitt was unwilling to deliver any particular messages to Parliament beyond a passing refer- ence to maintaining “the true principles of the constitution” (XXIV, 1383). However, aft er the controversy of the preceding year, the debate in the Commons was bound to bring up the question of parliamentary reform. Pitt took the initiative as soon as the question was introduced and assured the House that he “was willing to give it all the fair play to which the ardent desire of the people, its own consequence, and his sincere inclination, entitled it”. He is also reported to have rec- ognized the members of parliament as “the delegates of a great and powerful people” in this context (XXIV, 1393–1394). Such a recogni- tion was easy to make now that Pitt had such a large majority in the Commons. Th e above analysis has shown that the parliamentary reform move- ment aft er the lost American war had led to an increasing use of language referring to the people among various groups of the Brit- ish political establishment. Despite the lack of progress in the reform itself, the movement had given general currency to such language. A 320 chapter four fresh chance to express both traditional and new conceptions of the political role of the people was provided by Pitt’s introduction of his fi nal proposal for a reform on 18 April 1785. Th is proposal was cau- tious, intended to anticipate any criticism by not increasing the size of the Commons and by giving new seats to both the counties and London.139 Th e deliberation over the proposal created possibilities for a redefi nition of democracy which showed that the concept was no longer presented merely as a necessary (if problematic) element of the mixed constitution but as a potentially benefi cial and progressive ele- ment. While ‘democracy’ was not completely redefi ned in 1785, some signs of an ongoing conceptual change are visible. Pitt knew what he was talking about, having campaigned for reform as an opposition politician and made two previous proposals on the issue. In spring 1785, the prevailing myth of the excellence of the Brit- ish constitution and the likely opposition to the bill even within the government forced Pitt to present his reform as a moderate proposal, not as an innovation. At the same time, he claimed that it solved all the problems of proportional representation. Th e reform followed no “idea of general and complete representation so as to comprehend every individual”. It was not designed to give every man “his personal share in the legislature of the country”. Instead, Pitt defi ned “the pop- ular branch of our legislature” and “the original principle of represen- tation” in the following way: the Commons was “an assembly freely elected, between whom and the mass of the people there was the clos- est union and most perfect sympathy” (XXV, 433–435). By appealing to the original intentions of the constitution, Pitt wished to avoid any allegations that he was violating its fundamental principles. Pitt’s Parliament was to be based on popular election, but in a way that conserved much of the old system. Pitt justifi ed the reform with the suggestion that the reorganization of the relationship between the people and Parliament would create a stronger political community. British history provided the strongest evidence for this: It was most material that the people should have confi dence in their own branch of the legislature; the force of the constitution, as well as its beauty, depended on that confi dence, and on the union and sympathy which existed between the constituent and representative. Th e source

139 Christie 1962, 213; Mori 1997, 18. democracy in westminster, – 321

of our glory and the muscles of our strength were the pure character of freedom, which our constitution bore. [. . .] If we looked back to our history, we should fi nd that the brightest periods of its glory and triumph were those in which the House of Com- mons had the most complete confi dence in their ministers, and the peo- ple of England the most complete confi dence in the House of Commons. Th e purity of representation was the only true and permanent source of such confi dence (XXV, 449). Th ough he denied innovation, Pitt’s proposal strongly emphasized the connection between the Commons and the people (rather than refer- ring to “the King’s parliament”). Pitt also underlined the responsibility of the ministry to the Commons (rather than their status as the King’s ministers). Th is was now the essence of the freedom of the British constitution. Pitt had ensured a majority in Parliament and no longer needed to justify his position with suggestions that “the sense of the people” and that of the Commons diff ered. Th e historic momentum of Pitt’s proposal did not go unnoticed in the Commons. Henry Duncombe gave the most forthright interpre- tation of the event: “It was a new and interesting object, [. . .] to see the minister of the crown standing forth in this zealous and patriotic manner, the advocate of the people” (XXV, 450). Th ough still formally the King’s minister, Pitt presented himself, and was viewed by the sup- porters of the reform, as “the advocate of the people”. Th e interpreta- tion went unchallenged, which indicates that a major change in the understanding of the basic character of the political community was indeed taking place. Both the Pittites and the Foxites seemed happy with these formulations. Nevertheless, Pitt’s bill was opposed by the great majority of the House. Powys accused Pitt of attempting to change the constitution and emphasized the traditional interpretation of the Commons as being “guided equally by their loyalty to the crown, and their attachment to the interests of the people” (XXV, 453). He was actually repeating an argument made by Pitt himself in spring 1784. For Powys, the Com- mons continued to be a mediator between the monarch and the people rather than the centre of popular power. It listened to the petitions of the people but acted independently of them, while still conveying “the sense of the people” (XXV, 453–454). North, another consistent opponent of the reform scheme, repeated the argument that there was no evidence of the majority of the people wishing for a reform. Th e radicals were merely attempting to provoke such wishes. As “the 322 chapter four people’s rights” were already so well established in Britain, North main- tained, it did not make any diff erence exactly who acted as guardians of that freedom. Moreover, the established system not only protected the people against royal abuses but also “against the consequences of momentary delirium in themselves” (XXV, 458–461). Th e Commons was there to protect the people in every way. Th e most forceful supporter of Pitt’s motion came, unsurprisingly, from the opposition: Fox was strongly in favour of the reform and spoke in a way that redefi ned the concept of democracy as well. Th e language he used was a product of the potential for innovation cre- ated by the Prime Minister’s motion, his belief that the monarchy was threatening the balance of the British constitution, and perhaps his readiness to make use of any unconventional argument in his criticism of the monarch.140 In his response to the proposal, and as a reaction to what Powys and North had said in opposition to it, Fox was ready to defend democracy as an element which—together with the other essential elements of a mixed constitution—was capable of innova- tion (in a positive sense) and progress towards better forms of govern- ment. In his speech, “democracy” represented a dynamic concept. Fox explicitly rejected traditional pejorative understandings of ‘innovation’ and gave expression to an optimistic belief in the abilities of the people to achieve development within a political system created by them. As a consequence, the constitution could, and should, be an object of inno- vation. In this way, Fox was opening possibilities for seeing democracy as a progressive and future-oriented phenomenon and for distancing itself from its strictly classical interpretation, which anticipated an inherent future failure of the system if it came to be dominated by an excessive form of democracy: From the earliest periods of our government, the principle of innova- tion, but which should more properly be called amendment, was neither more nor less than the practice of the constitution. In every species of government [. . .], democracy and aristocracy were always in a state of gradual improvement, when experience came to the aid of theory and speculation. In all these, the voice of the people, when deliberately and generally collected, was invariably sure to succeed. Th ere were moments of periodical impulse and delusion, in which they should not be grati- fi ed; but when the views of a people had been formed and determined on the attainment of any object, they must ultimately succeed (XXIV, 466).

140 See Mitchell 2004. democracy in westminster, – 323

Both democracy and aristocracy were here used in a positive sense and seen as innovative constitutional elements, despite temporary setbacks in the historical process. A belief in progress made Fox trust in the “gradual improvement” of the British combination of various forms of government, and he saw “the voice of the people” as a potentially positive force in the process. Th is is the fi rst found explicit parlia- mentary speech that expressed such superior political potential in the people and spoke of democracy as a future-oriented goal, though still presented within the seemingly orthodox framework of the mixed constitution.141 A further demonstration that Fox was attempting to revaluate the concept of democracy is off ered by William Young’s reply, which was designed to reinforce the conventional meaning of democracy as taught by classical political theory. Young referred to Tacitus in tracing “the abstract theories of the regal, aristocratic, and democratic branches of government” (XXV, 471). For him, and probably for the overwhelm- ing majority of the House, democracy remained part of an abstract political theory that predicted how political systems developed as a consequence of each combination. According to Young, Tacitus had taught that democracy of any type was impossible in “mixed states” and would have been shocked to see the kind of democratic reform that was being planned in Britain in 1785: [. . .] the momentum of the democracy, whether acting by the body of the people, or by a representation unqualifi ed and adapted purely to popu- lar ideas, must quickly bear down one or both of the other branches of government; and it had been moreover told him, that in this pure and direct representation of the numbers of the people were to originate the resources of war and peace, [. . .] the doubts of Tacitus would not have been hypothetical; such a state, he could not have pre-conceived to exist a moment (XXV, 472). For Young, ‘democracy’ remained a dangerous form of government in the classical sense. Whether it be direct democracy with immediate popular participation or democracy functioning through a representa- tive body, the very form of government appeared as a threat to both monarchy and aristocracy. Th is was a major reason for preventing it from gaining true momentum in the fi rst place.

141 Burke was far more reserved in his reaction to the motion. He suspected that the reform was aft er all based on the principle of “universal representation”, and he described it as a mere delusion. XXV, 469–470. 324 chapter four

In referring to two versions of democracy, Young happened to give expression to a notion that came close to the later concept of ‘repre- sentative democracy’. He talked about “democracy [. . .] by a represen- tation [. . .] adapted purely to popular ideas”, the word “representation” referring to the House of Commons. Such an interpretation of ‘democ- racy’ was indeed emerging in the British Parliament—as a refl ection of the contemporary debate in the Netherlands and elsewhere and before the publication of the Federalist Papers in America and the debates of the French Revolution on representation and democracy. Th e idea of democracy working through representation was mostly viewed in a negative light in the British debates of 1785, but the theoretical possibility for such a system had been recognized, and an opposition speaker like Fox could already view both representation and democ- racy in positive and future-oriented terms. Young also pointed out an error which the Prime Minister and his supporters were making in their proposal. Pitt had understood repre- sentation wrongly: [. . .] if he meant a representation of poll or numbers, and so every point of his reform implied, he said, we were not the representation of the people, but of the people’s interests. Th e consistency of that House was qualifi ed by the equipoise of the landed, the commercial, and the popu- lar interest (XXV, 472). Young’s point was that the structure of the Commons refl ected the balanced considerations of the interests of the landowners, commerce and the people at the same time; it was not even intended to refl ect only the will of the populace. It followed that Pitt’s proposed reform would ruin the entire idea of parliamentary representation in its Brit- ish form. Th is is again revealing in that Young actually defi ned the Com- mons as an institution representing the interests of diff erent estates and not the people at large. In his traditionalist world-view, Parlia- ment remained a meeting of estates; it was not a representative body of a united people in a modern sense. It was not an institution to be interpreted through the concept of democracy either, no matter how this was defi ned. Young’s approach may sound old-fashioned, but his stand was the one that prevailed in Westminster in 1785. Th e re-evalu- ation of the content of ‘democracy’ had started, but it did not yet lead to any breakthrough. Nor would the reformers make any progress in the immediate future. Having lost his attempt to reform Parliament democracy in westminster, – 325 in 1785, and moving from youthful enthusiasm to administrative pragmatism and cynicism, Pitt never again initiated another bill of this kind.142 Even so, he continued to hold to much of the concept of democracy as redefi ned during the early 1780s.

Positive Understandings of Democracy before the French Revolution

Th e Speech from the Th rone in January 1786 made no reference to the failed parliamentary reform; indeed, it lacked political content to an unusual degree. Th ere was no longer any specifi c reference to the constitution, probably because the disappointed Prime Minister wanted to avoid all constitutional confrontation. During the debates, Surrey from among the Foxites, an independent nobleman, was the only speaker to openly recall the unsuccessful project for parliamen- tary reform (XV, 1000). Th e concept of democracy, however, remained current in Parlia- ment in 1786. On 7 March, Francis, an old opponent of Pitt, pointed out that the English procedure of impeachment (like the one of War- ren Hastings over his policies in India) was a democratic procedure unlike the arbitrary tribunals of other countries. He argued in terms that widened the sense of ‘democracy’ outside its traditional reference to a popular element in the system. For Francis, democracy was a highly positive term, a synonym for the House of Commons, and also a feature that distinguished England from the rest of the world: Th e trial by impeachment is founded on a popular right, coeval with the House of Commons. [. . .] When the House of Commons impeaches, it is a solemn appeal to the judgement of the world. [. . .] while the democracy of England advances in person to the charge, assumes the noble offi ce of accuser, and forces the crime to trial before every thing that is great, and noble, and wise, and learned, and venerable, in our country. Th e crime, the criminal, the prosecutor, the judges, the audience, and the trial, produce and constitute a scene which no other country can exhibit to the world (PR, XIX, 356–357). Th e representative assembly was seen as “the democracy”, and its actions in the political system were interpreted in very positive terms.

142 Ehrman & Smith 2004; Mori 1997, 17. 326 chapter four

When we come to debates on a proposed amendment to the India Bill in 1786, we meet a use of the concept of democracy in equally positive senses by a somewhat surprising speaker. Th e usage originates from Edmund Burke, who was to become a major critic of democracy in its French form only a few years later—as soon as the Revolution started to inspire new understandings of the concept. Burke’s case sug- gests that, without the Revolution the history of the word “democracy” in its English context would have been diff erent. Burke’s single use of the concept in 1786 should not be over-inter- preted, of course. Burke had previously been critical of extreme forms of the power of the people. He had been far from enthusiastic about proposals to reform Parliament as he had diffi culty in trusting the political integrity and independence of the masses. He had expressed his views repeatedly in parliamentary debates and published writings, arguing that the passive and ignorant people should be skilfully man- aged by the members of parliament. In this sense, Burke never was an uncritical defender of democracy. We can concur with F.P. Lock’s conclusion that Burke believed more in the theory than in the practice of democracy: While he endorsed the theory of political power origi- nating from the people and was convinced that the will of the major- ity should prevail, he remained unwilling to follow popular opinion uncritically.143 In 1786, he expressed admiration for the democratic element of the British mixed constitution to such an extent that he appeared to be a defender of democracy. But what exactly did ‘democ- racy’ mean to Burke during the debates on the India Bill? Did he join Pitt and Fox in making positive comments about the democratic ele- ment? If he did, how can we reconcile such a stand with his criticism of the French Revolution? Burke had lost his position in 1783, when Fox’s India Bill was rejected. In the years between, Burke had been active in preparing the impeachment of Warren Hastings, the Governor-General of India, insinuating that there was a link between Hastings’ actions and secret government infl uence in British elections. Th e impeachment was sup- posed to start in just a couple of weeks’ time, which meant that Burke was using an opportunity to prepare the Commons for the coming charges against Hastings. As he was not confi dent about the success

143 Lock 1998, Vol. 1, 340, 394–395, 422, 462–463, 465. democracy in westminster, – 327 of the charge,144 he used all available conceptual resources to oppose the proposed India Bill. Th ese resources included the use of the con- cept of democracy, which had been considerably revaluated during the preceding years. In speaking positively about democracy, he was referring essentially to the Commons in the Blackstonian sense145 and only through that institution to the people; he was not so much talking about any abstract ideal of how the government should be organized. ‘Democracy’ also off ered a useful tool for opposing Pitt’s government thanks to Pitt’s own defence of democracy in the early 1780s. Burke’s argument was that the new bill aimed at introducing “an arbitrary and despotic government in India”. Th e features of the bill that annoyed him included a form of trial that he saw as violating the Magna Charta and the Bill of Rights; in this respect, the object of Burke’s criticism recalled that of Francis. Th e proposed method of trial seemed to Burke to constitute “a libel on the liberties of the people of England, and a libel on the British constitution”. Despotism was thereby being introduced into the British Empire in disguise. Refer- ring to arbitrary governments of the Turkish type, Burke argued that the planned form of absolute power “was always sure to produce the reverse of energy, vigour, and dispatch”—in other words, results that were symmetrically opposed to what preceding speakers in favour of the bill had claimed (XXV, 1273–1276). Having opposed arbitrary governmental measures against the North American colonies in the 1770s, Burke now interpreted the policy on India in similar terms. In the midst of this anti-despotic oppositional speaking, Burke turned to ‘democracy’ as a way of defi ning exactly what he was defend- ing in the British constitution against Pitt’s proposal for the govern- ment of India. What was needed in India was “a government by law, trial by jury, and publicity in every executive and judicial concern”. Opposing the claims of the preceding speakers that absolute power

144 Langford 2004. 145 Th is synonymity is particularly evident in the formulation “the democracy or House of Commons”, printed in [Presbyterian of the Kirk of Scotland], A Letter to the Right Honourable William Pitt . . . (London) [1790], 33. It is likewise visible in James Green’s defi nition in 1790, which drew a connection between the British constitution and that of Sparta as described by Polybius: “Th e British Government is composed of a due mixture of Monarchy, Aristocracy, and Democracy, vested in their Repre- sentatives, King, Lords, and Commons; to whom the supreme legislative authority belongs.” James Green, An Attempt to Explain the Principles of the British Constitu- tion . . . (Newcastle 1790), 2. 328 chapter four was effi cient, Burke came to view democracy and the power of the many in such highly positive terms that they may appear to repre- sent a turning point in the use of the concept in British parliamentary debates: [. . .] where that arbitrary government existed, of which dignity, energy, and dispatch, were the characteristics. To what had democracy, in all ages and all countries, owed most of its triumphs, but to the openness, the publicity, and the strength of its operation. [. . .] It was in direct opposition to all our theories and knowledge of human nature, to expect from one more than from many; or that the opinion of an individual, in all cases respecting the government and regulation of society, should be more solid than those which result from the joint experience and wisdom of multitudes combined and matured for that purpose (XXV, 1276). Such an argument defending the right of the many to decide as ‘democracy’ or the popular element of the government—as opposed to despotic rule of any kind—was, despite the long tradition of popular government in Britain and the contextual reasons for its use, uncon- ventional. If the reporters got the formulation right, Burke was arguing that ‘democracy’ as the popular element of a mixed constitution could be strong and had ‘triumphed’ in a number of countries in the course of history. Furthermore, as a reply to what had been claimed about a centralized form of government, Burke associated the principles of openness and publicity with the positive infl uence of democracy, this term once again being understood as referring to the actual public at large rather than to some abstract ideology. Francis had used “democracy” as a sympathetic term for the role of the Commons and the people in general in the British constitution just days before. Fox had likewise spoken positively about democracy in the preceding summer. It is hence evident that Burke, too, was using the concept in this positive, even radicalized sense, in comparison with earlier customary references to democracy as one of the elements of the mixed constitution. He was talking about democracy not only as an element in the system, as had been the convention, but as a self-evi- dent attribute of it. Th is hardly yet means that democracy had become much more than a mere synonym for the popular element of the con- stitution, but it does indicate that its potential in the mixed system had been reassessed. Evidence from the debates of the 1790s, the subject of the following chapter, shows that no abstract concept of democracy seen as the opposite of arbitrary government had yet emerged. Th ough democracy in westminster, – 329 having a positive connotation, this was not yet a type of democracy that was totally distinct from the classical concept. We need to keep in mind that the speech of March 1786 was an extreme reaction on Burke’s part, provoked by the proposed consti- tutional reform in Britain and India. Burke made his speech in the context of the approaching trial of Hastings. It was the situation that caused Burke to explicitly declare his sympathy for democracy. He wanted democracy, not despotism. Th e tone of his speeches and writ- ings became quite diff erent once the French revolutionaries started to redefi ne democracy in their own manner, one that Burke regarded as totally despicable. His turn against the French Revolution came as a surprise to many, given his previous stands, the defence of the British type of democracy in 1786 included. Indeed, Burke’s attitudes tended to change as he took a stand on each new circumstance as it arose; they were not necessarily those of a consistent philosopher contemplating political theory independently of the history of events.146 Moreover, Burke occasionally spoke purely in order to strengthen his political authority, to excel in oratory, or to serve a patron; he did not always aim at persuading his audience.147 A further possible explanation is that the formulations were fabricated by a mischievous reporting of his words. Th e last possibility is unlikely, and it would in itself have con- stituted an innovation. Whatever the explanations for Burke’s words in 1786, by 1790 his and the French revolutionaries’ conceptions of democracy were quite diff erent. Th e highjack of ‘democracy’ by the French revolutionaries made Burke adopt a much more reserved atti- tude to the whole concept in the 1790s—a period when he was able to say what he wanted to without needing to win broad support in the House. Th e other members did not engage themselves in the constitutional debate in March 1786. Th is suggests that the meanings which Burke associated with democracy were reasonably conventional ones by that time, in that they provoked no strong opposition. Fox, speak- ing immediately aft er Burke, merely stated that he agreed with every- thing that Burke had said and did not consider it necessary to proceed to any further defence of democracy (XXV, 1280). Th e meanings of

146 Morris 1998, 44. 147 Bullard 2001, xxvii–xxviii. 330 chapter four

‘democracy’ which Burke had introduced hardly diff ered radically from those that Fox attributed to the concept. Th e government side viewed Burke’s claims as the products of pure fantasy. Henry Dundas, Pitt’s close ally who was responsible for Indian aff airs, emphasized that the liberties of the people were guaranteed in the Indian government. He told the House that the fact that the indi- viduals constituting Parliament were themselves part of the people, having been “in a great measure [. . .] elected by the people” accord- ing to the principle of representation, ensured that the liberties of the people would always remain safe (XXV, 1284, 1289). Without saying anything about democracy, the government spokesman rejected des- potism and emphasized the principle of popular representation. We might say that a democratic way of thinking was making an appear- ance here without the word “democracy” actually being used. Dundas further warned about the risk of large bodies, too, being persuaded to take despotic measures. Th is possibility made him recommend the concentration of power in the Indian Governor General (XXV, 1289). Th e logic of the argument may not have been perfect, but Dundas believed that it killed two birds with one stone: it rejected accusations of despotism in the British context and excluded the popular element in the Indian context. A slightly redefi ned concept of democracy was thus put forward by Burke in 1786. Burke spoke just three years before the French began to build a new political system, which he would label “pure democracy”. As a result of the Revolution, the concept of democracy started to take on quite diff erent connotations in Burke’s speeches. Th e history of democracy clearly needs to be interpreted as a transnational phe- nomenon and as a debate in which British thinkers and parliamentary politicians had engaged, extending the meaning of the old concept of democracy as a part of the mixed constitution. On the basis of the above-cited instances, we can argue that a grad- ual progress towards an increasingly positive concept of democracy had started before the French Revolution, in a traditional representa- tive body like the British House of Commons, but that the revolu- tion would cause a reassessment of the concept in Britain, too. French applications of the concept caused disappointed reactions in Britain and led to further re-evaluations of ‘democracy’. On the other hand, the Revolution also reactivated previous defi nitions and forced the British political elite to discuss the principles of their constitution further. democracy in westminster, – 331

At the opening of the parliamentary session of 1787, no-one referred to the political role of the people. In printed literature, only an impris- oned radical French aristocrat suggested that the French monarchy had originally been based on democracy and wrote about “the right of sovereignty, residing solely and inalienably in the people”.148 Th e Brit- ish debate on these matters had come to a standstill aft er the decline of the reform movement and probably also because of the current demo- cratic ferment in the Dutch Republic. By November, the focus was on the Dutch crisis, and the British silence on ‘the people’ continued (XXVI, 1245). A more radical redefi nition of ‘representative democ- racy’ and ‘popular sovereignty’ was taking place in Holland.149 “Democracy” had certainly not yet become a keyword in parlia- mentary debates. While its use remained strictly bound to particular contexts, it usually carried neutral or positive connotations. On 17 March 1788, for instance, the Marquess of Lansdowne (Shelburne), a political commentator and critic of George III with little real infl u- ence at that time, expressed his esteem for the democratic element of the constitution (PR, XXIV, 308). Th e government side favoured traditional ways of understanding democracy as merely the popular element in the constitution, but even among them rhetoric referring to the people had gained new dimensions aft er the parliamentary reform movement. Th e conventional meaning of democracy can be seen in Edward Bearcroft ’s mention of “the democratical part of the constitu- tion” as opposed to “aristocracy” in a debate on Scottish petitions on 17 June 1788 (PR, XXIV, 100). However, doubts about democracy had not disappeared either. Th e last pre-revolutionary series of debates in which democracy and the political role of the people were discussed concerned a constitutional crisis that arose from the inability of George III to take care of his royal duties as a result of illness. Th e state of the King’s health and the possibility of recognizing the Prince of Wales as regent were the top- ics of these debates in December 1788 and January 1789. In pamphlet literature, those speaking for the right of Parliament to decide on the regency were accused of “a democratic innovation”.150 Th e constitution

148 Gabriel-Honoré de Riqeti, comte de Mirabeau, Enquiries concerning lettres de cachet, the consequences of arbitrary imprisonment . . . (London 1787), Vol. 1, 13, 65. 149 See Velema 2007. 150 [Anon.], Th e Crisis, or Refl ections on the Proposed Settlement of the British Gov- ernment (Dublin 1789), 9. 332 chapter four was claimed to be excessively biased “to the Democratic side”, the implication being that Prime Minister Pitt was acting like a “demo- cratic dictator”151 or was planning the creation of “a democratic aris- tocracy”.152 While the opposition claimed that Pitt was an advocate of democracy, the government accused opposition writers of aiming at “a democratic anarchy and plunder”.153 Th is shows that the old prejudices against democracy were still there, to be revived when needed. During the opening debates of December 1788, Pitt appeared as the strongest advocate of the constitutional role of Parliament acting in the name of the people; obviously because this supported his attempts to postpone a decision on the regency issue. Pitt said that he wanted to “guard the liberties of the people from danger” and to ensure that Par- liament, “on the part of the people of England”, whom it represented, settled the issue (PR, XXV, 22, 26–27). Pitt knew that the Prince of Wales was likely to favour the Foxites when choosing his ministers, and hence he wished to delay decisions to create time for George III to recover—a tactic that proved a success.154 Fox was ready to recognize the right of the Prince of Wales to act as regent without any conditions set by the Commons, as he and the Prince were united in their opposition to George III.155 Both sides emphasized the role of Parliament as a popular and national represen- tative body156 but held diff ering views about the right way to proceed. To disprove doubts about his support for the royal cause, Fox, who was ill and unable to give due consideration to the implications of his argument, pointed out that the regency was “a trust, on behalf of the People, for which the Prince is responsible” and that “sovereignty was a trust depending on the natural liberties of mankind” (PR, XXV, 44). Sovereignty belonged to the monarch but was awarded to him by the people.

151 William Knox, Considerations on the Present State of the Nation. Addresses to the . . . Members of the two Houses of Parliament . . . (London 1789), viii, 66; William Knox, Extra Offi cial State Papers (London 1789), Vol. 1, 5. 152 Richard Brinsley Sheridan, A Letter to the Most Insolent Man Alive. Th e fourth edition, (London 1789), 29. 153 [Tartar], Th e Letter to the Most Insolent Man Alive, Answered (London 1789), 28. 154 Christie 1982, 205; Ehrman & Smith 2004. 155 Mitchell 2004. 156 Beaufoy, too, described the Lords and Commons as “the Representatives of the Nation”. PR, XXV, 119. democracy in westminster, – 333

Pitt, stronger in argument, emphasized the necessity of safeguard- ing both “the safety of the Crown, and the interests of the people” (PR, XXV, 48, 50, 55).157 For him, Parliament consisted of “the right- ful representatives of all the estates of the people of England” (PR, XXV, 50–51), while he himself was a spokesman “for the rights of Parliament; and, through Parliament, for the rights of the People” (PR, XXV, 54; also XXVII, 743). Th is was an entirely logical defi nition aft er all his emphasis on the representation of the people in connection with attempts to reform Parliament. His defi nition of the British con- stitution made a degree of democracy—in the sense of listening to the voice of the people—appear as a very positive phenomenon. Britain was not a pure democracy but a popular government based on the representation of the people as ‘estates’:158 If no provision in precedent, in history, or in law, was to be found, for the exercise of such authority, on the disability of the Sovereign, where was it to be found? It was to be found in the voice, in the sense of the People. [. . .] in this more happily tempered form of Government, equally participating in the advantages, and at the same time avoiding the evils of a Democracy, an Oligarchy, or an Aristocracy, [. . .] though the third estate of the Legislature might be defi cient, yet the organs of speech of the People remained entire in the representatives, by the Houses of Lords and Commons, through which the sense of the People might be taken. Th e Lords and the Commons represented the whole estates of the People, and with them it rested as a right, a constitutional and legal right, to provide for the defi ciency of the third branch of the Legislature, whenever a defi ciency arose; they were the legal organs of speech for the People; and such he conceived to be the true doctrine of the Constitu- tion (PR, XXV, 56). Democracy alone might have bad attributes, but the British system avoided them by combining the three necessary elements of govern- ment. Parliament was an organ for the expression of the voice and

157 Beaufoy made the same point by talking about Parliament as “trustees for the Sovereign as well as for the People”. PR, XXV, 119; Christie 1982, 206. 158 Identical formulations can be found in An Impartial report . . . published imme- diately aft er the debate in 1789, 89. Even Lord North, though disagreeing on the right way to proceed, recognised Parliament in nearly identical terms as “the true and lawful representatives of all the estates of the people.” XXVII, 749; Th e defi nition of Parlia- ment as “lawfully, fully, and freely representing all the estates of the people of this realm” was communicated to the Lords on 23 December and was echoed there by the Earl of Camden on 26 December. PR, XXVI, 37, 47; Pitt’s statement was again recalled on 29 January 1789 by Grey Cooper. PR, XXV, 304; Pitt himself made a nearly identi- cal statement a little later. PR, XXV, 339. 334 chapter four sense of the people, indeed “the organs of the people’s speech”. Pitt’s repeated argument was that the people should decide about fi lling the throne through Parliament (XXVII, 742). In practice, this meant spending so much time in deliberation that the King would recover. Pitt won also the argument in the public sphere as a result of Fox’s inconsistencies.159 Edmund Bastard160 referred to “the will of the people, expressed by the House of Peers and the representatives of the people in parliament assembled” as the origin of all royal power (XXVII, 749). Th is formulation emphasized—for the very fi rst time in the analysed parliamentary debates on constitutional issues—“the will of the people” as the ultimate mover of political life. Th is was a stronger expression for popular sovereignty than the conventional references to “the sense” or “the voice” of the people. Fox used vocabulary that was nearly identical to Pitt’s, despite the opposite goals of the two men. He referred to variation in the British constitution: just as absolute tyranny and aristocracy had sometimes dominated, “sometimes the democracy prevailed, and all the oppres- sions of a democratical government were practised in the fullest enor- mity” (PR, XXV, 72). In Fox’s interpretation of national history, there had been lamentable periods of pure democracy such as the Civil Wars. Th is kind of pure democracy appeared as far less progressive than Fox’s concept of democracy during the debates on parliamen- tary reform (PR, XXV, 72). An unprejudiced positive understanding of democracy remained diffi cult to maintain consistently in the late 1780s. Fox seems to have used radical arguments when they suited him and to have returned to traditionalist ones when needed to advance particular political ends. Th e contemporaries were perplexed by such inconsistencies, which partly followed from his absence because of ill- ness and his unrealistic belief in the possibility of successfully oppos- ing George III by allying himself with his son.161 Th e revaluation of democracy had been far from total: even par- liamentarians who had at one time spoken in favour of democracy were not uncritical advocates of the power of the people. Burke, for instance, advised his colleagues not to make the people believe that

159 Christie 1982, 206. 160 Alternatively, the speaker may have been John P. Bastard. Both were new rep- resentatives and supporters of Pitt. Edmund is known to have voted with Pitt in this case. 161 Mitchell 2004. democracy in westminster, – 335 they as a collective possessed all political power; instead, he declared himself ready to “speak against the wishes of the People, whenever they attempted to ruin themselves”. Parliamentary wisdom and power bypassed that of the people where the delegation of executive power was concerned. Only if the fundamental rights of the people were to be violated by the monarch, did “all right and power [revert] to the people”, Burke recalled, with an obvious reference to the Glorious Revolution of 1688 (PR, XXV, 125, 129). Th is suggests that Burke’s democracy had remained one that was constituted by a representative institution. While the example of the Dutch rising may have infl u- enced Burke to reintroduce old senses of democracy, there were other explanations. Burke was sceptical of the motives of popular politics in large constituencies. He was likewise cynical about how the people had rejected an independent Commons in favour of the Crown. In 1788, he supported the Foxite line in the regency crisis,162 which explains his anti-populist statements in that context. Th e common denominator for Burke and Pitt was that both now defi ned Parliament “as the representatives of the nation” (XXVII, 846; PR, XXV, 148). Th is choice of words, though implying no major turn in prevailing conceptions, illustrates a Europe-wide tendency to emphasize the political centrality of ‘the nation’ and to treat it as syn- onymous with ‘the people’ in a political sense. Th e state of British dis- course was not that diff erent from that of France, where preparations for the meeting of the States General were being made. Th e concept of ‘national representation’, forcefully articulated by Emmanuel-Joseph Sieyès in France, was emerging, and its appearance was not limited to the pre-revolutionary French debate: it also appeared in the British Parliament. In Britain, “the people” remained the usual term used in defi nitions of the political community, but by 1789 it was being treated as almost synonymous with “the nation”. In the Lords, Lansdowne made a connection between “a govern- ment known to be approved by the unanimous and genuine voice of the people, through their representatives” and “the general sense of the whole nation” (XXVII, 879–880). Th is independent peer and Pitt’s former mentor even maintained that “the People have rights, but Kings and Princes have none.” He also referred to foreign peoples with oppressive regimes:

162 Langford 2004. 336 chapter four

[. . .] it might be not only discussed but decided, that the eyes of all man- kind might be opened to the important fact which must result from the discussion and decision, that the People had most essential rights of their own, but that Kings and Princes had no rights whatever (PR, XXVI, 62, 64–65). Such a statement had become possible as a result of the gradually radi- calizing discourse on the political role of the people and bitter dissat- isfaction with George III in some opposition circles. During the debates in mid-January 1789, the political role of the people in the British system was generally recognized, but the debat- ers disagreed about how the will of the people should be determined. In the opposition, Powys criticized Pitt’s suggestions as an insult to the Crown, the power of which was “derived from the same source, from which that House derived its power. It was an integral part of the power of the People” (PR, XXV, 196–197).163 William Wyndham Grenville, the Speaker of the House, stated that all power or author- ity that had not been delegated by law “still resides with the People at large”. Th e Speaker urged the Commons to do its best to maintain the allegiance of the masses of the people to the King and Parliament (PR, XXV, 218, 233, 236).164 By 1789, the popular origin of power could be appealed to by anyone if it supported his argument. Th is shows how far the principle of political power being derived from the people had been established in British parliamentary language. Views about how the will of the people should be determined varied a lot, of course. Th e Solicitor General, John Scott, summarized the expressed views in these ironical terms, obviously directed at Fox: How was the sense of the people of England to be collected on the sub- ject? Perhaps, if a right hon. Gentleman were asked, he might adopt his fi rst opinion, and say “the sense of the people was spoken by their representatives in that House;” or he might take up his second opinion, and say, “the sense of the people can only be known from the people of England at large;” or he might go back again to his old doctrine, and say, “the sense of the people of England can only be collected in the House of Commons” (XXVII, 1024). Whatever the proper way of ascertaining “the sense of the people” might be, it had become diffi cult to legitimate any decisions without

163 Th omas 2004. 164 In addition to the fi rst-rank speakers, Joseph Mawbey stated that all power was originally derived from the people. PR, XXV, 301. democracy in westminster, – 337 reference to the sense (if not the will) of the people. Archibald Mac- donald, the Attorney General, therefore addressed the Commons in February 1789 as “the representatives of the People, the true source of power” (PR, XXV, 344). A shared conception of the popular origin of political power, though not yet called ‘the sovereignty of the people’, had obviously been radicalized in the Westminster Parliament in the course of the debates of the 1780s. Indeed, it lacked little in compari- son with the initial ideals of the French Revolution, which explains the positive reception of the Revolution in Britain in its early stages. But did it diff er from those of the American alternative?

Th e Rise of a Representative Republic in America: no Comment from Westminster

Th e formulation of the American Constitution in the late 1780s became a major moment in the history of the political role of the people. As Margaret Canovan puts it, the American Revolution had meant that the initially Roman ideas of ‘the sovereign people’, ‘popular govern- ment’ and the political role of the common people were once again connected and turned into an “enduring myth of the sovereign people in action”. In this way, the people could be viewed simultaneously as “an abstract authority in reserve” that was absent and as “a concrete power in action” that was present. Th is was realized in a popular rep- resentative government in which all the elements of the constitution were seen as the ‘agents’ of the people, while the people remained the sovereign power that was needed only in special circumstances. In Canovan’s words, “popular sovereignty” was “institutionalised” by the American Constitution.165 Despite its being a major event in world history, references to the new American state in contemporary British parliamentary debates remained few. Th e lack of explicit commentary on the new republic is understandable given the recently lost war and the fact that the Amer- ican Constitution was still in the making. Its infl uences were more indirect as can be seen from the fact that discussions about the exten- sion of franchise in Britain arose only aft er similar debates in the colo- nies.166 In public debates, on the other hand, the American example

165 Canovan 2005, 27–28, 91, 107. 166 Brewer 1976, 209, 214; Dickinson 1977, 217. 338 chapter four was rather more visible. Interest certainly existed among the radicals, language was no barrier, and some key American constitutional texts were also reprinted in London. As we have seen, the concept of democracy had begun to have increasing signifi cance in British parliamentary discourse in the era of the American Revolution. Th e American rebels, however, still built their political arguments on foundations provided by the classical tra- dition, viewing their emerging new political systems through analogies with ancient Rome. As Bernard Crick puts it, their revolution made it possible to see the precedents of Roman republicanism—perhaps even Athenian democracy—in new terms, no longer as threatening exam- ples but rather as experiences opening visions for organizing politics in the same way as in the past, or perhaps in some better way.167 In America, the War of Independence did not bring about any dra- matic change in prevailing understandings of “democracy”; the word did not yet belong to the programmatic vocabulary of the revolution- aries. Even Th omas Paine continued to argue in the early phase of the American crisis that the British constitution was likely to “degener- ate into democracy; a government which, [. . .], I hope to prove ineli- gible”.168 Paine saw democracy as “fl attering to the pride of mankind” and hence easy for demagogues to “hold up” to people even if they knew that it would never function in practice. Citing Rousseau, Paine pointed out that “there never existed, nor ever will exist a real democ- racy in the world”.169 For the American revolutionaries, ‘representa- tion’ remained the key concept.170 Th e most crucial period of constitutional debate in America did not take place until 1787–1788, preceding the outbreak of the French Revo- lution by no more than a year. Th e concept of the people played a cen- tral role in this debate, while statements about ‘democracy’ continued to be full of prejudices and reservations. Th e most signifi cant result of the debates as far as the rhetoric of popular power is concerned would be the opening of the American Constitution with the words “We, the people of the United States”, which outspokenly placed the high-

167 Crick 2002, 3, 5. 168 Th omas Paine, Common sense; addressed to the inhabitants of America . . . [Lon- don] (1776), 2. 169 Paine, Common Sense, 1776, 5. 170 Paine, Common Sense, 1776, 38. democracy in westminster, – 339 est political authority in the hands of the people.171 In the American Republic, the people prevailed, at least in theory. ‘Democracy’, however, was not re-evaluated in positive terms in the same way. Indeed, much American political theory in the late 1780s was anti-democratic despite the fact that it has been seen as embody- ing the rise of popular sovereignty.172 Th e key texts of the American constitutional debate were printed in Th e Federalist, authored mainly by James Madison and published by Alexander Hamilton. Th ese two architects of the new constitution distinguished sharply between the republic they were designing and direct democracy, something that they consistently rejected. Th e Federalist characterized “a pure democracy” as “a society, consisting of a small number of citizens, who assemble and administer the government in person”. It was an arrangement that “can admit of no cure for the mischiefs of faction”.173 Madison argued: [. . .] such democracies have ever been spectacles of turbulence and con- tention; have ever been found incompatible with personal security, or the rights of property; and have in general been as short in their lives, as they have been in their deaths.174 Democracy remained merely an object of speculation for “theoretic politicians” entertaining mistaken ideas of equality.175 Madison saw the emergent United States instead as a strong representative republic, thus combining the notions of representation and republic. Th e Amer- ican political system would by defi nition diff er from “pure democracy” because of the delegation of government, the larger size of the state, and the avoidance of faction. In a republic, the “representatives and agents” of the people took care of the administration, not the people themselves.176 Modern interpreters suggest that Madison’s outspoken conceptual distinction between democracy on the one hand and popular govern- ment and republic on the other, and the denouncement of the failures of democracies as the mistakes of republics, were conscious speech

171 Plan of the New Constitution for the United States of America, Agreed upon in a Convention of the States . . . (London 1787), 6; Markoff 1999, 666, 673. 172 Among attempts to explain this, see Miller 1991, 105–106. 173 Th e Federalist, Vol. 1, no. 10, 57–58; Hansen, 30. 174 Th e Federalist, Vol. 1, no. 10, 58. 175 Th e Federalist, Vol. 1, no. 10, 58. 176 Th e Federalist, Vol. 1, no. 10, 58, 60; Vol. 1, no. 14, 80. 340 chapter four acts aimed at vindicating the republican form of government.177 It may also have refl ected an entirely logical, even unconscious, way of thinking within the context of a long tradition of seeing democracy as based on direct citizen participation in decision-making, realizable only in small communities. In the Anglophone debate, it had not been the rule to associate republics and democracies; it was rather in the French Enlightenment debate that these concepts had been sometimes combined. Madison followed mainstream in eighteenth-century British politi- cal thought and was highly sceptical about democracy, in which “a multitude of people exercise in person the legislative functions” and were because of their lacking qualifi cations subject to manipulation. He continued to view democracy as a society with only a small num- ber of members who governed themselves in person and oft en suff ered from factions and individuals who were ready to sacrifi ce the interests of the others. Madison believed, like most thinkers for over two thou- sand years before him, that democracies tended to lead to constant confl icts, to violate the rights of individuals and to last only for short periods of time. He just could not conceive of a democracy of perfect equality.178 Nevertheless, interestingly, he found (quite anachronisti- cally) some instances of representation of the people even “in the most pure democracies of Greece”.179 Th e leaders of the American republic thus ruled out democracy, even if they were willing to view the United States as a “popular gov- ernment”.180 “Th e people in their collective capacity” were expressly excluded from government in the American system. In the American “popular or representative constitution”, the institutional solution for governance diff ered from that of direct democracies: the representa- tives of the citizens would govern instead of the people themselves.181 Th e American Constitution meant the victory of the concepts ‘repub- lic’ and ‘representation’, but it did not yet produce any concept of representative democracy.

177 Th e Federalist, Vol. 1, no. 14, 80–81; Dahl 1998, 16–17; Miller 1991, 107–109, 119; Much of the “confusion” and “contradictions” discussed in scholarship may actu- ally arise from a lack of respect for the eighteenth-century history of concepts. 178 Th e Federalist, Vol. 2, no. 61, 103; Dunn 2005, 77, 80. 179 Th e Federalist, Vol. 2, no. 63, 196–197. 180 Th e Federalist, Vol. 2, no. 39, 21. 181 Th e Federalist, Vol. 1, no. 21, 128; Vol. 2, no. 63, 197; Dunn 2005, 77–79. democracy in westminster, – 341

Sovereignty, too, resided in America with the states rather than the people. John Adams wrote, however, that already among the ancient Germans “the democratical branch” had been “so determined, that the real sovereignty resided in the body of the people”.182 Th is was a pos- sibility, but it was not the express choice of most American theorists.183 According to Jonathan Jackson, the greatest risk for the states was [. . .] their proneness to an highly democratical government; a govern- ment in which they would be directed by no rule but their own will and caprice, or the interested wishes of a very few persons, who aff ect to speak the sentiments of the people.184 Th ere were individual writers at that time like William Vans Mur- ray, however, who defended “American Democracies” irrespective of whether they were based on direct or representative government.185 Despite the prevailing strong doubts about democracy, the admiring way in which the American republicans talked about the principle of all power originating from the people certainly supported the arguments of the British parliamentary reformers. In the rhetoric of Th e Feder- alist, “the people of America” were to decide about the constitution and hand over some of their power to the government. Th e planned system would “rest on the solid basis of the consent of the people” so that “the whole power of the proposed government is to be in the hands of the representatives of the people”, all of their power being “derived from the people” or “from the great body of the people”. Th e representatives remained “agents and trustees of the people”, that is, servants of the people. Th e ultimate authority would reside “in the peo- ple alone” as “the people are the only legitimate fountain of power”.186 As a popular republican government of this type, the Americans regarded theirs as unique. In the Dutch Republic, for instance, “no

182 John Adams, A Defence of the Constitutions of Government of the United States of America (Philadelphia) [1787], xv–xvi. 183 Cf. Wood 2006, 621–623, on debates on popular sovereignty and the rise of the notion that all magistrates were agents of the people. James Wilson, among others, argued that all political power was borrowed from the people. 184 Jonathan Jackson, Th oughts upon the Political Situation of the United States of America . . . (Worcester, Massachusetts) [1788], 55. 185 William Vans Murray, Political Sketches, Inscribed to his Excellency John Adams . . . (London 1787), 62–63. 186 Th e Federalist, Vol. 1, no. 2, 6; no. 22, 143; no. 28, 175; Vol. 2, no. 37, 4; no. 39, 21–22; no. 46, 84; no. 68, 108; no. 78, 293–294; For further evidence of the prominence of the language of the people in Revolutionary America, see Miller 1991, 118. 342 chapter four particle of the supreme authority is derived from the people”. Britain did not deserve the name of republic at all.187 In Britain, in fact, some members of parliament would soon start to view themselves as no more than agents of the people, probably moti- vated by the American model of popular government. For quite some time, the notion of the people rather than Parliament as the ultimate source of power had been gaining strength. Th e reform movement, in particular, used arguments referring to the power of the people with increasing frequency.188 Th e British political establishment would soon receive another model to comment on: the French Revolution, which has customar- ily been regarded as the time when modern notions of popular sov- ereignty, national representation and representative democracy were born. As we have seen, however, a related debate had been going on in the British Parliament for some time. In the last chapter, we shall focus on how the British members of parliament and commentators in printed literature received the French Revolution and its redefi ni- tions of the common classical tradition of the power of the people and democracy. To what extent did they totally refute them, redefi ne their own concepts in response, or actually adopt revolutionary ideas in their parliamentary discourse?

187 Th e Federalist, Vol. 2, no. 39, 20–21. 188 Goldsworthy 1999, 215–216. CHAPTER FIVE

REACTIONS TO THE REVOLUTIONARY CONCEPTS OF DEMOCRACY AND POPULAR SOVEREIGNTY IN WESTMINSTER, 17891800

Th e French Revolution—as a “paradigm shift ” to more modern notions of nationhood and sovereignty and as the starting point of numerous ideological confrontations—also aff ected the history of the concept of democracy in many ways.1 John Dunn, a leading scholar of the history of democracy in the Anglophone world, emphasizes the unexpected rise of the concept of democracy during the French Revo- lution. Building on older research, Dunn argues that the popularity of the word “democracy” emerged only in the course of the Revolution. Th e rising new concept was not based on any idea of the restoration of an age of democracy in ancient Greece. Rather it took on an entirely new, future-oriented content, referring to what democracy was able to accomplish.2 Viewed in the context of the previously analysed British parliamentary debates of the 1780s, however, the rise of democracy in a positive and future-oriented sense in the early 1790s was not quite as unprecedented and unexpected as Dunn suggests. Th e concept obvi- ously has a pre-revolutionary history in the debate on the relative roles of the diff erent elements in a mixed government. Th is has previously escaped the attention of many scholars, particularly in works where the focus has been on leading theorists rather than on debating politi- cians or on the structures rather than linguistic content of politics. In the francophone academic world, Pierre Rosanvallon has likewise argued that democracy retained its classical connotations of the direct exercise of legislative and executive power—and consequent political instability—until the days of the French Revolution. Th e survival of this classical sense of the concept was also a major reason for its not being adopted by the revolutionaries in 1789.3 Rosanvallon is certainly

1 Hampson 1983, 3; Cranston 1988, 97; Baker 1990, 252; Livesey 2001, 2, 10; Powell 2002, 19; Hampsher-Monk 2005, 1–2; cf. Monnier 2005, 42. 2 Dunn 2005, 39. 3 Rosanvallon 1995, 143. 344 chapter five right in that no fundamental redefi nition of democracy had taken place before the French Revolution. Even so, the re-evaluation of the democratic element by British parliamentary speakers in the course of the 1780s described in the previous chapter deserves attention, as do related redefi nitions in French Enlightenment literature and the Dutch Patriot debate on representative democracy. Th e evolving British con- cept remained relevant in the 1790s and was then contrasted with the French revolutionary alternative, as a result of which it was modifi ed and thus further ‘modernized’. Dunn and Rosanvallon agree in that as soon as the word “democ- racy” was adopted more widely aft er 1791, like much of the revolu- tionary vocabulary, it began to be increasingly applied in new senses with connotations of the future possibilities that it opened up. Th e French revolutionary concept of democracy thus initiated a debate for and against a prospective democratic system. Th is meant that democ- racy was no longer just one of the three classical theoretical forms of government or one of the elements of a mixed constitution but was turning into a concept that could be used to describe and defi ne the political community and its goals more widely. Even if it is evident that this rise of a future-oriented conception of democracy as an ideal form of government was connected with the French Revolution, we would benefi t from a longer-term perspective that includes earlier attempts to re-evaluate and redefi ne democracy within traditional representative institutions. Th is means that we interpret conceptual change as a gradual process involving mutual debate between various political thinkers and actors rather than as a sudden and unexpected change introduced by innovative ideologists. While there were not yet really any revolutionary redefi nitions in Swe- den at the turn of the 1760s and 1770s, the rise of language referring to the people in Britain aft er the late 1760s and particularly in the 1770s, together with the American War of Independence, led to the fi rst distinct revaluations of democracy as part of the mixed constitu- tion of Britain in the early 1780s. Th ese revaluations turned democracy into an inalienable characteristic of the political system to be actively defended and developed to answer future expectations. Th is was not yet a conceptual revolution of the French kind; it was rather a concep- tual transformation taking place through transnational public discus- sion and parliamentary debates related to practical decision-making. Th e long-term signifi cance of such conceptual revisions should not be overshadowed by the more dramatic revolutionary conceptual change the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 345 and the related transformation of political culture in France in the early 1790s. In France, Enlightenment political philosophy had produced texts that slightly redefi ned the concepts of the people and democracy and led to the emergence of the explicit phrase “the sovereignty of the people”. Montesquieu rejected democracy, with the people as the pos- sessors of sovereign power, as incapable of securing liberty. Rousseau regarded democracy as inconsistent with human nature and as a sys- tem that had never really existed, although he recognized the original sovereignty of the people. Jaucourt, for his part, viewed democracy as an “admirable government” in the Encyclopédie.4 Even in spring 1789, however, most of the French intellectual elite continued to denounce democracy aft er suggestions for equal suff rage in the States General were made. At the time of the outbreak of the Revolution, democracy was still generally associated in France with the power of the people as a whole and with a theoretical form of government that produced nothing but anarchy, especially in a country the size of France.5 Th e public debate which preceded the convocation of the French States General on 1 May 1789 included Emmanuel-Joseph Sieyès’ famous pamphlets. Sieyès, a clergyman, argued in favour of the equal- ity of the citizens, inalienable national sovereignty and a representative government, but the language of democracy played no particular role in his thinking. Like in the Federalist papers in America, representative rather than participatory government was the ideal to be followed. Sie- yès actually recycled conventional notions of democracy as the direct rule of the people, which led him to consistently denounce it as a sys- tem. In his conception of representative government, “representatives are not democrats; [. . .] since real democracy is impossible amongst such a large population”. Sieyès did recognize the need for a demo- cratic spirit in the States General, but such a view was easy to recon- cile with the classical tradition of mixed government. In accordance with classical political thought, he argued that only in small political communities could the demos come together and actually make laws. France was not such a country, and hence the people simply could not constitute an effi cient political agent there. A much more effi cient solution for securing liberty was provided by a representative system

4 See Maier 1972, 841; Dippel 1986, 61–64; Monnier 1999, 50–52. 5 Rosanvallon 1996, 143. 346 chapter five with a limited group of qualifi ed elected citizens who were special- ized in governing. Such a system, in which the people elected depu- ties, could not be called democratic.6 Much of this argumentation is actually consonant with the established ways of viewing representation in the British Parliament. Th ere were two diff erences, however: the association between the nation and sovereignty was stronger in Sieyès’ description, and a further-reaching re-evaluation of democracy had already taken place in Westminster. “Democracy” was hence not initially a word typically used in con- nection with the French Revolution. Whenever it occurred in 1789, it was used in a conventional pejorative sense.7 Soon aft er the outbreak of the Revolution, however, circles that supported the court attempted to introduce a conceptual model known as démocratie royale.8 Th e term démocrate, though fi rst used in France in 1789 in a highly pejorative sense, did not appear so oft en in 1790 or 1791.9 Few leading revolu- tionaries spoke positively about democracy in the early phase of the Revolution. In 1791, Jacques-Pierre Brissot still distinguished between ancient ‘pure democracy’ and French republicanism, emphasizing rep- resentation as a preferable alternative to direct democracy.10 No revo- lutionary newspaper bore a name referring to democracy before 1793; up to then the words of “people”, “national”, “patriotic”, “republican” and “sovereignty” remained much more important.11 Th e history of the concept of the sovereignty of the people is quite diff erent. Th e idea of the sovereignty of the nation had been strongly present ever since Sieyes’ pamphlets and the declaration of the National Constituent Assembly by the Th ird Estate on 17 June 1789.12 Th e Dec- laration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen of 26 August 1789 contained the concept of national sovereignty in the sense that it found

6 Rosanvallon 1995, 144–145; Wright 2002, 302; Dunn 2005, 104, 110; Urbinati 2006, 164. 7 Tackett 1997, 98–99. 8 Hampson 1983, 3; Dippel 1986, 73. 9 Palmer 1953, 205–207; Th e term had been used in Denmark in 1760, in the Dutch Republic in the mid-1780s and in the Austrian Netherlands in the late 1780s. Meier 1972, 854; Dippel 1986, 83. 10 Rosanvallon 1995, 145–146; Observe, however, the highly positive sense which “democracy” took on in Claude Fauchet’s political sermon in February 1791. See Ihalainen 2008b; cf. Maier 1972, 859, who questions the “political” signifi cance of Fauchet’s use of the term. 11 Palmer 1953, 213; Rosanvallon 1995, 143; Monnier 1999, 54–55. 12 Tackett 1997, 94; Wright 2002, 302; Baker 2006, 630. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 347

“the source of all sovereignty [. . .] in the nation”. No authority was conceivable but one that proceeded from the nation. Yet the practical implications of this principle continued to be understood in confl ict- ing ways: while the moderates merely saw the nation as the ultimate source of power, the radicals placed sovereignty directly in the general will. Th eorists such as Sieyès, furthermore, spoke for a representative body speaking on behalf of the nation. Th e concept of representation made a parallel breakthrough in the formulation “all citizens have the right to participate personally, or through their representatives, in [the formation of the law]”.13 Rousseau was made into a pioneer of the sovereignty of the people, even though initially he had not advo- cated the notion that clearly. His writings could, however, be inter- preted as placing sovereignty permanently in the hands of the people. Th ey have been generally seen as supporting “radically democratic” ideas in which the deputies of the people were mere agents, not repre- sentatives.14 Th e Abbé Fauchet, for example, actively reinterpreted the concept of sovereignty as used by Rousseau in his Social Contract.15 Some revolutionaries, motivated by the writings of Rousseau, main- tained that all adults were eligible to participate in decision-making on public aff airs.16 In practice, of course, this was never the case in revolutionary France. To sum up the early revolutionary contribution to the history of democracy, Rousseau’s political thinking about the political role of the people was radicalized soon aft er the outbreak of the Revolution. Ideas about the sovereignty of the nation or the people became slogans of the Revolution quite early on, and they received increasingly radical formulations in the course of the revolutionary debate. “Representa- tion” was likewise a key term, though it was not yet generally associ- ated with democracy. “Democracy” made no breakthrough during the fi rst two or three years of the Revolution; only from 1793 onwards did it become more widely used as a political term that had a signifi cance beyond mere classical constitutional theory. By 1793, “democracy” was taking on more positive and future-oriented senses in the French

13 Baker 1990, 271, 285, 301; Wright 2002, 303; articles 3 and 6. 14 Cranston 1988, 100, 103; Crick 2002, 52; Monnier 2002, 392; Fetscher 2006, 577. 15 Rosanvallon 1995, 144; Ihalainen 2008b. 16 Crick 2002, 12. 348 chapter five language. Th e concept of representative democracy was also gradually emerging.17 While the early phase of the Revolution already made Burke recon- sider his interpretation of “democracy”, the alternative revolutionary concept of democracy and the connected notion of the sovereignty of the people only began to constitute a clear challenge for the British Parliament from latter part of 1792 on. Th e clash between the con- ventional British and alternative French concepts led to some interest- ing debates, but it did not involve any simple rejection of the French revolutionary alternatives or total denouncements of democracy in the mixed constitution either. Indeed, I suggest that British parliamen- tary conceptions of the political system were redefi ned in signifi cant ways as a result of the debates of the 1790s. Th e transformation of the concept of democracy and its association with the concepts of the sovereignty of the people and representation also took place within a traditional representative institution, not merely as a result of the exportation of the Revolution outside France.

Initial Responses to the Revolution in Britain

Th e impact of the French Revolution on the British language of politics was ambivalent: On the one hand, the Revolution led to the introduc- tion of new or modifi ed political ideas into the debate, acting as a cata- lyst for change in political thought and practice. On the other hand, it strengthened the hold of the traditional language of politics, delaying such political and conceptual change as had already started, although this had anyway been slowed down by the failure of parliamentary reform and perhaps also by the Dutch model of the democracy of the streets.18 Th e debate on democracy as an element of the mixed con- stitution that had led to a revaluation of the concept, as described in Chapter Four, assumed a quite diff erent tenor among British members of parliament as a consequence of the emergence of the revolutionary alternative.

17 Rosanvallon 1995, 140–145; Rosanvallon 2000, 13–14, 20–25, 56, 63; cf. Monnier 2001, 2–3, 19; Monnier 2005, 68–70. 18 Dickinson 1989b, 1. Dickinson has also emphasised the impact of other eighteenth- century revolutions, including the industrial one, on British political discourse. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 349

Th e most important context for the following analysis of the par- liamentary debates of the 1790s is provided by an increasingly intense public debate on democracy19 and the sovereignty of the people.20 For this chapter, all political writings containing the phrase “the sover- eignty of the people” that I have found have been consulted. Likewise, all works containing references to democracy and published in Lon- don in the 1790s have been taken into consideration. Th e emphasis has been on originally British comments on democracy in the British context rather than on comments on the French regime, whether writ- ten by Frenchmen or Britons. A corpus compiled with these thematic and geographical limitations enables a suffi cient contextualization of parliamentary debates, particularly as many of the analysed speeches were published individually in printed form in London and com- mented upon in London-based public discourse. Such interconnec- tions between the parliamentary and public debates had become very close by the 1790s, many speakers evidently addressing the wider pub- lic rather than their fellow members only. Th e relationship between the two forms of debate was reciprocal: while innovations in the public discussion could be introduced into, and developed further in, par- liamentary debates, it was oft en a new use of language in Parliament that popularized novel ways of political speaking. A wider conceptual

19 Th e sheer extent of the available printed literature has made selectivity essen- tial: full-text searches with the abbreviated keyword “democr*” in the ECCO database produce some 5146 titles from the 1790s, including multiple editions and works con- taining several occurrences of “democracy”. A limited search focusing on books clas- sifi ed under “social sciences” produces 1717 hits. Th e trends in frequencies of use are slightly more visible in the latter corpus: it shows an almost six-fold rise in the number of titles from 30 in 1789 to 175 in 1793. Another summit was seen in 1798 with 217 titles. Th is was followed by a rapid decline in frequencies. We can thus conclude that the 1790s saw two peaks in the use of “democracy” in British, London-based printed literature, the fi rst early in the decade and the second in the years 1797–1799. See also Palmer 1964, 327, on 1798 as “the high tide of revolutionary democracy” and Mon- nier 2002, 396, on the rise of the concept of the people in the French revolutionary discourse. 20 Th e frequencies of use of the phrase “the sovereignty of the people” are more approximate than those of “democracy”. Even so, the results reveal a parallel trend in the global corpus of ECCO and in “social science” titles. Th e fi rst rise in frequen- cies comes somewhat later than in the case of “democracy”, in connection with the introduction of the republican constitution in France and the outbreak of war, which is a clear indication of a time lag in the British reception of the concept. Th e number of titles rose from practically none in 1789 to 45 in 1793. Another summit of 43 fol- lowed in 1799 simultaneously with one in Parliament, but the frequencies declined thereaft er. 350 chapter five change could thus also be initiated by the active use of new linguistic resources in parliamentary debate. At the fi rst sight, the events in Paris in 1789 caused little concern in London. In some respects, right up till 1791, they were observed with curiosity and even enthusiasm, regardless of party or group. Th e French Revolution was generally viewed as a welcome parallel to the development of the British liberty and limited monarchy. Th e pro- paganda of the centennial celebrations of the Glorious Revolution of 1688 contributed to this association and revived hopes for a parlia- mentary reform. If some parliamentary reformers and radical societies expressed sympathy for the French Revolution, this too was usually seen as mere harmless enthusiasm.21 Aft er 1790, however, British understandings of the nature of the French Revolution became more diverse, and disagreements between the various interpretations were becoming inevitable.22 Sympathy for the French began to wane as soon as the goals of the revolutionaries seemed to diverge from the sanctifi ed British model of 1688. When the French Revolution was seen as threatening the estab- lished order in Britain, it became easy to reinforce inherited loyalist conceptions of the political community, particularly as these had been suitably recalled in connection with the centennial celebrations.23 Th e French Revolution also began to make the concepts of the people, and particularly the sovereignty of the people, contestable in an entirely new way. Press reports and numerous translations of French texts made Continental revolutionary vocabulary familiar in England, and domestic radicals were inspired by the Revolution. Th e confronta- tion with the language of the Revolution inhibited the revaluation of democracy which had been going on in British parliamentary debates for quite some time. Disagreements between the sympathizers and opponents of democracy of the French type took the debate on the concept to an entirely new stage.

21 Dickinson 1977, 232, 236; Goodwin 1979, 19–20; Christie 1982, 209; Cannon 1994, 116; Mori 1997, 78–79; Mori 2000, 31; Royle 2000, 13. 22 David Williams, aft er describing various British responses to the French Revolu- tion, argued quite correctly that the French did not intend “to introduce a democ- racy in any sense familiar” and did not aim at imitating the English Revolution. It remained unclear what the result was likely to be, but the old constitutional terms did not suffi ce to describe it. David Williams, Lessons to a Young Prince, on the Present Disposition in Europe to a General Revolution (London 1790), 70–72. 23 Dickinson 1989, 36–37. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 351

Th ere was also a considerable time lag in linguistic change in British parliamentary speaking. ‘Democracy’ already had established mean- ings, and it took time before the entirely new meanings given to it by the revolutionaries were adopted in Britain. In the year of the out- break of the Revolution, most British authors continued to understand ‘democracy’ as if no revolution had taken place. David Williams, for instance, described ancient democracies as having “generally exhibited only the caprices of a rabble” as a result of the dominance of pas- sion over reason and virtue. As Montesquieu had taught, democracies tended to become despotic. Th e only positive aspect of democracies was the rise of the public morale as a consequence of the involvement of the people in governing. Furthermore, political liberty benefi ted if “the people, though incapable of the ordinary business of government, should be organized into a capacity of forming judgment and exerting force to correct abuses of power”.24 For Williams, it remained clear that the British system was not based on any “Folkmote [sic], or a constitutional exercise of democratic power”.25 Th e ferment of the times sometimes brought democracy into politi- cal debate. Th e Annual Register of 1789 reported aft er some delay on the Patriot rising in the Dutch Republic in 1787, telling about “the prevalent democratic spirit” and the rise of “the democratical interest” there and referring to “the democratical parties” and fi nally to “demo- cratical government” on the other side of the North Sea.26 By 1789, such reports from Holland no longer caused particular concern as the emerging Dutch democracy had already been suppressed by Prussian troops two years previously, but they show how an extended vocabu- lary of democracy was evidently developing on the Continent. In the domestic debate of 1789, there was only one major contri- bution that broke with the conventions of talking about the politi- cal role of the people: on 4 November, Dr Richard Price, inspired by the French Revolution, preached a sermon to the London Revolu- tion Society, in which he accorded to the people of England a right

24 David Williams, Lectures on Political Principles; the Subjects of Eighteen Books, in Montesquieu’s Spirit of Laws: Read to Students under the Author’s Direction (London 1789), 36–37, 50–51, 60, 140. 25 David Williams, Letters on Political Liberty, and the Principles of the English and Irish Projects of Reform; Addressed to a Member of the English House of Commons. Th e third edition (London 1789), 15. 26 Th e Annual Register, or a View of the History, Politics, and Literature, for the Year 1787 (London 1789), 8–9. 352 chapter five to choose their rulers. Furthermore, Price, a leading Dissenter, saw “the Majesty, or Sovereignty of the people” as a power to be actively exercised so that new governors should be elected whenever old ones abused their power. As to the current system of representation, it did not adequately express popular opinion and needed to be reformed, following the example of the American and French revolutions.27 It was this particular contribution to the otherwise moderate British public debate of 1789 that made Burke respond fi rst in Parliament and then in a book, thereby opening a new phase in the debate on democracy.

Th e Heated Debate on Democracy in 1790

By 1790–1791, an increasing number of British politicians began to regard the French Revolution as embodying a kind of democracy they did not want. Th e members of parliament had to reconsider their rela- tionship to the established British concept of democracy and to take a stand on the emerging new French one. Th e concept of the sovereignty of the people had also become central in French revolutionary ideol- ogy, which diff ered from the mainstream British language of politics. Most reactions to the sovereignty of the people were highly condem- natory, but there were also some exceptions. Th e new contestability of these concepts among the members of parliament, though seemingly dominated by reactionary attitudes, did move the British language of politics in a direction that made it possible for some circles to view both democracy and the sovereignty of the people as key principles of the British constitution. It is, therefore, not quite correct to argue that the British political elite simply remained suspicious of democracy, adopted the word reluctantly from France and only used it in order to criticize the concept itself.28 It is my purpose to show that there was a continuous debate on democracy in Britain in the 1790s, based on a conception of it as an element of the mixed constitution that was already becoming trans- formed. Th e nature of the debate on democracy was not simply deter-

27 Richard Price, A Discourse on the Love of our Country, Delivered on Nov. 4, 1789 . . . to the Society for Commemorating the Revolution in Great Britain . . . (London 1789), 24; [A Free-Born Englishman], Paine’s Political and Moral Maxims; Selected from the Fift h Edition of Rights of Man, Part I. and II . . . (London 1792), 21; Dickinson 1977, 233; Royle 2000, 13. 28 Palmer 1953, 207, 223; Maier 1972, 855. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 353 mined by reactionary opposition to the French Revolution; rather, the British debate on democracy had a history of its own that was aff ected by the Revolution. British comments on democracy put forward in Parliament have oft en been bypassed in previous research. It is there- fore worth reconstructing the debate and seeing how a traditional representative institution reacted to the ideological challenge of revo- lutionary understandings of the political role of the people. George III made no explicit mention of the French Revolution in his speech opening Parliament in January 1790, which is an indica- tion that what he called “our excellent constitution” had apparently remained unaff ected half a year aft er the fall of the Bastille (XXVIII, 300). Th e concept of the people played only a marginal role in the cer- emonial speeches on all sides. Th e positive stance of Edward Boscaven, the Earl of Falmouth, towards the Revolution in the Lords’ debate illus- trates the prevailing notion of the Revolution as a struggle for liberty motivated by French envy of the British constitution. It followed that Falmouth saw no reason for any concern among the British people (XXVIII, 301). Not everyone viewed the Revolution as such a harmless event. In February 1790, both Burke and Fox spoke more extensively about the Revolution and democracy. Burke had described democracy as a part of the mixed constitution in positive terms in 1786, but by February 1790, provoked by Price’s sermon a few months earlier, he was already turning into an outspoken critic not of just the French Revolution but also of what he saw as mistaken forms of democracy. It is worth exam- ining exactly what29 Burke said about democracy before interpreting him as an opponent of all kinds of democracy at that stage. It is impor- tant to focus on the attributes that Burke ascribed to the French type of democracy and on how he redefi ned his own previous, rather more positive concept of it. And how did Fox, who had used the concept of democracy in highly optimistic terms in 1785 and welcomed the Revo- lution in 1789, respond to Burke’s devaluation of democracy, given that the two men were old ideological allies? Th e debate of February 1790 already revealed confl icting concep- tions of the political role of the people, but it did not lead to any simplistic rejection of democracy in the British Parliament. Th e topic under discussion was not the constitutional status of the people but

29 A variety of of reports on the debate were published, of course. Harris 2007, 126. 354 chapter five the army estimates. Even so, Prime Minister Pitt introduced a consti- tutional dimension to the issue by pointing out that it was one of the main guarantees of “the liberties of the people” that the Commons should decide on military spending (XXVIII, 339). In response, Burke made a speech that was designed to provoke the audience both inside and outside the Commons. He reinforced this act by having a version of the speech printed soon aft erwards (XXVIII, 351–352).30 Reviewing the relative strengths of the European powers, Burke considered the French nation as no serious threat to her neighbours aft er a revolution that had eff ectively destroyed the infrastructure of the country. More dangerous than confusion in France was exces- sive enthusiasm towards things French among some Britons, false notions of liberty of the French type included (XXVIII, 353–355). An important conceptual re-description occurred when Burke defi ned the Revolution as a transition from despotism to an undesirable kind of democracy and accused some Britons of wishing to follow the danger- ous French model: In the last age, we were in danger of being entangled by the example of France in the net of a relentless despotism. [. . .] Our present danger from the example of a people, whose character knows no medium, is, with regard to government, a danger from anarchy; a danger of being led through an admiration of successful fraud and violence, to an imitation of the excesses of an irrational, unprincipled, proscribing, confi scating, plundering, ferocious, bloody, and tyrannical democracy (XXVIII, 355). In brief, the French had transformed a despotic monarchical system into a form of government which, as a result of its attacks on property and religion,31 deserved no other names than anarchy and democracy. Such a system, if weak at the moment, could develop into a danger to the political future of Britain. For Burke, the French version of democ- racy appeared as one that violated the principles of reason and prop- erty; it was the worst kind of democracy and certainly diff erent from British democracy as discussed in the preceding decade. Burke was challenging not only Price but also Fox and other poli- ticians who had expressed sympathy for the Revolution. Burke, for his part, was “strongly opposed to any the least tendency towards the

30 Edmund Burke, Substance of the Speech of the Right Honourable Edmund Burke, in thr [sic] Debate on the Army Estimates . . . (London 1790), 12. Th e formulations are the same as in Cobbett. 31 Harris 1993, 299–300. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 355 means of introducing a democracy like theirs”, a democracy charac- terized by “the spirit of innovation, so distant from all principles of true and safe reformation” (XXVIII, 356–357). When Burke talked about “democracy like theirs”, his statement did not necessarily imply the denial of other types of democracy. Th e French nation had acted unwisely in rejecting the order of a balanced constitution in favour of anarchy and giving traditional concepts new revolutionary and mischievous meanings.32 Such a rejection of the model off ered by the British constitution and linguistic usage meant contempt for true free- dom and the rise of a distorted form of democracy—an “innovation” in a negative sense. Burke appealed to classical political theory when pointing out that democracy never worked in a country the size of France. Th is led him to conclude, in terms parallel to the contempo- rary French public debate, that the result in France might be the rise of an anarchical multitude of independent democracies of various kinds, leading to outright tyranny:33 [. . .] if they should perfectly succeed in what they propose, [. . .] and establish a democracy, or a mob of democracies, in a country circum- stanced like France, they will establish a very bad government; a very bad species of tyranny (XXVIII, 358). Th e French model would never constitute a regulated democracy of the British type but rather an anarchical form consisting of small democ- racies. Burke was not denouncing all forms of democracy, only the French version.34 In speaking of soldiers who rioted, he was actually lamenting the way in which democracy was being abused in France: Th eir conduct was one of the fruits of that anarchic spirit, from the evils of which a democracy was to be resorted to, by those who were the least disposed to that form, as a sort of refuge (XXVIII, 359).

32 Blakemore 1984, 284–307. 33 Burke was actually echoing much of Sieyès’ argument against the rise of “democ- racies” in France. Baker 1990, 300; Urbinati 2006, 163; he may have been aware of P.F.J. Robert’s suggestion in 1790 of creating representative democracy at the level of departments. Dippel 1986, 75–76; Stanhope viewed this statement as a reproach to the French nation and the National Assembly in particular. Charles Stanhope, A Letter from Earl Stanhope, to the Right Honourable Edmund Burke: Containing a Short Answer to his late Speech on the French Revolution. Th e second edition (London 1790), 27. 34 Cf. James Livesey’s suggestion that a “European” model of democracy, as an alternative to the Anglo-American liberal democracy, emerged during the French Revolution, especially aft er 1792. Livesey 2001, 2–3. 356 chapter five

Th e French revolutionary masses did not represent true democracy but constituted “a furious, licentious populace” (XXVIII, 359). Th ey had, indeed, hijacked the classical concept of democracy and devel- oped a degenerate form of it.35 It was this menace that made Burke, a former advocate of the British type of regulated democracy, view its current applications in France in such reactionary terms. Aft er Burke’s speech, Fox—who had been a spokesman for an extended political role of the people and a defender of the democratic element in the British constitution since about 1780—also felt a need to distance himself from the French type of democracy. Many Fox- ites had visited France frequently and applauded the Revolution, but Burke’s ideas, and perhaps also the radicalization of the French revo- lutionary process, made Fox choose his words more carefully than was typical of him. He, too, argued that the French Revolution represented a kind of democracy he did not wish to see in Britain. He was not to be considered “a friend to democracy”36 of the French type in support- ing the idea of a standing army. Instead, he emphasized his advocacy of the mixed constitution of Britain, limiting his statement to what was acceptable to say about democracy in the aft ermath of the French Revolution:37 He declared himself equally the enemy of all absolute forms of govern- ment, whether an absolute monarchy, an absolute aristocracy, or an absolute democracy. He was adverse to all extremes, and a friend only to a mixed government, like our own, in which, if the aristocracy, or indeed either of the three branches of the constitution, were destroyed, the good eff ect of the whole, and the happiness derived under it, would, in his mind, be at an end (XXVIII, 364). Fox further explained his good intentions in welcoming the Revolution and declared, in an orthodox fashion: “[T]rue liberty could only exist amidst the union and co-operation of the diff erent powers which com- posed the legislative and the executive government.” It followed that a French type of constitutional innovation was unthinkable in Britain.

35 See also Blakemore 1984, 284–285. 36 In the account published by Burke, Fox is reported to have stated that “he did not aff ect a democracy”. Burke, Substance 1790, 33. 37 According to Burke’s account, Fox “always thought any of the simple, unbal- anced governments bad; simple monarchy, simple aristocracy, simple democracy; he held them all imperfect or vicious: all were bad by themselves: the composition alone was good.” Burke, Substance 1790, 33. Burke and Fox thus understood the matter in the same way despite some variations in their choices of attributes. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 357

Fox needed an explanation for the French excesses in the building of democracy and found it in the harsh despotism which they had rejected (XXVIII, 364–365); despotism had caused this counter- reaction. Democracy as such was not wrong. Fox continued to sup- port the democratic element of the mixed constitution and moderated his views on the Revolution to play down suggestions—put forward previously in print and now in Parliament—that his party, with their French connections, aimed at a similar kind of revolution in Britain. Fox’s support for the Revolution as such had not withered away, but a vindication of his attitude to democracy had become timely.38 Richard Brinsley Sheridan, the playwright and a parliamentary reformist, was more willing than Fox to defend the revolutionary regime. He disputed Burke’s claims that the National Constituent Assembly was involved in actions that deserved to be called “bloody, ferocious, and tyrannical democracy”. Sheridan regretted the disre- spectful manner in which Burke had talked about democracy and the National Constituent Assembly as an institution of the French nation (XXVIII, 368–369). In response to this stubborn defence of the Revolution, Burke made an even more outspoken onslaught on “the outrageous democracy of the present government of France, which levelled all distinctions in society.” Th is interpretation of the Revolution was unavoidably lead- ing to a critical attitude towards democracy of all kinds, even though the qualities that Burke attributed to the French democracy still made it appear as a particular perverted version. Burke denied that he had accused the National Constituent Assembly of advocating “a bloody, cruel, and ferocious democracy”. It was rather “the republic of Paris” which was to be blamed for such political anarchy (XXVIII, 370–371). In 1790, even this growing critic of the Revolution recognized the legitimacy of the main institution of the French revolutionary regime. He warned of the democratic spirit of some of the revolutionaries and of their mistaken constitutional innovations, but he did not denounce all types of democracy as mischievous. Pitt looked for a compromise, acknowledging the arguments of both Sheridan and Burke but refraining from taking any clear stand on the

38 Mitchell 2004; Ayling has argued that Fox remained “deeply suspicious of democracy and [was] on the whole hostile to it”. Ayling 1991, 173. Fox’s own words do not quite support such an interpretation. Th e prevailing diverging understandings of democracy need to be taken into consideration. 358 chapter five concept of democracy. His criticism of the French system was rather expressed with such phrases as “the unqualifi ed nominal liberty” and “the most absolute, direct, and intolerable slavery” (XXVIII, 373). Despite such pejorative language, Pitt was not particularly worried about the French menace in 1790. He obviously retained the basically positive concept of democracy which together with Fox he had pro- posed in parliamentary debates in the early 1780s. He certainly did not see democracy as opposed to the British constitution. Burke’s defi nition of the Revolution as productive of democracy of a distorted kind changed the character of the parliamentary debate on other occasions as well. His attack on the Revolution was recalled by fellow members later in spring 1790. In debates on the repeal of the Test and Corporation Acts in March, for instance, aft er Burke had opposed Fox’s motion, William Smith, a radical independent politi- cian with a Unitarian background, criticized Burke for his attitude towards the French. Smith found it hard to accept that Burke [. . .] attacked a whole nation, while engaged in the very act of struggling for their liberties, and called them ‘an irrational, unprincipled, proscrib- ing, confi scating, plundering, ferocious, bloody, and tyrannical democ- racy’ (PR, XXVII, 187).39 Many parliamentarians continued to be amazed at Burke’s untypical attack on French democracy and preferred to retain their optimistic expectations about the outcome of the Revolution, particularly as the concept of democracy had taken on quite positive connotations in the course of the 1780s, including those given to it by Burke himself. Some radicals, at least, considered that Burke was only misusing the concept. When the diverse understandings of democracy became evident, members felt a need to defi ne the concept more clearly. Having quite consistently defended the democratic element in the British constitu- tion in the 1780s, Pitt contrasted “a limited monarchy” of the British kind with “the purest democracy” of the French type and rejected the view that the French alternative was a system where “the most perfect equality” reigned. Exploiting the rising discussion on democracy to support his arguments in the debate on the Test Act, he maintained

39 Also printed in Th e Debate in the House of Commons, on the Repeal of the Cor- poration and Test Acts, March 2nd, 1790 . . . (London 1790), 50. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 359 that even in a pure democracy the majority excluded any religious group “whose tendency might be to destroy the democratic equality” (PR, XXVII, 157). Pitt implicitly suggested that the Foxite faction and the Dissenters, in admiring France, favoured a wrong type of democ- racy and that even in such a system religious discrimination for politi- cal reasons was considered necessary. His point was that restrictions on the political rights of the Dissenters were still needed in order to protect the British constitution; he was not so much rejecting democ- racy in general. On 4 March 1790, Henry Flood’s motion for a parliamentary reform led to further uses and defi nitions of the concept of democracy. Flood was an independent member of parliament who, without gathering support in advance, took up the shortcomings of representation that had been repeatedly discussed in the Commons in the early 1780s. He argued that the Commons in its current form was not “freely and fre- quently elected by the body of the people” and proposed the creation of a hundred new seats as a solution to the problem. With reference to Fox’s recent rejection of absolute forms of monarchy, aristocracy and democracy, Flood argued that all three elements were needed. His premises were, fi rstly, “all just Government must be founded in the choice of the people” and, secondly, “the popular order of gov- ernment is at least as indispensable, and as valuable as either of the other.” Flood certainly did not present himself as an advocate of “democracy”; he rather talked about “popular order” and the strength- ening of “the popular form of government” or simply “the represen- tation of the people” in the British constitution. Th e system as such remained a mixed one and better than any of the alternative ancient models. Representation was the key concept here, just as it had been in the American Constitution and in revolutionary France: Th rough representation even “a great people can possess an effi cient infl uence in their own legislature, without being legislators themselves”. Accord- ing to Flood, this would be reached more effi ciently if virtual repre- sentation was developed into an actual one so that the majority of the people were allowed to vote. Counting on support from Pitt and the Foxites, he appealed to authors such as Blackstone and Hume as defenders of an increase in popular infl uence on Parliament. Aft er the suggested reform, “the entire representative of the nation” would no longer be elected by a minority of the people; instead, the Commons would no longer be “under another infl uence than that of the people.” Without the proposed kind of a reform, the Commons remained “a 360 chapter five second rate aristocracy, instead of a popular representation”, Flood concluded (XXVIII, 453–455, 457, 460–462, 464).40 Th e reception of Flood’s speech was far from enthusiastic. Flood’s questioning of virtual representation, in particular, was seen as inap- propriate.41 William Windham, a friend of Fox who had been enthu- siastic about the Revolution during his visit to Paris in 1789, opposed the suggested kind of parliamentary reform with arguments recalling those of Burke. In his view, a mere “triumphant appeal to the people” could not prove inadequacies in the representative system. Th e people at large hardly wanted the suggested kind of reform, and theorists provided no answers to practical political problems (XXVIII, 465, 467–468). Prime Minister Pitt also disappointed Flood’s expectations by rejecting theoretical speculations and the timing of Flood’s motion. Th e reform as such was needed but not at the proposed moment (XXVIII, 469). Not even Fox considered the moment right for a reform (XXVIII, 471–472). James Johnstone, the Earl of Hopetoun, dismissed the motion by saying that it belonged to “another century” (XXVIII, 470), probably meaning the seventeenth. Finally, Burke’s doubts about a parliamentary reform had turned into an outspoken criticism of constitutional innovations and a denial of the claim that the Commons did not represent the people. His major constitutional argument against a reform was that governments which had been “completely and purely popular” so that “the people held the power entirely in their own hands”—such as those of Athens and Rome—had been militant to a ruinous degree (XXVIII, 477).42 Flood’s motion found only one outspoken supporter, the Foxite John Courtenay, and with typical irony he denied suggestions that a reform was likely to lead to revolutionary developments parallel to those in France. In reply to a preceding remark by Powys, Courtenay ridiculed the fears of the parliamentary majority about the French type

40 Identical formulations can be found in Henry Flood, Th e Speech and Proposition of the Right Honourable Henry Flood, in the House of Commons . . . on a Reform of the Representation in Parliament (London 1790), 4. 41 Cannon 1994, 117–118; Mori 1997, 81. 42 Late in 1790, Edmund Burke published his famous critique of the French Revolu- tion. In his speeches in Parliament he put forward many of the same points. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 361 of democracy, suggesting with an absurd description43 that the oppo- nents of parliamentary reform were behaving [. . .] as if the members of the national assembly had come over and inoc- ulated the people of this country with democracy, and a rage of infection had spread the new French disease (XXVIII, 478, cf. 470, 475). Th e parliamentary reformists, aware of their minority position, did not dare to explicitly associate their proposal with revolutionary ideas such as democracy. Some members of parliament like Courtenay, however, held unprejudiced views about democracy and endeavoured to make the majority reconsider their attitudes by presenting prejudices against the French revolutionaries, the National Constituent Assembly and democracy as irrational and comparable to popular conceptions of diseases.44 French democracy was not to be seen as an alien phenom- enon threatening Britain through a foreign conspiracy and popular insurrection but rather as a natural part of the British constitution. Th e British type of democracy as an element of the balanced constitu- tion was still to be considered a positive phenomenon.45 Democracy had no outspoken defenders in this debate, but it was not openly attacked either. Flood’s independent attempt to launch a reform failed, and the proposer withdrew it without a division. Despite his obvious talents, Flood failed to win a seat in the elections of 1790.

43 Hamilton, a Pittite, who published a collection of advice on parliamentary speak- ing, recommended the use of absurd claims to demonstrate that opponents’ argu- ments were irrational. William Gerard Hamilton, Parliamentary Logick: To which are subjoined two speeches delivered in the House of Commons of Ireland, and other pieces (London 1808), 31. I am grateful to Taru Haapala for bringing this connection to my attention; see also Palonen 2008, 159–160. 44 Th e medical parallels referred to the eighteenth-century English fashion of call- ing the most feared and reprehensible venereal disease, syphilis, “the French disease” and to the widespread fear of inoculation against small-pox, which was regarded as ridiculous by enlightened people. 45 John Courtenay used a similar ironical style in a pamphlet in which he ridiculed the way in which the Anglican clergy had expressed their concern over “the danger- ous and rapid progress of democracy in France”, “the fermentation of democracy”, the innovations which it entailed and French plans to establish “a shocking system of universal democracy” based on an alliance between “atheism and democracy”. Th e implicit suggestion was that many of the reforms in France were entirely welcome. John Courtenay, Philosophical Refl ections on the late Revolution in France, and the Conduct of the Dissenters in England; in a Letter to the Rev. Dr. Priestley (London 1790), 1, 58, 63, 79. 362 chapter five

When Parliament convened in Westminster aft er the general election in November, both the monarch and the two houses had little to say about the constitutional role of the people. Th e only mention referred to the general election as “an opportunity of collecting the immediate sense of my people”. Th e ministry rather made the King speak of his subjects, whose will was identical with that of their monarch (XXVIII, 891–895). Th e Pittite Philip Yorke, the Earl of Hardwicke, maintained that with their unanimous Address the Lords communicated to the King not only “their own sense, but that of all the people of Great Britain” (XXVIII, 898). Th e notion of the Lords as representatives of the voice of the people thus still appeared entirely plausible from an aristocratic point of view. Th e Commons, too, saw it as their duty to “faithfully represent the sentiments of a loyal and grateful people” (XXVIII, 905)—a formulation which combined an assurance of the loyalty of the people and Parliament to the monarch with the constitu- tional principle of parliament representing the people (XXVIII, 905). In public debates, concern for the consequences of the Revolution was growing, partly as a reaction to Richard Price’s and Joseph Priest- ley’s argument about the applicability of revolutionary ideas to Britain. Aft er replying to Price in Parliament in February, Burke responded to Priestley’s “democratic and levelling principles” concerning the rights of the English people over their monarch—a king who ruled out of “the choice of the people”.46 In Refl ections on the Revolution in France, fi rst published in November 1790, Burke attacked the Brit- ish sympathizers of the French Revolution, denied analogies between the revolutions of 1688 and 1789 and defended “a representation of the people” in its current British form, rejecting the French political system as “new democracy”. While the French political establishment “aff ects to be a pure democracy”, Burke saw such “perfect democracy” as “the most shameless thing in the world” as a result of the will of the people having been made the highest authority. As in his speech in Parliament, Burke continued to distinguish between “pure democracy” or “perfect democracy” in France and democracy in the British con- stitution, which he had previously advocated. In Britain, he insisted, “we are resolved to keep [. . .] an established monarchy, an established aristocracy, and an established democracy, each in the degree it exists,

46 Priestley had argued that Parliament was the only proper sovereign. Goldsworthy 1999, 219. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 363 and in no greater”.47 Th e recognition of the three equal elements of the constitution corresponded with what Burke had argued before. Burke was still attempting to defend the classical concept of democracy as it had been slightly redefi ned in late eighteenth-century parliamentary debates before the French Revolution. Burke did not completely rule out democracy. He even conceded that, in some rare circumstances, “the purely democratic form will become necessary”, but a country the size of France was not such a case. Aristotle had ruled out “an absolute democracy” as a form of gov- ernment because of its corrupted, degenerated, tyrannical and intoler- ant nature. Only in a mixed constitution could democracy have good eff ects.48 Th e latter case was the concept of democracy which Burke had previously defended. Burke’s defi nition of the French system as a mistaken kind of democracy continued the line he had followed in his parliamentary speech, irrespectively of the fact that the revolutionaries themselves did not yet universally view their regime as a democracy.49 Burke was particularly concerned about the destruction of the tradi- tional institutions of the monarchy and the church as a consequence of putting unlimited power in the hands of the pretended representatives of the people.50 Harry Dickinson has suggested, in fact, that he spoke for most of the British political elite in condemning the doctrine of the sovereignty of the people and maintaining that the people had no power separate from that of the King and Parliament.51 Not everyone shared Burke’s views, however. George Rous, for instance, pointed out that problems linked with popular assemblies in democracies could be removed through the machinery of representa- tion. Provided that the French maintained some aristocracy together

47 Burke, Refl ections on the Revolution in France, 1790, 16, 83, 121, 135–139, 185; Goodwin 1979, 130. 48 Burke, Refl ections on the Revolution in France, 1790, 185–187. 49 According to Antoine Louis Claude Destutt de Tracy, the French were not build- ing a democracy but a representative government. Translation of a Letter from Mon- sieur de Tracy . . . to Mr. Burke, in Answer to his Remarks on the French Revolution (London 1790), 14. 50 Langford 2004. Some commentators replied to Burke that drinking in honour of the sovereignty or majesty of the people was mere harmless fun. John Scott, A Letter to the Right Hon. Edmund Burke, in a Reply to his “Refl ections on the Revolution in France, &c.” (London 1790), 50. 51 Dickinson 1976, 205; Burke’s denouncement of the concept of the sovereignty of the people only came later, in 1791 and more clearly towards the end of 1792, aft er the rise of its republican interpretation in France. 364 chapter five with democracy, they could actually achieve “a well-regulated democ- racy”,52 something that, by implication, was possible in Britain as well. Rous obviously defended the old concept of democracy as a positive element of the mixed constitution. Even the French notion of the sovereignty of the people found its defenders in Britain. Fox was reported to have rejoiced at the fall of the Bastille in 1789. As we shall see, he referred to the sovereignty of the people as a universal principle in some of his parliamentary speeches in the 1790s and drank in honour of “Our sovereign lord, the people” in 1798.53 Fox’s enthusiasm is partly explained by his francophile dis- position: he had made the acquaintance of several French aristocrats who supported the Revolution.54 Th us two leading British members of parliament, Burke and Fox, responded to the Revolution in confl ict- ing ways: Burke led the Old Whigs, who were suspicious of the Revo- lution, whereas Fox’s relatively modest group retained a sympathetic attitude towards the Revolution until the outbreak of the war with France in February 1793, and even beyond it.

Strengthening Criticism of the French Model of Democracy in 1791

In France, the popularity of the concept of democracy was growing and its meanings evolving. In April 1791, Jacques Pierre Brissot, a critic of “pure democracy”, argued—still within the ideal of a mixed constitution—for “a popular monarchy, tending to the popular side. Such is my democracy”.55 However, associations between sovereignty originating from the nation and democracy were emerging. Th is led to a clearer distinction between democracy and monarchy and contro- versies for and against representative and perfect democracy. In some circles, Rousseau’s concept of democracy had already been developed in a more radical direction aft er 1790.56 Representation was not yet generally combined with the concept of democracy, some revolution- aries fearing that the representatives would turn into a new aristocracy

52 George Rous, Th oughts on Government: Occasioned by Mr. Burke’s Refl ections, &c. Second edition. (London 1790), 7–8. 53 Crick 2002, 16; Evans 1996, 3; Mitchell 2004. 54 Mitchell 2004. 55 Palmer 1953, 213. 56 Dippel 1986, 74–76. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 365 free from popular control.57 However, associations between republic and democracy were becoming increasingly frequent.58 Simultaneously, “democrat” was, for the fi rst time, becoming a posi- tive term for self-identifi cation, indeed to such an extent that any sup- porter of the Revolution could adopt the appellation. While being a democrat did not at fi rst necessarily entail support for a form of gov- ernment called “democracy”, by 1792 one dictionary defi ned a demo- crat as “the subject of a democratic government” and someone who “is a partisan of democracy.” Democrats were depicted as honest citi- zens, good patriots and true Frenchmen who supported popular gov- ernment. Later on, under the Jacobin republic, however, “democrats” tended to turn into a discriminatory party denomination reserved for the supporters of direct democracy as opposed to the Jacobins, who supported representative democracy.59 Clearly, the Revolution was changing the meanings of “democracy” in ways that made a return to the classical concept quite impossible. It produced derivations referring to a political agent (“democrat”), to political allegiance in a positive sense (“democratic”), to democratic action aimed at reconciling politics with the idea of popular sover- eignty (“to democratize”) and to a political ideology (“democratism”). As a result of this semantic change, the concepts of democracy and the sovereignty of the people thus came to be seen as synonymous. It also meant that “democrat” was transformed, albeit only temporarily, from a partisan appellation into a name borne with honour. Further- more, a vision of creating a democracy for the benefi t of all the people emerged.60 For British parliamentary speaking, the emergence of revolutionary understandings of democracy was problematic; they involved a new concept of democracy that diff ered radically from the re- evaluated old one. A confrontation between the two interpretations became unavoidable, particularly aft er Burke’s criticisms of the French type of democracy. During 1791, numerous writings both supportive and critical of Burke were published in Britain. Th omas Paine, in particu- lar, popularized the revolutionary senses of democracy, but the old

57 Markoff 1999, 671. 58 Dippel 1986, 77. 59 Rosanvallon 1995, 144–145; Dippel 1986, 83–85; Markoff 1999, 665. 60 Dippel 1986, 89–90; Monnier 1999, 49–50; Monnier 2005, 42–43; Dunn 2005, 16–17. 366 chapter five interpretation of it as an element of the mixed constitution also found its defenders. Th e radicalization of the Revolution and the domestic debate made ‘democracy’ a concept that simply could not be bypassed in political debates. In public discourse, views on democracy were many and contradic- tory. One author hoped that the French would not establish a democ- racy, which “though speculatively the best, is practically the worst form of government.”61 James Mackintosh, by contrast, defended the revo- lutionary regime against Burke by distinguishing between it and other democracies. According to Mackintosh, “the application of the word Democracy to it is fallacious and illusive” if it were not used in a broad etymological sense “as the power of the people”. Once the supposedly original sense of democracy was applied, all legitimate government should be called ‘democracy’. Mackintosh could not accept Burke’s association between the French regime and ancient democracies, which had lacked representation and the division of power. In such “a degenerate democracy”, “the rabble”, “the multitude”, “the mob” and “a corrupt and tumultuous populace” had indeed constituted “the despotism of the rabble, not the domination of the people.” In con- temporary France, by contrast, the legislative authority belonged to the representatives of the people. Such “a direct emanation from the sovereignty of the people” was, according to Mackintosh, as legitimate a political system as that of Britain.62 Th is was a radical claim with regard to the British constitution, too. Catharine Macaulay called for a parliamentary reform to strengthen the democratic element of the mixed constitution and the legitimacy of the form of government in general.63 Priestley wrote about a compact of sovereignty between the King and the people, implying thereby that, as the servant of the peo- ple, the King was bound to observe its will.64

61 [Anon.], A Letter to a Member of the National Assembly: Containing Remarks on the Proceedings of that Legislative Body; Strictures on the Political Doctrines of Mr. Burke and Mr. Paine; and a View of the Progress of the British Constitution (London 1791), 12. 62 James Mackintosh, Vindiciæ gallicæ: Defence of the French Revolution and its English Admirers Against the Accusations of the Right Hon. Edmund Burke . . . (London 1791), 222–223, 297. 63 Catharine Macaulay, Observations on the Refl ections of the Right Hon. Edmund Burke, on the Revolution in France . . . (Boston 1791), 20. 64 Joseph Priestley, Letters to the Right Honourable Edmund Burke, Occasioned by his Refl ections . . . Th e third edition (Birmingham 1791), 7, 27–28, 32. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 367

Th e most sympathetic reactions to the Revolution thus far were published in the fi rst part of Paine’s Rights of Man in March 1791, a further reply to Burke’s Refl ections on the French Revolution. Rejoic- ing at the end of monarchical despotism in France, Paine claimed that governments emerged as “the individuals themselves, each in his own personal and sovereign right, entered into a compact with each other to produce a government”. Furthermore, he argued, “Th is is the only mode in which governments have a right to arise, and the only principle on which they have a right to exist.” Challenging the estab- lished order in Britain, he further maintained that government arose “either out of the people, or over the people”.65 Paine suggested that the sovereignty of the people was, initially, the sovereignty of every individual. Th is led to the conclusion that the sovereign will of the people could and should be actively and constantly expressed.66 Such a radical claim was immediately condemned as anti-monarchical and the author declared an outlaw. In 1791, Paine did not yet emphasize the concept of democracy to any great extent; he merely wrote about the superior potential of politi- cians who had been born “on the democratic fl oor” or out of “democ- racy”.67 In the written reviews of his book, however, Paine’s ideas were associated with democracy. He was seen as aiming at democracy and propagating a senseless “individual sovereignty” that subverted all government. Th e conventional counter-argument was provided by ancient Athens, which had shown that democracy produced nothing but “anarchy, faction, private interest, and metaphysical equality”.68 Aristotelian voices recalled how “the evils of an unqualifi ed democ- racy [. . .] resemble those of a no-government”, particularly as soon as virtue was lost and human passions took over.69 Th e concept of the sovereignty of the people was also interpreted in various ways, oft en in attempts to play down its most radical implications. Frederick William

65 Paine, Rights of Man: Being an Answer to Mr. Burke’s Attack on the French Rev- olution . . . (London 1791), 52, 57; Urbinati 2006, 167. 66 Dickinson 1977, 244. 67 Paine, Rights of Man, 1791, 71. 68 [Anon.], Letters to Th omas Paine; in Answer to his late Publication on the Rights of Man: Shewing his Errors on that Subject; and Proving the Fallacy of his Principles as Applied to the Government of this Country (London 1791), 17, 39–41. 69 [Anon.], Rights of Citizens; Being an Inquiry into some of the Consequences of Social Union, and an Examination of Mr. Paine’s Principles Touching Government (London) [1791], 114–115. 368 chapter five

Hervey, the Marquess of Bristol, for instance, viewed the sovereignty of the people as authority delegated by God.70 Th e radicalization in France together with the related public debate in Britain placed the members of parliament in a new situation in spring 1791. Th e controversy between Burke and Paine, in particu- lar, had given ‘democracy’ new senses and increased the frequency of its use. An opportunity to discuss these interpretations was provided by the need to reorganize the administration of Quebec, an over- whelmingly French-speaking colony liable to be aff ected by French revolutionary ideas and the republican constitution of America. Th e case opened up several constitutional questions, including one on the nature of democracy aft er the French Revolution. ‘Democracy’ needed to be defi ned, either in its traditional sense as an element of the mixed constitution, or in a new, potentially more extensive revolutionary sense, at a time when a constitutional development of the French type inside the British Empire was either feared or hoped for. Fox, who had not lost his enthusiasm for the French Revolution, opened the debate by talking in an admiring tone about the progress which the “enlightened principles of freedom” had made in various countries. His attitude towards the Quebec Bill, on the other hand, was negative: it undermined “popular government in Canada” in that the suggested assemblies were not truly popular (XXIX, 105–107). Such an accusation was answered by suggestions that Fox wished to see a regime resembling the French rather than the British kind in Canada. Th ese reactions in turn forced Fox to explain that he was not promot- ing French or American “republican principles” in calling for popular government in Canada (XXIX, 361). In the days of the Revolution, any speech on popular government could be treated with suspicion, especially when it came from someone like Fox, but Fox evidently had enthusiastic supporters as well. Burke could not use the opportunity to attack Fox in a protesting House but promised to return to the issue. An open confrontation between Fox and Burke on popular govern- ment and democracy seemed to be unavoidable. On 6 May 1791, Burke took the initiative and turned the debate on the form of government in Canada into an attack on French revo- lutionary ideas and their advocates in Britain. Th ough suspicious of

70 Frederick William Hervey, Marquess of Bristol, A New Friend on an Old Subject (London 1791), 13. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 369

American republicanism, Burke acknowledged its avoidance of the absurdity of a total popular government. Th e French Revolution, by contrast, had produced a constitution “involving every principle to be detested, and pregnant with every consequence to be dreaded and abominated”. Th is had recently been demonstrated by the prevailing anarchy in the French West Indies (XXIX, 365–367). A similar kind of revolutionary anarchy might creep into Britain if Quebec were given the wrong kind of constitution. If “the absolute authority” were given to a popular assembly, as had happened when it was taken over by the National Constituent Assembly in France, this produced not orga- nized government but a pure democracy based on nothing but the abuse of the monarchy. According to Burke, the National Constituent Assembly had “contented themselves with enjoying the democratic satisfaction of heaping every disgrace on fallen royalty.” (XXIX, 368). Aft er Fox had defended some of the achievements of the Revolu- tion, Burke carried on his attack. Th e verbal duel with Fox over inter- pretations of the French Revolution caused Burke to speak about the French constitution and its admirers in Britain as “the French mal- ady” (XXIX, 371–372), exploiting the connotation with syphilis to describe the ideological position of his political opponents. Given the provocation of this statement, the Foxites remained surprisingly calm, attempting to avoid further associations that were potentially detri- mental to them. Fox merely continued to defend his original under- standing of the Revolution, maintaining that “the original compact between the people of England and its government” was “a recogni- tion of the original inherent rights of the people as men” in the same spirit as in revolutionary France (XXIX, 379). Fox regarded the French Revolution as similar to the Glorious Revolution of 1688, the people having defended their liberty with similar means in both cases. It was evident to all that Burke and Fox, former political allies and advocates of the democratic element of the constitution in the 1780s, were clash- ing over interpretations of popular government in the aft ermath of the French Revolution. All sides felt a need to defi ne the concepts of democracy and popular government in a clearer fashion and in rela- tion to the French Revolution. Burke was uncompromising in his stand: no “wild theories” endeav- ouring to “methodize anarchy” were to be applied in Canada. Instead, forms of government based on “the wisdom of antiquity” should be followed (XXIX, 403); in other words, a mixed constitution was the only conceivable alternative. Pitt, too, asserted that the goal was to 370 chapter five create “a free constitution, in the English sense of the word.” (XXIX, 404) Fox considered it wise to join the advocates of a mixed constitu- tion at this stage, describing how “every part of the British dominions ought to possess a government, in the constitution of which monar- chy, aristocracy, and democracy were mutually blended and united” (XXIX, 409). Th is was an orthodox formulation of the British mixed constitution by a politician who had recently been accused of hold- ing revolutionary principles. It refl ects the ambivalence of Fox’s poli- tics: contemporaries wondered whether Fox saw himself as a reformer complaining that many people remained unrepresented in the dem- ocratic branch of the constitution or whether he shared the loyalist notion that the British mixed constitution had already achieved the most important of republican goals.71 Th is last apparent rejection of revolutionary ideas by Fox was received with cries of amazement in the Commons (XXIX, 409–410). Th e growing suspicions about revolu- tionary France were forcing the Foxites to retreat from their previous constitutional positions. Th e existing pressures also aff ected Fox’s following description of democracy. He argued, for instance, that an element of aristocracy was needed “in democracies, and was there considered as an essential part of the constitution” (XXIX, 410). Th e task of aristocracy was to func- tion as a counterweight against constitutional innovations no matter whether they originated from the people or the monarchy. Th is dis- tanced Fox from the French revolutionary hatred of aristocracy but retained the interpretation of the British constitution as democratic in some respects. By “democracies” and “republics”, Fox meant Athens and Rome, adopting the French Enlightenment understanding of the two concepts as synonyms (XXIX, 410–412). Th eir synonymous con- tent was not quite as self-evident in Westminster as it was in French political philosophy and revolutionary rhetoric. For Fox, both classical models were signifi cant, but the British application of the concepts was that of a mixed constitution: he did not advocate “republican” or “democratical principles” and wished to see democracy or repub- licanism only in the limited senses which they had in America. Quite early on, Fox interpreted the American Constitution as a compromise between a mixed constitution and extreme democracy, thus associating

71 Morris 1998, 79. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 371 himself with the American moderate revolution rather than with the French radical one. His argument was that it came closest to the Brit- ish ideal: Americans [. . .] had acted wisely, [. . .] they had [. . .] made that form of government which was best for themselves; consisting of the powers of monarchy, aristocracy, and democracy blended, though under a diff er- ent name (XXIX, 412). Th us by 1791, aft er the emergence of the French alternative, the Amer- ican republican model with its limits on democracy already appeared as acceptable to Fox. Even the inherently pejorative denomination “republican”—with its reference to popular participation in govern- ment—was applicable, and Fox declared: [. . .] he was so far a republican, that he approved all governments where the res publica was the universal principle, and the people, as under our constitution, had considerable weight in the government (XXIX, 414). Republicanism connected with monarchy and aristocracy was a con- ceivable, even positive, phenomenon. In his speech, Fox made clear his stance on the British constitution, the French Revolution and the American republican constitution all at the same time. Pitt’s reply was based on a fairly commonplace admiration of the three elements of the British constitution. Th e Prime Minister recog- nized a degree of democracy in Britain but only side by side with the other two elements of the constitution: [. . .] aristocracy refl ected lustre on the crown, and lent support and eff ect to the democracy, while the democracy gave vigour and energy to both, and the sovereignty crowned the constitution with authority and dignity (XXIX, 414). It was unthinkable to diminish the roles of monarchy or aristocracy but, at the same time, the positive function of democracy in the mixed constitution remained equally unquestionable. Unlike the French con- cept of the sovereignty of the people, the monarchy remained the sole possessor of sovereignty in the British system. Pitt’s constitutional views remained consistent: thanks to their mixed form of government, the British “felt the blessings of monarchy, aristocracy, and democ- racy all united.” (XXIX, 415) Aristocracy was represented as a force supporting democracy against monarchy and democracy as a source of dynamism for the entire political community. Th ough viewing democracy as no more than an element of the mixed constitution, Pitt 372 chapter five remained convinced of its positive eff ects. In spring 1791, his constitu- tional views had hardly yet been changed by the French Revolution. Th e debates on the new constitution for Quebec constituted the con- text for a kind of negotiation between the members of parliament on how democracy was to be understood in the aft ermath of the French Revolution. “Democratic principles” were almost exclusively associated with French revolutionary ideas, particularly aft er members who had been accused of harbouring them did their best to demonstrate that they did not support such ideas. For Burke, in particular, “democratic principles” remained a set of ideas to be rejected. He denied denigrat- ing Fox’s image by accusing him of the advocacy of such ideas; how- ever, he did not exclude the possibility that Fox held such principles anyway. Burke stated that he continued to hold the same views on the French regime that he had put forward in his book: France was not a republic but a mere monster (XXIX, 417–419, 423). Even if a regulated democratic element in the British constitution was seen as necessary by all sides, including Burke, the French type of regime was increasingly viewed as a threat to such a mixed constitution. Th e relations between the democratic, aristocratic and monarchical elements of the constitution also needed to be reconsidered. Accord- ing to Burke, democracy called for a counterbalance so that aristocracy would be allied with monarchy rather than with democracy: In a monarchy the aristocracy must ever be nearer to the crown than to the democracy, because it originated in the crown as the fountain of honour; but in those governments which partook not of any thing monarchical, the aristocracy there necessarily sprang out of the democ- racy. In our own constitution undoubtedly, [. . .] our aristocracy was nearer to the crown than the people, because it refl ected the honours of the sovereign (XXIX, 420). Burke opposed an elective council in Canada as that would make it “a democratical council” (XXIX, 420). In Quebec, too, the balanced constitution with three elements should be maintained and nothing resembling a pure democracy should be established.72 Burke implied that some British opposition politicians still advocated political ideas of the French type. Proof could be found in pamphlets

72 Wilberforce put forward the same argument: such an elected body “would be a democracy under another name, and give the popular branch of government too much power.” An aristocracy was a better choice (XXIX, 427). the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 373

“holding out a parade of democracy, in order to irritate a mob against the crown” (XXIX, 422). Democracy based on mob rule appeared as a looming threat, a subversive combination of ideas aimed at provoking the masses against the monarchy. But such revolutionary democracy was to be distinguished from a democratic element, the positive eff ects of which Pitt, Fox and Burke had all emphasized in the 1780s. Justify- ing his current stand in relation to his previous statements in Parlia- ment, Burke argued: [. . .] he now supported the monarchy, not that he thought it better than the aristocracy or the democracy, but because it was attacked and endea- voured to be run down (XXIX, 422).73 Even in the midst of Burke’s criticism of “democratical principles”, it remained essential to recognize the potentially benefi cial eff ects of democracy as an element of the British constitution. In British parlia- mentary culture, as it had been formed in the course of the eighteenth century, it was unthinkable to deny the political role of the popular element completely. It was there, but it had to be completely inte- grated into the structure of the mixed constitution. Defending monarchy and aristocracy at the cost of democracy would have been risky in a political culture in which the popular element was already regarded as a self-evident part of the political system. Th e opposition, including Burke, had for a long time criticized the min- istry for trying to extend the royal prerogative. Fox’s reply to Burke’s defence of the monarchy followed this traditional opposition strategy: “[T]he constitution of this country was more liable to be ruined by an

73 Burke repeated this in a printed text, arguing that the constitution consisted of three elements, all of which should be supported independently of each other. He also added an explicit claim that the Foxites were advocating a new “Whiggism” imported from France. Th e new Whigs made use of a peculiar and mistaken sense of the con- cept of the people, limiting it to refer to “their own faction” only. Th eir concept of sovereignty was perverted as well. While Burke at this stage accepted the notion that sovereignty originated from the people, he rejected ideas that “in the people the same sovereignty constantly and unalienably resides” to such an extent that the people were free to depose kings and change the form of government for any reason. It was like- wise unacceptable to maintain that “the people are essentially their own rule, and their will the measure of their conduct”. Edmund Burke, An Appeal from the New to the Old Whigs, in Consequence of some late Discussions in Parliament, Relative to the Refl ections on the French Revolution (London) [1791], 31, 39−40; Burke was answered by Capel Lofft , who emphasised the accountability of the rulers to the people and questioned the perfection of the combination of “an established monarchy, aristoc- racy, and democracy” in the British constitution. Remarks on the Letter of Rt. Hon. Edmund Burke . . . (Dublin 1791), 45. 374 chapter five increase of the power of the crown, than by an increase of the power of the people” (XXIX, 425). Th e Foxites had by no means rejected language referring to the people despite their attempts to avoid accusa- tions of sympathy for the Revolution. In the fi nal stages of the debate, Fox continued to argue for a more representative council for Canada, demanding “a proper share of democracy” for the country side by side with aristocracy (XXIX, 427). For Fox, democracy remained an ele- ment of the mixed constitution, but one which needed to be strength- ened in comparison with the other two elements, not limited, as Burke suggested. In the Lords, the debate on the Quebec Bill was not so clearly directed against “democratic principles” or extreme “democracy”. William Wyndham, Baron Grenville, pointed out that the Canadian government should not be “democratic” but mixed. Th e latter kind of constitution was much more likely to secure a proper degree of liberty than any other model: It was undoubtedly a mistake to suppose that any government was free only as it approached to democratic principles. Absolute monarchy, absolute aristocracy, absolute democracy, had, in the history of man- kind, been tried in the scale of experience, and had been found wanting (PR, XXX, 225). Th e majority of the British political elite continued to denounce all absolute forms of government, including “absolute democracy”, which was at that time associated with the French version of “democrati- cal principles”. Th e French threat was still seen as modest, however, Britain having declared its neutrality and refusing to join any alliance against France. It remained easy for all sides to retain the positive con- cept of democracy in its regulated British sense. However, the members of parliament had to constantly reconsider their conceptions of democracy. Th e political atmosphere outside Par- liament changed again during the latter half of 1791. In July, a loyalist mob rioted in the name of Church and King to oppose the celebrations of Bastille Day in Birmingham.74 In writings supporting the ministry, the concept of democracy was losing its positive senses in a reaction to the French Revolution and the writings and activities of its supporters in Britain. Th e reactionary response included an interpretation of the British constitution as developing excessively towards democracy as

74 Mori 1997, 91. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 375 a consequence of the misuse of the indefi nite concept of the people and tendencies to favour “an excess of popular power”.75 Th e opposi- tion was represented as having been a source of “democratic intoxica- tion” and “democratic poison” ever since the Wilkite aff air. Th e Foxite group was viewed as representing “the life of democracy” attempting “to render Parliament democratical, and themselves the head of that democracy.”76 In this kind of polemic, democracy was no longer seen so much as a necessary element of the balanced constitution but as an imported subversive and factional plot. It followed that in 1792 “democracy” increasingly became a term of disdain.

Proper British and Extreme French Democracy Contrasted in 1792

Th e French Revolution had turned out to be something else than a supportable struggle for the British kind of liberty. Th e concept of the people was defi ned in France in ways that challenged many of the basic premises of British parliamentary discourse. In Speeches from the Th rone, Pitt’s ministry decided to avoid the use of the concepts of the people and the nation altogether and in January 1792 advised the King to refer instead to “my subjects” (XXIX, 745–746, 787). Th e revolutionary potential of language referring to the people was thus recognized indirectly: no appeals to the people were to be made in a country which increasingly regarded itself as being engaged in a struggle against an extreme form of popular rule. Th e offi cial truth was that the established constitution ensured both liberty and order in the realm. Th e reactions of the two houses to the Royal Speech were more diverse than previously, refl ecting both concern and ideological dis- agreements. In the Lords, David Murray, Viscount Stormont and the Earl of Mansfi eld, a Scot who had made a long career in the diplomatic service, rejected what he saw as “modern reforms” propagated in printed literature and public meetings, and he emphasized the united character of the voice of Parliament and the people (XXIX, 749). Th ere

75 Rice Hughes, A Letter on the Meeting at the Crown and Anchor Tavern, on the Fourteenth of July, 1791, for the Purpose of Celebrating the Anniversary of the Revolu- tion in France . . . (London) [1791], 27–28. 76 [Common Sense], A Letter from Common Sense, Addressed to the King and People (London) [1791], 6, 25. 376 chapter five was a slight change here in that Parliament as a whole was seen to be communicating the unanimous voice of ‘the people’, no longer that of the King’s people. Grenville also opposed constitutional innovations by appealing to the voice of the people, which declared: “Our constitution shall be immutable” (XXIX, 749). Th e Lords’ Address was obviously formulated for the general public rather than for the ministry alone. In it, all references to the people were replaced with the traditionalist concept of subjects, just as in the Royal Speech. All of this suggests an awareness of the new kind of political potential which the Revolution had given to the concept of the people. Th e Commons likewise refrained from making any reference to the people or the nation. Only two Foxites used politically signifi cant senses of the concept during the debate. Charles Grey, an active mem- ber of the Whig Friends of the People (an exclusive reform association whose revolutionary name made it sound as more dangerous than it actually was), proposed a reference to the royal care for the people’s happiness, but this was rejected (XXIX, 761). Fox suggested that the Royal Speech made the people believe that the King wished to decrease taxation whereas their representatives did not. Fox could not accept the idea of the ministry appealing to the people and bypassing Parlia- ment, to the detriment of the latter (XXIX, 772). Th e events of 1792 forced the ministry to take an ever fi rmer stand on the Revolution. Associations like the London Corresponding Soci- ety and the Friends of the People were founded in 1792 to campaign for parliamentary reform. Th eir demands entered parliamentary debates in the form of renewed proposals for a reform of Parliament. Printed literature occasionally made the challenge quite explicit: in the free propaganda of the Corresponding Society, the Commons was presented as “so frequently and so falsely called the Democracy of the Nation”.77 Th is claim disputed Blackstone’s defi nition of the Commons as a synonym for the democratic element of the British constitution. Even among the reformists, we fi nd the Duke of Richmond wishing to avoid a situation in which the Commons was “reduced to its natu- ral dependence on the people alone” as that would make the system approach “a pure democracy”. A mixture of the democratic, aristocratic

77 Th e London Corresponding Society’s Addresses and Resolutions, (Reprinted, and Distributed Gratis.) (London) [1792], 8. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 377 and monarchical elements remained preferable despite the need for a parliamentary reform aiming at “universal representation”.78 Authors loyal to the established order replied with an anonymous treatise on “democracy in practice against democracy in principle”. Th e propagation of reform was rejected by emphasizing the inability of the majority of the nation to be virtuous and wise and the impos- sibility of achieving “a perfect national representation”. According to an anonymous writer, the British constitution diff ered radically from democracy and avoided “the spirit of democracy”, as had been wit- nessed during the Civil Wars. In dangerous times, the extremes of absolutism and democracy were to be avoided and the combination of the three elements retained in opposition to “democratic opinions”.79 At the same time, popular action against radicalism was also growing, with the loyalist mob on the move. Th e nation was becoming divided in its attitudes towards revolutionary France, the great majority having become highly suspicious of the country across the Channel.80 Th e most radical views were propagated in the widely circulated second part of Paine’s Rights of Man, published in February 179281 and commented on by members of parliament and a number of authors. Paine’s book took the escalating debate between radicals and loyal- ists one step further. An anonymous pamphleteer supporting a par- liamentary reform claimed that Burke had fi rst introduced the French revolutionary debate into Britain with his book in 1790 and that Paine had reacted to what Burke had claimed, and his book, being widely read, had given rise to such grievances among the people that had not

78 Charles Lennox, Duke of Richmond and Lennox, A Letter from His Grace the Duke of Richmond to Lieutenant Colonel Sharman, Chairman to the Committee of Cor- respondence . . . (London 1792), 11; Richmond’s ideas on parliamentary reform con- tinued to provoke reactions as late as 1794. An anonymous pamphleteer then argued that his revolutionary ideas about universal suff rage and shorter parliaments would “promote the confusion and horrors of Democracy, by giving equality to the thought- less, restless and tyrannic Multitude”. It was, aft er all, the tendency of democracy “under colour of the best principles to produce the greatest confusion and mischief, not knowing where to stop when the great Body of the People is raised and has gained an ascendancy.” [Anon.], An Answer to the celebrated Letter of the Duke of Richmond on a Parliamentary Reform . . . (London 1794), 22, 25. 79 [Anon.], Remarks on the Proceedings of the Society, who Style Th emselves “Th e Friends of the People”: and Observations on the Principles of Government, as Applicable to the British Constitution . . . (London 1792), 17–18, 31, 49, 54, 63. 80 Evans 1996, 3; Mori 2000, 31. 81 Th e highest estimate is 200,000 copies and twice that number of readers. Dick- inson 1995, 243. 378 chapter five

previously existed. It had supported the rise of “democratic societies” and the emergence of a “democratic” party, which in turn was chal- lenging the ruling elite to such an extent that a civil war loomed as a likely end result. Th is author did not see “a democracy” as the way out of the crisis. It would be better to wait and see what happened with “the bold experiment of a democracy extending over a large country; that of America, that of France”. To avoid the risk of experiencing a revolution in Britain, it was, however, important to proceed to “imme- diate and radical reforms”.82 Paine extolled “the democracy of the Athenians” even though he recognized that it had degenerated as a result of the growth of the state and the lack of the modern idea of representation. A major fail- ure in Burke’s reasoning on democracy was that he could not distin- guish between such simple democracy and representation, which was a modern idea. Burke could not see that representative government constituted a fourth form of government that could solve the problems of simple democracy.83 According to Paine: By integrating representation upon democracy, we arrive at a system of government capable of embracing and confederating all the various interests and every extent of territory and population.84 Th is was truly an unconventional defi nition of both democracy and representation.85 Increasingly modern concepts of an active sover- eignty of the people and dynamic democracy were clearly emerging in Paine’s thinking.86 Paine also presented an interpretation of the American Republic as democracy, as “representation ingraft ed upon democracy” and as a model for all other nations.87 For him, the republican government of

82 [Anon.], Is All We Want Worth a Civil War? Or Conciliatory Th oughts upon the Present Crisis (London 1792), 10, 19, 22, 32. 83 Th omas Paine, Rights of Man. Part the Second. Combining Principle and Practice, . . . Th e second edition (London 1792), 28–29. 84 Paine, Rights of Man, 1792, 33. 85 Cf. William White, who regarded representation as a modern and noble improve- ment but saw it as productive of “a popular form, in contradiction to the democratical, in which the people acting collectively acted generally with violence”. A Dissertation on Government, with the Balance Considered; or, a Free Enquiry into the Nature of the Constitution, and the Probable Eff ect of a Parliamentary Reform (London 1792), 18. 86 Dickinson 1995, 173. 87 Th omas Paine, Rights of Man. Part the Second, 33; References to “American democracy” had already been made in France in 1789. Dippel 1986, 72. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 379 the United States was an updated version of Athenian democracy.88 Its combination of democracy and representation was simple and prac- tical for any national context and avoided the risks connected with either monarchy or simple democracy.89 Th is was an interpretation that neither the Americans nor the British readily accepted; yet Paine’s innovation certainly changed the nature of the debate on democracy. He openly advocated a democratic republic based on representa- tion over a representative government with monarchy, whether in its French (until the autumn of 1792) or its British form.90 Obviously, Paine’s understanding of democracy was no longer derived from the classical concept of direct democracy; he argued for the combination of democracy and representation into a system that was later to be known as “representative democracy”.91 Paine’s claims were generally rejected in British public discourse. By the time of the trial against his book, which took place in December 1792, when war against France already looked likely, the existence of two distinct concepts of democracy in Britain had become ever more apparent. Th e Attorney General accused Paine of “not considering that the Constitution possesses such an infusion of the spirit of democracy, as prevents either monarchy or aristocracy from exercising the pow- ers of tyranny”,92 in other words, of ignoring that there was already a “spirit of democracy” in the British system. But democracy in its British form was limited, as the attorney continued: “[. . .] this Consti- tution possesses a very powerful infusion of democracy; but our Gov- ernment is not entirely democratic; God forbid that it should be!” No pure democracy was conceivable: Hobbes had been right in describ- ing democracy as “an aristocracy of orators, interrupted sometimes by

88 Parker 1953, 224; Markoff 1999, 670; Dunn, 113. 89 Dunn 2005, 113. 90 Urbinati 2006, 167. 91 Palmer 1953, 223–224; Dunn 2005, 112. 92 Th e Trial of Th omas Paine, for Certain False, Wicked, Scandalous and Seditious Libels Inserted in the Second Part of the Rights of Man, Before the Right Hon. Lord Kenyon and a Special Jury, at Guildhall, on Tuesday the 18th December, 1792. Taken in Short Hand by an Eminent Advocate. Original Edition, Copied from the Minutes Taken in Court (London), [1792], 20; Another way to put the same point was to argue that the freedom of the English “consists in their enjoying all the advantages of democracy” with some elements of monarchy as well. Oliver Goldsmith, Th e Citizen of the World; or, Letters from a Chinese Philosopher Residing in London to his Friends in the East . . . (London 1792), Vol. 1, 260. 380 chapter five the monarchy of one orator.”93 It was likewise a libel by Paine not to consider the other necessary elements of the constitution and to extol only democracy: Democracy is his sole delight. To democracy are all his raptures con- fi ned; [. . .] to democracy is to be attributed all the advantages that have accrued to man from the foundation of the world.94 Th ere was evidence from America demonstrating that Paine had been planning to “convene the people of Great Britain [. . .] to establish a Government proceeding directly from the sovereignty of the people”.95 In December 1792, it had become criminal to argue so outspokenly in favour of unlimited democracy and the sovereignty of the people in the printed media. Th is would not prevent members of parliament from doing the same in Parliament, of course, as we shall soon see. Indeed, a public debate that was curtailed by judicial means could be continued under the protection of parliamentary immunity by a few daring radicals. Th e debates of spring 1792 on the possibility of a parliamentary reform provide further evidence of an ongoing conceptual change in Britain caused by the radicalization of the Revolution in France. Dis- appointed in their hopes for cooperation with Louis XVI, the revo- lutionaries were increasingly using “democracy” as their slogan. As a result of the anti-monarchical nature of the emerging French concept of democracy, the pejorative connotations of “democratical principles” tended to strengthen further in Britain. Several attempts at parliamentary reform had been made in the early 1780s and in 1790, sometimes with statements openly defend- ing the democratic element of the constitution, but they had met with no success. In spring 1792, radical societies were active and were able to persuade Grey among the Foxites to bring up the possibility of a moderate reform in the Commons. Grey was a founding member of the Society of the Friends of the People. He and his associates were no supporters of Paine or French revolutionary extremes, but his opponents hardly drew such distinctions. Quite soon, Grey’s activities

93 Th e Trial of Th omas Paine, 1792, 26. 94 Th e Trial of Th omas Paine, 1792, 25. 95 Th e Trial of Th omas Paine, 1792, 32. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 381 appeared unwise even in Fox’s eyes.96 Given Paine’s book and the rise of anti-monarchical democracy in France, an interesting question is whether Grey’s group dared to associate their reform proposal with the concept of democracy. In fact, Grey chose to use language that recalled the reformist dis- course of the early 1780s rather than that of the 1790s. Th e language of democracy in the revolutionary sense was absent in his introduc- tion to the motion. Grey maintained, however, that the people were calling more actively than ever for a reform, in the hope of saving the constitution. “Th e minds of the people” were “agitated” and hence “a true representation of the people” should fi nally be established (XXIX, 1300–1301). Pitt’s immediate reply shows that the Prime Minister continued to take democracy seriously as an element of the constitution, even if he was unwilling to increase the relative weight of democracy in the cur- rent state of international aff airs. Considering the implementation of a parliamentary reform to be impossible without the risk of anarchy, Pitt expressed his support for the reform in principal and suggested that it could be discussed at a more appropriate time (XXIX, 1302– 1309).97 Even in April 1792, the leadership of the British government seemed to be open to the possibility of reform, at least at the level of parliamentary rhetoric. Pitt was not content with recognizing the centrality of a democratic element in the constitution but deliberately defi ned the British sys- tem as a model supporting “proper democracy” with “a representative assembly”.98 Th is re-description of the British representative political

96 Smith 2004; Th e leaders of this society included Lauderdale, Grey, Sheridan, Francis, Erskine and Whitbread. Cannon 1994, 122. 97 Counter-arguments were soon presented in the press. According to the radical James Mackintosh, an immediate reform was indispensable to prepare the constitu- tion for the likely rise of either “the spirit of extreme Democracy” or despotism in Europe as a consequence of the French Revolution. Th e reform would reinvigorate “the democratic part of the Constitution” and prevent popular discontent motivated by “the fascinating example of their superb Democracy” in France. It would also pre- vent the constitution from changing into “a pure Democracy” of a tumultuous kind and, with the maintenance of monarchy and aristocracy, curb “the most magnifi cent and seductive visions of democratic enthusiasm”. In brief, parliamentary reform was needed in order to stop the progress of the wrong kind of democracy. A Letter to the Right Honourable William Pitt, on his Apostacy from the Cause of Parliamentary Reform . . . (London 1792), 30, 32–34. 98 Pitt was also thanked for uniting the King and the people so that he “has directed the sceptre of the crown, and wielded the shield of democracy” in an anonymous 382 chapter five system was a direct reply to Paine and to the emerging French con- stitutional alternative of representative democracy. It emerged out of a combination of already revaluated, positive conceptions of democ- racy and representation in the mixed constitution that Pitt himself had helped to mould in the early 1780s. While providing a rhetorical re-description designed to maintain the status quo in Britain, Pitt’s formulation actually contained elements of the emerging revolution- ary notion of ‘representative democracy’. Paine had presented a more radical interpretation of related ideas, and Robespierre would take the idea to the extreme in less than two years time. Aft er his defi nition of the British political order in seemingly revolutionary vocabulary, Pitt distanced himself from parliamentary reform and presented Grey’s proposal as a mere unhelpful questioning of an already existing demo- cratic and representative system. Pitt presented himself as a defender of democracy, understood in the sense of the trust of the people being placed in their representatives: [. . .] he was sorry to confess, that there were persons who thought that the people were not adequately represented in parliament. It was essen- tial to the happiness of the people, that they should be convinced that they, and the members of that House, felt an identity of interest: that the nation at large, and the representatives of the people, held a conformity of sentiment: this was the essence of a proper representative assembly; under this legitimate authority, a people could be said to be really free; and this was a state in which the true spirit of proper democracy could be said to subsist (XXIX, 1309). Pitt’s formulation emphasized the ideal character of the British repre- sentative system and the need of the political elite to maintain the trust of the people in it. Pitt interpreted the British political order as one combining representation and democracy of the right type. Th ere was, he implied, a diff erence between “the nation at large” and “the people” who were truly represented in Parliament, but even so “the true spirit of proper democracy” was included in the system. In defending the British form of government as allowing for a “proper democracy”, Pitt was providing an alternative to the mistaken “liberty” of the French revolutionary regime. As the head of government, he was, for the time being, forced to argue that reform was not possible. Pitt concluded his pamphlet, “democracy” appearing here in the positive sense consistently given to it by the Prime Minister. [Member of the Jockey Club], An Answer to Th ree Scurrilous Pamphlets, Entitled Th e Jockey Club. Th e second edition (London ) [1792], 119. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 383 speech with harsh condemnations of opposition papers and meetings agitating the people to complain about the form of government at a time when such complaints were inappropriate. Th e unique strength of the British system constituted by the three elements of the con- stitution was not to be questioned in 1792 (XXIX, 1310–1312). Th e danger was that French anarchy might enter Britain as a result of such agitation. Pitt is known not to have been particularly alarmed by the French threat in the spring of 1792, but he warned Parliament about it anyway.99 What could the opposition do to counter the ministerial defi nition of the current state of representation as suffi cient to guarantee “the true spirit of proper democracy”? Fox responded with language refer- ring to the people, not with any programmatic concept of democracy. He suggested that there was desire for a reform among the public and that his party, unlike Pitt’s supporters, remained consistently in favour of one. Measures “to quiet the minds of the people” who were unhappy with the current policies and their lack of representation were needed, Fox maintained, emphasizing the role of the Commons as “the organ of the public voice”. However, Paine’s model was not to be followed; Fox denounced the latter’s approach as mere abuse of the British form of government by a foreigner.100 But a reform was essential: the very essence of the British constitution was its openness to innovation, improvement and reform. Fox’s overall picture of the state of aff airs remained much more optimistic than that of the other speakers: he continued to be convinced that liberty was making progress in France, Poland and America. Britain, to join this trend of improvement, now needed to introduce a parliamentary reform (XXIX, 1313–1317). Burke again became the major opponent of the Foxites. He main- tained that the calls for reform did not genuinely arise from among the people but were a result of agitation by the leaders of the opposition. Burke saw no evidence to demonstrate the truth of Fox’s interpreta- tion of “the public voice” or “the sense of the people”. In Burke’s view, the Commons always remained a platform of confrontation for the political establishment rather than the people at large:

99 Christie 1982, 212. 100 According to Mitchell, Fox was as critical of Paine’s book as Burke. Mitchell 2004. 384 chapter five

Let democracy get to its greatest extent in this country, or in that House, still it would be found that there were, and would continue to be, great men in that House upon diff erent sides of any question, that must and ought to have infl uence (XXIX, 1319–1320). Burke also pointed out the risks of activating the people excessively in the name of reform and innovation: What would the opposition leaders do when, as in France, “the ideas of the people, may probably carry them to an ungovernable length, upon a subject of which they understand so little?” Th e risk would be particularly grave if the rep- resentation of the people was changed. Paine’s book in particular, with its unfounded accusations of “a conspiracy against the privileges of the people”, was not to be recommended. Such a recommendation alone was for Burke an attack on the constitution (XXIX, 1320–1322).101 William Windham opposed the reform scheme by echoing Burke, emphasizing the diversity of views among the people aft er a mixed public debate (XXIX, 1325–1326). Having visited Paris in September 1791, he had been converted to Burkean views on the necessity to curtail the progress of French ideas. Henry Dundas, again, accused Fox and his allies of intentionally trying to “excite the people” (XXIX, 1337). Th omas Erskine, Fox’s ally and a rival of the Dundas family, argued that the intention of the constitution was that the Commons “should be a representation of the people” whereas that was not currently the case, as “the sense of the House and the people were diametrically opposite” in questions of foreign policy. Th e risk involved in not reforming the system was popular activism: “[W]hen the people began to act for themselves, it was to be feared, that their demand might not be so reasonable as at present” (XXIX, 1328–1330). According to M.S. Taylor, “it was necessary to go back to the people, and under the sanction of their authority to compel that House to do its duty” (XXIX, 1338). Th is statement placed the people above Parliament in an unconventional and downright radical way. Th e radicals obviously had

101 Th omas Cooper also replied to Burke in the public sphere, citing French ideas of the rulers being “no more than the Delegates of a Democracy”. A Reply to Mr. Burke’s Invective Against Mr. Cooper, and Mr. Watt, in the House of Commons, on the 30th of April, 1792 (London 1792), 55. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 385 no hesitation in exploiting the fears of revolutionary developments in their calls for reform. Sheridan, a member of the Society of the Friends of the People, challenged Pitt’s inconsistent opinions about reform. Th e Prime Min- ister seemed to change his views according to his current ambitions, advancing either the royal prerogative (in 1784) or joining “the wild- est advocates of democracy” (referring to the reform proposals of the early 1780s) (XXIX, 1334). Th e provocation was a pre-planned one, suggesting that Pitt had, contrary to his claims in the 1780s, aban- doned the democratic element in the constitution. Sheridan also made a pertinent observation about how the concept of the people tended to be used by speakers in Parliament: “Just as it answered the purpose for argument the people were lowered or exalted” (XXIX, 1334). Both concepts, democracy and the people, had become contestable in the Commons, though their meanings were still to a great extent deter- mined by the legacy of the reform debates of the 1780s rather than by some French revolutionary principles. Even if the anti-monarchical, republican and outspokenly “demo- cratic” nature of the French Revolution was challenging previous understandings of the democratic element in Britain in 1792, democ- racy continued to be discussed in favourable terms by some peers. Alexander Wedderburn, Lord Loughborough and the Earl of Ross- lyn, defi ned the British system in May conventionally as “a monarchy, something of an aristocracy, and a sober and temperate democracy” (PR, XXX, 207). Th e positive element of democracy was thus included, recognized by a nobleman who had recently moved from the oppo- sition to become a member of Pitt’s wartime cabinet. Lansdowne (Shelburne), known for his original use of language, found democracy in the British nobility in that while a seat in the Upper House was inherited by the oldest son, the younger sons could be elected to the Commons. As a consequence of this practice, “a degree of democracy was necessarily infused in every noble family throughout the kingdom, and the general interest united and strengthened” (PR, XXXIII, 442). It was this noble combination of aristocracy and democracy, familiar to Lansdowne thanks to his experience in both houses, that made the British system so strong. Lansdowne’s statement shows a disregard of French revolutionary conceptions of a necessary antithesis between aristocracy and democracy. Lansdowne had contacts with Mirabeau, Talleyrand and other French revolutionary aristocrats and obviously 386 chapter five continued to believe that the French Revolution was ultimately leading towards a peaceful system resembling the British one.102 Not all aristocrats were so unconcerned. Charles Townshend, the Baron of Bayning, a Portland Whig, expressed his disgust at what he saw as the absurd doctrines and socially levelling practices of the time, referring to annual parliaments and extended suff rage in particular. Th e lengthy disputes on contested elections demonstrated to him what excessively frequent voting led to: the British would soon “have no Parliament at all, but a democratic Government of the streets” (PR, Vol. 33, 476). “Democratic government” stood for mob action, and that was defi nitely something that the political elite rejected. Lans- downe countered Bayning by referring explicitly to d’Argenson and demanding the municipal regulation of popular disturbances. In his view, “this was no doctrine of wild democracy—it was a doctrine set forth by an aristocratic author” (PR, XXXIII, 479). D’Argenson pro- vided the equally unconventional Lansdowne with a means to argue that the British people would defend the constitution in case of any uprisings. And he urged the nobility not to oppose public opinion and ally themselves with the monarchy against the people. Such an unwise action would only strengthen calls for the rights of the people (PR, XXXIII, 479, 482). Lansdowne had welcomed the French nobility joining the Th ird Estate103 and obviously wished to see a similar union between the aristocracy and the people in Britain. Th ough politically marginal, Lansdowne’s reasoning demonstrates how some reconsid- eration of the constitution was going on among members of the Brit- ish high nobility as well. Lansdowne’s unconventional way of thinking led him to join the diminishing group of Foxite sympathizers with the Revolution in the Lords.104 In the meantime, the events of autumn 1792 in France, which led to the radicalization and internationalization of the Revolution, caused the Pitt ministry to publicly adopt an anti-revolutionary policy. Th e monarchy was vulnerable in France, and ideas about the permanent sovereignty of people as opposed to the original sovereignty of the people were rising. Th e relations of the two powers were deteriorat- ing towards an open confl ict, the intentions of the French exiles in

102 Cannon 2004. 103 Cannon 2004. 104 Cannon 2004. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 387

London were suspect, and British radical societies gave cause for con- cern with their campaigns for parliamentary reform and suggestions that violent means could also be used bring it about.105 Francophile comments were seen as alarming, as British accounts and translations of French texts communicated pejorative images of violence, absurd ideas and warning precedents which the notion of “the sovereignty of the people” seemed to be inspiring on the Continent.106 Attacks on the monarchy and the church in France caused deep disgust and fear among a great majority of Britons. As a consequence, Pitt adopted a policy that aimed at combining the support of the landowning, indus- trial, commercial and Anglican elements of the British establishment with an ideological defence of the established political and religious order.107 Th e notion of ‘the sovereignty of the people’, one of the major ideo- logical innovations of the Revolution, also found its way into Brit- ish parliamentary debates in late 1792, aft er the monarchy had been abolished in France, “direct democracy” adopted in Paris, the French Republic declared, and the trial of Louis XVI started. Th e balance of power on the Continent seemed to be threatened as well, particularly aft er the new National Convention declared its support for peoples attempting to restore their liberty.108 Th is second revolution in France, the rise of the Jacobin republic, also changed the meaning of the con- cept of democracy in ever more radical directions. All previous asso- ciations between democracy and monarchy were abolished and those between democracy and equality emphasized instead.109 A war between the two countries already seemed unavoidable. Th ese confrontations initiated a new stage in the history of the con- cept of democracy in Parliament. When Parliament was opened on 13 December 1792, the state of aff airs led to the reintroduction in royal speaking of vocabulary referring to the people and the nation, with

105 Palmer 1964, 35; Mori 1997, 108; Rosanvallon 2000, 53; Royle 2000, 16–17; Monnier 2002, 401. 106 See [Anon.], An Historical Sketch of the French Revolution from its Commence- ment to the Year 1792 (Dublin 1792), 161, 273; Jacques Necker, An Essay on the True Principles of Executive Power in Great States . . . (London, 1792), Vol. 1, 388; Vol. 2, 136; [Anon.], Th e Misfortunes of Geneva; or, a Picture of the Calamities that Th reaten, in the Present Crisis, the most Moderate Governments of Europe . . . (London) [1792], 7, 19, 29, 40. 107 O’Gorman 1989, 28, 34. 108 Christie 1982, 215–216. 109 Dippel 1986, 78–79. 388 chapter five an emphasis on their union with the Crown (XXIX, 1556). An idea of a monarchy supported by a people through the institutions of a popular government was constructed with statements such as: “Our joint eff orts will, I doubt not, be rendered completely eff ectual, by the decided support of a free and loyal people” (XXIX, 1559). Despite the grave state of aff airs, Lansdowne, now Pitt’s leading opponent in the Lords, protested against the way in which the current Parliament had been belatedly convened and addressed the necessity of reforming representation in order to conciliate “the people”. “If the people called for a parliamentary reform, he thought the House of Commons, [. . .] should [. . .] hear them constitutionally state their grievances” (XXIX, 1569). Th is was all the more necessary because, according to Lans- downe, “the people were too enlightened to be blindfolded” (XXIX, 1569). Lansdowne’s speech acted as a catalyst in the debate, as he was known to have connections with French revolutionaries and British radical societies. Grenville, a government spokesman, next attacked societies that had contacted the National Convention with the suspected inten- tion of superseding the British Parliament and establishing a British Convention “as the only genuine organ of representation.” By doing so they had questioned the status of the King as “the representative of the people” in foreign aff airs (XXIX, 1570).110 Grenville’s defi nition of the monarchy was similarly provocative in its traditionalism, seeing the monarch as the representative of the people. Th e threat of war and the activities of the Corresponding Societ- ies brought revolutionary concepts into the British Parliament among both the minority who called for parliamentary reform and the major- ity who opposed all developments that could be interpreted as origi- nating from the French Revolution. Stormont, who knew French intellectual currents well aft er working as Ambassador in Paris and as Foreign Secretary in London, quoted Condorcet in order to dem- onstrate the threat which the French revolutionaries and their mis- led advocates in Britain—“levellers” as he called them with reference to the 1640s—presented to the security of the British constitution. Condorcet’s advice to the Dutch, recommending the establishment of

110 Th e said Convention, associated both with the Convention of 1689 and that of France, was actually holding its meeting in Edinburgh on 11–13 December 1792. Royle 2000, 17. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 389

“a democracy like that of France”, proved to Stormont that the French aimed at destroying all limited hereditary monarchy. Th is was against the sentiments of Parliament and “a vast majority of the people” of Britain. Fortunately, according to him, the French had no chance of succeeding in Britain thanks to the universal adherence there to the most balanced constitution that ever existed (XXIX, 1571–1572). Stor- mont himself was moving from the opposition to become a supporter of Pitt’s ministry at this time, in recompense for which he was fi nally given offi ce. In their Address, the Commons confi rmed “the decided support of a free and loyal people” (XXX, 8), though considerable criticism of the formulations of the Royal Speech was presented during the debates. John Henry Petty, the Earl of Wycombe, argued that the speech had “calumniated the people of England” as it had made unfounded sug- gestions of a planned rebellion by the radical societies. Ministerial claims about the constitution being in danger had no justifi cation as it was essentially “the government of the people’s choice” (XXX, 10). Th e sharpest critic of the ministry’s policy was Fox, however, who saw its attack on the radical societies as “an intolerable calumny on the people of Great Britain” (XXX, 13–14). Emphasizing “the rights of the people” as the foundation of all government, he insisted on the right to speculate as necessary over “our liberties as a people” and argued that the power of the Hanoverians, too, originated “from the choice of the people” and “the will of the many” (XXX, 19, 21–22). As for the Commons, it should demonstrate that it represented every individual Briton even if not everyone was allowed to participate in elections. Th e problem with the current ministry was that it had, according to Fox, made every attempt to make the people lose their trust in the Com- mons, trying to show that it “is not the true representative and organ of the people” and thus decreasing its power (XXX, 30, 32–33). Grey was another opposition speaker who referred to the politi- cal role of the people. Th is major proponent of parliamentary reform could not believe in the possibility that the people would reject the constitution. In his view, the grievances of the people should rather be solved with reforms (XXX, 41). Erskine also joined in the argument, suggesting that the whole panic over the danger to the constitution had emerged only aft er the opposition had called for the extension of the representation of the people (XXX, 56). Fox again returned to his favourite topic of the rights of the people, suggesting that the only free 390 chapter five government was one which the people regarded as such (XXX, 61). Th e Foxite opposition was actively applying language referring to the people against the ministry despite the risk of being associated with the French republicans. Two days later, Fox’s motion for negotiations with the French republican regime initiated a further exchange of views on democracy and the current French form of government. Th e concept of the sover- eignty of the people, which had been central in revolutionary rhetoric for some time, appeared for the fi rst time in the British Parliament during this debate. A stand on the sovereignty of the people had to be taken aft er the French had publicly recommended its introduction into the British system as well. A reasoned debate was not possible under the threat of a military confrontation, however; the idea of popular sovereignty was simply condemned by an overwhelming majority. Fox hardly intended to instigate a constitutional debate on the political role of the people, but even his suggestion for reconciliation irritated his opponents, causing them to reveal that their animosity towards France arose increasingly out of its constitutional development. Fox also made himself a target of accusations of poisoning the minds of the people with sedition (XXX, 82). North rejected Fox’s attempt to infl uence foreign policy as questioning the royal prerogative and dis- missed the motion to negotiate with the French National Convention as unthinkable aft er this organ had declared the British “an oppressed people” whom the revolutionaries should assist to recover their liberty (XXX, 86). Robert Jenkinson, a 21-year-old eyewitness of 14 July 1789 in Paris and an opponent of the Revolution ever since, denounced all cooperation with France, which was a “natural enemy and rival” irrespective of its form of government. Jenkinson warned particularly that the recognition of the French regime by the Commons, as dis- tinct from George III, would give “a sort of oblique confi rmation of the justness of their principles, in the democratic appearance it would have” (XXX, 87, 90). Th e Commons could not be associated with the revolutionary regime in a way that could be viewed as “democratic”; it would lead to the type of internal confrontation which the revolution- aries had been insinuating already existed in Britain. William Wind- ham went further, maintaining that even if “the temper and feelings of the people” must be consulted in a free government, that was not the case in decisions on war and peace (XXX, 102). In his eyes, the situation was so grave that he denounced cooperation with Fox and changed sides to support Pitt instead. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 391

Th e support for the Foxites was evaporating, although Samuel Whitbread II, a defender of the Friends of the People, still empha- sized the role of the people in decision-making. Whitbread attempted to defi ne his political creed in a seemingly conventional manner: “[H]e loved the monarchy, he loved the aristocracy; above all he loved the democracy of this country; but he had no attachment to abuses in any department” (XXX, 102, 105). Even this appeared to many not as just an appropriate defence of the democratic element but as an attempt to introduce an extension of democracy into the country. Whitbread’s distinction between British democracy and the French revolutionary regime was unlikely to be understood in sympathetic terms in the cir- cumstances of December 1792. Aft er Whitbread had invoked ‘democracy’, his opponents responded by taking up the concept of the sovereignty of the people. Sir William Grant, a lawyer, initiated the criticism of this principle by referring to a transition from monarchical despotism into “the still more wild and unlimited despotism of the people” in France (XXX, 106). Burke next declared the sovereignty of the people to be the most pernicious element of the French regime. Th e radicalization of the French Revo- lution was leading to a denunciation of all associations between the British constitution and the sovereignty of the people, which was seen as an essentially French doctrine. No British parliamentarian had pre- viously spoken explicitly about the sovereignty of the people;111 now Burke employed the concept only to denounce it as a new doctrine totally inconsistent with the British constitution. Th e pejorative con- tent attributed to the concept was overwhelming. Pointing to the treat- ment of Continental monarchs and contrasting this with the British monarch, who was loved by his people, Burke declared: “Kings are anointed with oil—the new sovereignty of the people with blood!” (XXX, 108, 111). Burke did add an important qualifi cation, however: he spoke specifi cally about “the new sovereignty of the people”, thus implying that the French had reinterpreted the sovereignty of the peo- ple wrongly. Even in the heat of the debate, Burke was not denying the

111 As we saw in the Introduction, a number of scholars focusing on the seventeenth century have suggested that the concept of popular sovereignty had already become established in British political culture in the 1640s. However, no defi nite concept of the sovereignty of the people existed in British parliamentary discourse before 1792. See also Quentin Skinner’s criticism of the interpretation of the Levellers as champi- ons of democracy in Skinner 2002, 76. 392 chapter five popular origin of political power as a theoretical assumption; he only questioned the French innovation and was ready to fi ght a war against the regime that had introduced it (XXX, 112, 115). Views on the political role of the people divided the House: Burke’s speech was interrupted by Th omas Whitmore. Sheridan attempted to reply to Burke with the irony befi tting a dramatist. In his words: “Th ese gentlemen must have all the democratic metaphysicians of France extirpated, or they cannot sleep in their beds” (XXX, 121). According to Sheridan, Burke had gone too far in his condemnation of revolutionary and republican ideas, many of which were harmless and even amusing rather than threatening. Sheridan himself rejected war, particularly one fought to restore the French monarchy (XXX, 124–125). Th ere were thus still some who opposed an ideological war against France, but they were waning in strength in the Commons.

Combating both French and Domestic Conceptions of Democracy in 1793

During the next few months, the content of the concept of democracy was redefi ned in a number of debates. Its revolutionary associations with the sovereignty of the people were generally condemned, but the old concept of democracy as an element of the mixed constitution was also defended, at least implicitly. In the midst of a debate on the Alien Bill, for instance, Burke and Fox made points about the political role of the people in the revolutionary world. Burke held the initiative for most of the discussion, looking for an opportunity to say more about the French republican notion of the sovereignty of the people. He considered sovereignty in Britain to be monarchical, not popular, and representation parliamentary, not national: In talking of the English nation, they talked of the sovereignty of the people: the constitution of this country knew no such sovereignty; the king was sovereign of the Lords and of the Commons; the King, Lords, and Commons, were the representatives of the country at home; the king was its only representative abroad. Th ey talked of the nation: we knew of no nation as a distinct body from the representative powers. We talked indeed of the people, but the sovereignty of the people was a phrase not recognized by law, and inconsistent with our constitution (XXX, 184). Burke maintained that the King-in-Parliament, as a representative institution, formed the only imaginable “nation” in Britain; no larger the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 393 nation outside Parliament—contrary to what the opposition had been suggesting—was conceivable. Th e people did have a recognized role in the British system but not as a source of constant sovereignty; sover- eignty in everyday politics could only come from the monarchy. An ideological confrontation was leading to a war between a mixed monarchy and a newly-declared republic based on the principle of the sovereignty of the people. Burke drew the ultimate conclusion that the call of the National Convention for the introduction of the sover- eignty of the people in Britain was, in itself, a declaration of war. War was unavoidable as “the National Convention will not acknowledge any institution derogatory from the sovereignty of the people” (XXX, 184). Burke maintained that the King-in-Parliament held all power in Britain, a power based on popular consent, but this parliamentary system was totally irreconcilable with the French revolutionary con- cept of popular sovereignty. Th e British system was free without such a doctrine: Where the crown had its power enlarged or diminished by the people, according to times and circumstances, there the people could not be justly said to live under despotism, but to be perfectly free (XXX, 188). Aft er the debates of mid-December, the opposition wanted to avoid statements that could be interpreted as treasonous. Without engaging himself in the debate on the sovereignty of the people, Fox expressed his concern about “the word ‘people’ ” being consciously “expunged from our political dictionary” (XXX, 226). Fox further reminded the House of the role which the people should play in the British political system, replying thereby to Richard Philips, the Baron of Milford, who lamented the entry of revolutionary phrases such as “the national will” into the resolutions of some Corresponding Societies and even into reports on parliamentary debates.112 According to Milford, concerned about undesirable linguistic innovations, only Parliament could express the national will, and no more than “the national opinion” could exist beyond it (XXX, 218). Th e role of the people was marginalized in the language of the gov- ernment under the threat of war. Th e attitude of Prime Minister Pitt had changed to the extent that even he now justifi ed preparations for

112 Milford suggested, perhaps in order to deprecate the phrase, that these words may have been inserted into a speech of Th omas Erskine by the reporter. 394 chapter five war with the claim that the French constitution challenged the Brit- ish one. Th e sovereignty of the people and universal representation of the French type were out of the question for the British mixed constitution: Th ey had seen within two or three years a revolution in France, founded upon principles which were inconsistent with every regular govern- ment—which were hostile to hereditary monarchy, to nobility, to all privileged orders, and to every sort of popular representation short of that, which would give to every individual a voice in the election of rep- resentatives (XXX, 232). According to Pitt, the French challenge seemed to be fi nding advo- cates in Britain as a consequence of the propagation of revolutionary ideas (XXX, 232). Aft er Pitt reported to the Commons on 1 February 1793 about the actual opening of hostilities aft er the French declaration of war and call for English republican help, he also addressed the constitutional justifi cation for the war, which, together with references to violence against religion in France, demonstrates the highly ideological motiva- tion of the confrontation.113 Th e war was fought against revolutionary principles, and thus it also aff ected the way in which democracy and the sovereignty of the people were understood. Th e goal, according to Pitt, was to defend the British constitution, which was based on a uniquely happy combination of “the sacred person of the sovereign” with “a mixture of aristocratic and democratical power in the frame of legislation”.114 Th e prevailing system protected the British not only from absolute power but also from “the still more dangerous conta- gion of popular licentiousness”, the destructive character of which had been seen in France (XXX, 270–273)—in the execution of Louis XVI less than two weeks earlier. Pitt was particularly annoyed by the French claims that their imposition of models of government on neigh- bouring nations was “dictated by the will of the people”, which was

113 Christie 1982, 216; Mori 1997, 143. 114 Th e Parliamentary Register had reported in nearly identical terms how the Prime Minister had referred to the monarchy and “the Legislature [. . .] composed of a mixture of democracy and aristocracy”. PR, XXXIV, 386; An off print of the speech gave an identical formulation. William Pitt, Speech of the Right Honourable William Pitt . . . on Friday, Feb. 1, 1793 (London 1793), 8–9. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 395 determined by the National Convention alone (XXX, 278–279, 285). Th e Prime Minister considered that Britain was defending democracy as a classical element of her mixed constitution against the French version of democracy based on the so-called sovereignty of the people and popular representation. She was also fi ghting against the attempt of the French to dominate the rest of Europe. More particularly, the British opposed the French attempt to separate “the king and parlia- ment of Great Britain from the people, who are called republicans” (XXX, 286). Pitt’s war politics did not go entirely unchallenged. Lord Beauchamp reminded Pitt that, in a free country, the Prime Minister “must wait with patience for the will of the people” (XXX, 290). Samuel Whitbread II pointed out that “the national will was supreme in every country”, and that the power of the British monarch was also based on “the will of the nation” (XXX, 296–297). Even if not necessarily intended to be provocative, mentioning “the will of the people” or “the national will” in this context was taken as such by the audience, who hardly missed the introduction of these French conceptual innovations into the Westminster debate. Fox went even further: his reply to Pitt’s announcement constituted a turning point in that he argued that the British political system was also, in principle, based on the sovereignty of the people. Such an argument was an outright provocation, made as it was in the face of the outbreak of war with a regime that advocated the very notion and despite strong opposition to the idea in previous debates. Furthermore, Fox was linked to the need to listen to the people in deciding on war policies. Fox’s claim was hardly moderated by his condemnation of the execution of Louis XVI, and it was certainly reinforced by his claim that Pitt’s war was all about the French form of government. Th is kind of positive characterization of the sovereignty of the people had never been heard in Parliament before. It did not help much that Fox imme- diately applied the phrase to the British regime with references to the Revolution of 1688 and the Succession Settlement of 1701 (XXX, 302, 306–307, 310, two entirely legitimate cases of the people deciding on who should possess executive power. Th e opening of the Revolutionary War thus coincided with the fi rst open claims in the British Parliament that the British constitution was based the sovereignty of the people rather than on the sovereignty of parliament only. Th e course of international aff airs and previous 396 chapter five disputes between Burke and Fox led to the following conceptual revi- sions by Fox, as reported in the written sources:115 [. . .] the people are the sovereign in every state; [. . .] they have a right to change the form of their government, and a right to cashier their gover- nors for misconduct, as the people of this country cashiered James 2nd, not by a parliament, or any regular form known to the constitution, but by a convention speaking the sense of the people; that convention pro- duced a parliament and a king. [. . .] He could not admit the right to do all this but by acknowledging the sovereignty of the people as paramount to all other laws (XXX, 302, 306–307, 310). Fox’s interpretation implied that the British had no right to intervene in French aff airs. But it also meant that the British monarchy was founded on nothing else but “the right and choice of the people”, the reference being to the Revolution Settlement of 1689 and to the Suc- cession Settlement of 1701. Furthermore, Fox maintained, the people had never given their sovereignty away forever (XXX, 310). Or, as another printed version of Fox’s speech stated more explicitly: “[. . .] the present Family enjoyed the throne from the sovereignty of the people.”116 Th e reformulated constitutional stand was that the British constitution, including its monarchy, was derived out of the sover- eignty of the people. Such a notion found few proponents in the public debate in 1793.117

115 In a version of the speech published separately, possibly on Fox’s own initiative, the formulation was slightly more radical in that it referred to individual sovereigns in the Painite fashion and took up the possibility of abolition of the monarchy as well: “Th at the People are the sovereigns in all countries.—Th at they might amend, alter, and abolish the form of government, under which they lived, at pleasure—that they might cashier their monarchs for misconduct.” Charles James Fox, Th e Speeches of the Right Hon. C.J. Fox, in the British House of Commons, on Feb. fi rst and twelft h, M,DCC,XCIII (London 1793), 17. 116 Cartwright, An Appeal, 1799, 17. 117 Fox’s views were echoed by Norman Macleod, a Scottish member: “Th e Con- stitution, as established by its fundamental laws, maintains, that all Sovereignty is derived from the People—that all the powers lodged in the King, Lords, and Com- mons, in Parliament assembled, proceed from the People, and ought to be exercised only for their good.” Macleod also provided a defi nition of the concept of the people as the source of “social authority, the measure of political value, and the pedestal of legitimate power”. Letters from Colonel Macleod, Member of Parliament for Inver- ness-shire, to the Chairman of the Association for Parliamentary Reform in Scotland [London 1793], 6–7; A more traditional application of the notion can be found in [Offi cer], Letter on the Present Associations. . . . (London 1793), 10, according to which the British monarchy constituted a practical application of power being delegated from the people. Th e existence of a king constituted “the Sovereignty and Majesty of the People, which can only remain vague and ideal, till thus collected, as it were, into the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 397

William Windham, who had deserted the Foxites, opposed what he saw as Fox’s approval of “French principles”. Windham’s reactionary Whig group denounced any application of revolutionary principles to the British constitution. Th e people had a say in British politics but not in the spirit of the sovereignty of the people: As to what had been said of the sovereignty of the people, he should at present go no farther into the discussion than to enter his protest against the doctrine, that the people, or a majority, have a right to make and unmake governments according to their caprice; though he admit- ted that it was a general subject of intricate and important discussion (XXX, 315). It would have threatened the war eff ort to open a more extensive constitutional debate and, therefore, Windham chose to pass over Fox’s provocation, branding it as excessive admiration of the already damned French regime. Th e sovereignty of the people was simply not a British principle. Th e Lords, too, were generally critical of the French constitution. According to the Earl of Kimont, there was no real government at all in France “be it of either monarchical, aristocratical, or even demo- cratical form” (PR, XXXVI, 82). Some opposition lords were critical of the British government as well. Stanhope, a former chairman of the Revolution Society, pointed out that the war was not that of “the peo- ple of Great Britain” but that of the Pitt ministry, aimed at the French form of government (XXX, 323). James Maitland, the Earl of Lau- derdale, “professed himself to be one of the people” when expressing compassion for the victims of French counter-revolutionaries (XXX, 326). Lauderdale, a Foxite Scottish representative peer since 1790, had joined the Society of the Friends of the People, visited Paris in the autumn of 1792, met Jacques-Pierre Brissot (a leader of the moder- ate Girondin faction), started to call himself a citizen and to wear a Jacobin costume.118 If there was a single Jacobin in the British Parlia- ment, it was Lauderdale. Parliamentary immunity allowed this radical aristocrat to freely express his views despite the war.

one focus, and so rendered effi cient and permanent.” A third author recognised the sovereignty of the people but insisted on “the will of the people” being controlled as well as the other parts of the constitution. [Anon.], Th e Expediency of a Revolution Considered: In Which the Advantages held out to the People are Examined and Refuted (London 1793), 13. 118 Th orne 2004. 398 chapter five

Fox’s suggestion that the British system was based on the sover- eignty of the people was answered more extensively on 28 February when the Commons met to discuss the alleged existence of seditious practices in the country. Burke had prepared his response well and reacted as soon as the opposition suggested that the government was conspiring against the rights of the people (XXX, 524–525). Burke opposed not only calls for reform but also used the opportunity to denounce the French idea of the sovereignty of the people, which he, unlike the opposition speakers, associated with reform and any sym- pathy towards the revolutionary regime. According to Burke, the idea was impossible to realize and conducive to nothing but vicious mob rule: Th e sovereignty of the people was the most false, wicked, and mischie- vous doctrine that ever could be preached to them. It was false, because they had no means of exercising their sovereignty. [. . .] If the majority of the public was to be taken not by weight, but by tale, the most ignorant would elect, and none but the craft y and wicked would be elected. [. . .] Th e moment that equality and the sovereignty of the people was adopted as the rule of government, property would be at an end, and religion, morality, and law, which grew out of property, would fall with it (XXX, 551, 554). Burke rejected the idea of the sovereignty of the people completely. However, the reformist side did not give up their struggle, and in May they revived the debate on a moderate reform and the representation of the people. A petition compiled by the Association of the Friends of the People, in which Foxites such as Grey and Sheridan were involved, was then introduced to Parliament. Th e formulations of the petition were challenging to the highest degree; even Fox had diffi culties in agreeing with them.119 Th e petition suggested that the lack of appropri- ate popular representation tended to lead to either “a despotic mon- archy” or “a dangerous oligarchy”. French revolutionary language was unashamedly applied in the defi nition of “a third estate” as “created by, representing, and responsible to, the people themselves.” (XXX, 788) In previous parliamentary debates, “the third estate” had oft en referred to the monarch; now the radical Foxites made it a synonym of the people in the French fashion.

119 Dinwiddy 1992, 2; Mitchell 2004. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 399

Furthermore, the petitioners demanded the use of the concept of representation “in its fair and obvious sense” and not in the uncon- stitutional sense in which it was currently used to refer to Parliament. Th ey also urged the Commons to admit that they thought that the people of England did not deserve full representation or that they believed that the people already were fully represented (XXX, 788). Finally, the petitioners insinuated that private parliamentary patron- age not only excluded “the great mass of the people” from parliamen- tary elections but actually constituted a threat to all the elements of government, aiming at a takeover of “the sovereignty of the country” (XXX, 795). No mention of the sovereignty of the people or univer- sal suff rage was made; rather the document appeared as a defence of the combined sovereignty of the King, the Lords and the Commons. Th e reformers themselves saw their proposal as an eff ective way to curb the growth of the radical societies.120 Even so, the challenge to the politi- cal establishment was outspoken. Th e attempt was doomed to failure, given the ongoing Terror in France, the war against that country and the split among the opposition Whigs.121 All that followed was a highly confrontational debate on the political role of the people. Grey urged the Commons to take a positive stand on what he saw as an “enlargement of popular rights”. In its current form, Grey argued, the Commons did not constitute any real representation of the people. Th e creation of “a free and fair representation of the people” was inevi- table in that the people would sooner or later make it happen in any case. It was not democracy but “the popular part of the constitution” that Grey was defending, however. He tried to show that the British case should be discussed separately from the French Revolution, and hence he linked the proposal with previous corresponding motions, Locke’s and Blackstone’s ideas and the promises of reform made in the Royal Speech of 1784, written by Pitt (XXX, 800–803, 805–807). Many members protested against Grey’s claims. Robert Jenkinson, who had encountered related terminology during his studies in Paris, was the next to import the vocabulary of democracy into the debate. Th e timing and methods of the motion were wrong, he argued, because the reformers were agitating a people that had not complained inde- pendently. Th e French case demonstrated what kinds of extremities

120 Dickinson 1977, 237; Christie 1982, 213. 121 Goodwin 1979, 280–281; Christie 1982, 217–218. 400 chapter five such a malicious excitement of the people produced. Jenkinson also considered it wrong to justify constitutional innovations with specula- tive theories. He did not rule out all reform, but used the opportunity to lobby the interests of the professional classes (including military offi cers, his future reference group) whose entry into the Commons, side by side with the landed and moneyed interests, was enough to make it “the representation of the people”, even “the people at large” (XXX, 809–810, 813–814). Such an approach made Jenkinson take a positive, Pittite, view of the Commons as a democratic institution based on virtual representation and independent deliberation among the members: Th e House of Commons, as the democratic part of the constitution, as the virtual representatives of the people, certainly, to a degree, ought to be aff ected by public opinions in their operations. It must, however, never be forgotten, that the fi rst quality of the House of Commons is, that of being a deliberative assembly. If public opinion is necessarily to aff ect their decisions on every occasion, it will cease to be that delibera- tive assembly, [. . .] Public opinion, then, ought to have a certain weight in the conduct of that House; but public opinion ought never to have so great a weight, as to prevent their exercising their deliberative functions (XXX, 816).122 No French type of volatile public opinion was to steer the superior Commons. Th e danger involved in such opinion was obvious: [. . .] he was fearful lest our government should become too democratic. Every man who pushed the democratic principles of the constitution too far was, in fact, an enemy to it. [. . .] It was certainly the principle of the British constitution, that monarchy, aristocracy, and democracy should serve as a control on each other; but it was likewise a principle, that on ordinary occasions they should and must co-operate. If the monarchy, the aristocracy, and the democracy are too much unconnected, the pur- pose of control may be answered, but the purpose of co-operation will be defeated (XXX, 818). In all circumstances, the balance of the British constitution should be maintained, Jenkinson argued. Th ere was already a suffi cient amount of democracy in the British system, and the introduction of

122 Th e entire debate was printed with identical wordings in Authentic Report of the Debate in the House of Commons, on the 6th and 7th May, 1793, on Mr. Grey’s Motion for a Reform in Parliament . . . (London 1793), 14ff . the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 401

additional “democratic principles” would constitute a threat to the whole system. ‘Democracy’ as a constituent of the mixed form of government was acceptable but “democratic principles” of the French type were extreme and potentially very dangerous. By talking in favour of moderate forms of monarchy and aristocracy, Jenkinson was able to implicitly speak in favour of “moderate democracy” of the British form as well. It was much better than “a simple democracy” of the French kind. Th is meant no “exclusive attachment to the democratic part of our constitution”; it meant the avoidance of a (French) “democratic tyranny” that was just as bad as monarchical or aristocratic tyranny (XXX, 819). Democ- racy in its regulated form appeared as equal with the other elements of the constitution with regard to its good and bad sides and preferable to the French perversions.123 Jenkinson left no doubt as to the unde- sirable nature of “the turbulent, factious, and unsettled disposition of democracy” if adopted on its own, without the balancing eff ect of the other two classical elements of government (XXX, 820).124 Th omas Powys admitted no such optimistic applications of the con- cept of democracy. According to him, the petition had nothing to do with the opinion of “the crowds of the people” and was designed to lead to a similar kind of upheaval to that which had been seen in France. He, too, argued that the Commons was already “an organ, not merely to speak the public voice, or register the public opinions, but possessing judgment to deliberate” (XXX, 821). Windham elabo- rated on this point, rejecting what he saw as a mistaken idea among new political philosophers that “all government proceeded from the people”. What these philosophers seemed to be demanding was “pure democracy” and assemblies “emanating from the people”, the results of which were being seen in France (XXX, 823, 825). Th is was danger- ous, as the Commons should, in his view, never become pure “agents

123 For related views in the public sphere, see John Almon, Th e Causes of the Present Complaints Fairly Stated and Fully Refuted (London 1793), 9. According to Almon: “[W]e all approve and admire a state of democracy in our government; but it is con- stitutionally, and must be a democracy under certain limitations. If it were permitted to embrace all ranks of people, to put all persons upon an equality, it would here, as it has done in France, destroy every thing else.” 124 Th e distinction between democracy in general and its French form can be seen in Francis’ amazement aft er Archbishop John Moore had compared his fellow party member to Marat and Robespierre as “two of the most abandoned and desperate ruffi - ans [. . .] that ever disgraced the cause of democracy” in June 1793 (PR, XXXV, 640). 402 chapter five of the people” in the French fashion but should instead remain wiser than the people: With respect to a perfect coincidence in opinion with the people, he contended that all good proceeded on a diff erence in opinion with the people, and that nothing could be so calamitous to the House as to become the agents of the people (XXX, 825). Representation in its parliamentary form did not mean behaving like “the agents of the people” or being subject to the direct supervision of constantly fl uctuating popular opinion.125 Windham was implying that the French revolutionary understanding of democracy either in its direct Sansculottic form or in the form of representation as formulated in the Jacobin constitution of June 1793 was not applicable in Britain. If a reform in that direction was begun, Windham saw no end to the people’s yearning for more power (XXX, 825). Th is former Foxite and enthusiast for the Revolution had indeed reconsidered his views as a consequence of the radicalization of the French Revolution: language appealing to the people was no longer his chosen idiom. However, his phrase “the agents of the people” survived and was reintroduced into the debate later on. Th e reformists were unable to defend democracy aft er Jenkinson’s and Windham’s arguments. Th omas Erskine pointed out that the peti- tion only aimed at supporting the existing government but did not advocate “universal representation”. Turning to history, he presented “the free spirit of the English people” as the source of the principle that the Commons was based on “the people’s authority”. Th is “pop- ular branch of the constitution” was not functioning properly any more, however, because of corruption. He justifi ed this claim by cit- ing Burke’s Th oughts on the Cause of the Present Discontents from the time of the Wilkite controversy, in which Burke had warned of the rise of an authoritarian government and viewed the Commons as “the express image of the feelings of the nation” and “a control for the people” (XXX, 827–830). In 1770, Burke had, without doubt, called for measures to reform the government rather than to punish the

125 Not everyone rejected this idea, however. Some two hours later, Sheridan talked about the members of parliament as “agents” of the people. XXX, 904. He repeated his argument more clearly two years later. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 403

discontented.126 Burke’s change of attitude towards popular govern- ment had not gone unnoticed by his opponents.127 On the second day of the debate, a major contribution was made by Richard Colley Wellesley, the Earl of Mornington, Pitt’s loyal sup- porter. He considered that the danger of the motion lay precisely in an attempt to turn democracy into the dominant element of the constitu- tion. Mornington had initially had a positive attitude towards parlia- mentary reform, but in 1793 he opposed all constitutional changes, including the attempt [. . .] to separate those elementary principles of monarchy, of aristocracy, and of democracy, which are now mixed and blended in the frame of this House, and by combining them again, according to some new and diff erent rule of proportion, to create a system, of which we at present know nothing more [. . .] (XXX, 850). All experience and recent observations from abroad spoke against such an experiment. In Mornington’s description, the British element of democracy was not unique, but its fortunate combination with the other two elements was: We know, that in many other countries a large share of political power has been directly exercised by the people. Th e form of all such govern- ments is, in the common acceptation of the word, free; but the practi- cal result has been the most odious and intolerable tyranny; [. . .] (XXX, 851). Mornington found the origins of the reform proposal in Rousseau, a canonical saint of the French Revolution. He refuted the idea of “uni- versal suff rage” by demonstrating the logical inconsistencies of both Rousseau’s thinking and its application by the revolutionaries. Rous- seau had himself argued that the sovereignty of the people and repre- sentation were irreconcilable concepts: Th e author of the Social Contract maintains, that the national will or sovereignty of the people cannot be represented at all; [. . .] that the peo- ple of England are never in a state of freedom, excepting when they are in the very act of exercising the elective franchise; and that they become

126 Reid 1985, 30. 127 A posthumous text of Burke denied the existence of “any tenets of democracy” in the quoted pamphlet which, according to him, had rather advocated an open aris- tocracy. Edmund Burke, Two letters on the Conduct of our Domestick Parties, with Regard to French Politicks . . . (London 1797), xxix. 404 chapter five

slaves the moment a general election is concluded; and fi nally, that every government by representation is, in its nature, a tyranny, however extended the right of suff rage may be, because the national will, or, in other words, the vote of every individual, is not directly consulted in every act of legislation (XXX, 870–871). Furthermore, Rousseau had recognized, and the ancient Greek experi- ence had demonstrated, that the exercise of “the national sovereignty” caused individuals to neglect their other duties, which would lead to economic disaster. Th e events in France showed “the miserable error of those who imagine, that by infusing a greater portion of the spirit of democracy into the frame of parliament” they would improve on the British constitution. For Mornington, France was “that democratic government” where “the spirit of democracy” had also led to the mili- tancy and expansionism typical of such regimes.128 Th e French had produced a peculiarly French interpretation of the sovereignty of the French people as “the assumed sovereignty of the universe” (XXX, 871, 874, 876):129 Th eir fi rst proposition was, that the sovereignty of every nation resided essentially in the people at large of that nation. From thence they drew a most extraordinary inference, that, for the present, the people of France were the only legitimate representatives of all the nations in the world (XXX, 876). Mournington’s speech illustrates how the Enlightenment and revolu- tionary debates infl uenced the long-drawn-out British parliamentary debates on the political role of the people. Th us far, reconsiderations of what the proper share of power in the people seem to have been rather minimal.

128 William Godwin disagreed on this, see Enquiry Concerning Political Justice, and its Infl uence on Morals and Happiness. Th e second edition corrected (London 1796) [1793], 138. 129 Th e point about “a democratic people” generally disturbing the peace of both themselves and their neighbours was also made by William Young in Th e Rights of Englishmen; or, the British Constitution of Government, Compared with that of a Dem- ocratic Republic . . . (London 1793), 8, and by an anonymous writer in A Letter to the Rt. Hon. Lord Grenville, one of His Majesty’s Principal Secretaries of State, &c. in which the Present State of the British Nation is Considered . . . (London 1793), 16–17. Th e lat- ter saw “the arch democrat Cromwell” as a warning example of “republicanism” based on “democracy”. A further metaphorical revision in the description of the French military and ideological menace was provided by George Dallas’ phrase “propagation of this islam of democracy by fi re and sword” in his Th oughts upon our Present Situa- tion, with Remarks upon the Policy of a War with France (London 1793), 50. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 405

Democracy in its traditional British sense as one of the three ele- ments of the constitution was by no means rejected by the speakers, even if criticisms of excessive popular involvement continued. Samuel Whitbread II insisted that the interests of the people and the Commons should, aft er the people had elected their representatives, be identical and that the direct infl uence of “the popular will” on the decisions of the House would be ruinous. However, he set it as a goal “to restore to the democracy that power which it ought to possess”, with “the democracy” standing here for the Commons in a conventional sense (XXX, 885–889).130 Th is can be seen as an early version of democracy based on representation in the British Parliament, without the active involvement of the people in the political process. Th e reaction of Prime Minister Pitt also shows what was acceptable in the defi nition of the British constitution as opposed to the French. Pitt was not at all enthusiastic about the motion. He recognized the central role of the Commons as “the representation of the people” but rejected any association between this and the sovereignty of the people. According to Pitt, the French had “added new words to the dictionary”, including the defi nition of “the nation itself in a state of sovereign insurrection” (XXX, 900–902).131 Without calling it “democ- racy”, he gave the French system the following defi nition and excluded the possibility of a similar regime emerging in Britain: In what is called the government of the multitude, they are not the many who govern the few, but the few who govern the many. It is a species of tyranny, which adds insult to the wretchedness of its subjects, by styling its own arbitrary decrees the voice of the people, and sanctioning its acts of oppression and cruelty under the pretence of the national will (XXX, 901–902). Fox, too, was cautious about Grey’s motion, doubting the practical implications of universal suff rage. Yet he continued to argue consis- tently for “government originated not only for, but from the people” and restated the provocative notion of the people being “the legitimate

130 For a positive use of vocabulary referring to democracy in the public sphere, see [Impartial Observer in London], Fact Without Falacy: or, Constitutional Principles Contrasted with the Ruinois Eff ects of Unconstitutional Practices . . . (London 1793), 57, according to whom: “Th e democratical privileges of the people are rooted in the vitals of our constitution.” 131 Pitt was obviously referring to the notion of the sacred right of insurrection in the people, included in the Jacobin constitution of June 1793. Baker 2006, 649–650. 406 chapter five sovereign in every community.” Furthermore, he considered that “representation was the sovereign remedy for every disorder” (XXX, 915, 920, 922). Th e advocacy of the principle of the sovereignty of the people could hardly have been expressed more outspokenly than by Fox in spring 1793, attempting desperately to distinguish the principle from French revolutionary developments. Th e public response to debates on parliamentary reform varied, but the reaction to the idea of the sovereignty of the people was over- whelmingly negative. One response was to reprint Robert Walpole’s speech against shorter parliaments from 1734. Almost sixty years later, Walpole’s arguments were still presented as an orthodox defi nition of the character of the British constitution. In the introduction, the anonymous editor reformulated Walpole’s arguments in the vocabu- lary of the revolutionary period in order to deal a fi nal blow to all opposition claims about the existence of the sovereignty of the people: [. . .] a sovereign people, [. . .] is a perfect solecism in politics. Th e people are the subjects of every state to which they belong, and the description of sovereign subjects is an absurdity in terms. Indeed adventurers, such as the restless, the factious, and seditious, who amuse the people, to betray them, may stile the people the sovereign power; but, even such pests of society know that the sovereignty is not in the multitude, but in the constitutional authority [. . .] Th e supremacy is, beyond a doubt, in the government of all countries, and not in the people governed. It is quite as absurd to say, the sover- eignty of the people at large, as the sovereignty of the aristocracy or the democracy. It is impossible there can exist a sovereignty in the people, or a state of equality. Even in France, [. . .], the sovereignty is not in the people, for that is absolutely impossible, but in their representatives who usurped the sovereignty and controul the people [. . .].132 “Subject” rather than “citizen” continued to be the word used to defi ne the political role of individual members of the community; the sov- ereignty of the people was seen as a mere propaganda device of the French rebels. Th ere was no point in Britons adopting the concept to describe their constitution as it simply was not based on any popular

132 “Preface” to Th e Celebrated Speech of Sir Robert Walpole, Against Short Par- liaments; to shew that a Parliamentary Reform is both Unnecessary and Dangerous. With a Preface on the Times, to the Right Honourbale Henry Dundas . . . (London 1793), 9–10. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 407 sovereignty but on the sovereignty of the nation lodged in the King- in-Parliament: Were the English, aft er the example of the French, to talk of the sov- ereignty of the people, they would talk like madmen. Th e sovereign authority is vested by the constitution not in the people at large but in a limited monarchy, consisting of three estates or component parts of constitutional government, which makes a happy mixture of powers, [. . .] the component parts of the constitution, [. . .] together create the sovereignty of the nation, but not the sovereignty of the people, for there cannot be any such popular sovereignty, since a supremacy, or controul of them, must be lodged some where.133 Th e conventional view continued to be that “the political Trinity” of monarchy, aristocracy and democracy prevented the absolute, ambi- tious and tyrannical power which each component respectively was likely to produce. Th e worst scenario was that of the rage of the uncon- trolled sovereignty of the people in a “popular or democratical” govern- ment. As Walpole had once put it, democracy produced an unstable, ineffi cient and divided system open to abuse by the people and should thus be avoided by all possible means. In the circumstances of 1793, this meant the rejection of all plans to shorten the term of parliaments and the avoidance of “too frequent an appeal to the people”.134 Little seemed to have changed in the mainstream public debate since the days of Robert Walpole’s ministry. Both government offi cials and the loyalist mob readily used the concept of democracy pejoratively in attempts to silence their opponents.135 Democracy was seen as pos- sible only within the confi nes of the mixed constitution, not in any democratic republic.136 Th e idea of “a new language” of “the exclusive sovereignty of the people at large” in a moderate government was ridi- culed as absurd.137

133 “Preface” to Th e Celebrated Speech of Sir Robert Walpole, 1793, 10, 13. 134 “Preface” to Th e Celebrated Speech of Sir Robert Walpole, 1793, 13–16. 135 For example, Vicesimus Knox reported about the reactions to his sermon in Brighton: “Out with him—a Democrat, a Democrat, a Democrat—da capo—a Democrat.—No Democrat, a d—d Democrat.” Th is made him wonder why the audi- ence did not instead shout out “No people! No people! No people for ever.” 136 Oliver Goldsmith, Th e English Constitution [London 1793], 1, 3; William Young, Th e Rights of Englishmen; or, the British Constitution of Government, Compared with that of a Democratic Republic . . . (London 1793), 54. 137 Th omas Hearn, A Short View of the Rise and Progress of Freedom in Modern Europe, as Connected with the Causes which led to the French Revolution (London 1793), 75–76. 408 chapter five

Further inspiration for innovative rethinking in politics emerged from philosophy, however. William Godwin wrote a radical reply to Burke, but Pitt’s government saw no reason to prosecute the author because it was published in the exclusive genre of philosophy. Godwin pointed out that democracy was, despite its disadvantages, preferable to either pure monarchy or aristocracy. In ancient Athens, this form of government had inspired patriotism, independence and virtue.138 Godwin’s notion of democracy was highly optimistic, even idealistic, in comparison with most other writers of the day: Democracy restores to man a consciousness of his value, teaches him by the removal of authority and oppression to listen only to the dic- tates of reason, gives him confi dence to treat all other men as his fellow beings, [. . .].139 Godwin believed in improvement in politics, setting a new kind of democracy as a future goal of the political community: [. . .] if a form of political society can be devised in which men shall be accustomed to judge strictly and soberly, and habitually exercised to the plainness and simplicity of truth, democracy would in that society cease from the turbulence, instability, fi ckleness and violence that have too oft en characterised it.140 With the combination of democracy and representation it was, accord- ing to Godwin, possible [. . .] to call upon the most enlightened part of the nation to deliberate for the whole, and may thus generate a degree of wisdom, [. . .] which it would have been unreasonable to expect as a result of primary assem- blies.141 Such speculative radicalism was, for the time being, overshadowed by classical and condemnatory understandings of democracy. Th ere was no doubt, however, that Godwin’s ideas of democracy as the most likely system to advance the common good opened a new utilitarian vision of democracy.142

138 Godwin, Enquiry Concerning Political Justice, 1796, Vol. 2, 114. 139 Godwin, Enquiry Concerning Political Justice, 1796, Vol. 2, 115–116. 140 Godwin, Enquiry Concerning Political Justice, 1796, Vol. 2, 117. 141 Godwin, Enquiry Concerning Political Justice, 1796, Vol. 2, 118–119, 173; cf. Dickinson 1995, 197, 250. 142 Dickinson 1995, 180. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 409

Reactions to Robespierre’s Redefi nition of Democracy in 1794

As the British debate has already revealed, the popularity of the con- cept of democracy was growing in the Jacobin republic during 1793. Th ese radicals saw direct government by the people as a solution to the problems of the Revolution. In May 1793, Maximilien Robespi- erre was still speaking about “representative government”, not “pure democracy”, but in the proposed Jacobin constitution of June 1793 the French political community was already defi ned as “a democratic republic” and sovereignty placed in the people as a unifi ed political body. Th e expression “representative democracy”, which had been used rarely aft er 1790, was also becoming more popular. In February 1794, Robespierre already combined the concepts ‘democracy’, ‘repub- lic’ and ‘representation’, making ‘representative democracy’ a goal for the republic and a vision for the future. Th is happened at a time when the most ferocious phase of the Terror was in full spate, a new state religion was being introduced and the people was becoming a major political actor in the Revolution.143 Since 1789 Robespierre had defended the idea of broad representa- tion based on the principle that “sovereignty resides in the People, in every member of the populace”.144 In 1794, following the Jacobin trend of using the language of democracy to legitimate their power and developing Louis de Jaucourt’s defi nition in the Encyclopédie, he set democracy as the goal of the republic, both at home and abroad. Th e Jacobins hence demanded that the English should “democratize them- selves”.145 Aft er this change of parlance in France, an English author, who had declared himself “democratic [. . .] as every Englishman ought to be”,146 considered it necessary to defend himself “from the charge of democracy”, lamenting “the malicious interpretation which has lately been given to a word of considerable import to mankind”.147 Robespierre himself, like other revolutionary leaders of the time, used the concept of democracy in confusing ways.148 In a speech to the

143 Dippel 1986, 79; Rosanvallon 1995, 146; Monnier 1999, 53; Monnier 2001, 3, 19; Dunn 2005, 92, 114–115; Baker 2006, 650. 144 Dunn 2005, 115. 145 Palmer 1953, 213–214; Maier 1972, 859; Dippel 1986, 80–81. 146 William Augustus Miles, A Letter to the Duke of Graft on . . . (London 1794), 17. 147 William August Miles, Th e Author of Th e Letter to the Duke of Graft on Vindi- cated from the Charge of Democracy . . . (London 1794), 5. 148 Rosanvallon 1995, 146–148. 410 chapter five

National Convention on 5 February 1794, he saw the revolutionaries as fi ghting for a democratic republic based on representation. Robe- spierre attempted a redefi nition of the concept of democracy, rejecting the old negative understandings of direct democracy: Only democratic or republican government: these two words are syn- onymous, despite the vulgar abuse of language, [. . .] Democracy is not a state in which the people, continuously assembled, itself directs all public aff airs, [. . .]. Democracy is a state in which the people, as sovereign, guided by laws of its own making, does for itself all that it can do well, and by its delegates what it cannot. It is therefore in the principle of democratic government that you must look for the rules of your political conduct.149 Robespierre argued, furthermore, that “the French are the fi rst people in the world to establish a true democracy, by calling all men to enjoy equality and the fullness of civic rights [. . .].”150 According to Pierre Rosanvallon, Robespierre was trying to identify the people as the source of power through representation; he was not arguing in favour of direct popular government. Even Robespierre denounced “absolute democracy” or “pure democracy”. He was able to connect the concepts of democracy and representative government by interpreting both as originating from the principle of the sovereignty of the people.151 By 1794, the French Revolution had already provoked numerous debates for and against the principle of the sovereignty of the people in Britain. Conceptions of democracy, on the other hand, had retained the relatively positive tone which they had taken on in the 1780s, as the proper British and degenerated French forms of democracy had been consistently distinguished from each other. When the Revolu- tion reached its most radical phase in 1793–1794, its redefi nitions of democracy were bound to infl uence British debates as well. Th e revolutionaries aimed at the creation of a democratic republic based not only on representation but also on the revolutionary principle of national sovereignty. Britain had already become the major military opponent of the revolutionary regime, and Robespierre’s redefi nitions now made most Britons join a reactionary consensus against ‘democ-

149 Palmer 1953, 214; Palmer 1964, 115–116; Dunn 2005, 116–117. 150 Palmer 1953, 215. 151 Rosanvallon 1995, 147–148. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 411 racy’ as well.152 Another phenomenon supporting the rise of loyalty to the British monarchy and criticism of democracy was the organization of a number of radical meetings calling for parliamentary reform in spring 1794.153 When the parliamentary session was opened in January, the Royal Speech aimed primarily at motivating the political community in fi ghting the war. Th is was done in a new language of nationhood that was coming into being around Europe. Th e war was being fought to defend “all that is most dear to us, and relying, as we may with confi - dence, on the valour and resources of the nation”; it was a joint battle of the national community against another nation (XXX, 1046–1047). Th e debates that followed reveal that the battle concerned the ideologi- cal concepts of democracy and the sovereignty of the people as well. While some lords were convinced that the English would never follow the French example (XXX, 1065, 1075, 1086), others rejected French anarchy in forceful terms. Viscount Stormont exploited prejudices against extreme forms of democracy: “We know, and did know even before the sad example of France, that a wild and lawless democracy is the sharpest tyranny that can be endured by man” (XXX, 1079). Th e French advice that the British should rise against their political system led to denouncements not only of the revolutionary regime but of democracy of all kinds, the traditional positive associations of the democratic element of the mixed constitution being bypassed. Th e Commons assured the monarch that loyalty was only what “might well be expected from a brave and free people” (XXX, 1092). In the debate itself, a turning point in the understanding of democracy was heard when the Earl of Mornington, a major spokesman for the Pittites, attacked both popular sovereignty and democracy. His speech, obviously provoked by Robespierre’s speeches in 1793, refl ects the conceptions of the revolutionary regime that prevailed in the admin- istration.154 Mornington’s speech preceded Robespierre’s speech of 5 February 1794 by approximately two weeks, which, in principle, allowed time for Paris to be informed about ideological developments in London. It was on 21 January that for the fi rst time the revolution- ary concepts of democracy and the sovereignty of the people were used

152 Powell 2002, 19–21. 153 Mori 1997, 191. 154 Mori 1997, 166–167. 412 chapter five in the Commons debates on the Address of Th anks. Th is introduction of revolutionary vocabulary to British high politics did not go unrec- ognized, as Sheridan replied to Mornington, sarcastically pointing out his choice of words: “Have we not adopted the very words as well as spirit of democratic tyranny?” (XXX, 1218). Th e Commons debate focused on the French form of government. Th e loyal approach was to be horrifi ed by the cruelties committed by the revolutionaries. Isaac Hawkins Browne, a Pittite, maintained that the war was not being fought with the intention of restoring French monarchy or moulding the form of government on the other side of the Channel, provided that it did not threaten the established order in Britain: [. . .] while they adopted a form of government that endangered that social order, whether it was monarchical or democratical, such govern- ment was aggressive, and provoked opposition from a principle of self- defence (XXX, 1105).155 Th is was the general spirit of the debate. Colonel Banastre Tarleton, a Foxite who had been denied entry to Jacobin clubs during his visit to Paris, was one of the few members who complained about the British ministry undermining the authority of Parliament in the eyes of the people (XXX, 1100). Th e most thorough presentation of the stand of the Pitt ministry in relation to the French revolutionary ideas of democracy and popu- lar sovereignty came from Mornington,156 who argued, among other things, that the revolutionary ideology threatened all government and order. Th e revolutionaries had distorted Enlightenment philosophy into combinations of ideas that could never work. One of these was the combination of a new notion of political liberty with the “sanc- tion of the whole collective body of the people” (XXX, 1133–1134).157

155 In 10 April, Major Th omas Maitland saw the war as a “favourable opportunity of overturning the democracy of France”. PR, XXXVIII, 99. 156 Th e speech was also printed in Richard Wellesley, Substance of Lord Morning- ton’s Speech in the House of Commons, on Tuesday, January 21, 1794, on a Motion for an Address to His Majesty at the Commencement of the Sessions of Parliament (Dublin 1794). 157 A related point was put forward by John Stewart, who argued: “Th e active sover- eignty of the people in populous nations can have no existence; the present plebocracy of France must terminate in some democratical constitution.” Th e Tocsins of Britan- nia: With a Novel Plan for a Constitutional Army (London 1794), 22–23. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 413

Th e revolutionaries were propagating a “theory of universal liberty, founded upon universal insurrection”, a “system of exciting the people against all regular government, of whatever form, against all authority of whatever description” and a “plan for the instruction of the mob in the advantages of disorder, and in the facility of outrage and plunder” (XXX, 1113–1114). In their ideology, “insurrection became both the most sacred right, and the most indispensable duty, not only of the people at large, but of every portion and division of them”. Such ideas could emerge only in the mind of “the most wicked conspirator in the cause of absolute and unqualifi ed democracy” (XXX, 1135). French democracy simply meant that: [. . .] in defi ance of the sovereign people, a new and unheard-of species of government was established, which, growing out of the theory of impracticable liberty, was to be maintained by the practice of the most unmitigated tyranny (XXX, 1136). In reality, the Jacobin government abused the principle of “the sover- eignty of the people” to suppress the will of the people, to persecute dissidents, to deny individual liberty, to take over private property and to blunder (XXX, 1136, 1168, 1171, 1191). Th e principle had turned into “the sovereignty of the Jacobin faction” (XXX, 1180–1182) with the result that the French were forced to adopt the principles of their rulers against their will (XXX, 1195). Furthermore, the absurd notion of “the indefeasible sovereignty of the people” seemed to give the French the right to reinterpret the polit- ical system of every other state (XXX, 1116). Th e British had conse- quently been advised by the Jacobins to rebel against their established order. Robespierre had attacked the British people, their constitution and above all their monarchy, monarchs being to him no more than “slaves in a state of insurrection against the sovereignty of the people” (XXX, 1207). Aft er such a devastating interpretation of the French “sovereignty of the people”, one which did not arouse any clear counter-arguments in the House, the possibilities of the concept entering the language of the British members of parliament in a positive sense seemed non- existent. Th e ongoing war had been justifi ed as being waged against the ideologies of the sovereignty of the people and the French type of democracy, possibly democracy of any kind. It would take some time before alternative, positive, understandings of democracy could be convincingly presented in Parliament. 414 chapter five

On 10 February 1794, just days aft er Robespierre’s famous speech, the Commons debated Grey’s motion concerning the landing of Hes- sian troops in Britain without the prior consent of Parliament. Grey had defended the French Revolution and campaigned for parliamen- tary reform even though he did not accept extreme forms of democ- racy.158 Th e key issue in the debate was the impact of the arrival of foreign troops on the balance of power in the constitution, and the motion denounced what Grey saw as unparliamentary practice. Th e concept of democracy was actively employed in the debate, and mostly with utterly pejorative connotations, particularly on the government side. However, it was fi rst used by Samuel Whitbread II, Grey’s old friend, who argued that the royal prerogative was being increased in circumstances in which [. . .] the artful deceit and misrepresentation of ministers held forth an idea, that much was to be feared from the democracy of the times, and if it were not checked, tyranny of the worst kind would soon overwhelm us.159 Th e French version of democracy had been used as a deterrent by the British government, but this also brought counter-arguments from the opposition. From the opposition’s point of view, the risk of the mon- archy being strengthened excessively was much greater than the pos- sibility of a popular uprising of the democratic kind. Th is was a clear suggestion that the government was abusing the word “democracy” in order to strengthen its own standing.160 Th e government replied by accusing the opposition of overreact- ing to the strengthening of the royal prerogative. Th is was particularly inappropriate at a time characterized by “the general alarm against democratic principles”.161 John Th omas Stanley rejected opposition criticism and interpreted it by using a phrase (“democratic princi- ples”) that had been given a pejorative connotation in Parliament ever since the outbreak of the French Revolution as “calculated to encour- age complaint and discontent with those who held democratic prin- ciples”.162 Th e excesses of the Revolution had thus been added to the

158 O’Gorman 1997, 256; Powell 2002, 20. 159 An Impartial Report of the Debates Th at Occur in the Two Houses of Parliament, ed. William Woodfall (London 1794), Vol. 1, 325. 160 Woodfall, An Impartial Report, 1794, Vol. 1, 325, 328. 161 Woodfall, An Impartial Report, 1794, Vol. 1, 327. 162 Woodfall, An Impartial Report, 1794, Vol. 1, 330–331. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 415 existing negative classical associations of the concept of democracy. ‘Democracy’ had become a concept about whose meaning the parlia- mentarians were in open disagreement. To Pitt’s government, democ- racy seemed more suspect than before, and any opposition criticism of government measures could be easily presented as “democratical” political ambitions. Th e opposition, in turn, accused the government of exploiting the new associations of democracy for its own purposes. However, even during all the criticism of democratic principles in spring 1794, older favourable meanings of democracy also survived. Viscount Mahon (Stanhope), for instance, aft er recently moving in vain for the recog- nition of the French Republic and the ending of the war, called the Commons “the democratic House below” (PR, XXXIX, 219). Fox once again took up the concept of the people during the debate of 10 February. He had defended the Revolution, opposed the war against France, criticized royal infl uence and advocated a parliamen- tary reform. Not even the extremes of revolutionary radicalism had made him change his mind. He argued that the liberties of the people and the privileges of Parliament were both in danger if royal power was extended on the grounds of the war in the planned manner. Fox urged “the Commons [to] prove true to the people, and the people would remain obedient to the Commons”, who continued to defend their rights and safeguard the balance between the elements of the constitution. With reference to the failed attempts to reform Parlia- ment, Fox argued that the concerns of the public would abate if Par- liament proved that the Commons were “virtually, if not literally, the representatives of the people” by opposing both the rise of the monar- chical prerogative and “any too popular party”.163 Th is last statement demonstrates the limits of Fox’s desire for reform. He defended the status of the Commons as representatives of the people, but he did not really want a system of universal suff rage.164 A debate on 17 March regarding Britain’s policy over the impris- onment of the Marquis de Lafayette—a former French revolutionary leader and a supporter of limited monarchy who had been forced into exile in 1792 and was being held in prison by the Prussians—gave rise

163 Woodfall, An Impartial Report, 1794, Vol. 1, 345–346; Fox did not regard his Whig group as belonging to “the democratic or popular party”. Dinwiddy 1992, 2. 164 See O’Gorman 1997, 258, 269. 416 chapter five to some positive arguments related to democracy. Th e Commons did not approve the motion that Britain should support Lafayette despite his opposition to “democratic principles” during his leadership. Rich- ard Fitzpatrick, a leading Foxite, a founding member of the Whig Club and a personal friend of Lafayette, introduced the motion, in which he divided the French into four groups: those advocating traditional absolutism; those advocating a limited monarchy; those who supported “a popular form of government by a representative assembly”; and those “who, possessing democratic principles, had established the present tyranny which exists in the country”. Th ose Frenchmen who defended a limited monarchy appeared to be closest to the spirit of the British constitution. By the spring of 1794, some of the Foxite opposi- tion were thus denouncing the French democrats and distinguishing between popular government and extreme democracy. Lafayette was thanked for having opposed “popular excesses”, for suppressing “the violence of an outrageous multitude” (also referred to as the “populace” and “the mob”), for rejecting “the fury of democracy in Paris” and for denouncing “the democratic fury of the ruling power of France”. Th e argument was that the people should be resisted like this when they rejected lawful government. By supporting Frenchmen like Lafayette, Fitzpatrick argued, the British could “confound and falsify the invec- tives of democrats against kings in general”.165 Fitzpatrick’s motion was, aft er all, a demonstration of loyalty to the established order from a man who had been critical of the Friends of the People, and this implied a more critical conception of “democratic principles” of the French type and those who advocated them, the “democrats”. Th ere was a tendency to associate the latter term with the British opposition, and this had to be opposed by rejecting revolutionary radicalism.166 Even in this dispute on British and French varieties of democracy, the concept still found some cautious advocates in the British Parlia- ment. Courtenay was one who viewed democracy in positive terms, though only if it constituted no more than a temporary period of upheaval. Courtenay could well take such a stand as he was known for

165 Woodfall, An Impartial Report, 1794, Vol. 2, 339–346. 166 On 28 March 1794, an alarm about “the proceedings of the Democrats in Brit- ain” in their societies had reached the Lords. Marquis Townsend cited Fox’s speech in defending the formation of a citizen militia to combat such activities. Th is should be recruited from “the middle classes”, who knew those who might be disaff ected with the British constitution. PR, XXXIX, 189. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 417 his sympathies towards the Revolution, had ridiculed fears of democ- racy in 1790 and visited France in the autumn of 1792. He frequently used humour to get his points across, and he knew the potential of metaphors as rhetorical fi gures which could be interpreted in a vari- ety of ways and used to present controversial points. Hence the other members of parliament may not have been all that surprised when this Foxite with contacts in radical circles declared that he considered:167 [. . .] democratic insurrections to be useful: From the nature of things they could last but a short time, and, like hurricanes and thunder-storms, they cleared the stagnant atmosphere; and he would rather be tossed about in the wildest blasts and tempests of democracy, than breathe for an hour the still and pestilential breath of regal despotism.168 Courtenay knew that he was presenting a provocative argument in viewing democracy as a natural though temporary phenomenon and seeing the type of dynamic change it eff ected in political systems as positive. Even the French Revolution was not to be condemned com- pletely; it might accomplish something positive in the end. Such a modern notion hardly won much acceptance despite its met- aphorical re-description of democracy, particularly as it evoked old opposition claims about the despotic tendency of the British monar- chy and saw democracy as a remedy. Th ere was an opposition point hidden in all this: Courtenay reminded the House of the risks of an increase in the royal prerogative in Britain during the war against France if Pitt’s policies were pursued without check. His argument was parallel to Godwin’s suggestion in the preceding year that it was better to experience “turbulence and fl uctuation” in democracy than “unwholesome calm” under monarchy or aristocracy.169 While God- win’s book had presented mere theoretical speculation that was inac- cessible to the general public, Courtenay was popularizing the notion to the members of parliament and through reports of the proceedings of the House to a wider audience. Courtenay, with his straightforwardness expressed with meta- phors, was an exception. Democracy was mostly rejected in a debate at the end of March on government borrowing without the consent of Parliament, but the language of the opposition was also strong.

167 Th orne 2004. 168 Woodfall, An Impartial Report, 1794, Vol. 2, 368. 169 Godwin, Enquiry concerning Political Justice, 1796, Vol. 2, 115. 418 chapter five

Sheridan condemned the practice of the government as violating “a representative system”.170 Fox criticized the government’s mea- sures for alarming the public at a time when “a dangerous democratic sprit” was said to be prevalent throughout the country.171 Th e gov- ernment side responded by maintaining that the opposition shared constitutional views with “a set of men, whose wild and frantic ideas of democracy, if brought into practice, would accomplish universal destruction”.172 Th ere was a particular reason for the caution of the opposition and for the government’s readiness to attack democracy: it was planning an investigation into the entertainment of French ideas of democracy among the British radicals. In May 1794, the minis- try suspended Habeas Corpus, and soon a group of leading radicals were arrested. Th e country was entering an increasingly authoritarian phase, with the majority of the politicians supporting Pitt, and the Foxite opposition becoming further depleted in numbers. In June 1794, Parliament saw a very concrete breakthrough in the use of the language referring to democracy and the sovereignty of the people when the Committee of Secrecy published two reports on so- called seditious practices and attached documents confi scated from the Corresponding Societies as evidence. Th e language of the societies, as reported by the Committee, undeniably demonstrated that much French revolutionary discourse had been adopted by some of them, even though a number of their members were only innocently curi- ous about the Revolution and continued to base their claims on rights accorded by the ancient constitution rather than on a theory of univer- sal natural rights. Th e conclusion of the Committee was that the soci- eties were prepared to challenge the British form of government with revolutionary violence.173 Paine, the presumed founder of the radical movement, was accused by the Committee of recommending to the public the replacement of the established British constitution with “a democratical senate, as the sole legislative and executive power of the state” (XXXI, 709), associating his suggestions with French revolution- ary assemblies. Paine’s work had certainly inspired the foundation of

170 Woodfall, An Impartial Report, 1794, Vol. 2 535–536. 171 Woodfall, An Impartial Report, 1794, Vol. 2, 562. 172 Woodfall, An Impartial Report, 1794, Vol. 2, 567. 173 Goodwin 1979, 333–337; Christie 1982, 225; Dickinson 1989, 9; the quotations presented here were published in the documentation on seditious practices. Th ese do not, of course, provide a trustworthy picture of the activities of the societies. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 419 these societies, which appealed to the middle classes, aft er 1791, but few of the members were ready to go as far as Paine.174 Th e membership of the societies was considerable: 2000 in Sheffi eld and perhaps 10,000 in London, mainly drawn from the middle and lower classes.175 Correspondence between the Norwich and London Societies in November 1792 indicated that some of the members them- selves had suspected that the activists were aiming at the replacement of “monarchy” with “democracy” (XXXI, 798). However, the members had not necessarily regarded themselves as campaigning for democ- racy at that stage. One member in Leeds complained in May 1793 about how the aristocrats had abused “democratic ignorance” among the people in order to incite them to oppose the society (XXXI, 819). Th e attitudes of the corresponding societies towards the established political order in Britain had become more radical—and potentially revolutionary—in the course of the French Revolution. Royal preroga- tives, the privileged aristocracy and the intolerant clergy had all been verbally attacked, even though many societies had denounced Paine’s most far-reaching conclusions on the British constitution. Th e foun- dation of the fi rst French Republic in September 1792 was a turn- ing point towards further radicalization as well as the condemnation of the societies.176 In the course of 1793, the outspoken denial of the existence of a British version of democracy increased among the mem- bers, and this developed into a radical version of the criticism that the parliamentary opposition had previously presented. In April 1793, the secretary of the Society for Constitutional Information pointed out in a letter to Norwich: “Th e supposed democracy of the country has become a matter of property and privilege, and that we have therefore no longer that mixt government” (XXXI, 813). In other words, the current system of representation in the Commons had weakened the democratic element to such an extant that there was no longer a mixed constitution with three elements. In November 1793, the secretary of the Sheffi eld Society declared himself “a staunch democrat” (XXXI, 833), associating himself with the revolutionary kind of activism. By the spring of 1794, the phrase “the sovereignty of the people” had also entered the language of the societies. In their meetings of

174 Cannon 1994, 121; Dickinson 1985, 14. 175 Christie 1982, 211, 225; Royle 2000, 15. 176 Goodwin 1979, 125–130, 171–173, 200, 241–242. 420 chapter five

April 1794, the London and Sheffi eld Corresponding Societies saw “all sovereign, legislative, and judicial powers” as “the rights of the people” and viewed the people as “the true and only source of government”. Th is could also be expressed with the French formulation, according to which “the people is the sovereign”. Th e Norwich and Sheffi eld branches even spoke about “the majesty of the people”, employing a phrase which had been seldom used since the polemic against the col- onists during the American war (XXXI, 706, 715, 736, 821), but which had been used by Richard Price with reference to the British monar- chy in 1789. According to Price, civil governments should be seen as servants of the people, as they had been created by the people, were maintained by the people, and remained responsible to the people.177 When published in Parliament, all this correspondence showed that the challenge of democracy and the sovereignty of the people no lon- ger came just from outside the country but also from within. Such a proven ideological development automatically aff ected the meanings of the key concepts in parliamentary debates. Democracy could no longer be viewed merely as a positive element of the mixed constitu- tion; it now appeared as a threatening concept that implied an admira- tion of the French Revolution. Even if there was no longer any doubt as to the existence of the chal- lenge to the established order, references to democracy were avoided in the Commons’ debates of 16 June 1794 on radical societies.178 Th e activities of the societies were about to be declared seditious, and con- sequently the members also denied their legitimacy by deliberately not mentioning the democratic element of the constitution. At the same time, the idea of the sovereignty of the people, which had already been forcefully denounced during the preceding one and a half years, became made a major target of criticism. When the Prime Minister questioned the legitimacy of the societies by describing how they had been planning French kind of national conventions as “the represen- tative of the national sentiment, and the sole organs of the sovereign

177 Cited and analysed in Morris 1998, 42. 178 Th e Lords had debated the same issue three days earlier, viewing the societies as a conspiracy aiming at the importation of “the tyranny of France”. Lord Grenville had expressed his disgust at the societies sending misleading reports to France about the people of England opposing their government. As for the language of the societies, he saw it as identical with that of the French Convention. XXXI, 910–911. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 421 will of the people” (XXXI, 916),179 he made it clear to everyone that the position of both the monarchy and Parliament were being chal- lenged by the societies. Pitt, increasingly concerned about the emer- gence of Jacobinism in Britain,180 had adopted the language of Burke and Mornington to depict treasonous ideas such as the right of the people to be in a sovereign state of insurrection, the sacred duty of subverting established governments, the propriety of investing conventions with a species of despotic power (XXXI, 916). Such language appeared to have been copied from the Jacobins. Pitt did not attack democracy; he rather refused to defi ne the radical soci- eties as democratic and instead presented them as aiming at an out- right “tyranny”. Th is discussion on the nature of what had initially been a move- ment for parliamentary reform was awkward for the opposition, who wanted to avoid excessive associations with radicalism. Fox was forced to respond in order to demonstrate the integrity of his supporters. He did so by emphasizing “the good sense of the people at large, and their attachment to the system” and by warning the Commons “against the fatal error of bringing the constitution into contempt with the people”. He insisted on the right of the people to meet and to discuss poli- tics. As an old proponent of popular political activity, he maintained that, in cases such as the Revolution of 1688, it had actually been “the duty of the people, assembled by their delegates in convention, to call upon parliament to do what parliament would not do of itself ” (XXXI, 922, 925). Th ough not defending the sovereignty of the people181 or democracy here, Fox emphasized the legitimacy of popular activism as corresponding with the spirit of the constitution. In some cases, the people might even act collectively and independently of Parliament, if the latter did not fulfi l its responsibilities.

179 Such a Convention had been demanded in a meeting in London on 14 April 1794, held aft er the suppression of the Edinburgh Convention. Goodwin 1979, 27; Royle 2000, 17. 180 Ehrman & Smith 2004. 181 In a letter to Christopher Wyvill, Fox made the same point as in the Commons in February 1793 about the British monarchy being based on “the sovereignty of the people”. Political Papers, Chiefl y Respecting the Attempt of the County of York, . . . to Eff ect a Reformation of the Parliament of Great-Britain: Collected by the Rev. Christo- pher Wyvill . . . (York) [1794–1802], Vol. 6, 21. 422 chapter five

Th is was an argument that the Attorney General John Scott (later Lord Eldon), the leading prosecutor of societies accused of treason, disputed. In his view, no reasonable link between 1688 and 1794 could be drawn to legitimate “the extraordinary powers of the people”. Th e diff erence was, according to this offi cial interpretation of events, that the revolutionaries of 1688 had rightly asserted “the privileges of the people” as understood in Britain, while the French rebels of 1794 wanted nothing but “to tyrannize over the people” (XXXI, 930). Th is was not a real revolution for the benefi t of the people. Neither was it to be described as “democracy” of any kind. Th e French system had already been so widely discussed and con- demned in 1794 that the members of parliament saw no reason to debate it further at the opening of a new session in December. Th e King merely summarized the criticism by referring to “the instability of every part of that violent and unnatural system, which is equally ruin- ous to France, and incompatible with the tranquility of other nations.” (XXXI, 959–961). Th e Lords used the words referring to democracy in their debate to an unprecedented extent, mainly for derision and sar- casm. Once the enemy government had adopted democracy as its goal, it had become impossible to bypass the concept. Th e Pittite Henry Phipps, Lord Mulgrave, a former army offi cer, suggested an iden- tity between the foreign policy goals of the despotism of Louis XIV and those of “the present democratic tyranny of France” (XXXI, 981), associating democracy with what was regarded as the worst kind of European tyranny thus far. Grenville scornfully used the derogatory phrase “these despotic democrats” in talking about their economic state (XXXI, 989). Mulgrave made an ironical point on “the entertain- ing democrat” who had written about the Corsican crisis in a way that he found impossible to approve (XXXI, 984–985). Th ere were still also some solitary speakers who suggested that the French were hostile not to the British as a people but rather to their administration. A further suggestion was that the ministry was manipulating the British people by revealing conspiracies that did not necessarily exist at all (Mahon & Stormont, XXXI, 987). In the public discourse of 1794, some defences of democracy and the sovereignty of the people as realized in the British parliamentary system still appeared. Arthur O’Connor defi ned the Commons as the “representative democracy of England” but criticized noble infl uence the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 423 and narrow representation.182 Th is took Blackstone’s original defi ni- tion further and gave it a highly positive connotation. Others also challenged clerical authors for their opposition to the notion of the sovereignty of the people, claiming that it was indeed “a doctrine pro- fessed and practised in this country.”183 Radical writers maintained not only that the people was the origin of all sovereignty, but that this was a truth already generally held in Britain.184 Th e revolutionary challenge thus remained present in the public sphere, even if loyalist criticism of democracy prevailed.

Th e Political Rights of the People in a Time of Crisis

Th e year 1795 saw perhaps the most intense discussion on democracy and the sovereignty of the people in the Westminster Parliament in the entire eighteenth century. Public discourse, by contrast, had calmed down somewhat as a consequence of the measures against radical societies. Parliament thus continued to address the conceptual chal- lenge presented by the French regime. Th e majority of the two Houses and most authors were disillusioned with the French Revolution and

182 Arthur O’Connor, Th e Measures of Ministry to Prevent a Revolution, are the Cer- tain Means of Bringing it on. Th ird edition (London 1794), 36, 64; An pseudonymous author recognised that the British constitution contained “some portion of democ- racy”. [A graduate of the University of Cambridge], Considerations on the Causes and Alarming Consequences of the Present War, and the Necessity of Immediate Peace (London 1794), 29; Another anonymous author found the “exact share of democracy which is necessary to constitute a good government” in that members of Parliament gave “speeches for and against every question of importance, (and these speeches pub- lished as they are, with great care and correctness, generally contain all that can be said on both sides of the question)” and, consequently, that “the public are able to form a very just opinion of its merit or demerit.” If unhappy with the measures, the public could force the ministry to change its policies. [Anon.], Dialogues Between a Reformer and an Anti-Revolutionist (London 1794), 68. Th is is, indeed, a surprisingly far-reaching defi nition of modern parliamentary democracy. 183 David Jones, Th e Welsh Freeholder’s Farawell Epistles to the Right Rev. Samuel Lord Bishop (lately, of St. David’s) now, of Rochester . . . (London 1794), 28; Robert Hall, An Apology for the Freedom of the Press, and for General Liberty. To which are Prefi xed Remarks on Bishop Horsley’s Sermon, Preached on the Th irtieth of January last. Th e third edition. (London 1794), 64. 184 [Gracchus], An Appeal to Britons (London 1794), 4. 424 chapter five rejected its vocabulary referring the sovereignty of the people185 and perhaps democracy, too, particularly aft er evidence that revolution- ary ideas had found supporters among the lower orders of Britain. In a time of war, such attitudes were oft en understood as synonymous with treason. While it remained unthinkable for most to accept the French defi ni- tion of democracy, attempts to vindicate the old democratic element in the British constitution, which had been widely adopted before the Revolution, still emerged. Th ere were also those who wanted to let the French themselves decide on their political system. In one post- humous publication, the concept ‘democrat’ could still be defi ned in a positive and progressive sense as “one who maintains the rights of the people”, was “an enemy to privileged orders” and advocated “peace, economy, and reform”.186 One pamphlet suggested aft er the French fashion that in Britain as well there were two parties, the aristocrats constituting the majority and the democrats a suspect minority.187 John Cartwright, an old supporter of parliamentary reform, suggested that Britain should actually be called “a mixed democracy” rather than “a mixed monarchy”. His “democracy” stood for the electors of the Commons rather than the House as such.188 Th e year 1795 was also one of economic troubles, high infl ation and food riots, which contributed to the radicalization of arguments on both sides in Parliament. A debate on the situation was opened with Grey’s motion in January to conclude peace with France. Th e motion forced Pitt to justify the war again. He did so in ideological terms, arguing that there was nothing in the French system on the basis of which a peace could be concluded, whereas its challenge to the British system remained obvious. Pitt asked:

185 John Bowles took “the sovereignty of the people” in its French sense to be a “preposterous, disorderly, and antisocial term” standing for “organized anarchy and unbounded licentiousness”. Th e Dangers of Premature Peace . . . (London 1795), 12. 186 Charles Pigott, A Political Dictionary: Explaining the True Meaning of Words . . . (London 1795), 14. While Pigott recognised Aristotle’s condemnation of democracy as a danger to liberty, he argued that Montesquieu had regarded democ- racy as “the nursery of virtue”. 187 [A.L.], An Impartial Address to all Parties: By a Well-Wisher to the Constitution (London 1795), 6, 13. 188 John Cartwright, Th e Commonwealth in Danger; with an Introduction, Contain- ing Remarks on some late Writings of Arthur Young, Esq. (London 1795), 98–99. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 425

[. . .] whether the manner in which they had cried up the sovereignty of the people, whether the manner in which the pride and passions of the populace had been erected into the criterion and rule of government, aff orded any rational ground of security to any peace that could possibly be made (XXXI, 1217). Britain continued to fi ght against a regime that advocated the rejected principle of “the sovereignty of the people”, defi ned here in a way that recalled classical prejudices against a system in which “the pride and passions of the populace” set the agenda (XXXI, 1212). When the motion was discussed in the Lords, Dr Richard Watson, the Bishop of Llandaff , set out to defi ne the character of the ongo- ing war and also the meaning of democracy. Watson, who held Lock- ean views and had even defended the French Revolution in its early phase, recognized the principle that the French had “the sacred right” to choose their own form of government themselves. Respecting this principle was essential in “a free nation” like Britain (XXXI, 1257, 1259). As far as the reasons for the war were concerned, however, he had reconsidered his views on the Revolution: it had become neces- sary for Britain to curtail extreme forms of “democratical principles”, as extreme democracy of the French type threatened the foundations of all sorts of government: Th at the war was [. . .] entered into by ourselves, with a view of stop- ping the propagation of democratic principles, is a proposition which I believe to be true. Th ere may have even some other causes [. . .] but I take this to be the chief; nor do I see any dishonour in avowing it. Every gov- ernment has within itself an inherent principle of self-preservation; from this principle springs a right of resisting every attempt which evidently tends to the subversion of established governments (XXXI, 1259). Extreme forms of democracy needed to be opposed, but Watson was not sure that the methods used in this war “to impede the progress of democratic principles” were the right ones. Perhaps with religious persecution in mind, Watson argued for a degree of toleration for the democrats: [. . .] an unsuccessful war is more likely to accelerate than to impede the progress of democratic principles, and a successful war will not stop them. Th e history of the world informs us, that opinions are not subdued but confi rmed by persecution; they are seated in the mind, and the mind is not suspectible of change from that coarse instrument of government-force (XXXI, 1259–1260). 426 chapter five

Watson recommended “a seasonable attention to popular requisition” instead of any total dismissal of democratic ideas. Such a readiness to listen to the popular voice, in his view, well befi tted “this enlightened state of Europe” and “a free people”. As for the loyalty of the British people, Watson was convinced that it could be counted on: not only the majority of Parliament but also the majority of “an enlightened people” outside it “detest a republic” (XXXI, 1260–1261). Watson’s speech was not so much for or against democracy but essentially analytic, which is quite unusual for debating speeches in the eighteenth-century British Parliament. He continued with a classifi ca- tion of the elements of the mixed constitution and the current forms of government, combining the ideals of classical political theory with a political vocabulary that was typical of the 1790s. Watson divided the parties of the British constitution in conventional terms into the monarchy and “aristocratical” and “democratical” men, all of whom were needed to keep the due balance in case some excess of the other elements should emerge. All parties preferred the British legal, parlia- mentary and monarchical system to things French. As they preferred to stay “a free people”, the British constitution had nothing to fear from the foreign republicans. All was well when “the people is with the crown, and [. . .] the crown is with the people, and [. . .] both are with the constitution” (XXXI, 1261–1262, 1268). Republican forms of government may appear to be expansionist, but the British form of government was sure to prevail. According to Watson, it continued to be the common goal of all Britons to support the monarchy and aristocracy and “to protect the people themselves from the insidious machinations of their own demagogues, from the bloody tyranny of French fraternities” (XXXI, 1268). As an essential element of the mixed constitution, the people needed to be protected from themselves as well as from the other two elements. Watson’s discourse on republics is equally noteworthy. He made a tripartite division which recognized the claims of both the American and French revolutionaries, although he continued to regard republi- can forms of government as inferior to the mixed constitution. Robe- spierre and other French revolutionaries seem to have succeeded in their combination of republic and democracy to such an extent that an Anglican bishop could—just a year later—characterize the French republic indirectly as a “democratical republic” instead of merely call- ing it a tyranny. Rather surprisingly, Watson also accepted the associa- tion of the French republic with “the democratical republics of ancient the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 427 times, and especially that of Athens”, in which he saw “something like a prototype of the French republic” (XXXI, 1262–1263). Th is recogni- tion of identity between Athenian democracy and French republican- ism and the adoption of Robespierre’s phrase “democratical republic” demonstrates the degree of conceptual change that had taken place despite the war. Informed contemporaries in Britain recognized the change by combining ‘republic’ and ‘democracy’ in a new way. We should not overestimate the extent of the transition, of course. Watson’s basic attitude towards democracy remained unchanged in that, for him, both Athens and France created only “a dreadful tyranny exercised by pestilent men, through the instrumentality of the mul- titude”. In democracies, power was “exercised over valour, learning, justice, over every thing that was great and excellent among mankind”. Watson denied the claims by the Americans and the French that “the representative republics” were “essentially diff erent from all republics of either ancient or modern times” and that they were “machines of government, built upon a new construction”. Before believing such claims, he wanted to see these republics function for more than a cen- tury, just as the British mixed constitution had remained unchanged for over a century. He was sure that people in both Britain and in “the present aristocratical republics” of Europe knew that the British system was better than any of the novelties of the time (XXXI, 1262–1263). A few weeks later, the Lords deliberated political theory again, focus- ing on the suspension of the Habeas Corpus Act. Francis Russell, the Duke of Bedford, opposed the measure, considering it excessive at a time when no serious treason had been discovered in spite of numer- ous trials (PR, XLII, 120). Th is wealthy heir of a Whiggish aristocratic family had become the leading advocate of Fox’s policies among the tiny number of lords that remained loyal to the opposition leader. Now he wished to defi ne the political role of the Lords in a way that recognized democracy in its traditional British sense, as a part of the mixed government. He did so in paternalistic terms but also empha- sized the centrality of the popular elements in the British Constitution: [. . .] they were placed as a barrier between democracy and despotism; [. . .] they were not only the guardians of the rights of the Th rone, but of the privileges of the people; and [. . .] they ought equally to beware how they permitted themselves either to trample upon the one, or to trifl e with the other (PR, XLII, 120). Th is view of the Lords remained exceptional; in the 1790s few nobles endorsed a description of the House as a defender of the rights of 428 chapter five the people. Nevertheless, there were three other radical lords—the Earl of Guildford, Lauderdale and Charles Howard, the Duke of Nor- folk—who opposed the suspension of Habeas Corpus. Th e protesters referred to “the national spirit of English freedom” and to the fame of “this free and enlightened nation” as further reasons for Parliament to refrain from such an anti-libertarian measure (PR, XLII, 124). As pointed out above, democracy was not very actively discussed in printed literature in 1795. At the beginning of September, however, John Th elwall, a leading radical, gave three lectures on “the State of Popular Opinion, and the Causes of the rapid Diff usion of Democratic Principles”. Th elwall popularized the views of William Godwin in his lectures, which he also had printed, with an innovative language. He put forward highly unorthodox views on democracy—ones that may have aff ected some opposition circles in Parliament as well. Th e main point in the lectures was to demonstrate that “there was a consider- able increase of the democratic principle in this country” caused by the repressive policies of the authorities.189 Th e lectures contained a major re-description not only of the concept of democracy but also of the British political system in general. Th elwall started his redefi ni- tion by locating two confl icting senses of democracy, suggesting that “the Aristocrats” had deliberately given the concept inappropriate meanings: If we look at the real meaning of the term, we shall fi nd it to be a govern- ment by the great body of the people. Now, a government by the great body of the people, taken in its strict and original sense, does certainly describe a pure republic. Nay, more, it describes a republic without any intermediate order, such as we now call a representative assembly. But this is a system whose advocates, in the present day, if any, are extremely few; [. . .] Modern legislators [. . .] have invented what is called a represen- tative democracy, which is, in reality, if you adhere to the strict defi nition of terms, no democracy at all; [. . .] Th is representative democracy is the real essence of what was formerly, theoretically, called aristocracy.190 Th elwall proceeded to redefi ne the British constitution within this rev- olutionary conceptual framework as a “glorious constitutional democ-

189 John Th elwall, Th e Tribune, a Periodical Publication, Consisting Chiefl y of the Political Lectures of J. Th elwall. Taken in Short-Hand by W. Ramsey, and Revised by the Lecturer . . . (London 1795–1796), Vol. 2, No. 24, 185–186; Goodwin 1979, 28; up to 150,000 people may have been listening to Th elwall in a meeting held on 26 October 1795. Royle 2000, 22; Livesey 2001, 42. 190 Th elwall, Th e Tribune, No. 25, 209–210. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 429 racy” which every Englishman, as a democrat in the right sense of the word, should support. As the Commons constituted “the democ- racy of the country, who by their representatives are (ought to be I mean) represented”, the entire British constitution should be seen as a democracy with some aristocratic and monarchical elements. Th elwall went on to challenge the conventional defi nition of the constitution as “mixed monarchy” and defi ned it as “a limited or restrained democ- racy” instead. It was democracy in the sense that it was the great body of the people that passed all the laws and delegated all political power to its users.191 To avoid the impression that he was introducing a total innova- tion, Th elwall insisted that democracy was the original foundation of the British constitution and that “representative democracy” had been the implicit goal of the revolutionaries of 1688 as well. What was now needed was “the purifi cation and support of the democracy of this country, and a zealous attachment to the principles of that democ- racy”—in opposition to men fearful of democracy.192 Th is was, indeed, a challengingly new understanding of democracy albeit one seemingly derived from the old use of “democracy” as a synonym of the House of Commons. Th ese were views which the majority of the political establishment hardly wished to hear. However, it was they who, quite soon, took the conceptual change one step further. Th e Lords continued to discuss the possibility of peace in late Octo- ber. Grenville maintained that negotiations with France were possible only “so far that it rested upon principles diff erent from those of a wild and restless democracy” (PR, XLV, 31). Constitutional changes in France were still seen as the way to reconciliation between the two countries. Grenville suggested, with reference to the Speech from the Th rone, that “when the present Constitution of France should be actu- ally accepted by the People”, then it would be time for Britain to con- clude peace (PR, XLV, 39, 55). While France could not be allowed to remain a degenerated kind of democracy, some other kind of constitu- tion acceptable to the French people would do. Th is interpretation was to a great extent shared by the Duke of Norfolk, who maintained that the French Revolution had not been initiated by either the philosophers

191 Th elwall, Th e Tribune, No. 25, 211, 213; cf. Dickinson 1977, 251, on Th elwall’s reservations about genuine democracy. 192 Th elwall, Th e Tribune, No. 25, 217–218. 430 chapter five or the people but by the mistaken policies of the French government (PR, XLV, 54). Th is old aristocratic defender of the cause of the people and Enlightenment philosophers had not changed his views, which he could freely entertain thanks to his status and wealth.193 Seventeen ninety-fi ve was also a year of the continued persecution of radical societies. Th ere was evidently a tendency among the politi- cal establishment to reject democracy as a form of government that had not worked in the past and worked even less well in the era of the French Revolution. In November and December, the idea of the power of the people and the newly redefi ned concept of democracy were debated extensively when the Treasonable Practices Bill against publishers and the Seditious Meetings Bill against public meetings and political associations in general—two more measures by Pitt’s govern- ment against the Corresponding Societies—were placed on the agenda. Any written or spoken expression of contempt for the constitution was to be punishable by transportation. Not even 95 petitions with 130,000 signatures against such legislation could stop the parliamentary major- ity from adopting this policy.194 Lauderdale’s criticism of the bill in the Lords, however, demonstrates the determination of some Foxite noblemen to defend the political rights of the people despite the war against France, accusations of Jacobinism and investigations into their political activities. Lauderdale himself was coordinating the opposition with Fox, whom he accom- panied in protest meetings,195 and hence he did not hesitate to char- acterize the bill as “the severest and most dangerous to the rights and liberties of the people that had ever been introduced.” (XXXII, 246). He was particularly unhappy with the new way in which the word “people”—his favourite in the revolutionary context—had been used in the text of the bill. He argued that “the people” were referred to in a way that diff ered from the conventional legal use. Lauderdale insinu- ated that the government actually tended to commit “new crimes by new phrases” (XXXII, 251).

193 Norfolk continued to entertain revolutionary ideas, off ering a toast to “Our sov- ereign’s health—the majesty of the people” before 2000 people in January 1798 and thereby angering George III. He was attacked for attempts to present the British mon- archy as based on the sovereignty of the people in [Anon.], Sound an Alarm to all the Inhabitants of Great Britain . . . Th ird edition (London 1798), 8–11. 194 Goodwin 1979, 387–388; Christie 1982, 228; Dickinson 1995, 243–244; Royle 2000, 23. 195 Th orne 2004. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 431

Dr Samuel Horsley, the Bishop of Rochester, a champion of tradi- tional monarchy, defi ned the political role of the people in highly tradi- tionalistic terms, emphasizing deference and limiting popular political activities to mere petitioning. Horsley’s attitude was probably the real object of Lauderdale’s criticism of the misuse of “the people”: [. . .] the bill was merely directed against those idle and seditious public meetings for the discussion of the laws where the people were not com- petent to decide upon them. In fact, he did not know what the mass of the people in any country had to do with the laws but to obey them, with the reserve of their undoubted right to petition against any particular law, as a grievance on a particular description of people (XXXII, 258). Horsley’s interpretation of the marginal political role of the people forced Lauderdale into an immediate reply. Even if his opposition was unlikely to gain any considerable support, he continued to defend the popular cause by associating Horsley’s argument with oriental despo- tism. Th is provocative association was accompanied by a reminder of the proper role of the Anglican clergy in a free state: He should have supposed the noble prelate had been educated in a for- eign country, and not in England, when he declared that he did not know what the people had to do with the laws, but to obey them. If he had been in Turkey, and heard such a declaration from the mouth of a Muft i, he should have attributed it to his ignorance, the despotic govern- ment of his country, or the bias of his religious opinions; but to hear a British prelate, in a British house of parliament, declare that he did not know what the people had to do with the laws but to obey them, fi lled him with wonder and astonishment (XXXII, 258). Nor was Lauderdale alone in his opposition to the bill and what appeared to him as the negation of the political relevance of the peo- ple. Two days later, the Duke of Bedford emphasized the necessity of the people fi nding an interest in politics and actively discussing it. In his view, an active people of this kind would guarantee the survival of the British political order. Th e words of this Bloomsbury aristocrat mentored by Fox demonstrate the survival in the British political elite of a tiny Foxite group ready to advocate a vital political culture char- acterized by an increasing degree of popular participation: If the privilege of political discussion was allowed on matters of trivial concern, how much more ought it to be permitted on subjects of general interest? Th e ministers might go on for a time in the ruinous measures which they have adopted, but he warned them of the danger of driving a once free and high spirited people, to those rash and violent steps which 432 chapter five

despair alone can dictate. He hoped that the spirit of the people would show itself throughout every part of the kingdom; because he was per- suaded that nothing else would save the state from ruin (XXXII, 265). Once again it was Horsley who responded to these opposition claims. He was unwilling to withdraw anything he had stated about the politi- cal role of the people. He did know the political system of his country, contrary to what his opponents had claimed, and he was convinced of the correctness of his views. He was deeply hurt by the suggestion that he had advocated despotic views and reacted by insinuating that Lau- derdale himself was a spokesman of what he called “Genevan ideas”. Th is probably had multiple connotations: on the one hand, Geneva was the cradle of Calvinism, from which the doctrine of the Puritans, who had murdered a king and abolished the Church of England in the mid-seventeenth century, originated. Th e suggestion was that Lauder- dale was a disciple of the generally denounced tradition of republican- ism. On the other hand, of course, Geneva was also the hometown of Rousseau, the philosopher who was generally held responsible for having introduced the revolutionary principle of the sovereignty of the people in the fi rst place. Furthermore, the damage which revolu- tionary ideas had caused to the moderate government of Geneva had been recently discussed.196 Horsley defended his traditionalist views by repeating the statement that “the individual has nothing to do with the laws, but to obey them” and by attacking “democracy”, “democratic tyranny” and “a capricious democratic sway”, as reported by two ver- sions of the same debate, given here to demonstrate the diff erences that reporting could produce:197 But the noble Earl has stated, that the bill before this House is more calculated for the meridian of Constantinople than of Britain. Does the noble Lord recollect, that in that miserable and despotic country, the inhabitants are neither called to study, nor obey the laws—for, unhappy people! they have none! I would say then, that this bill is not calculated for the meridian of Constantinople; I would say also, that it is not cal- culated for the meridian of Geneva, whose inhabitants are subjected to a

196 [Anon.], Th e Misfortunes of Geneva (London 1792). 197 Th ese two quotations illustrate some diff erences in formulations of the argu- ment as conveyed by the diff erent reports, but they contain the same basic argument and confi rm Horsley’s use of references to “democracy”. However, not even Horsley attacked all kinds of democracy (including the old element of the British constitution) as he used the attribute “turbulent” to defi ne the Genevan version. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 433

capricious democratic sway. Th e rule of our conduct, as Britons, is to be found in the statute-book of this kingdom. Th is is a truth, which nothing shall prevent me from advancing, or deter me from repeating, were even the unhappy time arrived, when Nobles and Prelates were forced to bend their necks to the guillotine (PR, XLV, 114). My lords, the noble earl is mistaken; the maxim is not calculated for the meridian of Constantinople. Th e miserable inhabitants under that dismal sky have no law to study or to obey; they have only to obey the change- able will, caprice, or whim, of their tyrant. My lords, it is a maxim not calculated for the meridian of Geneva, or of any other turbulent democ- racy; in such governments, the people have only to obey the uncertain veering humour of popular assemblies. But in this country, . . . [with law- based government] the individual subject, [. . .] “has nothing to do with the laws but to obey them.” My lords, it is a maxim which I ever will maintain,—I will maintain it to the death,—I will maintain it under the axe of the guillotine, if, [. . .] the time should ever come when the prelates and nobles of this land must stoop their necks to that engine of demo- cratic tyranny (XXXII, 267–268). Enthusiastically engaged in the defence of what he saw as the estab- lished order against any sort of radicalism and countering the claims that the people should discuss politics, Horsley further questioned the publications of the day: Have not the minds of the common people been turned by such publi- cations to subjects to which it had been better if their minds never had been turned? Have they not been poisoned with false and pernicious notions? And has not a great change in the demeanour of the lower orders actually been produced? (XXXII, 269). To use anachronistic terms, it might be possible to see here a “conser- vative” voice opposing a more “liberal” one, but these were not yet the party denominations of the mid-1790s. Bedford and Lauderdale considered it best to reply to Horsley’s speech by referring to the parliamentary practice of avoiding personal attacks. Both pointed out how Horsley had changed his formulations from one speech to another. Th e Duke of Abingdon wanted to chal- lenge the bishop—and perhaps thereby the involvement of the Angli- can clergy in the reactionary propaganda of the 1790s—one more time. Opposing the bill as an unnecessary restriction on the liberty of the people, this radical nobleman, who never considered the revo- lutions of 1688 and 1789 to be comparable, questioned the bishop’s understanding of the Christian religion and the British political system as formulated aft er 1688: 434 chapter five

He wished to ask the reverend prelate, whether vox populi was not vox Dei? He would prove it was; and that God Almighty always inspired the people upon such occasions, and would do so still: [. . .] if the compact settled by the Bill of Rights was broken, the government might happen to be in a state of rebellion against the people (XXXII, 270). Abingdon’s words demonstrate the readiness of some members of the secular elite with a radical background to participate in the ongoing redefi nition of the state religion in ways that supported more dem- ocratic understandings of the political system. Such views had been developing in the scholarly discourse on contractual political theory for some time and had been applied by some radical clerics as well.198 A similar readiness to reinterpret the political teachings of the Chris- tian religion can be found in speeches made in the Commons. Th ere was a tendency to use the vocabulary of sacred rights and holy duties increasingly to refer to political rather than religious issues.199 Th e Lords passed the Treasonable Practices Bill by an overwhelming majority, but even in the fi nal debate both the concept of democracy and broader references to the people were employed. Explaining the tough measures in domestic policy by the ongoing war with France, William Wentworth-FitzWilliam, Earl FitzWilliam, pointed out that there had been no major changes in the French constitution and that the war should therefore be continued. Th e French type of democracy was still not to be trusted: Of the probable stability of that Government, no experience which they had had, could allow them to pronounce any opinion; but in its prin- ciple, he affi rmed it to be precisely the same as those which had preceded it. It was still a pure unqualifi ed Democracy, containing the seeds of dissention and anarchy, and aff ording no security for religion, property, or order (PR, XV, 184–185). Th e opponents of the bill avoided references to the French democ- racy and instead focused on the rights of the British people. Bedford was unhappy with several details in the bill, and especially with the limitations on petitioning which it introduced. However, he rejoiced at the amendments which the opponents, acting as the conveyors of the wishes of the people, had managed to have made to the original proposal: “I cannot help rejoicing that the voice of the people, which

198 See Ihalainen 2009. 199 For the French equivalent, see Monnier 2002, 398, 403. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 435

I in common with others exerted myself to bring forward, has pro- duced so salutary and benefi cial an eff ect.” Th e suggestion was still that the government was aiming at something resembling the enslave- ment of “the whole people of England” because of the sedition of a marginal group of people and that this denial of the enjoyment of freedom by the people was only likely to lead to abuses (PR, XL, 186, 188–189). Bedford turned to a prophetic mode in advising the Lords not to accept the bill: “[. . .] there is a spirit rising in the people, which must fi nally defeat the mad and futile attempts of those, who seek to curtail or abrogate the privileges of their free Constitution.” (PR, XL, 190) Bedford was one of the few noblemen in the kingdom who could aff ord to present such calls for concessions from the nobility to the people without endangering his position. It remains doubtful, how- ever, whether he actually wished to see any radical reform.200 Th ree more lords joined the defence of the popular cause in Decem- ber 1795. Lansdowne, already accused of being a Jacobin in the press, claimed that the people “still possessed the feelings of Englishmen, and would not tamely be deluded into a base surrender of their rights” (PR, XL, 195). Lauderdale complained that the bill demonstrated to the people nothing but a desire to restrain their liberties. Particu- larly regrettable was the tendency among the ministers to think that nobody could wish “the lowest order of the people to meet upon pub- lic questions”. In Lauderdale’s view, derived from revolutionary ideas of equality, no division of the people on the basis of their wealth was defensible, as all orders were equally entitled to enjoy British liberties (PR, XL, 198–199). Lauderdale carried his pro-revolutionary politics so far that he was no longer re-elected a representative of the Scottish lords in 1796.201 Finally, Th urlow pointed out that “the poisoned part of the people” was only a marginal one and could be easily controlled without mea- sures “which insulted the good sense, and stigmatised the loyalty of the great mass of the English people.” According to this former Lord Chancellor, the bill was merely “a libel on the people of England” and should therefore be opposed (PR, XL, 201, 203). Th e opponents also signed protests against the bill, representing it as a violation of “the rights of the people” and emphasizing “the sacred occasion of a free

200 Smith 2004. 201 Th orne 2004. 436 chapter five people applying to their Legislature” (PR, XL, 207–208). In 1795 the Lords was still clearly a forum in which the constitutional role of the people could be advocated by a handful of Foxite aristocrats. Concep- tions of the political role of the people had been transformed to the extent that an invasion of popular rights produced this kind of orga- nized resistance among some members of the British higher nobility. Grenville was another nobleman who discussed the political status of the people, but he did so as a supporter of the bill. He consistently denied the possibility that the bill would alienate the people from their monarch. He also disputed claims that the situation in France was developing in a more favourable direction. Grenville was positive that the bill did not endanger the liberties of the people but instead pro- vided measures necessary to protect them (PR, XL, 196–197). Most defenders of the bill did not attempt to use vocabulary referring to the people to construct their arguments. It was a recognition of the centrality of the concept that Grenville attempted to do so. Th e Commons’ debates on the Seditious Meetings Bill were opened by the Prime Minister, whose wartime policies were based on concerns other than the political rights of the people. Economic and political protests were widespread in the autumn of 1795, and even Pitt him- self had been attacked by the mob.202 In these circumstances, Pitt pre- sented the bill as an attempt to curtail meetings and public lectures that poisoned the minds of the people with anti-monarchical notions. Th e fi rst minister assured the House that the rights of the people were not being violated but only temporarily limited to avoid their abuse. He countered claims that the legislation was arbitrary by emphasising the rights of the people to petition (XXXII, 275–276). A tiny opposition protested against Pitt’s decisive line of action dur- ing his speech, and Fox continued the attack by depicting the politi- cal role of the people in an entirely diff erent light. Despite his loss of supporters, he carried on his criticism, expressing fear for a total loss of liberty if government policies were followed.203 He emphasized the natural rights of man as the basis of all free government and suggested that a free constitution was about to be abolished with the Seditious Meetings Bill. He urged Pitt to admit this aim. According to him, “the

202 Ehrman & Smith 2004. 203 Mitchell 2004. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 437 people [. . .] had a right to discuss the topics from which their griev- ances arose” in meetings as well as to complain by petition. If they were not allowed to do so, they no longer deserved to be called “a free people”. Fox went on to declare the bill an attempt “to prevent all political discussion whatever” and as such a major insult to the people of Britain (XXXII, 279–280). Fox saw it as inconsistent with the principles of the Glorious Revolution that “the people are to be prevented from discussing public topics publicly: they are to be pre- vented from discussing them privately.” He argued that the plan had “no regard for the liberty of the people” and that it was mistaken in supposing that “popular opinions”, “popular meetings” or “a popular discussion of grievances” constituted a revolution. On the contrary, he argued, the proposed measures to curtail public debate threatened public law and order. In his view, the bill should never be passed and if it was, the people should actively oppose it: “[. . .] while we have the power of assembling, the people will assemble”. Fox concluded by interpreting the bill as a change in the British constitution and expressing his admiration of the constitution for giving “scope to the people to exercise the right of political discussion” on any occasion (XXXII, 280–281, 283). Stanley, by contrast, sought a compromise by recognizing the need of the people to be jealous of their rights but arguing that the freedom of the press was enough to maintain “all the blessings of the people” in Britain. Th e problem with meetings was, in his view, their tendency to inculcate sedition “to the multitude” and to seduce the ignorant into action. “Th e public mind” should be protected from such activi- ties (XXXII, 284). Morris Robinson’s contribution distinguished itself from most of the others in that he focused on the relationship between monarchy and democracy in the mixed constitution. He did so with language that continued to exclude the notion of the sovereignty of the peo- ple from the British system. Th e assumption was that the monarchy understood what the people needed and that the people were inher- ently loyal to their monarch. Robinson interpreted the preceding gov- ernment speakers to have meant: [. . .] the people would have a right to read, but not to speak complaints against the burdens they endured. Th us the interests of the sovereign were opposed to those of the people, whereas he had always heard that the sovereign was a third branch of the legislature, and was bound to 438 chapter five

understand the democratical interests as much as his own. Th e bill went to impeach the loyalty of the people, who, except a few indeed, had con- stantly shown their veneration for the sovereign: [. . .] (XXXII, 294). John Christian Curwen, a consistent opponent against autocracy, car- ried on the defence of the political right of the people to freely discuss the defects of the government. Th anks to such a right “the people of this realm were never obliged to recur to acts of violence to obtain redress of their grievances”, he maintained. He suspected that the Prime Minister had good reasons “to suppress the voice of the people” because of the criticism his policies had met and because of the ability of “the voice of the people” to change his war policies. Th e bill should thus be seen as a result of nothing else but the willingness of the min- isters to stop the people from complaining to the monarch about the measures of the administration (XXXII, 291–292). William Wilberforce, an independent member of parliament who had been concerned over both the war with France and the rise of radicalism, returned to Pitt’s basic argument, according to which the bill was necessary to protect “the minds of the people” from the poison of “French politics” and “French philosophy” as propagated through debating societies. He tried to convince the audience both inside and outside Parliament that the bill did not aff ect “the expressing to parlia- ment of the national will”—this previously condemned revolutionary phrase thus entering the vocabulary of a Pittite—and that the Com- mons remained “a popular assembly [. . .] in which all popular griev- ances might be freely and safely discussed” and “to which the people might be encouraged to bring their complaints”. In the Commons, “the national humour might be suff ered to ferment without danger” (XXXII, 292–294) also in the future. Wilberforce argued that such an existing system was much better than anything created in France. Sheridan, who had contacts with the radical London Corresponding Society and had been questioned in May 1794 for alleged treason,204 reacted to these views with harsh words, stating that Wilberforce did not realize the danger which the bill constituted for British liberty by trying to use magistrates to “set the people to rights”. Th e suggested bill made the members of parliament into no more than “the prattling representative of a dumb and enslaved people” (XXXII, 296).

204 Jeff ares 2004. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 439

Th e debate was concluded by William Windham, the Secretary at War since July 1794 and a loyal supporter of Pitt, with a summary of the proposal. Denying suggestions that the people were being enslaved, he argued that the Foxite opposition was so closely connected with the organizers of the seditious meetings that they could not see the dan- gers involved. Th e bill was needed to counter the already witnessed plans for developments towards republicanism and the wrong kind of democracy that the French were imposing on all of Europe and more particularly on Britain, the Dutch Republic and the United States: Th ey had endeavoured to exterminate all traces of ancient institutions, and had attempted to make the world adopt a new principle. Was there a country in Europe safe from the poison of these principles, or which had not felt the eff ect of this great democracy? Were not the principles openly avowed in every country, and acted on by men of information and talents? (XXXII, 297–298). Th e last opposition speaker, Grey, pointed to inconsistencies in the ministerial arguments with regard to democratic principles, which the ministers seemed to be willing to undo by all possible means: Th e decline of democratic principles had, on a former occasion, been much dwelt on, as the happy eff ect of the war; yet, at that moment the prevalence of those very principles was made the ground of the bill pro- posed by ministers (XXXII, 298–299). Grey argued that popular protests in Britain were a product of unsuc- cessful war policies rather than any democratic principles of the French type. Th e ministry was now attempting “to rob the people of their dearest rights and enslave the nation”. He concluded that the “ministers proposed to crush the people and must necessarily destroy the constitution under the fl imsy pretence of defending it” (XXXII, 299–300). Th e arguments were uncompromising on both sides but the parliamentary power of the opposition was too limited to make any diff erence in the legislative process. When the debate was resumed in mid-November, a new kind of “sanctifi cation” of the status of the people—characteristic of the revo- lutionary rhetoric of the 1790s—is observable in that their political rights and duties were described as “sacred” and “holy”.205 Despite such statements, the debate also contained repeated and categorical

205 See Ihalainen 2007. 440 chapter five denials of the principle of the sovereignty of the people and arguments in favour of the infl uence of Parliament. Pitt, among other speakers, rejected the very principle, even in times of interregnum. He presented the principles of 1689 as better than French revolutionary ones in every possible respect. Th ey, too, spoke in favour of the sovereignty of parliament rather than of the people: Th e two remaining Houses of parliament, and those two Houses alone, were then resorted to, and not the sovereignty of the people, as the means through which the other branch of the legislature [the monarch] was to be supplied. It was not to that sovereignty of the people which is now talked of, that recourse was had. Th us, therefore, the revolution itself conspired to show that it was to parliament, or to the people in parlia- ment, and not to the people out of parliament, that the right of framing alterations in the constitution always devolved (XXXII, 357–358). Th e ultimate power to regulate the form of government thus remained in the hands of “the people in parliament” in all circumstances, not in the hands of the people at large. A number of alternative understandings of the political role of the people were introduced in the debate. Solicitor General John Mitford’s opening speech illustrates the strategy which the ministry had chosen in order to win the vote. While recognizing “the sacred freedom of speech” (XXXII, 306) and the “sacred” right of petitioning, the min- ister consistently emphasized abuses of that right and the consequent necessity to curb it with the proposed law. Classical examples were invoked to demonstrate the need to control the engagement of the masses in politics: Th e most free states that had existed; the Roman Republic itself, in the zenith of its liberty and fame, had never permitted the people to assem- ble but in a regular body, formally collected, and under the control of a magistrate (XXXII, 308). Britain remained perfectly free thanks to her Parliament. Unregulated meetings of the people could well be forbidden without this prevent- ing the people from participating in “political discussions” whenever true grievances emerged (XXXII, 308). Pitt, for his part, took not democracy but “representative government” of the French type as an object of disdain. Th e ministry argued that such a government based on “universal suff rage” had only led to the destruction of the monar- chy and all government in France (XXXII, 309–310). Th is suspicion of all “representative government” is interesting given the high regard the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 441 for representation expressed in earlier parliamentary language and the existence of the American model. Apparently, any French idea appeared questionable in the context of 1795. Th e opposition could hardly accept such an interpretation. Erskine, one of the most consistent opponents to the sedition bill, continued to argue that it constituted “a fl agrant invasion of the people’s privi- leges” and destroyed the mixed constitution by denying the right to petition. He played down the Roman precedent with a boldly mod- ernist assertion that only the British experience since 1688 mattered when decisions on the constitution were made. In arguing that the British Constitution as such was “sacred” (XXXII, 311–312), Erskine distanced himself from the classical conception of the mixed consti- tution, in which the democratic element had been traditionally kept within its due limits. Even more radical was his acceptance of popular resistance in cases where the rulers were about to abolish the rights of the people: “He would say, again and again, that it was the right of the people to resist that government which exercised tyranny.” Th e bill was tearing the ministry and the people into opposite sides, which created the possibility that the case would be “fairly tried between the people and the government!” (XXXII, 312–313). Erskine’s provoca- tive speech meant that the inherited British parliamentary system was being challenged with arguments appealing to a more direct kind of power of the people. A further radical argument was Erskine’s sugges- tion that the bill divided the people socially: “Th e higher orders of the people separated themselves too much from the lower.” Th is had been, according to him, a major cause of the French Revolution and should therefore be avoided in Britain (XXXII, 314). Such a reference to social inequality was entirely new in the eighteenth-century parliamentary context. It provides one more instance of the degree of radicalization which the war against revolutionary France and measures against radi- cal associations produced in British parliamentary debates. Th e Earl of Mornington, an old opponent of the revolutionary ideas of popular sovereignty and universal suff rage, eagerly associated such denounced notions with the British opposition. In 1795 he depicted the French model as “the wild principle that every individual had a right to share in the sovereignty”. Robespierre had, indeed, rightly characterized it as the “despotism of liberty”. Th e British Correspond- ing Societies seemed to be claiming the submission of Parliament to “the absurd and extravagant doctrines of universal suff rage and annual parliaments”, that is, to the abolition of the entire constitution 442 chapter five

(XXXII, 349–350). Th e ministry thus did not content itself with merely denouncing the sovereignty of the people but attacked British radicals in order to justify stricter legislation against the societies. Sheridan, who had links with various radical societies, spoke in defence of the British people and extended his admiration—quite provocatively—to the Americans as well. From his point of view, the members of parliament should adopt a more humble attitude towards the people. Sheridan maintained that Britons, having such a long expe- rience of living the life of a free people, would not be carried to any French kind of excesses when participating in politics: Th e noble lord had represented the lower classes of the people of all countries to be alike. Th is was a gross misrepresentation. Nothing could be more false and absurd, than to suppose, that a people, bred up in a free country, and in the habits of enjoying and considering their rights, would ever conduct themselves like slaves just rescued from a vile, grind- ing, and infamous despotism (XXXII, 335). Th e members of parliament should regard themselves as representa- tives of all the people. Th is conception of representation was hardly new, but Sheridan extended it so far as to claim, in symmetrical oppo- sition to what Windham had maintained in May 1793, that the mem- bers of parliament should indeed view themselves as the agents and servants of the people: Th ey should consider that they were all of them the servants of the people of England. Th ey voted and acted in that House not in their individual capacity, but as agents and attorneys for others (XXXII, 337). Such a humble attitude on the part of the members of parliament was necessary as there was always the possibility of the people resisting legitimately if their rights were violated by the Crown (XXXII, 337). Such undesirable consequences were to be avoided with the right kind of policy. Sheridan’s formulation demonstrates the length to which an opposition radical was ready to go in appealing to the power of the people in the aft ermath of the French Revolution. Whereas in 1793 it had still been unthinkable for Windham to present the Commons as mere agents of the people, in 1795 Sheridan could claim that this was the very raison d’être of the House. Sheridan’s argument demonstrates the potential of parliamentary style of debating for and against a motion to produce new ways of conceptualizing politics. Th e government side also contributed to the process of the re-conceptualization of politics by presenting old argu- the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 443 ments in new ways. In the eighteenth-century parliamentary debate on democracy, a leading minister quite oft en introduced a controver- sial conception into the debate only to demolish it for the purpose of defending the established order. His arguments could then be disputed by the opposition with major re-conceptualizations. Henry Dundas replied to the Foxites by representing the bill as a measure that secured the very rights that the people had been given in the Bill of Rights, a document that he called a “sacred declaration of our liberties”. Rejecting claims that the interests of the lower orders were being ignored, Dundas maintained that the English classes were more united than those of any other country. Th e claims themselves originated from the very principles which the bill appropriately lim- ited. Th e point was that the Foxites had maliciously abused popular politics, attacking ministers not only in the Commons but also outside Parliament, where the government was unable to defend itself. It was, according to Dundas, extremely dangerous to advocate such a broad doctrine of the right of resistance of the people, as resistance never belonged to organized government (XXXII, 337–341). Fox was thus challenged to reply and to continue using the rhetoric of the sacred rights of the people, an expression used by both sides in the debate. However, he had to be careful not to take his arguments in favour of the loathed sovereignty of the people too far. Recalling the debates of the time of the Middlesex election, he maintained that he had then been “in favour of the sovereignty of parliamentary law” but he had never been “the least unfavourable to the right which the people indisputably possessed of expressing their sense of every public measure” (XXXII, 342–343). Th is was a statement altogether dictated by hindsight, as Fox had spoken out quite explicitly against popular involvement in the early 1770s. Now he was arguing that while sov- ereignty belonged to Parliament rather than the people at large, the people still possessed a universal right to express their political stands in any issue. In this debate, Fox explicitly defended the political rights of the people but avoided any outright claim that this was the same thing as the sovereignty of the people. It was necessary to use with the French concept with caution, but Fox consistently defended right of the members of parliament to main- tain contacts with the people. Referring to debates on parliamentary reform in 1784, he insisted that he had never questioned “the sacred right of the people to assemble and freely discuss political subjects”. Furthermore: “Never in any one instance had he uttered a syllable 444 chapter five that went to question the right, or to blame the practice, of holding public meetings of the people.” Th at was, however, what the proposed bill was doing (XXXII, 343–344). At this point, Fox could not avoid the temptation to comment on what Bishop Horsley had stated in the Lords six days previously. Published newspaper reports and contacts with Foxite lords facilitated such a continuation of the Lords’ debate in the Commons. Fox considered Horsley’s view that “the mass of the people had nothing to do with the laws, but to obey them” to be very strange and inconsistent with Christian teachings about the natural equality of men. Th e good populist that he was, Fox argued: [. . .] the people of England would not tamely surrender their indisput- able and hereditary right, whatever inclination an arbitrary minister or a supercisious [sic] prelate might betray, to wrest them out of their pos- session (XXXII, 349). Prejudices against the Pittite ministry and the traditionalist clergy were thus eff ectively combined. Finally, approaching the issue of parliamentary reform, Fox sum- marized the arguments on both sides as he saw them. While the proponents of the reform argued that the people were not equally represented, the ministry’s view was that “the aggregate body was to all intents and purposes, virtually represented”, that all people could appeal to “the virtual representatives of the nation.” Fox could not support the idea of virtual representation, particularly if it included restrictions on the right of petitioning to Parliament. Indeed, by doing so, the bill tended to “convert the government of the country into an aristocracy, or an oligarchy” (XXXII, 349–350). Th ese were grave accu- sations. Even if the atmosphere of 1795 made Fox avoid references to democracy, he remained consistent in his defence of the popular element in the mixed government. To avoid being seen as an extrem- ist, and also out of genuine conviction, he continued to denounce the ideas of universal suff rage and annual parliaments (XXXII, 353). Prime Minister Pitt’s rejection of the principle of the sovereignty of the people was well thought-out. Fox’s criticism of his policies had certainly strengthened his resolution to win the vote and to use sug- gestions that his opponents were importing French principles to Brit- ain to do so. In answer to the suggestion that the bill widened the distinction between “the lower and the higher orders of the people”, he argued that it was designed to counter the “Jacobinism” that divided the people into orders (XXXII, 358). Still avoiding any explicit attack the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 445 on democracy, Pitt labelled the opposition outside Parliament “Jaco- binism” which needed to be suppressed. Repeating his view of the British principle of virtual representation, he rejected universal suf- frage, annual parliaments and thereby also the proposals for parlia- mentary reform. For the time being, Parliament should demonstrate to the people that it alone could change laws (XXXII, 360, 363). During the second reading of the bill, the Strangers’ Gallery remained closed for much of the debate, and hence we have a report of just one speech—by Sheridan, who repeated his arguments about the people being deprived of “their dearest and most sacred right” and the diverse natures of the people in England and France (XXXII, 364–366). On 23 November, petitions against the bill gave rise to a further verbal duel between Fox and Pitt.206 Fox compared the bill to a repeal of the Bill of Rights and described it as an attack on “the rights and liberties of the nation”. Th e people at large were hardly ready for such “slavery”; if they were, Fox could no longer see himself as “a profi table servant of the people”. He was assured that the people saw the violation of the constitution and “might be roused to its defence” (XXXII, 382–383). Th e Prime Minister condemned such violent expressions as a crimi- nal injunction to use violence, likely to cause anarchy and bloodshed (XXXII, 384). Two more examples at the end of 1795 illustrate the prevailing state of confusion over the meaning of the concept of democracy caused by its having been made the programmatic goal of revolutionary France. ‘Democracy’ was no longer understood merely as an element of the British constitution; it could be seen as an ideology of its own, com- parable to Toryism. Th is is shown by Stanley’s description of the state of the old Whig party, according to which the Whigs were being chal- lenged by “the extremes of toryism and democracy” (PR, XLIII, 425). Democracy thus appeared as the radical opposite of traditional sup- port for monarchy. At the same time, the parliamentarians held diverse views about how to deal with the French form of government aft er the fall of Robespierre. William Wilberforce, who shared Pitt’s longing for peace, maintained

206 Reports on the proceedings of 23 and 24 November are much shorter in Cobbett than in Th e Parliamentary Register. 446 chapter five on 9 December that the new French government (the Directory) was more moderate and stable than that of the days of the Terror: Is there not a considerable diff erence between that no-government, that wild democracy, which formerly prevailed in France, and the more limited and regulated government which they have now adopted? (PR, XLIII, 657–658). France was thus moving away from the detested “wild democracy”. Wilberforce’s suggestion was that the American system could off er a suitable model for the French people (PR, XLIII, 658). Pitt shared his interpretation that the danger of French “pure democracy” was already declining, which justifi ed attempts to achieve a peace settle- ment with France: Th ey are now far removed from a state of pure democracy, and so far the less liable to be again involved in the horrors of anarchy and confusion. Is it no material diff erence in situation, that in consequence of the divi- sion into two Houses, the representative body can no longer, under the infl uence of violent gusts of passion, rashly and wildly pass the most per- nicious decrees, and are not likely to be again controlled by a sanguinary mob, a lawless rabble? Is it no material diff erence that they should have infused into their Constitution the elements of a mixed Government, and have placed in separate hands the legislative, judicial, and executive powers? (PR, XLIII, 666). Pitt suggested that France was abandoning the worst kind of democ- racy and turning towards a mixed constitution of the British type. Th e war had been fought to oppose the expansion of the French type of democracy, and now that this danger was disappearing, peace seemed possible. Pitt’s advice to the French was self-confi dently British: “[. . .] they do well in proportion as they come nearer that description of Government, which experience has proved to be benefi cial to man- kind” (PR, XLIII, 666). Aft er the Revolution, too, democracy should remain, according to the Prime Minister, no more than a strictly regu- lated element of the mixed constitution in the British sense. By add- ing consistently pejorative attributes to the French perversion of the system, British parliamentarians, and Pitt in particular, had been able to retain at least something of a positive attitude towards democracy in general. Th is conception could be revived as soon as there was a prospect for peace with France. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 447

Calls for Representative Government and Defences of Democracy in 1796–1797

Th ere was no peace settlement with France in 1795. Instead, in 1796, Spain joined the war against Britain and, aft er the French occupation of the Dutch Republic, the British extended their military eff orts to the Dutch colonies as well. War remained a dominant subject in parlia- mentary debates, aff ecting constitutional discussions as well. In France, however, the political situation was rapidly changing. Th e Convention was replaced by the Directory in October 1795, which implied the end of the most radical phase of the Revolution. As much of the upper bourgeoisie was turning hostile to the totalitarian ver- sion of democracy experienced under Jacobin rule, “democrat” was by 1796 being increasingly used as a name of disdain rather than respect. Democracy, demagogy, ochlocracy and anarchy were oft en regarded as synonyms in France as well. Associating one’s own political views with democracy was deliberately avoided by all except the Sanscu- lottes, who further extended the egalitarian socio-economic dimension of their conception of direct democracy and included the goal of the redistribution of property in it. By 1798 “democrats” was used in some French texts to refer to the losers of the Revolution, and especially to the politicized members of the lower orders. By the late 1790s, the winners of the upheaval thus no longer associated themselves with the Revolution, democracy and popular sovereignty. When a period of what Horst Dippel has called “Napoleon’s pseudo-democracy” started, many of the old pejorative senses of democracy as the source of insta- bility and despotism were reintroduced.207 In Britain, the concept of democracy re-entered the debates of both Houses on 10 May 1796, with Prime Minister Pitt and Foreign Secre- tary Grenville taking the initiative in the Commons and Lords respec- tively. In the middle of a discussion on wine-duties, Pitt drew a sharp distinction between French and other types of democracy in replying to Fox, affi rming his old view that a degree of democracy in the mixed government was a positive phenomenon. His estimate of the threat

207 Dippel 1986, 87–96; Monnier 1999, 57–58; Royle 2000, 23; cf. Livesey’s sugges- tion that a culture of democratic republicanism was actually created in France only in 1794–1799. Livesey 2001, 13. 448 chapter five which the policies of the French presented to every established system of government was less optimistic than at the end of 1795: All Governments alike fell under its vengeance; the old forms were con- temned and reprobated; those which had stood the test of experience, whether monarchy, aristocracy, or mixed democracy, were all to be destroyed (PR, XLIV, 686). Pitt’s passing use of “mixed democracy” to refer to a system prefer- able to the French one is noteworthy. Th e statement implied that Brit- ain possessed all these elements in its constitution, including “mixed democracy”. Perhaps the British system was, indeed, a mixed democ- racy, as had been suggested by Th elwall the year before. As usual, Fox used references to the people in his reply.208 He went back to the American war to point out how “the sense of the people without doors” and also that of the Commons had then changed (PR, XLIV, 698). Fox’s suggestion was that if a preceding national crisis had been solved by a Parliament opposing the ministry in the name of the people, this could also be the case during the current war. Both sides shared a respect for popular infl uence in politics but disagreed over practical politics. In the Lords, Grenville referred to French democratic practices in responding to opposition remarks about the national economy in case peace with France was concluded. Among the opposition lords, George North, the Earl of Guildford, and Augustus Henry FitzRoy, the Duke of Graft on, both complained that the ministry had declared war in the name of saving the British constitution but had itself suspended it. Th e war had led to the rise of a military government and produced an alliance that was hardly advancing liberty (PR, XLV, 326, 330). Stor- mont, now a government spokesman, attempted to explain the alliance with a reference to the French “affi liating themselves with the people of other countries, who might be disposed to resist the Government” (PR, XLV, 330). Finally, Earl FitzWilliam outspokenly urged Gren- ville to state whether the British government was suffi ciently “forti- fi ed against the infl uence of French anarchy” (PR, XLV, 330). Th is caused Grenville to explain that the war was being fought because of the express aim of “the tyranny of Robespierre [. . .] to destroy the Brit-

208 Th e use of such language in Parliament should be contrasted with Fox’s defi ni- tion of himself as fi ghting on the side of the democrats rather than the court when writing to his nephew in 1796. Mitchell 2004. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 449 ish Constitution” as “a step necessary in order to prepare [France’s] triumph over every nation in Europe, and the dissemination of her principles throughout the world”. If the war did not lead to the res- toration of the French monarchy, “the system of democratic intrigue must be expected to run its course” (PR, XLV, 331). Grenville’s image of the French democracy was a dark one: it was a warning example. Burke, too, though no longer sitting in Parliament, continued to repeat his warnings in his published works, arguing that a parlia- mentary reform would only make England the leader of “the death- dance of Democratic Revolution”.209 Such views on the detrimental eff ects of “the idea of the sovereignty of the People” found support in other printed texts as well, in which conventional accusations of anar- chy, sedition, rebellion, irrationality, immorality and irreligion were repeated.210 Th elwall and Paine were generally criticized for propagat- ing democratic principles. Th omas Richard Bentley suggested, how- ever, that the danger of “the sovereignty and the philosophy of the people” was already over as not even the French took them so seri- ously any longer.211 Seventeen ninety-seven was a year of adversity in that the economic crisis was deepening, naval seamen mutinied and the French made an invasion attempt. However, the diffi cult circumstances did not curb the debate on democracy and the sovereignty of the people in Parliament. In May, Grey put forward a further motion to reform Parliament, and Fox used the occasion to redefi ne the concept of democracy. Th e Foxites could be outspoken: Burke was no longer present to protest, and they were themselves considering the possibility of renouncing parliamentary activities completely.212 Th ey constituted no more than

209 Edmund Burke, A Letter from the Right Honourable Edmund Burke to a Noble Lord, on the Attacks made upon him and his Pension, in the House of Lords, by the Duke of Bedford and the Earl of Lauderdale, early in the Present Sessions of Parliament (London 1796), 7. 210 [Anon.], A General Reply to the Several Answerers, &c. of a Letter Written to a Noble Lord, by the Right Honourable Edmund Burke (London 1796), 50–51. 211 Th omas Richard Bentley, Considerations upon the State of Public Aff airs at the Beginning of the Year 1796. Fourth edition (London 1796), 43–45. 212 Burke’s published writings continued to contain strong counter-arguments to Fox. In a posthumous text, Burke lamented how numerous aristocrats had adopted “the new species of democracy”. He also presented fi ft y-four arguments for the impeachment of Fox and his circle. Th ese included the suggestions that Fox had failed to convincingly renounce the idea of “individual representation” and that his policy was likely to lead to “wild Democracy” of the French kind. Burke, Two Letters, 1797, 5, 73; Edmund Burke, A Letter from the Rt. Honourable Edmund Burke to His Grace the 450 chapter five a tiny opposition group, yet they gave expression to a major rethink- ing of the concept democracy following the most radical phase of the French Revolution. Fox, in particular, had re-established his contacts with radical reformers,213 had obviously read radical thinkers like Wil- liam Godwin, and was ready to view the ancient democracies in a posi- tive light, seeing them as worthy models for the British parliamentary system as well. In his opening speech, Grey argued in favour of a reformed repre- sentation of the people that would restore the constitution, which had been endangered during Pitt’s government. Challenging the authority of the Commons, Grey suggested that if the House should fail to pass a reform “the public might pass a diff erent decision upon them; and to the public would the eventual decision belong” (XXXIII, 644). In the aft ermath of the constitutional experiments of the French Revolu- tion and radical polemic in Britain, Grey argued for what he called “universal representation”, not for universal suff rage or full equality of representation. A reform was needed because the current state of pop- ular representation did not enable the Commons to suffi ciently control the government. Members of parliament gained seats “without hold- ing any communion with the people”, without “defending the rights of the people” and without “consulting for the good of the people”. A “full, free, and fair representation of the people” was necessary to restore “the confi dence of the people” in the Commons (XXXIII, 645, 648, 650, 652). Th omas Erskine went further in his Foxite argumentation, suggest- ing that the Commons did not fulfi l its role as “the popular branch of the constitution” and that hence there was a danger that “the people [would] have no more political existence than slaves”. Th e members of parliament simply did not have “a common interest with the whole body of the nation”. Contrary to the intentions of the revolutionaries of 1688, the monarchy had taken over total control of the govern- ment while “appearing to act with the consent of the people through their representatives” (XXXIII, 654–656). To demonstrate his point,

Duke of Portland, on the Conduct of the Minority in Parliament. Containing Fift y-Four Articles of Impeachment Against Rt. Hon. C.J. Fox . . . (London 1797), 76; Burke, in turn, was claimed to have missed the fact that the time of “high democracy” was already over in France. James Workman, A Letter to His Grace the Duke of Portland . . . Against the Attack made . . . by the Right Hon. Edmund Burke . . . (London 1797), 63. 213 Mitchell 2004. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 451

Erskine cited Burke’s old statement according to which the forms of government and administrators “all originate from the people”, that the Commons was “designed as a control for the people” and that it should “bear some stamp of the actual disposition of the people at large” (XXXIII, 657–658). While rejecting universal suff rage of the French type, Erskine maintained that the Commons “should emanate from the people”. Th is could happen through “an universal right of suff rage”, meaning that everyone could be said to be “virtually and in substance represented”. Erskine also justifi ed his views with an explicit appeal to the people: “Whatever the House may think of this language, I shall not be condemned for it by the people who gave it its author- ity” (XXXIII, 654–655). His further implicit justifi cation for the reform was that it reintegrated the people into the British constitution and thus curtailed the popularity of revolutionary theories among them (XXXIII, 660, 669–670). Erskine said nothing about democracy, avoid- ing superfl uous associations with the French Revolution and knowing that he was likely to be attacked for his views by the loyalist press.214 Prime Minister Pitt was in a weaker position than before aft er political setbacks and the strengthening of the opposition in spring 1797.215 However, he continued to consistently defend the established order in Parliament, refuting claims that Parliament did not refl ect the opinion of the people. Referring to the joint war eff ort, Pitt made two references to the people: the fi rst when he claimed: “At no time were the functions of parliament more consonant with the feelings of the people”; and the second when he stated: “Th e system pursued by parliament in support of the measures of government, is the system of the people” (XXXIII, 676). No matter what the Foxite opposition claimed, the British parliamentary government was to be viewed as “the system of the people”. According to Pitt, the contested elections of 1796 showed that the opposition claims about Parliament not rep- resenting the body of the nation or the sentiments of the people were unfounded (XXXIII, 677–678).

214 See John Giff ord, A Letter to the Hon. Th omas Erskine; Containing some Stric- tures on his Views of the Causes and Consequences of the Present War with France. Second edition (London 1797), 39–40, which set out to prove on the basis of a “true defi nition of the word people” that “the Majesty of the People” and “the Sovereignty of the People” were no more than “the Majesty of the Mob” and “the Sovereignty of the Mob”. 215 Ehrman & Smith 2004. 452 chapter five

Charles Jenkinson, Baron Hawkesbury, elaborated on Pitt’s points, questioning the claims that the decisions of the Commons were “not in unison with the opinions of the nation”. As the Prime Minster had said, “the popular power was continually improving” so that “the House of Commons was now more popular than ever it had been before this time”. Th e Commons was, indeed, using language refer- ring to the people (XXXIII, 687–689). Hawkesbury introduced a new argument into the debate to demonstrate the rise in popular power. As a young man, he found it easy to regard the publication of parliamen- tary debates as a positive link between the members and the people: [. . .] the very proceedings of the House were continually published, by which the people had opportunities of knowing what was passing daily, which must have great infl uence on the House, by the opportunities that were aff orded to the people of forming their opinions from time to time (XXXIII, 689). Given that such a system connecting Parliament and the wider pub- lic already existed, there was, according to Hawkesbury, no need for opening all doors to popular participation by introducing universal suff rage of the French type. Such a reform was likely to swift ly abol- ish both the monarchy and Parliament (XXXIII, 689). William Young echoed this view, seeing the French Revolution as a providential dem- onstration of what would happen if excessive power was given to the people. Quite simply, regulation was needed “to guard people against the extravagance of their own passions” (XXXIII, 696). Fox spoke next, making a speech that was printed in thirteen extra editions in addition to the usual press reports. Th e speech, which was the most popular of all his published ones,216 can be interpreted as an attempt to redefi ne the British parliamentary concept of democracy in the aft ermath of the Revolution, leading to a more positive conception of democracy as a form of government than in the past. Moreover, Fox’s formulations made it possible to view democracy as a potentially dynamic political system with a future orientation.217 It was important for Fox to demonstrate his adherence to classi- cal political theory by denouncing democracy in its pure form. While recognizing the instability and vices of ancient democracies, however,

216 Dinwiddy 1992, 2. 217 See Koselleck 1972, 848–853, on the transformation of the concept of democracy in the revolutionary era. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 453 he also found much that was admirable in them. Th e support which democracy gave to national feeling in times of crisis had been their particular strength. Th is was something that monarchical regimes had also made use of. Th ough referring to history, Fox’s interpretation contained traces of ideas to be found in modern nationalist thought in that he saw a national community—preferably democratically gov- erned—as the ideal political unit:218 When we turn to the ancient democracies of Greece, when we see them in all the splendour of arts and of arms, when we see how they aroused and invigorated genius, when we see to what an elevation they carried the powers of man, it cannot be denied that, however vicious on the score of ingratitude or of injustice, they were, at least, the pregnant and never-failing source of national strength, and that in particular they brought forth and aff orded this strength in a peculiar manner in the moment of diffi culty and distress. [. . .] they compel us also to admiration by their vigour, their constancy, their spirit, and their exertions in every great emergency in which they are called upon to act. We are compelled to own, that it gives a power, of which no other form of government is capable. Why? Because it incorporates every man with the state, because it arouses every thing that belongs to the soul, as well as to the body of man: because it makes every individual creature feel that he is fi ghting for himself, and not for another: [. . .] (XXXIII, 715). Fox argued, like Godwin, that even if democracies could be turbulent, short-lived and vicious, “they have exacted from the common suff rage of mankind the palm of strength and vigour.” (XXXIII, 715). Th is was—despite Fox’s orthodox rejection of pure democracy—a radical and in many ways modern argument: Fox was saying that democracy based on universal suff rage could be more dynamic than any other form of government. Th e secret of this dynamism was “the demo- cratic spirit” which it inspired among the members of the community (XXXIII, 716). An increasingly modern concept of democracy now had a spokesman in the British House of Commons, even though this did not yet stand for a regime without a monarchy.

218 Th e wording of the separately printed edition was slightly longer. Th e additions are distinguished here with italics. Charles James Fox, Th e Substance of the Speech of the Right Honourable Charles James Fox, on Mr. Grey’s Motion in the House of Com- mons, Friday, May 26, 1797 . . . as Reported in the Morning Chronicle (London 1797), 17. Th e widely sold off print, which had probably been approved by Fox, thus gave a yet more positive picture of ancient democracies. 454 chapter five

In the circumstances of 1797, Fox’s views were unlikely to be con- sidered seriously, let alone universally accepted; in fact, they were brushed aside by the majority of the members. A number of Foxites had been imprisoned, and Fox himself was being constantly attacked in the press for his parliamentary and extra-parliamentary speeches, particularly those which were interpreted as advocating the sover- eignty of the people.219 Fox was losing hope of bringing about a change of government, believing that the battle for freedom had been lost to a despotic crown, and he ceased to attend Parliament later in 1797. By that time, his party had few ideological goals other than opposing the infl uence of the Crown. Some scholars have also doubted the sin- cerity of Fox’s willingness to promote parliamentary reform and the cause of the people in general, despite all his popular rhetoric.220 Th e evident popular appeal of loyal support for the monarchy during the Revolutionary War may have reinforced his aristocratic distrust of the masses. No matter what his intentions were, in May 1797 Fox had nothing to lose, and, considering the passage of the reform unlikely, he was able to give free expression to the kind of radical opinions about democracy quoted above. Th e practical conclusion which Fox drew out of his revaluation of democracy was equally signifi cant. While unable to explicitly recog- nize the French revolutionary model, he dared to present the French case as evidence of the potential of representative government, that is, democracy—the synonymity of the terms being thus explicitly stated. France was by no means to be imitated, but even so the French Revo- lution demonstrated how a “representative system has proved itself capable of vigorous exertion”. Th e French case showed how “genu- ine representation alone can give solid power, and that in order to make government strong, the people must make the government”. Not only were popular government and democracy synonyms; so too

219 John Bowles recalled that Fox had presented “the Will of the Many” and “the Sovereignty of the people” as the source of all royal power. Such doctrines, he claimed, subverted all authority, destroyed all social ties and guided the multitude to conspir- acy, treason and regicide. A Th ird Letter to a British Merchant: Containing Refl ections on the Foreign and Domestic Politics of this Country, Together with Strictures on the Conduct of Opposition. Th e second edition (London 1797), 84–85; Th e accusations were repeated in [Ghost of Alfred], Letters of the Ghort of Alfred, Addresses to the Hon. Th omas Erskine, and the Hon. Charles James Fox . . . (London 1798), 55 and 58, Fox’s ideas being declared to be Jacobin principles. 220 Christie 1982, 250–251; Dinwiddy 1992, 1, 3; Mitchell 2004. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 455 were democracy and the people, in Fox’s use of the phrase “the mon- archy, the aristocracy, the people”, already familiar from Th elwall’s writings (XXXIII, 714, 734). Such a revision had implications for the British system as well: it meant that the political elite should “call in the people, according to the original principles of your system, to the strength of your government.” In Fox’s rhetoric, this type of reform was neither an innovation nor an imitation of the French Revolution but rather the restoration of the original British constitution. He con- cluded by declaring that extending “popular representation” would make the British government stronger by winning “the hearts of the people” onto the side of government (XXXIII, 714–715). In a time of war, in particular, the people as a whole should be integrated into the political process. No-one bothered to dispute Fox’s claims, probably because of their sheer marginality. Th e word “democracy” made no breakthrough aft er Fox’s speech; it remained a term used to describe the representative governments of France and the United States at most, but it was not usually applied to the mixed British constitution.221 Th ere was no par- liamentary reform for another 35 years. Even so, the idea of repre- sentative government understood synonymously with democracy had evidently entered the British Parliament. Th e issue was never again removed from the agenda, and the reform itself became simply a ques- tion of time. No peace with France was reached in 1797. New translations of French émigré texts continued to depict the grave problems and cata- strophic consequences of the application of the notion of the sover- eignty of the people to the French regime and foreign policy, including attempts to export the notion to other countries.222 In British ceremo- nial speaking, the ministry endeavoured to motivate the political com- munity to support the war eff ort by using nationalist language. In the

221 See John Price, Th e Englishman’s Manual: Containing a General View of the Constitution, Laws, Government, Revenue . . . of England . . . (London 1797), 2. 222 See Trophime-Gérard, Marquis de Lally-Tolendal, A Defence of the French Emi- grants . . . Translated from the French by John Giff ord, Esq. (London 1797), xviii; Jacques Mallet Du Pan, Letter to a Minister of State, on the Connection Between the Politi- cal System of the French Republic, and the System of its Revolution . . . (London 1797), 51; François Xavier Pagès, Secret History of the French Revolution, . . . (London 1797), Vol. 2, 5, 459; Jacques Necker, On the French Revolution . . . (London 1797), Vol. 2, 393, 397–398; Abbé Augustin Barruel, Memoirs, Illustrating the History of Jacobin- ism . . . (London 1797–1798), Vol. 2, 148; Vol. 4, 545. 456 chapter five

Speech from the Th rone of November 1797, the King presented “a great and free people” as an agent in the struggle side by side with the monarch: I have the fullest reliance, [. . .] on the zeal, magnanimity, and courage, of a great and free people, sensible that they are contending for their dear- est interests, and determined to show themselves worthy of the blessings which they are struggling to preserve (XXXIII, 857). George III also emphasized the strength of “the public spirit of my people” (XXXIII, 857). In responding to the Lords, he listed “the laws, liberties, and religion of my people” before references to the honour of the monarchy (XXXIII, 885). All of these minor rhetorical changes, though far from changing the constitutional reality, implied that the people had a signifi cant role in the political community. Some comments in the Lords illustrate deep suspicions about any redefi ned concept of democracy, however. FitzWilliam attacked the “absurd conceptions of popular representation” and “false and pre- tended representation of the nation” in France, adding that little evidence of the existence of popular representation, “this primary principle in modern democracy”, had been seen in the enemy nation (XXXIII, 867–868). Even Lansdowne, an old sympathizer of the Revo- lution, rejected “the nonsense of universal suff rage” as far as popular representation was concerned (XXXIII, 876, 878). Th e frequency of references to the people and the nation had declined somewhat by the time of the next Royal Speech in November 1798, possibly as a result of the stronger standing of the ministry aft er a series of naval victories. An Irish rebellion had also been crushed, and the press at home had been put under stricter regulation. Even if the number of titles in which democracy and the sovereignty of the people were mentioned was high, few new arguments were put for- ward; rather it was a question of old works being reprinted. In the new titles, the idea of the sovereignty of the people and particularly its propagation among the lower classes continued to be condemned.223 Th e Duke of Norfolk and some other radical aristocrats were accused of “ascribing to the people the majesty of the King.”224 Likewise, “the

223 Arthur Young, An Enquiry into the State of the Public Mind Amongst the Lower Classes . . . (Dublin 1798), 8–9. 224 [English constitutionalist], A Cool Appeal to the Sober Sense of Englishmen: or, Republicanism and Monarchy, Considered (Salisbury 1798), 37–38. Th e author pre- the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 457 present unparalleled adoption of democratic principles” on the Conti- nent as well as in Britain was viewed with deep concern.225 In November 1798, aft er a successful year of warfare, the execu- tive power expressed an unusual degree of trust in the ability of the nation to determine its destiny. Evidently, “the security and happiness of the British nation have depended (under the blessing of Providence) on its own constancy, its energy, and its virtue” (XXXIII, 1529). Th e national victories were acknowledged to be due to “the zeal and spirit of my people” (XXXIII, 1543, 1558). Among the Lords, only Lansd- owne used similar references to the people (XXXIII, 1533–1535, 1539). Th e Commons happily repeated the ministerial interpretation that the nation, rather than the Crown only, was the source of its own well- being (XXXIII, 1549). Th e naval victories of 1798 thus seem to have created a feeling of national superiority that made this update in the defi nition of the political community possible. Th is language, however, referred to the nation rather than to the people. Th ere were no plans to strengthen the democratic dimension of the national community by means of reform.

Post-Revolutionary Visions: the Sovereignty of Parliament Becomes the Sovereignty of the People

Even if the late-1790s saw no triumph of language referring to democ- racy and the sovereignty of the people, some innovative speech acts like Fox’s constituted examples of the conceptual change that had gathered momentum with the French Revolution. It had become possible for individual politicians, particularly ones with an aristocratic indepen- dent status in either house of Parliament, to redefi ne democracy and the sovereignty of the people in post-revolutionary and increasingly modern terms. At the beginning of 1799, Parliament debated for nearly three months a proposed union of parliaments with Ireland. Th e union was concluded in March 1800 but only aft er complicated constitutional discussions. It is noteworthy that some members who opposed the

sented Blackstone’s famous book of the 1760s as evidence that sovereignty belonged exclusively to the king. 225 George Burges, An Address to the People of Great Britain (London, 1798), 4, 20. 458 chapter five union not only advocated the universal principle of the sovereignty of the people but also defi ned the British system as based on this principle. Some Foxites had talked positively about the sovereignty of the people at the time of the outbreak of the Revolutionary War, but the claims of 1799 went further. Th ey provoked fi erce opposition in both houses but also found some outspoken supporters. Fox contin- ued to play a role in this radicalization of language: the parliamentary defences of the sovereignty of the people were preceded by an incident in which Fox toasted the people as the sovereign and in consequence was dismissed from the Privy Council in 1798.226 Even in 1800, Fox publicly argued: I shall ever maintain, [. . .] that the basis of all Constitutions is the Sov- ereignty of the People:—and that from the People alone, Kings, Parlia- ments, Judges, and Magistrates, derive all their authority.227 Th e main questions in 1799 were whether the Parliament of Ireland was eligible to conclude a parliamentary union with Great Britain, or whether a more fundamental approval of the people was needed. Th e dispute allowed some opponents of the union to redefi ne the very basics of the British constitution. Even the more conservative side gave new formulations to conventional constitutional conceptions. Prime Minister Pitt, once again, initiated the process of redefi nition by branding the opponents of the parliamentary union as champions of the sovereignty of the people. Pitt’s rejection of the notion and of the current opposition to his proposal was straightforward: [. . .] it is connected in part with all those false and dangerous notions on the subject of government which have lately become too prevalent in the world. It may, in fact, be traced to that gross perversion of the principles of all political society, which rests on the supposition that there exists continually, in every government, a sovereignty in abeyance (as it were) on the part of the people, ready to be called forth on every occasion, [. . .] (XXXIV, 281).

226 Mitchell 2004; For polemic on the signifi cance of the toast, see Th e Anti-Jacobin, or Weekly Examiner, Vol. 2, No. 27, 14 May 1798, 294. 227 Charles James Fox, Th e Celebrated Speech of the Honourable C.J. Fox, with the Proceedings of the Meeting at the Shakespeare Tavern, on Friday, October, 10, 1800, Being the Anniversary of his First Election for Westminster . . . Fourth edition (London) [1800], 18. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 459

For Pitt, this type of the sovereignty of the people was not so much democratic as it was Jacobin: “this false and dangerous mockery of the sovereignty of the people is in truth one of the chief elements of Jacobinism” designed to “infl ame the passions of the mass of man- kind” (XXXIV, 283). In using words like “mockery” and “sovereignty in abeyance”, however, Pitt was not necessarily denouncing the sov- ereignty of the people as a general principle, which may be a sign of his continuous adherence to Lockean political theory. Nevertheless, the Prime Minister remained a fervent opponent of any revolution- ary interpretation of a sovereignty of the people that would constantly interfere in politics. Th e idea appeared to him as absurd as that of pure democracy. For Pitt, the British constitution remained an ideal mixture of the three classical elements: In every government there must reside somewhere a supreme, absolute, and unlimited authority. Th is is equally true of every lawful monarchy— of every aristocracy—of every pure democracy (if indeed such a form of government ever has existed, or ever can exist)—and of those mixed constitutions, formed and compounded from the others, which we are justly inclined to prefer to any of them (XXXIV, 282).228 Pitt did not denounce the ultimate origin of political power in the people, but he was uncompromising with regard to the impossibility of “the people collectively” interfering in politics in other than extreme cases (XXXIV, 282). For Pitt, the sovereignty of the people remained merely a theoretical tenet; it did not entail constant active participa- tion by the people. As a consequence, in Pitt’s view, the “principle of the sovereignty of the people strikes at the foundation of all govern- ments” (XXXIV, 284).229 No member wanted to immediately challenge such a categorical rejection of popular sovereignty. Th e offi cial theory seemed to be that the people had once been involved in the creation of government but they could no longer appeal to any continued sovereignty of the peo- ple. In March 1799, a committee of the Commons actually condemned the advocacy of the sovereignty of the people by radical societies.230

228 Th is was also published separately in William Pitt, Speech of the Right Honour- able William Pitt, in the House of Commons, Th ursday, January 31, 1799 . . . Th ird edi- tion (London 1799), 61. 229 Printed identically in Pitt, Speech, 1799, 66. 230 Report of Committee of Secrecy of the House of Commons. Ordered to be Printed 15th March, 1799 (London 1799), 14. 460 chapter five

Printed literature continued generally to question the religious legiti- macy of, and practical possibilities for, the sovereignty of the people in any form of government.231 Th e loyalist press also declared that democ- racy was the most tyrannical, factious, sanguinary and repressive of all governments. Only “delegated sovereignty” of the people was intel- ligible and practicable. Robert Fellowes, among others, defi ned such sovereignty in the following words: [. . .] “the sovereignty of the people” means, that the power which upholds, and, in fact, constitutes the strength of the government, is essentially and physically resident in the great mass of the people; but who, not being able, of themselves, to bring this power into any simultaneous action, or to make it subservient to the protection of the state and to the several great ends of social and political economy, have devolved the right of doing it on others. Th ey forego the impracticable right of universal sover- eignty, that they may enjoy the practical benefi ts of universal subjection. Th e sovereignty of all is delegated to a few.232 Despite continuous criticisms of the notion, by 1799 it had thus become possible to defi ne the sovereignty of the people in terms acceptable within the tradition of the mixed constitution. While the centrality of popular consent was recognized, the authority of government was not questioned. In some published comments on Pitt’s speech, the suggestion was that an active sovereignty of the people had prevailed in the Roman Republic and that the Saxon constitution had also contained elements of it.233 Th e most outspoken criticism came from Cartwright, who challenged “the almighty and omniscient Mr. Pitt” and, with repeated references to Locke’s ideas of a supreme power in the people, insisted: “In the primary and full sense of the word sovereignty, there is none known to the English constitution but the sovereignty of the people.”234

231 [Anon.], Th e Origin of the Gallic Plant, with its Baneful Infl uence in the Garden of Europe (Manchester 1799), 15, 18; John Bowles, Refl ections on the Political and Moral State of Society, at the Close of the Eighteenth Century (London) [1800], 16. 232 Robert Fellowes, An Address to the People, on the Present Relative Situations of England and France: With Refl ections on the Genius of Democracy . . . (London 1799), 18, 22, 39–40. 233 [Member of the Honourable Society of Lincoln’s Inn], Th oughts on National Inde- pendence, Suggested by Mr. Pitt’s Speeches on the Irish Union . . . (London) [1799], 60, 64; John Reeves, Th oughts on the English Government . . . Letter the second. . . . (London 1799), 62. 234 John Cartwright, An Appeal, Civil and Military, on the Subject of the English Constitution . . . (London 1799), 289–290. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 461

According to Cartwright, two types of sovereignty existed, the “under- ived and absolute sovereignty [. . .] inherent in the people” and the derivative and limited “vicarious sovereignty being entrusted to that legislative which the nation hath willed and created”.235 A new debate on the nature of sovereignty was coming into being, based on a radical interpretation of the original and active sovereignty of the people. A week aft er Pitt’s opening speech, Sheridan, who had defended the Irish rebels in 1798 and now opposed the scheme for union,236 com- mented on Pitt’s statements, speaking for the opposition. He thanked the Prime Minister for introducing the phrase “a sovereignty in abey- ance” and presented it as identical with his understanding of the nature of political power derived from the people. Th e phrase referred to “rights, not in operation, nor in assertion, until the great occasion calls it forth, but always existing in the remembrance and contempla- tion of the constitution”. Sheridan found it problematic, however, that Pitt had ridiculed appeals to this basic principle of the sovereignty of the people: [. . .] it seems even if the right honourable gentleman were disposed to admit the existence of such a right in any case, he is still more decided that the people should never be told they possess such a right (XXXIV, 377). Sheridan’s provocative suggestion was that both sides shared an adher- ence to the sovereignty of the people but that government wanted to hide the principle from the public. Such an attitude was not compat- ible with “the great fundamental truth on which the revolution [of 1688] was built”. Nor did it follow what theorists such as Sidney and Locke had said about the political position of the people or fi t with the idea of the British monarchy as based on “the free choice of a free nation” (XXXIV, 377). Some days later, Laurence French again summed up the confronta- tion between Pitt and Sheridan as one in which the Prime Minister held “doctrines [. . .] against the sovereignty of the people”, while the opposition interpreted the Revolution of 1688 as based on that very principle. According to French, the latter argument was wrong: the Revolution had meant the reinforcement of the limited monarchy, not the sovereignty of the people (XXXIV, 433–434). French’s description

235 Cartwright, An Appeal, 1799, 290. 236 Jeff ares 2004. 462 chapter five aptly summarizes the state of the debate between the Pitt ministry and the Foxite opposition at the very end of the eighteenth century. When the question of the union was resumed on 14 February, Ben- jamin Hobhouse, a supporter of parliamentary reform and a suspected sympathizer of the French, cited Locke on the legislative power being “delegated power from the people”. He argued that the people had originally created civil government and given all power into the hands of the legislature. In other words, “[t]he power of the legislative” was “derived from the people” (XXXIV, 474–475). Hobhouse’s application of the sovereignty of the people to the case of the union with Ireland was that “the sovereignty was with the people” and remained with them (XXXIV, 475). Like Sheridan, Hobhouse presented the Prime Minister as a supporter of the principle, something that Pitt himself never bothered to deny in later debates: “Indeed, he understood the minister himself to entertain the same sentiment, when he talked of the sovereignty of the people in abeyance.”237 Th is appeared to Hob- house as fully in line with what Blackstone had written about the right of the people to petition and even possess arms to defend their liber- ties. Th e conclusion was that the entire British political system was, in fact, based on the sovereignty of the people:238 Th is was a recognition of the sovereignty of the people in the last instance; it was an acknowledgment that the people have a right to resist their legislature in case it attempted to destroy their liberties. Indeed, this was a doctrine which formed the basis of all free governments; [. . .] (XXXIV, 475). Despite making such far-reaching claims, Hobhouse recognized the risk of anarchy related to this principle. Anarchy, however, was a smaller problem than the kind of despotism that the denial of the right of the people to resist in extreme cases entailed (XXXIV, 476). Th e practical conclusion was, he argued, that no incorporative union of parliaments should be concluded.

237 William Woodfall managed to record a slightly longer version of the same speech: “Indeed he understood the Minister himself had some idea that the Sover- eignty of the People was unalterable, he understood so, when he talked of Sovereignty in abeyance.” He also noted that the audience protested against such a notion by shouting “No! No! No!” William Woodfall, An Impartial Report of the Debates that Occur in the Two Houses of Parliament, in the Course of the Fourth Session of the Eighteenth Parliament . . . (London 1798–1799), 234. 238 Woodfall reported this passage in practically identical terms. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 463

Mitford responded to Hobhouse by denouncing the sovereignty of the people as a strange Continental notion incompatible with the Brit- ish constitution. Th e original delegation of power by the people did not deserve such a name. Th e views of the people were rather com- municated through the existing systems of government: Th at doctrine had, he was aware, been lately propagated in those books which had deluged Europe; but the consequence of that principle was, that it led to anarchy and confusion. Th e principle upon which all gov- ernments stood, was this, that the people had delegated their power to the government, and that was the only organ by which their will could be known, or that they could do any thing by. He conceived, therefore, that as long as government continued to exist, it alone could act; and that any voice from the people, except as a voice of opinion, tended directly to subvert the power of government (XXXIV, 502). Th e government thus consistently denounced the sovereignty of the people in any other sense than that relating to the original creation of government in the ancient past, and even this event did not deserve such a loathed name. Some opposition members, by contrast, defi ned the British constitution as based on the sovereignty of the people and suggested that the ministers, too, would do better to recognize this basic principle. A change in attitudes towards the recognition of the sovereignty of the people had obviously begun in the Westminster Parliament, but still only among a small minority of the members. A parallel confrontation on the defi nition of the sovereignty of the people was witnessed in the Lords on 19 March 1799. Grenville, echoing much of what Pitt had said in the lower house, associated the sovereignty of the people with Jacobinism and denounced it as an absurd innovation that was impossible to realize even in the so-called democracies: [. . .] the admission of the modern doctrine of the sovereignty of the people, would be to destroy the very frame of government; it implied in its very statement an inconsistency and contradiction. Th e sovereignty of the people did not exist, even in the purest democracy, for in the purest democracy, there had always existed a medium or channel by which the sovereignty of the whole was exercised (XXXIV, 668). One reason for Grenville’s denial of the sovereignty of the people was his rejection of Robespierre’s defi nition of the concept of representa- tive democracy. For the majority of the British Parliament, representa- tion was not to be associated with either the sovereignty of the people 464 chapter five or democracy. In that sense, the sovereignty of the people remained too modern a doctrine for most of the parliamentarians. Despite such a hostile environment, Francis Rawdon-Hastings, the Earl of Moira (later Marquess of Hastings) took the initiative to intro- duce a conceptual redefi nition. As an old opponent of Pitt, Moira had nothing to lose in the case, and readily defended the Irish in the aft er- math of their rebellion. In doing so he performed an important speech act, referring favourably to the sovereignty of the people and redefi ning the British political system by the means of this concept. In response to Grenville, Moira argued, with a hint of class consciousness: He feared that the noble lord, when he painted the ignorant peasantry as maintaining the doctrine of the sovereignty of the people, intended it should be inferred, that they who could here talk of the sovereignty of the people must be in purpose as much anarchists as the rebels in Ireland. If so, the noble lord had introduced the term unfi tly and invidi- ously. Th e misconstruction of that phrase had already done great mis- chief in this country, [. . .] (XXXIV, 704). Th e terms “the sovereignty of the people” and “democrat” were not to be used loosely to vilify all reformists as Jacobins. According to another report, Moira even repeated a defi nition for which Fox had recently been chastised: Of this principle, the sovereignty of the people, he must be permitted to observe [. . .], that it was that very principle in the Constitution of Great Britain which had placed the present Royal Family on the throne.239 Such a potentially anti-monarchical formulation was cut out by the more cautious reporter, which reveals its delicate nature. Moira went on to describe the lamentable consequences of these terms being used without clear defi nitions and turned—to avoid accu- sations of extremism and innovation—to a classical text written by Aulus Gellius (125–180 A.D.) to fi nd a universal (albeit anachronistic) defi nition for ‘democrat’: [. . .] democrat was now become, in this country, as savage a war-whoop against any opponent as ever aristocrat had been in France; [. . .] He was astonished that nobody had fi xed the meaning of the phrase, by

239 William Woodfall, An Impartial Report of the Debates that Occur in the Two Houses of Parliament, in the Course of the Fourth Session of the Eighteenth Parlia- ment . . . (London 1798–1799), Vol. 2, 484. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 465

appealing to the defi nition which Aulus Gellius furnished ready pre- pared to their hand, in the words of Ateuis Capito: “In populo, omnes gentes, omnesque ordines civitatis, continentur: plebs vero en dicitur in qua ordines patriciae non insunt.”240 Th e discrimination is as strongly marked in the English language, by the distinction between people and populace (XXXIV, 704–705). Moira thus continued, in an aristocratic fashion, to draw a traditional kind of distinction between the people in a political sense and the populace at large. But he also provided a defi nition for the sovereignty of the people which made the phrase wholly compatible with the Brit- ish parliamentary political system: When the sovereignty of the people is asserted, it stands simply in denial of the bestial doctrine of divine right. It maintains, that the welfare of the people or nation at large, and not the interest of a single individual, is the object of government. It is nothing more than the declaration of that very parliamentary control under which [. . .] the regal functions must be always exercised in this country (XXXIV, 705). According to an alternative report, Moira was even more precise when defi ning the sovereignty of the people: But a strange misconception of terms had gone abroad with regard to the sovereignty of the people. It had been stiled the sovereignty of the mob. It was the sovereignty of the property, the virtue, the talents, the genius, the intrepid courage, the honourable portions of a nation.241 Th e British parliamentary government was, quite simply, based on the sovereignty of the people. Th is did not mean the rule of all; such an idea would simply be absurd. It was a fundamental assumption for Moira, and most others, that the English system could not be founded on the power of the masses: Th e supremacy of the populace was a notion that never could enter into the conception of any man in his senses. No one had ever advanced, in any time or any country, a proposition so self-evidently absurd, as that the uninformed ought to rule the enlightened part of the community (XXXIV, 705).

240 “Th e people includes all clans and all orders of the state: the populace, on the other hand, is the name for that part of the state from which the patrician orders are excluded.” 241 Woodfall, An Impartial Report, 1798–1799, 484. 466 chapter five

Virtual representation of the British type was, in Moira’s under- standing, based on “the sovereignty of the people” and not on any “sovereignty of the mob”. Such a principle could involve “the suf- frage of all that could be wise, virtuous, and respectable in a nation” (XXXIV, 705), but not every inhabitant. Th e functioning of the British Parliament itself was, furthermore, an embodiment of the principle of the sovereignty of the people: Th e sovereignty of the people was acknowledged and recognized by par- liament, even on every new return of a member to its body; and the writs of general election were a universal, unequivocal, unsophisticated recognition of it, according to the principles and imprescriptible usage of the constitution (XXXIV, 705–706).242 Such a conceptual redefi nition of the British constitution, repeated several times by various opposition speakers in both houses of parlia- ment, did have its consequences in the long run. Quite soon, in fact, it was carried slightly further, when Gilbert Elliot-Murray-Kynynmond (1751–1814), Baronet Minto, entered the debate on the union with Ireland in the Lords on 11 April. Th e initiative for the discussion on the sovereignty of the people came from William Eden, Baron Auck- land, a former diplomat, who attacked the opponents of the union by denouncing both contested concepts (‘the sovereignty of the people’ and ‘democracy’) in the same sentence. Auckland argued that the way of thinking of the opponents [. . .] has been revived in the schools of modern democracy by the admir- ers of the sovereignty of the people, and accordingly has the strongest claims to contempt and rejection (XXXIV, 717).243 Auckland saw no place for these revolutionary concepts in descrip- tions of the British system. Th ere was evidently a need to clarify the meanings of the key concepts in the context of the union debates. Th e debate also repeatedly demonstrates the tendency of the conservative side to contribute to conceptual change with their insistence on keep- ing to the conventional meanings. While Moira had taken a positive stand on the meaning of the word “democrat”, Minto was slightly more cautious. He had studied with

242 Th is passage is reported identically in Woodfall, An Impartial Report, 1798– 1799, 484. 243 Printed also in William Eden, Baron Auckland, Substance of the Speech of Lord Auckland, in the House of Peers, April 11, 1799 . . . (London 1799), 7. the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 467

Mirabeau in France and admired Fox in politics, but he was concerned about the possibility of the emergence of a French-inspired “Irish democratic republic, or rather anarchy” or simply “democratic anar- chy in Ireland” if there was no union (XXXIV, 771, 776). He rejected the idea of the people at large running the government and saw such pure democracy as impossible “[b]ecause no people on earth, not even the smallest population in the smallest territory, could ever exercise a democratic legislation in its entire and theoretical purity”. It was also evident that “the people of England cannot make law for themselves in any democratic form of constitution” because of purely physical constraints (XXXIV, 804, 811–812). Nor was the union an occasion to awaken “the supposed dormant title of the people to administer the sovereignty in their own persons”. In Minto’s view, it was a “new and strange invention” to conjure [. . .] the latent sovereignty of the people, and [substitute] some phantom and chimera to represent that sovereignty in the room of its only true and acknowledged form, I mean that of Parliament, [. . .].244 Minto’s classical concept of democracy and conservative idea of sover- eignty led him next speak in favour of “the sovereignty of parliament” and to defi ne this concept as synonymous with the sovereignty of the people. According to Minto, [t]he sovereignty of parliament, [. . .] is neither more nor less, but iden- tically and precisely the same with the sovereignty of the people itself, appearing in the only visible, tangible or perceptible form in which it can be recognized in this country (XXXIV, 808, 811–812).245 Th ere was “the inherent sovereignty of the people”, but Parliament was the institution that made it real. In Parliament, there was what Minto called

244 Woodfall, An Impartial Report, 1798–1799, 621. Th e same words appear in Gil- bert Elliot, the Earl of Minto, Th e Speech of Lord Minto, in the House of Peers, April 11, 1799 . . . (London 1799), 151. 245 All these passages were printed identically in Gilbert Elliot, the Earl of Minto, Th e Speech of Lord Minto, in the House of Peers, April 11, 1799 . . . (London 1799), 137, 140. According to Minto’s later remark, “the supposed dormant title of the people to administer the sovereignty in their own persons” had only been imaginable aft er the abdication of James II in 1688. XXXIV, 816. 468 chapter five

[. . .] an established organ of the general will,246 qualifi ed by its frame and constitution, to apply the collective interests, and to administer the sovereign power of the state” (XXXIV, 812). A gradually modernizing concept of the parliamentary representation of the people, connected with the initially revolutionary concept of the sovereignty of the people, was emerging in Minto’s concept of the sovereignty of parliament. It must have been a conscious speech act on the part of several members, both opponents and proponents of the union, to challenge the ministerial defi nition of the sovereignty of the people in this way in both Houses during the early months of 1799. Th is did not yet represent any breakthrough of mass democ- racy, of course, particularly as Minto proposed a conservative defi - nition and anyway had diffi culties in getting his political opinions accepted. Th e attitudes of the members of parliament to the people at large as a political force had hardly become any more favourable. Minto’s description of the popular politics of London, for instance, continued to be as full of contempt as any expressed in the early part of the century (XXXIV, 812–813). However, there undeniably existed a considerable potential for conceptual redefi nition. With the reforms of the nineteenth century, it would become ever more easy to recon- cile, as Jeff rey Goldsworthy has put it, “the legal sovereignty of parlia- ment and the political sovereignty of the people”. In the reforms, the sovereignty of parliament was given a newly formulated justifi cation, Parliament being increasingly understood as representing the whole national community.247 Th e last phase of the debates on democracy and popular sovereignty to be discussed within the confi nes of this study took place on 23 April 1799, when the Commons was debating the formulation of an Address concerning the union with Ireland. Th e ministry wanted to ensure that none of the radical ideas advocated by certain members should enter the Address. With this end in mind, Sylvester Douglas opened the debate with a speech in which he systematically denounced both democracy and the sovereignty of the people.248 Th e available reports

246 “Th e general will” contains a, perhaps unconscious, reference to Rousseau’s notion of volonté générale. 247 Goldsworthy 1999, 219–220. 248 Printed separately in Sylvester Douglas, Baron Glenbervie, Speech of the Right Honourable Douglas in the House of Commons, Tuesday, April the 23rd, 1799 (London 1799). the british parliament and revolutionary democracy 469 do not record any attempts to counter the ministerial claims, and in that sense the government won the argument. According to Douglas, a lawyer by profession, “the people at large” could not be incorporated in decision-making; indeed, that was a measure that had never been implemented anywhere: [. . .] the people at large [. . .] never, I believe, in the smallest state, or most complete democracy, have exercised, in fact, by universal individual suf- frage, deliberative, judicial, or legislative authority (XXXIV, 830). Th e problem with the opinion of the opposition that the parliaments could not decide on the union with Ireland without consulting “the mass of the nation” was, according to Douglas, that it [. . .] leads immediately to the false and mischievous principle of the direct sovereignty of the people, and to that equally mischievous fi ction to which it has given rise, viz. that an original compact between the governors and governed is the only lawful foundation of government (XXXIV, 830). Noteworthy here is the emphasis on a “direct” sovereignty of the peo- ple—as opposed to its sovereignty in principle—and the point that the original contract had merely been a point of departure, not a premise on which all politics was to be based. A direct appeal to the people was out of question, and the union remained for the parliaments to decide. In Douglas’ view, it was fatal “to restore, as it is called, to the people the sovereignty they are imagined to have farmed out, as it were, to their rulers”; the results had already been seen in France (XXXIV, 831). Th e rise of “the restless and proselytical spirit of democracy” and the establishment of “a democratic republic” in Ireland was what made British parliamentarians especially concerned (XXXIV, 879, 886). Th e concepts of democracy and the sovereignty of the people remained highly contested ones, but a debate leading to their redefi nition had evidently started. ‘Democracy’ did not yet become a dominant concept in the Euro- pean political debate in the course of the 1790s. It had been a clas- sical academic word for such a long time, and its re-evaluation had only just started. Revolutionary France took the lead in introducing a new concept of democracy, which meant that responses to the con- cept remained confl icting and mainly negative. Robespierre’s use of the concept during the Terror made it highly suspect in the eyes of most Europeans: Th e Jacobin rule demonstrated to many what the worst type of democracy could be like, and democracy hence became 470 chapter five a fi ercely contested concept. According to R.R. Palmer, ‘democracy’ could stand for popular government or equality of political rights, but it could also still refer to the classical idea of direct democracy run by popular assemblies. Disagreement over the meaning of “democracy” was increased by uncertainty as to how democracy and a function- ing government could actually be reconciled. Despite its continuing pejorative connotations, the word “democracy” became slightly more common in European political discourse until about 1798. Aft er that year, according to Palmer, democracy went out of fashion for quite some time.249 In the 1860s and around 1900, many British politicians would still be suspicious of and opposed to democracy.250 Yet concep- tions of the role of the people in politics and democracy were already changing in the course of the nineteenth century.251 As the analysis of British parliamentary debates has shown, a conceptual debate leading to redefi nitions of ‘democracy’ and ‘the sovereignty of the people’ had started in the 1780s, and continued, within a traditional representative institution, in the 1790s. In the fi nal chapter, I shall summarize the main stages of this eighteenth-century redefi nition. Th e debate would fi nally result in modern representative mass democracy, though this was not to happen until the following centuries.

249 Palmer 1953, 212, 216, 226. 250 Palonen 2008, 17, 41–48. 251 Robertson 1995, 4–5; Hansen 2005, 14. CONCLUSION

In this book, I have suggested that the eighteenth-century history of democracy should be studied primarily as the history of the recep- tion, use and redefi nition of the concepts of the people, democracy, representation and the sovereignty of the people in parliamentary debates, that is, in discussions in which the leading decision-makers of each political community participated. Th is research strategy has meant a concentration on the analysis of the original arguments and exact choices of words by past speakers—as far as they are conveyed by the extant records—in the context of the debates and in the relevant circumstances of the time, including political events and structures, debates in the public sphere and the background of the speaker. Th e primary objective of this study has been to estimate how and to what extent the parliamentary establishments in eighteenth-century Britain and Sweden became advocates of the emerging more modern notions of democracy and the sovereignty of the people by giving them a clearer linguistic expression, recognition and acceptance in parliamentary and associated public debates. Th e reception of philosophical notions of democracy and the sovereignty of the people and concomitant con- ceptual revaluations and redefi nitions introduced by the parliamentar- ians have been the focus of my interest. I was interested in learning how the notion of political power being derived from the people was received by the parliamentary elites and what kinds of practical conclusions they drew from it. Th e gradually growing distance from the Aristotelian tradition that was critical of democracy, and related revaluations and redefi nitions of the key con- cepts, were of particular interest, as were old and new anti-democratic arguments. I also wanted to fi nd out whether democracy became a positively understood, progressive and future-oriented concept only as the result of the French Revolution, or whether the Revolution merely initiated a more radical stage in a process of redefi nition that had already begun earlier. Here, I was seeking a solution to a contra- diction between the established view of the French Revolution as a major event redefi ning democracy and suggestions that ‘democracy’ and ‘popular sovereignty’ had been given modern meanings much ear- lier in some countries. 472 conclusion

I also set out to examine more closely the prevalent assumption in eighteenth-century studies that innovative ideas about democracy were products of the exploitation of the developing public sphere by radical philosophy. I have suggested that the reception of such notions among political elites should not be regarded as self-evident and sometimes took place aft er a considerable time lag. Republican tracts awarding sovereignty to the people were seldom echoed in session chambers. On the other hand, conceptual modifi cations could take place within traditional systems of representation, arising out of a constant, cre- ative and intensifying parliamentary debate for and against a variety of political subjects. Even modifi cations of the concept of democracy by those who wanted the political system to remain as it was could contribute to the joint reformulation of ideas in a debate. Parliamentary records turned out to provide extensive and in many ways invaluable sources for the study of the history of the developing vocabulary referring to democracy and the sovereignty of the people. Despite a certain variation in the choice of words as a result of the eighteenth-century methods of compiling the records, the available documents allow the analysis of active uses of political key concepts in actual decision-making situations. Th ey reveal both the conscious and the less refl ected recycling of previously heard conventional arguments and contributions to change in the language of politics. Th e change could take place as a result of pre-planned revisions, but it could also happen as a consequence of polemical encounters between conserva- tive and innovatory voices, both using the relevant concepts in order to win the argument in a particular debate and redefi ning them for that purpose. As a consequence of a number of repeated redefi nitions of ‘the people’ and ‘democracy’, the meaning of these concepts became modifi ed among the parliamentary establishment and even the entire political community. Arguments for and against a particular motion presented dur- ing parliamentary debates introduced diff ering conceptualizations of political reality. Emerging notions of parliamentary government and existing party divisions together with the parliamentary practice of speaking for and against any proposition made for the expression of a diversity of views. Th ere was not only disagreement between the government and opposition; there might also be considerable diff er- ences within both groups. During the debates, all sides who wanted to infl uence decision-making were forced to present their points clearly, and this led to the introduction of central—oft en contested—political conclusion 473 concepts into the debates. New usage could come from the application of notions already presented in the published literature, but they could also arise out of the needs of the actual moment of speaking. Inno- vatory speaking in Parliament might reciprocally provoke responses in the published literature. Th is potential for conceptual innovation in parliamentary speaking is hardly surprising given that the debaters were highly aware of both the classical traditions of political thinking and the political discourse of their time. Many of them demonstrated considerable creativity in their use of language, aiming at controlling the debate both inside and outside the representative institution. Th e developing public sphere provides the most important context for the analysis of parliamentary debates. It was possible for members of parliament to infl uence the agenda of public political discourse as debates within representative institutions and in the published political literature became increasingly interconnected in the course of the late eighteenth century. Politicians addressed audiences outside the rep- resentative institution, and commentators became more interested in reviewing the content of parliamentary debates. Th e latter were closely integrated with public debates, the initiative coming either from the reporters or the parliamentarians themselves. While it could still take a long time before innovative philosophical notions introduced in tiny circles of intellectuals or ephemeral printed literature were received and applied in parliamentary speeches, conceptual reformulations introduced by debating politicians had an obvious eff ect on related debates in published literature. As debates in representative institutions are always combinations of numerous discourses, linear trends in the change of political attitudes may be diffi cult to discern. It is therefore worth once more reviewing the most important turning points and fi ndings of our long-term anal- ysis of parliamentary references to the political role of the people and democracy. Th e analysis revealed fi ve distinct periods of conceptual change in the British Parliament and the Swedish Diet: reactions to Wilkite radicalism in the early 1770s; the (simultaneous) last two Diets of the Age of Liberty in Sweden (1769–1772); the active campaign for parliamentary reform during the fi rst half of the 1780s; the confl ict between British and French concepts of democracy during the fi rst half of the 1790s; and, fi nally, the fi rst redefi nitions of the sovereignty of parliament as the sovereignty of the people in the late 1790s. In Britain, the debate of 1734 on shortening the term of Parliament, with Robert Walpole’s speech in support of long parliaments and in 474 conclusion opposition to pure democracy, was signifi cant for later eighteenth- century debates. Indeed it was reprinted and used to oppose propos- als for parliamentary reform six decades later. Walpole introduced the concept of democracy for the fi rst time in recorded parliamentary discourse, providing it with an authorized defi nition that recalled the classical pejorative sense that the concept still carried in contempo- rary public discourse. He was replying to Bolingbroke’s extra-parlia- mentary accusation that the ministry was inhibiting the functioning of the democratic power in the constitution. While Walpole recognized the existence of a democratic element in the mixed constitution, he rejected pure democracy as leading to the rise of factions, an inability to reach decisions and inconsistency in executing them. For Walpole, the people was synonymous with the populace; he expressed no partic- ular appreciation of the people and ruled out popular government. He regarded democracy—in the sense of the government observing the constantly changing “Pulse of the People” as opposed to merely listen- ing to what Parliament had to say—as a potential catalyst for the utter destruction of a consistent and balanced system. He suggested that, in such a system, the opposition would abuse the possibility it would give them to appeal to the people constantly, while the established practice allowed the ministry to govern the people in a proper manner. Th e opposition debaters, while emphasizing the need to listen to the voice of the people in 1734, did not dispute the premise that the democratic element of the constitution needed to be kept in due check. Th ere existed a more radical line in mid-eighteenth-century pub- lished literature that defi ned democracy as a form of government in which sovereignty was in the hands of the people. However, asso- ciations between sovereignty and the people remained rare even in theoretical defi nitions, “supreme power” being rather the favoured expression. Th e turn of the 1730s and 1740s witnessed the rise of a radical oppositional discourse in the press questioning the ability of Parliament, under the manipulation of Walpole as it was, to consti- tute “the People’s Power”. Seventeenth-century republican authors were cited in calls for supreme power to be reserved in the hands of the people. Democracy was sometimes represented as the best guar- antee of freedom, and the executive power was characterized as “the Servants of the People”. However, such views remained fairly marginal and were countered by governmental pamphlets, which, for instance, ridiculed opposition claims that the voice of the people is the voice of God. conclusion 475

Walpole’s fall in the early 1740s, a milestone in the emergence of the notion of responsible government, was connected with the intro- duction of the concept of popular government into parliamentary discourse, which illustrates the links between political and linguistic change. In 1741, Lord Carteret justifi ed his call for Walpole’s resigna- tion by defi ning the British constitution as a “popular government”, asking whether “in a popular government, a man who has incurred the general odium of the people, ought not to be continued in the king’s counsels”. He underlined the right of the people (the current elec- tors) to withdraw their support from the ministry, or at least the lead- ing minister. Th e implication was clear: “the voice of the people [. . .] ought always to be attended to, and generally to be obeyed.” Although Carteret’s argument was supported by Sandy’s related motion in the Commons, it did not lead to an immediate vote of no-confi dence, the government successfully questioning such strong appeals to the opin- ions of the people, but it shows the availability of the popular argu- ment for use in opposition to the executive power. Th e notion of Britain as a popular government remained a con- tested one; seventeenth-century theorists and the suggestions of indi- vidual contemporary tracts did not change the basic assumptions of the political establishment. In 1745, a dispute on the government of London caused the ministry to warn about the risks of an excessive form of popular government. William Yonge insisted on the need to keep popular power under strict control in order to avoid the inherent inconstancy and turbulence of popular forms of government. A few years later, in 1749, the invocation of the people by the parliamentary opposition and perhaps also the prevailing scholarly emphasis not only on the weaknesses but also on the strengths of democracy again forced a prime minister to respond in Parliament. Th omas Pelham regarded the concept of the people, as exploited by the opposition, as a mere rhetorical device: “the sense of the people” was an imaginary creation of the opposition aimed to serve the particular interests of a politi- cal faction. Th e Pelham ministry provided a counter-defi nition of ‘the people’, emphasizing the confi dence of the people in the parliamentary majority and expressing their trust that the people would avoid show- ing excessive loyalty either to the monarch or to the ministry. Th e ministerial defi nition of the people was viewed as patronizing by John Hynde Cotton, among others; he developed the argument that popular power had declined under the Whig oligarchy: the voice of the people had had an infl uence in the past, when the voice of the people and 476 conclusion the voice of Parliament corresponded, but this was no longer the case. Th us, by the mid-century, the meaning of the concept of the people had become an object of open dispute between a prime minister and a member of the opposition. In the 1750s, stable ministries and a victorious war that united the British nation meant a standstill in the parliamentary debate on the political role of the people. Nor did the public debate see any major developments either, the classical concept of democracy as “a monster with innumerable heads” still being seen as applicable. Some authors regarded the prevailing degree of democracy as most advantageous provided that it was regulated by the monarchy in the mixed consti- tution. Others suggested that democracy had thrived excessively since the Revolution of 1688, which could lead to the rule of the multitude and ultimately to despotism. Th e situation changed somewhat aft er the Seven Years’ War, and the subject of the political role of the people came to be seen as increas- ingly relevant in parliamentary debates as well. In his public speeches, George III had extended the political role of the Crown in relation to the people with the obvious support of Parliament. However, in November 1763, his one-sidedly monarchical speech no longer went unchallenged. Th e confrontations with the North American colonies, however, caused the Commons to emphasize the liberty of the people under George III in 1766. In public discourse, criticism of the Crown was growing, and mid- seventeenth-century republican arguments that the people constituted the fountain of all power were reprinted. Th e ministry reacted to claims about the growth of the royal prerogative aft er the contentious Middlesex election in 1768 by cutting down references to the mon- arch in the Royal Speech and recognizing the ability of Parliament to cooperate with the Crown on a more equal basis. Th e Commons was also activated to discuss the relative political power of the people and Parliament as a consequence of the controversy over John Wilkes’ election to Parliament. Th e Commons now defended, in their own voice, their role as the guarantors of a free constitution and the happi- ness of the people even against a popular vote in a general election. In 1768, “the people” appeared for the fi rst time in a Commons’ Address as a collective political agent independent of the monarch albeit one constituted by Parliament as their representative. At this point the notion of the sovereignty of parliament strengthened, partly as a result of William Blackstone’s description of the constitutional position of conclusion 477

Parliament as “a kind of democracy”. In pamphlet literature, too, the fi rst references to “national representation” and “sovereignty” lying in Parliament appeared at about that time. Th e troubles in America and the Wilkite controversy at home made North’s ministry emphasize “the just rights and interests of my people” in the Speech from the Th rone in 1770. When the Wilkites challenged the secrecy of parliamentary proceedings in 1771, the government side took a stand on ideas about the original sovereignty lying with the people for the fi rst time. Welbore Ellis rejected all appeals to an “all- ruling supremacy in the people” and denounced an inclusive notion of the people as the source of political authority. His counter-argument was that the Commons—and not the population or even the voters at large—constituted “the only people of England which the law acknowl- edges”. Th e concept of the people, as defi ned by Ellis and supported by Charles James Fox, remained exclusive: popular interventions in government were unimaginable and the idea that the Commons, as “the people of England”, could violate the rights of the people was unconstitutional. Th is Court Whig notion of the supreme authority of Parliament rejected all active popular political participation. How- ever, it met with fi erce opposition. John Dunning argued, in Lockean terms, that the people were “the original spring from which the three streams of government proceeded, and must in fact be paramount to all”. Even before the American war, ideas of an active—rather than merely original—power in the people were thus being articulated in the British Parliament. By the early 1770s, the issue of the power of Parliament on the one hand and that of the people on the other had become highly con- tentious in the British debate. Th ese constitutional debates sometimes also gave rise to comparisons between Britain and other countries with (presumably) parallel forms of government. One of the sister regimes was “the kingdom or rather republic of Sweden”, as the Speaker of the Lords called that country in 1766. At the Swedish Diet, on the other hand, the Wilkes aff air was used as a warning instance of what to expect in “free regimes” if the rights of the people were not defended. Some eighteenth-century members of the British Parliament and the Swedish Estates thus took the comparability of the English and Swed- ish political communities as self-evident—despite their one-sided pref- erence for their own systems. Th e Swedish Diet in the late Age of Liberty (1766–1772) has oft en been passed over in international accounts of the modernization of 478 conclusion political cultures, despite the fact that Sweden (and hence also present- day Finland) then had a political system based on the extensive rule of the Estates. At the same time, there has been a tendency among other historians to overemphasize the unique role played by the Swedish Estates as forerunners of what has even been characterized as “popular sovereignty” and “representative democracy”, the suggestion being that these notions had been adopted in Sweden by 1772. Our comparative analysis has shed new light on this fi eld, in which previous interna- tional comparisons are limited, dated and not based on the analysis of parallel parliamentary sources from Sweden and a comparable country like Britain carried out by the same historian. Sweden in the late Age of Liberty undeniably provides a signifi cant case in the development of the notions of popular government. Dur- ing their sessions, the Estates ruled the country, sometimes explicitly in the name of the people. However, it is less evident that the terms “popular sovereignty” or “representative democracy” could be legiti- mately used to characterize the Swedish rule of the Estates—despite the increase in the use of “the people” (folket) in political arguments and suggestions in the press that the members of the Riksdag were representatives of the people, and even despite some individual deni- als of the traditional pejorative senses of the concept of democracy. Although, by the end of the Age of Liberty, the concept of the people could be used to legitimate political stands by all major groups of the political establishment, any modern, post-French Revolution notions of “popular sovereignty” or “representative democracy” simply could not yet have existed. By the end of the 1760s, the concepts of the people and the nation were clearly being increasingly used at the Swedish Diet in political contexts, and sometimes in quite radical senses. Interesting changes of emphasis within and between the estates in their use are traceable during the dispute over noble privileges at the turn of the 1760s and 1770s, however. For much of the Riksdag of 1769−1770, these concepts still predominantly belonged to the vocabulary of the Noble Hat oppo- sition and some individual allies of theirs in the Burgher Estate. In the 1720s, many Nobles had already adopted far-reaching notions of the relationship between the Noble Estate as “the people” and the King as a delegate of that people, and they reasserted them at the time of the failed royal coup of 1756. Now it was in the interest of the Hat oppo- sition to extend their ideas to their allies in the lower orders, using the recently liberated publishing activity in order to challenge the Cap conclusion 479

Senate. Many Cap noblemen also viewed the Estates generally, and the Noble Estate in particular, as the embodiment of the nation making use of its supreme power to advance the common good. Th e Cleri- cal and Peasant Estates, as well as almost all members of the Burgher Estate, still avoided involving themselves in the debate on the popular origin of political power or the active realization of the sentiments of the people by the Estates, despite the rise of calls for extended privi- leges for the lower estates. In 1769, there were debates in the Noble Estate on the form of the constitution. Monarchy, aristocracy and democracy could all be opposed there as threats to liberty; they were not regarded as abso- lutely necessary elements of the Swedish constitution. Th e ideal balance of the Swedish constitution was seen to consist in the majesty of the monarch, the authority of the Senate and the liberties of the Estates; however, the Estates were not conventionally presented as a demo- cratic element in the constitution, although some individual noblemen such as Carl Johan Ridderstolpe, Carl Sparre and Carl Fredrik Pechlin did use more radical references to the notion of the people possess- ing power in the meetings of the Noble Estate and in some special committees in 1769. Ridderstolpe spoke openly about “the supreme power of the nation” and about “the nation, the power of which is the cornerstone of our entire constitution”. Pechlin, an opportunist politician in the pay of the Russians, who counted on his ability to keep the Swedish monarchy weak, argued that there was a legitimate democratic element in the Swedish constitution. He also supported Gyllensvahn’s suggestion that democracy as part of the classical mixed constitution was to be located in the plenary sessions of the Estates. Th is radicalization of the political uses of the classical concepts of the people and democracy seems to have come to a sudden end in November 1769. To most Nobles, the suggestion that the Peasant Estate together with the Burghers and the Clergy should be involved in economic and foreign political decision-making appeared to be a repugnant move towards democracy. Th is concept, still generally understood in its classical sense as immediate rule by the common people, remained an unthinkable option for the great majority of the dominant Noble Estate. Th ey spoke against such democracy and per- suaded their allies at home and abroad to do so, too. During the Riksdag of 1771−1772, the Cap opposition with its majorities in the three lower estates eff ectively monopolized the use of language referring to the people, now turning it against the 480 conclusion governing Hat Party, which retained a majority only in the Noble Estate. From the Nobles’ point of view, both “the people” and “the nation” continued to mean primarily their own estate and the other estates of the Diet only to a lesser extent. As further demands for privi- leges for the lower estates grew during autumn 1771, the Noble Hats became increasingly cautious in their use of the concept of the people. In winter 1772 they endeavoured to reintroduce it in its older senses, emphasizing obedience and the conservation of the established order. Th e Nobles adopted a more cautious line, and they probably regret- ted the propagation of a radicalized concept of the people during the preceding diets and in the printed literature for party-political purposes. Th e Cap majorities in the lower estates, by contrast, tried to exploit the use of the concept as eff ectively as possible. First the Burghers and then also the Clerical Estate actively redefi ned the con- cept during their campaigns for extended privileges, the obvious aim being to exclude the Nobility outside ‘the people’. In some speeches by Burghers and Clerics, it was the lower estates, and sometimes also the populace as a whole, that constituted the people and the nation proper. An awareness of the existence of a public opinion and a wider nation outside the Riksdag had been aired in the debates of the Nobil- ity in 1769, and it became frequent in the discussions of all the estates in the Riksdag of 1771−1772. It has been pointed out in previous research that the confronta- tion between the estates in the late Age of Liberty was mainly social and economic. It seems evident that the broader concept of the people was also primarily used to legitimate the demands of the lower estates for social and economic privileges to be extended to them; none of the lower estates aimed at extending political rights outside their own estate. Th e Peasants continued to talk about the security of the common people and avoided drawing any challenging conclusions even when their spokesmen followed their party allies in the higher estates and activated the old concept of ‘the rights of the people’ in spring 1772. It is diffi cult to fi nd any suggestions that all the adult male inhabitants of the country, rather than the Estates, should actively constitute the highest decision-making entity of the realm. Nor were any propos- als for an extensive reform of the complicated electoral system put forward. Radicalization in the use of language referring to the people by some Burghers in November 1771 and Clerics in April 1772 drew a distinction between the Nobility and the other estates so that the conclusion 481 meaning of the concept of the people became more contested than ever before. In February 1772, foreseeing that they were bound to lose the confl ict over privileges to the lower orders, some noblemen were ready to recognize at least to other Nobles the existence of ‘the people’ in a broader sense and to concede that the nobility were not a part of ‘the people’ when the concept was defi ned in social terms. Some defenders of noble privileges, on the other hand, tried to invoke the wider concept ‘the nation’ in order to defend the rights of the Nobility against the demands of the lower estates at the Diet. When speaking to the lower estates in joint committees, the Noble members consistently used the concept of the people in reactionary senses, fi nding support from Bishop Jacob Serenius, who might have been expected to diff er from them for party-political reasons. Outside the Riksdag, some lead- ing Hat noblemen were by this time becoming active supporters of the King, hoping that he would rescue their threatened estate. Some further observations can be made concerning references to the political power of the people at the Swedish Diet. Th e debaters had no exact concept of popular sovereignty on which to build their argu- ments; the word “sovereignty” was never associated with the people as it was used exclusively to refer to a universally condemned monarchical sovereignty, in particular to the absolutism of the reign of Charles XII. At the same time, the popular origin of political power in the past was recognized by many, the supreme power of the Estates by most, and the relevance of the sentiments of the people in actual daily decision- making by some of the speakers. In all cases, the basic assumption was that political power had been surrendered by the people to the Estates once and for all. Suggestions that the Swedish system constituted a popular government were relatively few. References to popular gov- ernment mostly appeared in warnings expressed in the Noble Estate about a development in that direction, not in positive defi nitions of the polity as a popular government as in some mid-eighteenth-century parliamentary speeches in Britain. ‘Democracy’ provided an even less useful concept for defi ning the character and future prospects of the form of government. While this concept was not relevant at all in the debates of the lower estates, most Nobles who used it during the Riksdag of 1771−1772 understood it as contrary to liberty (or privileges) and hence as a threat to the entire established system. Some publications referred to the existence of a democratic element in the Swedish constitution, but the members of the Diet were hesitant to argue in that way. Democracy continued to 482 conclusion be seen as a constitutional threat rather than as an element that was truly worth advocating. Th e classical, suspicious attitude to democracy was not questioned by anyone in or outside the Diet. Th e only logical conclusion is that the Swedish system in its mid-eighteenth-century form cannot be properly characterized as a “democracy” either in the classical sense of direct democracy or some modern sense of repre- sentative democracy. As long as the members of the political estab- lishment did not defi ne their system as a democracy, no democracy existed. It is rather more plausible to characterize the Swedish government as “representative”, though this too has to be done with reservations. It goes without saying that only a small part of the population was represented through the estate system. Contemporaries were cautious in speaking about “representation” as the offi cial view was that the assembly of Estates at the Diet actually constituted the people rather than merely represented it. Even so, in printed media and Carl Fredrik Scheff er’s advice to the Crown Prince we do fi nd some instances in which the members of the Estates were explicitly defi ned as the representatives of the people. At the Diet, the members consistently defi ned themselves as “plenipotentiaries” (fullmäktige), using a word that expressed the full power given by the electors to their representa- tives. Sven Bunge and Arvid Schauw were among those few members who used the word “representative” during the radical phase of the noble Hat attack on the Caps in autumn 1769. All in all, there is a clear diff erence in the frequency of references to the representatives of the people in Britain and Sweden, the notion being more distinctly recognized in English parliamentary language. With regard to the proper translation of the word fullmäktige as “plenipotentiary”, we should take care not to assume a complete cor- respondence between it and the concept of representative. However, because of its semantic closeness and the prominence that it has in the history of political theory, “representative” has been used in this study side by side with the more exact “plenipotentiary” and instead of alternative terms like “delegate” or “deputy”. Th e favoured word fullmäktige underlined the independent status of the members in rela- tion to their electors, something that had already been emphasized in the 1740s and was consistently maintained by the Estates. Th e alterna- tive terms, by contrast, suggest rather that the members were respon- sible for their actions to the people. Th is leads us to the conclusion that Sweden of the Late Age of Liberty can, indeed, be called a representa- conclusion 483 tive government, albeit one based on a traditional estate system and the concept of plenipotentiary rather than any modern parliamentary concept of representative. Sweden in the late Age of Liberty was regarded by the people of the time as a special type of representative mixed government with a strong popular element in legislative power and in controlling the actions of the executive power. Th is popular element was provided by the Estates, but it was seldom explicitly called “democratic” in any positive way. Th e rise of democracy in a classical sense was, on the contrary, genuinely feared in the Noble Estate. Even though the popu- lar origin of the political power wielded by the Estates was recognized in the language of politics used by all of them, explicit defi nitions of the system as a popular government were avoided. A few solitary radi- cal noblemen might make such suggestions, but traditionalists warned of the possibility of any development to that direction. Th e members of the estates regarded the representation of the inter- ests of their own estate and attempts to widen its privileges at the cost of the other estates as more important than popular representation. Along with this dispute between the estates, the meanings of the con- cept of the people were radicalized by the lower estates during the Riks- dag of 1771−1772 and in public discourse outside the Diet, following the model originally provided by the Noble Estate. However, this did not yet involve any conception of a “representative democracy” based on “popular sovereignty”. Nor can we talk of any kind of “democratic debate” without the reader drawing anachronistic conclusions about the meaning of the concept of democracy at that time. Such broad and positively understood concepts would become possible only aft er the French Revolution, and in quite diff erent contexts. A form of government based on representation residing in the Estates in the Diet, even in cases where the political centre of grav- ity was located there, should not be interpreted in a simplistic and teleological way as a stage of development towards modern represen- tative democracy. References to some “democratic” features in the system and warnings about the possibility of the advent of immediate democracy do not constitute evidence of the existence or the gradual emergence of such a system. Th e discussion about democracy still took place mainly among the Nobles, starting as part of the party-political rhetoric of the Hat opposition in that Estate; it led to some polemical statements in favour of certain kinds of democracy; and it ended with concern about the rise of democracy aft er the lower estates adopted a 484 conclusion related vocabulary to advance their own oppositional and predomi- nantly social goals. Th e lower orders never claimed that they were aim- ing at democracy; they rather used the concept of the people in radical senses to advance the interests of their own particular estates. Even the notion of the popular origin of political power was radicalized only in order to defend and broaden the privileges of each estate in relation to the others, not to reform the system in the direction of broader popular representation. Th is kind of rivalry was typical of systems of estate representation and in no way resembled a political revolution like the future French one. Only the French Revolution would force the political establishments of countries with estate representation such as Sweden to reconsider and modernize their conceptions of democracy. Even that would only constitute the beginning of a very long process in the actual democratization of these political systems and others that inherited their principles in the twentieth century. To summarize, there was an abundance of popular rhetoric at the Swedish Diet in the form of appeals to the rights and interests of the people, but this did not yet entail a break with the classical concept of democracy and the rise of a modern one. Th e Swedish coup of 1772, which ended the Age of Liberty there, necessarily aroused comment in Britain. In 1776, the Duke of Rich- mond considered that the British, like the Swedes earlier, were likely to lose their liberty as a consequence of the war in America and the way in which the government was misleading the people on issues related to the war. Th e drawing of parallels with Sweden, of course, only constituted a marginal strategy in the criticism of the government in the British Parliament. In the early phase of the American war, British parliamentarians simply ignored American appeals to the concept of the people. Th e British ministry began to reconsider its formulations in the Speeches from the Th rone only aft er the entry of France into the war in 1778, when it employed references to the people more extensively in order to appeal to patriotic feelings in the political community. Th e King urged the British national community to fi ght with “the active and enterpris- ing spirit of my people” for “the national honour and security”. Even if the American colonists never claimed to be fi ghting for democracy, the concept of democracy began to feature more promi- nently in British parliamentary debates aft er 1780. Th is is a turning point that has escaped the attention of most historians of democracy. conclusion 485

Th e reasons for the new debate on democracy were domestic ones: there was a sense of a deepening constitutional crisis aft er the Crown had been accused of disparaging the democratic element of the consti- tution during the war, and there were calls for parliamentary reform. Published literature also contributed to the rise of the vocabulary of democracy. Radical publications in the 1770s, including some by Marat, had defended a democratic government over a monarchical one and represented the people as the real sovereign. James Burgh had defi ned “power in the people” as “original, inherent and unlimited”. He had even employed the phrase “the majesty of the people”, although he regarded parliamentary power as supreme. Richard Price went further, writing about “omnipotence” in the people and depicting all govern- ment as the execution of “the will of the people”. Edward Gibbon fi rst used the exact phrase “the sovereignty of the people” in printed Eng- lish in describing ancient democracies. Translations of French works supported this conceptual innovation, depicting the Swedish regime of the Age of Liberty as one based on the sovereignty of the people. Jean Louis Delolme’s writings, though highly critical of “democratic” gov- ernment in both its English and its Swedish forms, provided a strong argument for representative government with a democratic element like the British one. At home, William Blackstone was criticized for promoting notions of sovereignty independent of the people. Jeremy Bentham also rejected Blackstone’s suggestion that the Commons was “a kind of democracy”. Instead, the suggestion that pure democracy was the original form of English government was put forward in 1780. Even if ‘democracy’ was more frequently referred to in the published literature and increasingly used as a neutral or even positive synonym for popular government, comments critical of democracy still pre- dominated in the public debate. Ideas of omnipotent popular power and the majesty of the people were rejected as rebellious republican- ism and democracy, and the role of Parliament as the voice of the people was emphasized instead. Th e British Crown certainly did not recognize ‘democracy’ in its offi cial speeches, but it had to make concessions in its defi nition of the people. Th e battle of Yorktown constituted a turning point in this respect: as soon as the news of the defeat was received in London in November 1781, the King defi ned himself, for the fi rst time, as “the sovereign of a free people”. Th e ministry combined the concepts of sovereignty, freedom and the people in a way that retained royal sov- ereignty but made the King an executive of “a free people” in a manner 486 conclusion quite unprecedented in British ceremonial speaking. Th e Commons were likewise transformed from the representatives of the King’s people to the representatives of “a brave and free people”. Th e disputes that followed in debates on the Royal Speech demonstrate the existence of a major conceptual redefi nition. Th e opposition wanted to proceed further in the redefi nition of the relationship between the executive power and the people. William Pitt the Younger set out to defend democracy as a necessary element of the mixed constitution. For the fi rst time in recorded parliamentary debates, democracy was presented in an unreservedly positive sense when he declared that the British sys- tem was unthinkable without democracy. Democracy appeared as an indispensable ingredient of the British constitution, which had been admired at home and internationally; it was now being undermined and needed to be restored. Pitt’s revaluation of democracy, repeated in 1782 and 1785 sup- ported in all cases by Charles James Fox, contributed to a rise in the frequency of use of the concept and gave it a more positive connota- tion. Th e revaluation was a response by the parliamentary opposition to Prime Minister Frederick North’s attempt to redefi ne monarchical sovereignty. It demonstrates how encounters between conservative and innovative forces in Parliament could produce signifi cant conceptual change, particularly in times of acute crisis. Pitt and Fox would retain much of their shared basic sense of democracy as a positive element of the mixed constitution even in the 1790s, when they confronted each other over the alternative French concept of democracy. Pitt continued to campaign for parliamentary reform using lan- guage referring to the people. In 1782, defi ning the constitution as one based on popular participation, he argued that democracy had suff ered from the corrupt state of the representative system and was in need of restoration. Fox went further, representing the people as a political agent independent of both the monarch and the ministry and reliant only their representatives in the Commons. Pitt’s rise to power in 1783 made him more cautious in his references to democracy; even so, his and Fox’s revaluations of democracy had already made vindica- tions of “the democracy of the country” part of constitutional debates, democracy being understood as “the popular powers of the constitu- tion”. Democracy was seen, however, as no more than an element in the constitution; it was not presented as a preferable form of govern- ment in its pure form, let alone as a prospective system that opened up positive expectations for the future. In other words, the revaluation conclusion 487 made democracy an inalienable and positive part of the British mixed constitution, one that needed to be actively defended, but it did not lead to the advent of an entirely new concept of democracy. Th e mid-1780s, with Pitt’s last motion for parliamentary reform in 1785 and Burke’s defence of democracy in 1786, provided further opportunities for the revaluation of ‘democracy’. Pitt’s supporters in the Commons willingly viewed his bill as one made by “the advocate of the people”, and not even his opponents denied the historical momen- tum of the reform proposal. Fox’s opposition to George III induced him to regard democracy as an element in the constitution that could lead to improvement. He was ready to view the constitution as an object of innovation and to make democracy and “the voice of the people” the engines of the process. Th is Foxite revaluation of democ- racy opened visions of a progressive and future-oriented element in the mixed constitution, distanced itself from the classical criticism of democracy and modernized the meaning of the concept in ways that have usually been regarded as products of the French Revolution. Even less consistent with the conventional history of democracy is the fact that Edmund Burke spoke in favour of democracy as an over- whelmingly positive phenomenon in 1786. Th e available contextual explanations cannot remove the trail-blazing nature of Burke’s argu- ment. Indeed, his statement suggests that the history of the concept of democracy in the British context might have been diff erent if the French revolutionaries had not given it a radically diff erent mean- ing. Despite his suspicions of extreme forms of popular power, Burke joined those politicians who defended the positively revaluated demo- cratic element of the British constitution in opposing the constitutional innovations proposed in the India Bill of 1786. Rejecting despotism, he saw in democracy (the Commons) a counterbalance to the Crown. In opposing absolute power, Burke regarded the power of the many as a positive antithesis to it and presented democracy as a universal phenomenon that was capable of inspiring great achievements, par- ticularly if combined with the principle of publicity. Evidently, an increasingly positive, more optimistic and future-ori- ented concept of democracy was emerging in British parliamentary debates in the mid-1780s. To be sure, it remained linked to the tra- ditional notion of a mixed constitution in its British form. It was a product of a representative institution of a traditional kind, and it was initiated and propagated by some of the leading parliamentary speakers. Th ese men may have received some radical ideas from Enlightenment 488 conclusion political philosophy and the polemics of the parliamentary reform movement, but mainly they were acting in their parliamentary speeches as innovative ideologists opposing monarchical tendencies in government. By the late 1780s, British published literature had already become less innovative in its statements on the nature of democracy, prob- ably due to the simultaneous radicalization of the concept in Holland. Nor did American debates on the Constitution contribute much to the British revaluation of the concept of democracy. Among native authors, Th omas Wycliff e summarized the radical ideas of the parlia- mentary reformers in 1786, writing in favour of “the real sovereignty of the people” and the realization of “the will of the people” and reject- ing the notion of the King as sovereign. Th e emerging British parliamentary concept of democracy was chal- lenged by an alternative one during the French Revolution. Th e central role of the French Revolution in the rise of the modern concept of democracy has been emphasized—and possibly overemphasized—by a number of writers on the history of political theory. Th is study has shown, however, that the revolutionary redefi nition of democracy, which started only around 1791, had a clear historical precedent, albeit a more moderate one, in the British Parliament. Th e rise of democracy as a goal for the future in a positive sense was thus facilitated by preceding discussions not only in radical Enlighten- ment philosophy but also by debates in an established representative institution: British parliamentarians had revaluated the concept within the old paradigm of their mixed constitution. Th e late eighteenth- century debates on democracy clearly need to be investigated as a transnational, interactive, phenomenon. British thinkers and par- liamentary speakers participated in the process by revaluating and extending the meaning of the old concept of democracy as a part of the mixed constitution. Th e revolutionaries would, of course, fi nally adopt an alternative understanding of democracy, which made the concept contested in an entirely new manner in the British Parliament as well. Th e rise of the radical French alternative decreased the chances for any revalua- tion of democracy as one of the elements of the mixed constitution of the kind that had been evident in British debates. Th e three British spokesmen for the redefi ned concept reacted in very diff erent ways to the revolutionary challenge: Fox became an advocate of an ever more radical concept of democracy and the sovereignty of the people; Pitt conclusion 489 looked for a compromise between his favoured concept of democracy as an essential constitutional element and his opposition to the poli- cies of republican France; Burke, in contrast, turned into an arch-critic of pure democracy. Aft er an optimistic initial response to the French Revolution in much British political discourse, confrontations between the defend- ers and opponents of a democracy of the French type emerged in the British Parliament. Th e transformation towards a positive understand- ing of democracy was challenged, and a period of conceptual ferment followed. Th is ferment has received rather marginal attention in pre- vious research as a result of the assumption that the British were the staunchest opponents of revolutionary democracy in the 1790s and hence unable to contribute to it, the only exception being Th omas Paine. Before long, the French Revolution provided an example for many members of the British political elite of the kind of democracy they did not want. Richard Price’s positive views on the Revolution in Novem- ber 1789 brought the explicit phrase ‘the sovereignty of the people’ onto the political agenda in an entirely new way. While reactions to the sovereignty of the people were mostly condemnatory, the debate of the 1790s for and against democracy and the sovereignty of the people led to a gradual transformation in the British language of politics, making it possible for some opposition members to reconceptualize the British constitution and see it as based on the sovereignty of the people and on a limited democracy. Th e British parliamentarians had previously engaged in a debate on their own kind of democracy, and the debate on this and other interpretations of democracy was continued in the new circumstances of the 1790s. Even this debate was not guided by mere reactionary opposition to the French Revolution but evolved into a dispute between two alternative concepts of democracy. Th e debate on democracy became heated in February 1790, when Burke and Fox made speeches commenting on the Revolution, the political role of the people and democracy from confl icting perspec- tives. Burke played a major role, defi ning the French Revolution as a change from despotism to an undesirable kind of democracy. He also accused the Foxites and other British radicals of being ready to adopt this French model. In Burke’s view, the French had exchanged their previous despotic system for an anarchy that endangered the British political system as well. Th ey had introduced a version of democracy that violated both reason and property. A “democracy like theirs” 490 conclusion diff ered both from the classical sense of the word and from British democracy as a positively defi ned and regulated element of the mixed constitution. It was guided by “the spirit of innovation, so distant from all principles of true and safe reformation”. In his response, Fox was forced to resort to the paradigm of the mixed constitution and to denounce “all absolute forms of government, whether an absolute monarchy, an absolute aristocracy or an absolute democracy”. In 1790, the parliamentarians emphasized the diff erent nature of what they viewed as a mistaken French type of democracy. Burke also published his famous comments on the French Revolution in that year, rejecting “a perfect democracy” or “absolute democracy” of the French type but still defending “an established monarchy, an established aristocracy, and an established democracy” of the British type. ‘Democracy’ was not initially a programmatic concept of the French Revolution. Nor did British parliamentarians feel any immediate need to discuss the meaning of the concept before the radicalization of the Revolution in France, the publication of the fi rst volume of Th omas Paine’s Rights of Man in 1791 and the decision on the constitution of Quebec forced them to react to the rising conceptual challenge. Th e exact meanings of democracy and the sovereignty of the people now became subjects of public debate. Paine’s book was interpreted as a defence of democracy even though the concept was not advocated in it. Paine did write favourably about the notion of the sovereignty of the people, however. In Parliament, the rise of the French revolution- ary concept of democracy forced the Foxites to publicly reject “demo- cratical principles” in order to deny the accusations of their opponents. Th is did not mean the rejection of democracy in its established British sense. Nor was it a rejection of “democracy” as it existed in Amer- ica—Fox, too, having adopted a new understanding of the American Republic. In 1791, even Pitt had no problem in recognizing the posi- tive balancing eff ects of a degree of democracy in Britain side by side with monarchy and aristocracy. Th e question of the role of democracy in the British constitution became highly topical with the parliamentary reform debates of spring 1792, soon aft er Paine had, in his second book, presented the combi- nation of democracy and representation as a solution to the classical problems of democracy alone. Pitt continued to give the democratic element its conventional recognition, defi ning the British system as a model supporting “proper democracy” with “a representative assembly” and arguing that the British form of representation, despite its short- conclusion 491 comings, supported “the true spirit of proper democracy”. Th ereby he combined democracy, which had been revaluated in the course of the 1780s, with the idea of representation, to provide an alternative model for the emerging revolutionary concept of representative democracy. Even if aimed at maintaining the status quo in the face of Paine’s claims, Pitt’s formulation contributed to the rise of the notion that the British parliamentary regime, too, was a form of representative democracy, and indeed a better one than its French counterpart. Such an interpretation was possible even on the basis of Blackstone’s writ- ings. Paine, on the other hand, was prosecuted for not distinguishing between the British and French concepts of democracy. Th e course of events in France in 1792 and perhaps also the heated debate for and against democracy in the British press forced Pitt to choose a new line of argumentation, one more suitable for the leader of a nation that was on the point of engaging itself in a war against the Revolution. Samuel Whitbread and Edmund Burke, who had been the fi rst to condemn democracy in its French form, introduced the exact revolutionary expression “the sovereignty of the people” in the House of Commons during a debate on whether or not to prepare for war against France. Th e suggestions of the National Constituent Assembly that the sovereignty of the people should be introduced into Britain had provoked Burke into addressing the issue. In these circum- stances, the reactions to the concept were naturally highly condemna- tory. However, the speakers still emphasized the novel character of the French version of the sovereignty of the people, which did not rule out the old principle according to which the origin of political power had resided in the people at some time in the past. For Burke, “the new sovereignty of the people” meant regicide, bloodshed and anarchy. In the British alternative, the King-in-Parliament, as a representative institution, formed the only “nation”, and no broader nation outside it was conceivable. Th e people could not be the source of continued sovereignty, according to Burke, as sovereignty could only spring from the monarchy once it had been established. A monarchical and par- liamentary form of government was the direct antithesis of a republic based on the sovereignty of the people. When war broke out in February 1793, Pitt openly argued that the war was being waged, among other things, over the way in which democracy should be understood. Th e British were defending “the sacred person of the sovereign” and “a mixture of aristocratic and democratical power in the frame of legislation”. Th ey were fi ghting 492 conclusion for democracy as a classical element of the mixed constitution against the French mode of democracy legitimated by the sovereignty of the people and popular representation. Pitt’s reactionary formulation pro- voked Fox, his former ally in the revaluation of democracy, to argue— notwithstanding the seriousness of the foreign political crisis—that even the British government was, like any government, based on the sovereignty of the people, as “the people are the sovereign in every state”. Th is was about as controversial a constitutional claim as a Brit- ish parliamentarian could make in the circumstances of 1793. It is little wonder that Fox was repeatedly attacked in the press for this statement. It is noteworthy, indeed, that democracy in its British form still remained acceptable in the debates on parliamentary reform in May 1793 despite the widespread polemic (including a reprint of Walpole’s speech of 1734) against the notion of the sovereignty of the people and the extension of democracy. In some publications, the very word “democracy” began to regain a pejorative connotation. William God- win was one of the very few advocates of democracy based on rep- resentation as a future goal. In Parliament, Robert Banks Jenkinson contrasted British “moderate democracy” with “a simple democracy” and “democratic tyranny” in France. William Windham denounced claims in recent political philosophy that “all government proceeded from the people” and rejected calls for “pure democracy” with assem- blies “emanating from the people”. Representation in its British form did not mean that the members of parliament acted as “the agents of the people”. Th ere were also those like the Earl of Mornington who began to express prejudices against democracy of any kind. In his view, an excessively “democratic government” of the French type let loose a “spirit of democracy” that led to idiotic ideas such as “the assumed sovereignty of the universe” in the French people. Fox was left almost alone with his insistence that “government originated not only for, but from the people, and that the people were the legitimate sovereign in every community.” Th is became just another statement for pamphleteers to condemn. Further reconceptualizations of democracy followed in France. In early 1794, the revolutionaries aimed at a democratic republic based on national sovereignty and representation. In Britain, ministerial con- cern was focused on the proliferation of references to democracy and the sovereignty of the people among radical societies. Aft er the revo- lutionary concept of democracy was so widely adopted by the middle conclusion 493 classes, the old positive notion of democracy as a synonym for the Commons could no longer be used so easily. Pitt, responsible for lead- ing the battle against France, denounced all language referring to the sovereignty of the people, while Fox, protected by his parliamentary immunity, insisted that the popular activism of the radical societies was entirely in line with the spirit of the constitution. In 1794, some authors endeavoured to redefi ne the British system as one based on the sovereignty of the people and democracy being realized in Parlia- ment and to view the Commons as “representative democracy”, but there was widespread opposition to such ideas. By 1795, the prospects for ‘democracy’ both in the positive sense which Pitt, Fox and Burke had given it in the 1780s and in its new rev- olutionary sense had become poor. Th ere were some sporadic attempts to defend the old democratic element in the British constitution, but the principle of the sovereignty of the people continued to be cat- egorically rejected by the great majority of the political establishment. Th e Foxite opposition was running out of spokesmen, but we still fi nd Richard Brinsley Sheridan arguing that the members of parliament should see themselves as the agents and servants of the people. Th e public debate saw John Cartwright’s suggestion that the British con- stitution was “a mixed democracy” and John Th elwall’s proposal that “a limited or restrained democracy”, “constitutional democracy” or “representative democracy” would be proper defi nitions of it. Th e reorganization of the French regime aft er late 1795 had impli- cations for the British debate, with the menace of the French type of pure democracy and the notion of the sovereignty of the people appearing slightly less acute than before. In the reform debates of May 1797, Pitt defended the existing parliamentary form of government as “the system of the people”, while Fox set out to redefi ne the con- cept of democracy to a degree which had not been previously heard in the Commons. He viewed ancient democracies as worthy models for the British system. More particularly, he presented democracies as paramount in fostering national morale in times of crisis. Fox gave what can be characterized as an early British expression of modern democratic nationalism when he suggested that a democracy based on universal suff rage was likely to overcome other forms of govern- ment thanks to the dynamic “democratic spirit” that it inspired among the members of the community. As for the reform, he argued that the broadening of “popular representation” would win “the hearts of the people” onto the side of the government. Th e French revolutionary 494 conclusion idea of democracy thus continued to fi nd an advocate in Fox—and Fox’s views continued to fi nd fi erce opponents in the press. Finally, 1799 was a signifi cant year in the history of parliamentary notions of the political role of the people in that some members from various political groups then defi ned the British political order as based on the principle of the sovereignty of the people. Once again Pitt took the initiative in labelling the opponents of a union between the British and Irish parliaments champions of the sovereignty of the people. While not rejecting the notion of the sovereignty of the peo- ple as a theoretical principle, Pitt opposed all appeals to a continued sovereignty of the people, something that Sheridan, as the opposition spokesman, defended. Benjamin Hobhouse went further in exploit- ing the opportunity for conceptual redefi nition, suggesting that Pitt himself was, despite his contrary claims, a supporter of the principle of the sovereignty of the people and that the entire British regime was in fact based on that very principle. Th is redefi nition was not univer- sally accepted, government spokesmen still insisting that the original delegation of the power by the people should not be called “the sov- ereignty of the people”, but there evidently existed some pressure for the recognition of the principle of the sovereignty of the people as the foundation of the British constitution. Th e same way of thinking found supporters in the Lords, too. Baron Grenville opened the door for opposition redefi nitions by denouncing both the sovereignty of the people and democracy as an independent form of government. Th e Earl of Moira responded by arguing that the British representative government was indeed based on the sov- ereignty of the people, though one that was distinct from any “the supremacy of the populace”. Th e work of Parliament itself was the realization of the very principle of the sovereignty of the people. Moira was supported by Lord Minto, who argued that “the sovereignty of parliament” was synonymous with” the sovereignty of the people”. In this redefi nition of the legitimacy of Parliament and the sovereignty of the people, Parliament appeared as “an established organ of the gen- eral will, qualifi ed by its frame and constitution, to apply the collective interests, and to administer the sovereign power of the state”. Th e notion that the parliamentary representation of the people was derived from the principle of the sovereignty of the people appeared in Minto’s redefi ned concept of the sovereignty of parliament. Such a redefi nition of the key concepts of the British constitution did not yet represent any breakthrough of mass democracy, of course. Th e pre- conclusion 495 vailing conceptions of the people at large as a political force had hardly become any more positive, and polemical publications denouncing democracy and the sovereignty of the people continued to appear. However, a potential for a conceptual redefi nition had emerged, and some publications also started to write about a delegated sovereignty of the people as the fundamental principle of the British constitution. Such redefi nitions of the constitution, repeated several times in both houses of parliament and in the press, would become signifi cant in the long run. British parliamentary debates in the late eighteenth century evidently constituted a forum for conceptual revisions that would lead, later, towards more modern notions of popular sovereignty and rep- resentative democracy.

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Manuscript Sources

Rikssarkivet (RA), Riksdagsarkivet, Stockholm Prästeståndets konceptprotokoll 1769–1770 (PrP), R 703. Prästeståndets protokoll 1771–1772 (PrP), Vol. 1, R 704. Prästeståndets protokoll 1771–1772 (PrP), Vol. 2, R 705. Borgarståndets protokoll 1769–1770 (BrP), R 1392. Borgarståndets protokoll 1769–1770 (BrP), Vol. 1, R 1393. Borgarståndets protokoll 1771–1772 (BrP), R 1410. Secreta utskottets protokoll 1769–1770 (SUP), R 3457. Protocoller, hållne vid 1769 års Riksdag uti Sammanträdet mellan Secrete Utskottet samt Secrete och Justitiae Deputationerne angående Lagarnes Verkställighet 1769 (PSUSJD), R 3480. Secreta Utskottets Berednings Protocoller och Handlingar Rörande Svea Konunga Försäkran 1771 (SUBP), R 3570.

Printed Primary Sources

Adams, John, A Defence of the Constitutions of Government of the United States of America. Philadelphia [1787]. [Anon.], Afh andling om Engellands, och Polens Borgerliga Författningar. Stockholm 1771. Almon, John, Th e Causes of the Present Complaints Fairly Stated and Fully Refuted. London 1793. [Anon.], Anglia Rediviva: No Defence of the Aristocratic Party, but the King and Peo- ple, Mutually Restored to Th eir Constitutional Action . . . London 1782. Th e Annual Register, or a View of the History, Politics, and Literature, for the Year 1787. London 1789. [Anon.], An Appeal to Reason and Justice, in Behalf of the British Constitution . . . London 1778. [Anon.], An Answer to the Celebrated Letter of the Duke of Richmond on a Parliamen- tary Reform . . . London 1794. Th e Anti-Jacobin, or Weekly Examiner, Vol. 2, No. 27, 14 May 1798. Authentic Report of the Debate in the House of Commons, on the 6th and 7th May, 1793, on Mr. Grey’s Motion for a Reform in Parliament . . . London 1793. [Author of the Political Looking Glass], Th e Duty of the King and Subject, on the Principles of Civil Liberty . . . London 1776. Bailey, Nathan, An universal etymological English dictionary . . . Th e sixth edition. Lon- don 1733. Barruel, Abbé Augustin, Memoirs, Illustrating the History of Jacobinism . . . Vols. 2, 4. London 1797–1798. Basset, Francis, Th oughts on Equal Representation. London 1783. Bentham, Jeremy, A Fragment on Government; Being an Examination of what is Deliv- ered, on the Subject of Government in General, in the Introduction to Sir William Blackstone’s Commentaries . . . London 1776. 498 bibliography

Bentham, Jeremy, An Essay on Political Tactics, or Inquiries Concerning the Discipline and Mode of Proceeding Proper to be Observed in Political Assemblies; . . ., James, Michael et al. (eds). Oxford 1999 (1791, 1738−43). Bentley, Th omas Richard, Considerations upon the State of Public Aff airs at the Begin- ning of the Year 1796. Th e fourth edition. London 1796. Berkeley, George, A Discourse Addressed to Magistrates and Men of Authority . . . Dublin 1738. Blackstone, William, Commentaries on the Laws of England, Vol. 1. Oxford 1765. Bolingbroke, Henry, A Dissertation upon Parties; in Several Letters to Caleb D’Anvers, Esq; Dedicated to the Right Honourable Sir Robert Walpole. Th e third edition. Lon- don 1735. Bondeståndets riksdagsprotokoll 1769–1770 (BdP). Sten Landahl (ed.). Stockholm 1975. Bondeståndets riksdagsprotokoll 1771–1772 (BdP). Sten Landahl (ed.). Stockholm 1978. Bowles, John, Th e Dangers of Premature Peace . . . London 1795. ——, A Th ird Letter to a British Merchant: Containing Refl ections on the Foreign and Domestic Politics of this Country, Together with Strictures on the Conduct of Opposi- tion. Th e second edition. London 1797. ——, Refl ections on the Political and Moral State of Society, at the Close of the Eight- eenth Century. London [1800]. Brandenburg, Henrik Albrekt, Swenska Odal-Folkets Rätt, Sammandragen i Project til et dem gemensamt tilhörigt Privilegium, Wid Riksdagen År 1771. Stockholm 1771. [Anon.], Bref till utgifwaren af folkets röst. Upsala 1769. [Anon.], Bref til politiske eqvilibristen, Eller hwar på en Patriots tankar . . . Stockholm 1769. [Briton], Public Clamours Traced to Th eir Original Sources . . . London 1741. Burges, George, An Address to the People of Great Britain. London 1798. Burgh, James, Political Disquisitions: or, an Enquiry into Public Errors, Defects, and Abuses . . . Vol. 1. London 1774–1775. Burke, Edmund, A Vindication of Natural Society . . . London 1756. ——, Th ought on the Cause of the Present Discontents. London 1770. ——, Refl ections on the Revolution in France. London 1790. ——, Substance of the Speech of the Right Honourable Edmund Burke, in thr [sic] Debate on the Army Estimates . . . London 1790. ——, An Appeal from the New to the Old Whigs, in Consequence of some late Discussions in Parliament, Relative to the Refl ections on the French Revolution. London [1791]. ——, A Letter from the Right Honourable Edmund Burke to a Noble Lord, on the Attacks made upon him and his Pension, in the House of Lords, by the Duke of Bed- ford and the Earl of Lauderdale, early in the Present Sessions of Parliament. London 1796. ——, A Letter from the Rt. Honourable Edmund Burke to His Grace the Duke of Port- land, on the Conduct of the Minority in Parliament. Containing Fift y-Four Articles of Impeachment against Rt. Hon. C.J. Fox . . . London 1797. ——, Two letters on the Conduct of our Domestick Parties, with Regard to French Politicks . . . London 1797. Burlamaqui, Jean-Jacques, Th e Principles of Politic Law: Being a Sequel to Th e Prin- ciples of Natural Law . . . London 1752. Campbell, John, Liberty and Right: or, an Essay, Historical and Political, on the Con- stitution and Administration of Great Britain . . . London 1747. Cartwright, John, Take Your Choice! . . . London 1776. ——, Th e People’s Barrier Against Undue Infl uence and Corruption . . . London 1780. ——, Th e Commonwealth in Danger; with an Introduction, Containing Remarks on some late Writings of Arthur Young, Esq. London 1795. bibliography 499

——, An Appeal, Civil and Military, on the Subject of the English Constitution . . . London 1799. Cawthorne, Joseph, A Constitutional Defence of Government. London 1782. Chalmers, George, Second Th oughts: or, Observations upon Lord Abingdon’s Th oughts on the Letter of Edmund Burke, Esq. To the Sheriff s of Bristol. London 1777. Chambers, Ephraim, Cyclopædia: or, an Universal Dictionary of Arts and Sciences . . . Vols. 1–2. London 1728. Cobbett’s Parliamentary History of England: From the Norman Conquest in 1066 to the Year 1803. London 1806–1820. [Common Sense], A Letter from Common Sense, Addressed to the King and People. London [1791]. [Anon.], Th e Constitutional Right of the Legislature of Great Britain. To Tax British Colonies in America, Impartially States. London 1768. Cooper, Th omas, A Reply to Mr. Burke’s Invective Against Mr. Cooper, and Mr. Watt, in the House of Commons, on the 30th of April, 1792. London 1792. Courtenay, John, Philosophical Refl ections on the late Revolution in France, and the Conduct of the Dissenters in England; in a Letter to the Rev. Dr. Priestley. London 1790. [Anon.], Th e Crisis, or Refl ections on the Proposed Settlement of the British Govern- ment. Dublin 1789. Dallas, George, Th oughts upon our Present Situation, with Remarks upon the Policy of a War with France. London 1793. Th e Debate in the House of Commons, on the Repeal of the Corporation and Test Acts, March 2d, 1790 . . . London 1790. Delolme, Jean Louis, Th e Constitution of England, or an Account of the English Gov- ernment . . . London 1775. Demosthenes, Th e Orations of Demosthenes, Delivered on Occasions of Public Delib- eration . . . London 1771. [Anon.], Dialogues between a Reformer and an Anti-Revolutionist. London 1794. [Dodsley, Robert ], Th e Preceptor: Containing a General Course of Education . . . Vol. 1. Dublin 1749. Vol. 2. Th e second edition. London 1754. Douglas, Sylvester, Speech of the Right Honourable Douglas in the House of Commons, Tuesday, April the 23d, 1799. London 1799. Dulany, Daniel, Considerations on the Propriety of Imposing Taxes in the British Col- onies . . . Th e second edition. Annapolis 1765. Dyche, Th omas, A New General English Dictionary . . . Th e third edition. London 1740. Eden, William, Substance of the Speech of Lord Auckland, in the House of Peers, April 11, 1799 . . . London 1799. Edwards, Samuel, A New Compendium of Geography . . . Dublin 1765. Elliot, Gilbert, Th e Speech of Lord Minto, in the House of Peers, April 11, 1799 . . . Lon- don 1799. [English Constitutionalist], A Cool Appeal to the Sober Sense of Englishmen: or, Repub- licanism and Monarchy, Considered. Salisbury 1798. [English freeholder], Th e Sentiments of an English Freeholder, on the Late Decision of the Middlesex Election. London 1769. Erskine, James, Th e Fatal Consequences of Ministerial Infl uence: or, the Diff erence between Royal Power and Ministerial Power, Truly Stated . . . London 1736. [Anon.], An Essay on Civil Government. In two parts . . . London 1743. [Anon.], An Essay on Liberty and Independency: Being an Attempt to prove, that the People under a Popular Form of Government, May be as much Slaves, as those Sub- ject to the Arbitrary Will of One Man. London 1747. [Anon.], Th e Expediency of a Revolution Considered: In Which the Advantages held out to the People are Examined and Refuted. London 1793. 500 bibliography

[Anon.], Experience Preferable to Th eory. An Answer to Dr. Price’s Observations . . . London 1776. Fenning, Daniel, Th e Royal English Dictionary: or, a Treasury of the English Lan- guage . . . London 1761. Ferguson, Adam, An Essay on the History of Civil Society. Edinburgh 1767. ——, Th e History of the Progress and Termination of the Roman Republic, Vol. 3. Lon- don 1783. Flood, Henry, Th e Speech and Proposition of the Right Honourable Henry Flood, in the House of Commons . . . on a Reform of the Representation in Parliament. London 1790. Folkets Röst, Vols. 1–2, 16. Stockholm 1769. Fox, Charles James, Th e Speech of . . . Charles James Fox, at a General Meeting of the Electors of Westminster, Assembled in Westminster-Hall, July 17, 1782 . . . London [1782]. ——, Th e Speeches of the Right Hon. C.J. Fox, in the British House of Commons, on Feb. fi rst and twelft h, M,DCC,XCIII. London 1793. ——, Th e Substance of the Speech of the Right Honourable Charles James Fox, on Mr. Grey’s Motion in the House of Commons, Friday, May 26, 1797 . . . as Reported in the Morning Chronicle. London 1797. ——, Th e Celebrated Speech of the Honourable C.J. Fox, with the Proceedings of the Meeting at the Shakespeare Tavern, on Friday, October, 10, 1800, Being the Anniver- sary of his First Election for Westminster . . . Th e fourth edition. London [1800]. Th e Federalist: A Collection of Essays, Written in Favour of the new Constitution, as Agreed upon by the Federal Convention, September 17, 1787, Vols. 1–2. New York [1788]. Fellowes, Robert, An Address to the People, on the Present Relative Situations of England and France: With Refl ections on the Genius of Democracy . . . London 1799. [A Free-Born Englishman], Paine’s Political and Moral Maxims; Selected from the Fift h Edition of Rights of Man, Part I. and II . . . London 1792. [Friend to the Public], Th e Delusive and Dangerous Principles of the Minority, Exposed and Refute . . . London 1778. Frink, Th omas, A King Reigning in Righteousness, and Princes Ruling in Judgement. A Sermon . . . Boston 1758. Fry, William, A New Vocabulary of the most Diffi cult Words in the English Lan- guage . . . London 1784. [Anon.], A General Reply to the Several Answerers, &c. of a Letter Written to a Noble Lord, by the Right Honourable Edmund Burke. London 1796. [Gentleman of the Middle Temple], Th e Out-of-Door Parliament. London 1780. [Ghost of Alfred], Letters of the Ghost of Alfred, Addresses to the Hon. Th omas Erskine, and the Hon. Charles James Fox . . . London 1798. Gibbon, Edward, Th e History of the Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire, Vol. 1. London 1776. Giff ord, John, A Letter to the Hon. Th omas Erskine; Containing some Strictures on his Views of the Causes and Consequences of the Present War with France. Th e second edition. London 1797. Godwin, William, Enquiry Concerning Political Justice, and its Infl uence on Morals and Happiness. Th e second edition corrected . . . Vol. 2. London 1796 (1793). Goldsmith, Oliver, Th e Citizen of the World; or Letters from a Chinese Philosopher, Residing in London . . . Vol. 1. London 1762. ——, Th e English Constitution . . . [London 1793]. Goodricke, Henry, Observations on Dr. Price’s Th eory and Principles of Civil Liberty and Government . . . York 1776. [Gracchus], An Appeal to Britons. London 1794. bibliography 501

[Graduate of the University of Cambridge], Considerations on the Causes and Alarming Consequences of the Present War, and the Necessity of Immediate Peace. London 1794. Green, James, An Attempt to Explain the Principles of the British Constitution . . . New- castle 1790. Hall, Robert, An Apology for the Freedom of the Press, and for General Liberty. To which are Prefi xed Remarks on Bishop Horsley’s Sermon, Preached on the Th irtieth of January last. Th e third edition. London 1794. Hamilton, William Gerard, Parliamentary Logick: To Which Are Subjoined Two Speeches Delivered in the House of Commons of Ireland, and Other Pieces. London 1808. Harrington, James, Th e Oceana of James Harrington, Esq; and his other works . . . Dublin 1737. Hatsell, John, Precedents of Proceedings in the House of Commons; under Separate Titles. With Observations, Vol. 2, London 1818 (reprinted Shannon 1971). Head, Erasmus, Loyalty Recommended on Proper Principles. A Sermon Preached in the Cathedral Church of Carlisle, During the Special Assizes held there, for the Trial of the Rebels . . . on Sunday, September 14, 1746. London 1747. Hearn, Th omas, A Short View of the Rise and Progress of Freedom in Modern Europe, as Connected with the Causes which led to the French Revolution. London 1793. Hervey, Frederick William, A New Friend on an Old Subject. London 1791. [Anon.], An Historical Sketch of the French Revolution from its Commencement to the Year 1792. Dublin 1792. Th e History and Proceedings of the House of Commons of Great Britain (HPHC), Vols. 1–3. London 1741. Hobbes, Th omas, Th e Moral and Political Works of Th omas Hobbes of Malmesbury. Never Before Collected Together . . . London 1750. Home, Henry, Sketches of the History of Man . . . Vol. 1. Edinburgh 1774. Hughes, Rice, A Letter on the Meeting at the Crown and Anchor Tavern, on the Four- teenth of July, 1791, for the Purpose of Celebrating the Anniversary of the Revolution in France . . . London [1791]. Hutcheson, Francis, A Short Introduction to Moral Philosophy, in Th ree Books; Con- taining the Elements of Ethicks and the Law of Nature. Glasgow 1747. [Impartial Observer in London], Fact Without Fallacy: or, Constitutional Principles Contrasted with the Ruinois Eff ects of Unconstitutional Practices . . . London 1793. [A.L.], An Impartial Address to all Parties: By a Well-Wisher to the Constitution. London 1795. An Impartial Report of the Debates Th at Occur in the Two Houses of Parliament, Wil- liam Woodfall (ed.), Vols. 1–2. London 1794. An Impartial Report of the Debates that Occur in the Two Houses of Parliament, in the Course of the Fourth Session of the Eighteenth Parliament . . . William Woodfall (ed.), Vol. 2. London 1798–1799. [Ingman, Carl], Svenska Folkets Röst, Framburen Inför Rikets Församlade Ständer Vid Riksdagen 1771. Stockholm 1771. [Invariatus, Pileus], Folkets Rätt, At Obehindrat Wälja Riksdagsmän, Såsom En wäsen- telig del af Nationens Frihet. Stockholm 1771. [Anon.], Is All We Want Worth a Civil War? Or Conciliatory Th oughts upon the Pres- ent Crisis. London 1792. Jackson, Jonathan, Th oughts upon the Political Situation of the United States of Amer- ica . . . Worcester, Massachusetts [1788]. Johnson, Samuel, A Dictionary of the English Language . . . Vol. 1. London 1756. Jones, David, Th e Welsh Freeholder’s Farawell Epistles to the Right Rev. Samuel Lord Bishop (lately, of St. David’s) now, of Rochester . . . London 1794. [Junius], A Complete Collection of Junius’s Letters . . . London 1770. 502 bibliography

Knox, William, Considerations on the Present State of the Nation. Addresses to the . . . Members of the two Houses of Parliament . . . London 1789. ——, Extra Offi cial State Papers, Vol. 1. London 1789. Kryger, J.F., Tankar om et Nationelt Intresse i Fria Stater och i synnerhet i Swerige. Stockholm 1769. Leijonancker, Fredrik Vilhelm, Fri Frågor, Til Et Fritt och Sjelft änkande Folk. Stock- holm 1769. Lennox, Charles, A Letter from His Grace the Duke of Richmond to Lieutenant Colonel Sharman, Chairman to the Committee of Correspondence . . . London 1792. [Anon.], A Letter to a Member of the National Assembly: Containing Remarks on the Proceedings of that Legislative Body; Strictures on the Political Doctrines of Mr. Burke and Mr. Paine; and a View of the Progress of the British Constitution. London 1791. [Anon.], A Letter to the Rt. Hon. Lord Grenville, one of His Majesty’s Principal Sec- retaries of State, &c. in which the Present State of the British Nation is Consid- ered . . . London 1793. [Anon.], Letters to Th omas Paine; in Answer to his late Publication on the Rights of Man: Shewing his Errors on that Subject; and Proving the Fallacy of his Principles as Applied to the Government of this Country. London 1791. [Anon.], A Letter to the Right Honourable William Pitt, on his Apostacy from the Cause of Parliamentary Reform . . . London 1792. Locke, John, Two Treatises of Government: In the Former, the False Principles and Foundation of Sir Robert Filmer, and his Followers are Detected and Overthrown. Th e latter, is an Essay Concerning the true Original, Extent, and end of Civil-Govern- ment. London 1713 (1689). Lofft , Capel, Remarks on the Letter of Rt. Hon. Edmund Burke . . . Dublin 1791. Th e London Corresponding Society’s Addresses and Resolutions, (Reprinted, and Dis- tributed Gratis.) London [1792]. Th e London Magazine, and Monthly Chronologer, Vols. 5–6, 9, 15. London [1736–1746]. [Anon.], Th e London Magazine: Or, Gentleman’s Monthly Intelligencer, Vol. 44. Lon- don [1774]. ——, A Parallel between the English Constitution and the Former Government of Sweden . . . London 1772. ——, An Essay on Constitutional Liberty: Wherein the Necessity of Frequent Elections of Parliament is Shewn to be Superseded by the Unity of the Executive Power. London 1780. Mably, Abbé de, Observations on the Government and Laws of the United States of America . . . London [Amsterdam] 1784. Macaulay, Catharine, Observations on the Refl ections of the Right Hon. Edmund Burke, on the Revolution in France . . . Boston 1791. Mackintosh, James, Vindiciæ gallicæ: Defence of the French Revolution and its Eng- lish Admirers Against the Accusations of the Right Hon. Edmund Burke . . . London 1791. Macleod, Norman, Letters from Colonel Macleod, Member of Parliament for Inverness- shire, to the Chairman of the Association for Parliamentary Reform in Scotland. [London 1793]. Mallet Du Pan, Jacques, Letter to a Minister of State, on the Connection between the Political System of the French Republic, and the System of its Revolution . . . London 1797. Marat, Jean Paul, Chains of Slavery: A Work Wherein the Clandestine and Villainous Attempts of Princes to Ruin Liberty are Pointed out . . . London 1774. [Anon.], Medborgelighetens och Enighetens Echo, Wid Genomläsandet af Protocollerne och Projecterade Swea Konunga-Försäkran. Stockholm 1771. bibliography 503

[Member of the Honourable Society of Lincoln’s Inn], Th oughts on National Indepen- dence, Suggested by Mr. Pitt’s Speeches on the Irish Union . . . London [1799?]. [Member of the Jockey Club], An Answer to Th ree Scurrilous Pamphlets, Entitled Th e Jockey Club. Th e second edition. London [1792]. Miles, William Augustus, Th e Author of Th e Letter to the Duke of Graft on Vindicated from the Charge of Democracy . . . London 1794. —— A Letter to the Duke of Graft on . . . London 1794. [Anon.], Th e Misfortunes of Geneva; or, a Picture of the Calamities that Th reaten, in the Present Crisis, the most Moderate Governments of Europe . . . London [1792]. Montagu, Edward Wortley, Refl ections on the Rise and Fall of the Antient Republicks. Adapted to the Present State of Great Britain. London 1759. Montesquieu, Charles de Secondat, Baron de, Th e Spirit of Laws: Translated from the French of M. de Secondat, Baron de Montesquieu. With Corrections and Additions Communicated by the Author. Vol. 1. London 1750 (1748). Montesquieu, Charles-Louis de Secondat, Oeuvres de M. de Montesquieu, Vol. 1. London 1767. Montin, Johan, Borgelig Regering til des Uprinnelse och Art, Beskådad. Stockholm 1749. Mortimer, Th omas, Th e Elements of Commerce, Politics and Finances . . . London 1780. Murray, William Vans, Political Sketches, Inscribed to his Excellency John Adams . . . London 1787. [Anon.], Mörker och Förwillelse För Swenska Folket, I Politiska Saker. Stockholm 1770. Necker, Jacques, An Essay on the True Principles of Executive Power in Great States . . . Vol. 1. London 1792. ——, On the French Revolution . . . Vol. 2. London 1797. Nedham, Marchamont, Th e Excellencie of a Free State. London 1767. [Anon.], Nödig Granskning Af En så kallad Patriots Tankar Om Grundlagens Nödwän- diga Förbättring. Stockholm 1769. Nordencrantz, Anders, Undersökning om de rätta Orsakerne til den Blandning som skedt af Lagstift ande, Redofordrande och Redoskyldige Magternes Gjöromål . . . Stock- holm 1770. O’Connor, Arthur, Th e Measures of Ministry to Prevent a Revolution, are the Certain Means of Bringing it on. Th e third edition. London 1794. [Offi cer], Letter on the Present Associations . . . London 1793. [Anon.], Th e Origin of the Gallic Plant, with its Baneful Infl uence in the Garden of Europe. Manchester 1799. Otis, James, Th e Right of the British Colonies Asserted and Proved. [London 1764]. Pagès, François Xavier, Secret History of the French Revolution . . . Vol. 2. London 1797. Paine, Th omas, Common Sense; Addressed to the Inhabitants of America . . . A new edi- tion. [London] 1776. ——, Rights of Man: Being an Answer to Mr. Burke’s Attack on the French Revolu- tion . . . London 1791. ——, Rights of Man. Part the Second. Combining Principle and Practice . . . Th e second edition. London 1792. Parliamentary History, William Cobbett (ed.), London 1806–1820. Th e Parliamentary Register; or, History of the Proceedings and Debates of the House of Commons (PR). London 1775–1790. Th e Parliamentary Register; or, History of the Proceedings and Debates of the House of Commons (PR). London 1782–1796. Th e Parliamentary Register; or, History of the Proceedings and Debates of the House of Commons (PR). London 1797–1800. 504 bibliography

Parliamentary Register . . . Speech of the Right Honourable William Pitt . . . on Friday, Feb. 1, 1793. London 1793. [Anon.], Th e People the Best Governors: or A Plan of Government Founded on the Just Principles of Natural Freedom. [United States 1776]. [Anon.], A Perspective View of the Complexion of some late Elections, and of the Can- didates. London 1768. Pigott, Charles, A Political Dictionary: Explaining the True Meaning of Words . . . London 1795. Pitt, William, Speech of the Right Honourable William Pitt, in the House of Commons, Th ursday, January 31, 1799 . . . Th e third edition. London 1799. Plan of the New Constitution for the United States of America, Agreed upon in a Con- vention of the States . . . London 1787. Plato, Th e Republic of Plato. In ten books. Translated from the Greek by H. Spens, D.D. With a Preliminary Discourse Concerning the Philosophy of the Ancients by the Translator . . . Glasgow 1763. Political Papers, Chiefl y Respecting the Attempt of the County of York . . . to Eff ect a Reformation of the Parliament of Great-Britain: Collected by the Rev. Christopher Wyvill . . . Vol. 6. York, [1794–1802]. [Anon.], Th e Politician’s Dictionary; or, a Summary of Political Knowledge . . . Vol. 1. London 1775. [Anon.], Politiske Refl exioner, Vol. 7. Stockholm 1771. Polybius, Two Extracts from the Sixth Book of the General History of Polybius . . . Trans- lated from the Greek . . . By Mr. Hampton. London 1764. Pownall, Th omas, A Memorial Addresses to the Sovereigns of America. London 1783. [Presbyterian of the Kirk of Scotland], A Letter to the Right Honourable William Pitt . . . London [1790]. Price, John, Th e Englishman’s Manual: Containing a General View of the Constitution, Laws, Government, Revenue . . . of England . . . London 1797. Price, Richard, Observations on the Nature of Civil Liberty, the Principles of Govern- ment, and the Justice and Policy of the War with America . . . Th e second edition. London 1776. ——, A Sermon, Delivered to a Congregation of Protestant Dissenters, at Hackney, on the 10th of February Last, Being the Day Appointed for a General Fast. Th e second edition. London 1779. ——, A Discourse on the Love of Our Country, Delivered on Nov. 4, 1789 . . . London 1789. Priestley, Joseph, An Essay on a Course of Liberal Education for Civil and Active Life . . . London, 1768. ——, An Essay on the First Principles of Government; and on the Nature of Political, Civil, and Religious Liberty. Dublin 1768. ——, Letters to the Right Honourable Edmund Burke, Occasioned by his Refl ec- tions . . . Th e third edition. Birmingham 1791. Proby, John Joshua, Copy of a Letter from . . . Lord Carysfort, to the Huntingdonshire Committee . . . [London 1780]. —— Th oughts on the Constitution, with a View to the Proposed Reform in the Repre- sentation of the People, and Duration of Parliaments. London 1783. Proceedings of the General Meeting of the Freeholders of the County of York, held at the Castle of York, March 25, 1784. York 1784. Quist, Johan Fredric, Tal om Svenska Folkets Glädje och Hopp vid Konung Gustav IIIs Höga Kröning, Den 29 Maji 1772. Örebro 1772. Qvanten, Carl von, Tankar om Regerings-Sättet; Med bifogade Anmärkningar öfwer Finance-Wärkets bidragande til Frihetens både säkerhet och bestånd. Stockholm 1769. Raleigh, Walter, Th e works of Sir Walter Ralegh, Kt. Political, Commercial, and Philo- sophical . . . Vol. 1. London 1751. bibliography 505

Raynal, Abbé de, A Philosophical and Political History of the Settlements and Trade of the Europeans in the East and West Indies . . . Translated . . . by J. Justamond, Vol. 2. Dublin, 1776, 31; Vol. 4. London 1776. Reeves, John, Th oughts on the English Government . . . Letter the second . . . London 1799. [Anon.], Refl exioner, Angående den lagstift ande magten i Engeland, med mera. Stock- holm [1771]. [Anon.], Refl exioner angående Romerska Republiquens olyckelige tilstånd, eft er Konunga-Magtens afskaff ande. Stockholm 1771. [Anon.], Remarks on Dr. Price’s Observations . . . London 1776. [Anon.], Remarks on the Proceedings of the Society, who Style Th emselves “Th e Friends of the People”: and Observations on the Principles of Government, as Applicable to the British Constitution . . . London 1792. Th e Remembrancer, or Impartial Repository of Public Events . . . London [1775–1784]. Report of Committee of Secrecy of the House of Commons. Ordered to be Printed 15th March, 1799. London 1799. [Anon.], Rights of Citizens; Being an Inquiry into some of the Consequences of Social Union, and an Examination of Mr. Paine’s Principles Touching Government. Lon- don [1791]. Riqeti, Gabriel-Honoré de, Comte de Mirabeau, Enquiries Concerning Lettres de Cachet, the Consequences of Arbitrary Imprisonment . . . Vol. 1. London 1787. Rollin, Charles, Th e Method of Teaching and Studying the Belles Letters . . . London 1734. [Rothman, J. G.], Philolalus Parrhesiastes, Eller Den Pratsjuke Fritalaren. En Wecko- Skrift . Första Flocken, No. 21. [Stockholm] 1768. Rous, George, Th oughts on Government: Occasioned by Mr. Burke’s Refl ections, &c. Th e second edition. London 1790. Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, Emilius and Sophia: or, a New System of Education, Vol. 4. London 1763. ——, A Treatise on the Social Compact: or the Principles of Politic Law . . . London 1764. ——, Th e Miscellaneous Works of J.J. Rousseau . . . Vol. 3. Edinburgh 1774. ——, An Inquiry into the Nature of the Social Contract; or Principles of Political Right. Translated from the French of John James Rousseau. Dublin 1791. Rutherforth, Th omas, Institutes of Natural Law . . . Vol. 2. Th e second edition. Cam- bridge 1779. Sallust, Th e Works of Sallust, Translated into English. With Political Discourses upon that Author . . . London 1744. Salvius, David, Påminnelser angående successions-rättigheten i Sweriges rike . . . Stock- holm 1720. Scheff er, Carl Fredric, Tal, Om Förbindelsen, Imellan Grund-Lagarnas Art och Folkets Sällhet, Som Aft er Dem Styras Skal; Hållit Uti Kongl. Vetenskaps Academien, Vid Praesidii Afl äggande, den 28 October 1772. Stockholm 1772. [Schönberg, Anders], Anmärkningar, Wid En Ny Skrift , kallad: En Patriots Tan- kar . . . Stockholm 1769. Scott, John, A Letter to the Right Hon. Edmund Burke, in a Reply to his “Refl ections on the Revolution in France, &c.”. London 1790. Sharpe, Gregory, A Short Dissertation upon that Species of Misgovernment, Called an Oligarchy. London 1748. Shebbeare, John, An Essay on the Origin, Progress and Establishment of National Soci- ety; in which the Principles of Government . . . Contained in Dr. Price’s Observations, &c. are fully Examined and fully Refuted . . . London 1776. Sheridan, Richard Brinsley, A Letter to the Most Insolent Man Alive. Th e fourth edi- tion. London 1789. 506 bibliography

Sheridan, Th omas, A General Dictionary of the English Language . . . London 1780. Shower, Bartholomew, Cases in Parliament Resolves and Adjudged, upon Petitions, and Writs of Error. Th e third edition. [London] 1740. [Anon.], Sound an Alarm to all the Inhabitants of Great Britain . . . Th e third edition. London 1798. Stanhope, Charles, A Letter from Earl Stanhope, to the Right Honourable Edmund Burke: Containing a Short Answer to his late Speech on the French Revolution. Th e second edition. London 1790. [Anon.], Th e State of the Nation, as Represented to a Certain Great Personage, by Junius and the Freeholder: and the Petitions of the Citizens of London . . . London 1770. Stewart, John, Th e Tocsins of Britannia: With a Novel Plan for a Constitutional Army. London 1794. Sveriges ridderskaps och adels riksdagsprotokoll från och med år 1719 (SRARP). 1769– 1770, I–II , Vols. 27–28. Sten Landahl (ed.). Stockholm 1962–1964. Sveriges ridderskaps och adels riksdagsprotokoll från och med år 1719 (SRARP). 1771– 1772, I–III, Vols. 29–31. Sten Landahl (ed.). Stockholm 1969–1971. [Anon.], Swänska Frihetens Företräde, Framför Engelska och Polska Regeringar. Stock- holm 1771. [Anon.], En Swensk Patriots Bref. Til Författaren af Uplysningen för Swenska Fol- ket . . . Stockholm 1769. [Anon.], Tankar Om De Ämbetsmän, som wid förfl utne Riksdagsmans-Wal, gjordt inbrott i Folkens Rätt och Wal-Frihet. Stockholm 1771. [Tartar], Th e Letter to the Most Insolent Man Alive, Answered. London 1789. Temple, William, Th e Works of Sir William Temple . . . Vol. 2. Edinburgh 1754. Th elwall, John, Th e Tribune, a Periodical Publication, Consisting Chiefl y of the Politi- cal Lectures of J. Th elwall. Taken in Short-Hand by W. Ramsey, and Revised by the Lecturer . . . Vol. 2, No. 24. London 1795–1796. Tracy, Louis Claude Destutt de, Translation of a Letter from Monsieur de Tracy . . . to Mr. Burke, in Answer to his Remarks on the French Revolution. London 1790. Th e Trial of Th omas Paine, for Certain False, Wicked, Scandalous and Seditious Libels Inserted in the Second Part of the Rights of Man, Before the Right Hon. Lord Kenyon and a Special Jury, at Guildhall, on Tuesday the 18th December, 1792. Taken in Short Hand by an Eminent Advocate. Original Edition, Copied from the Minutes Taken in Court. London [1792]. Trophime-Gérard, Marquis de Lally-Tolendal, A Defence of the French Emigrants . . . Translated from the French by John Giff ord, Esq. London 1797. [Anon.], Th e True Principles of the Revolution Revived and Asserted. Being a Defence of the Present Administration . . . London 1741. [True Scotchman and Lover of his Country], Hereditary Right not Indefeasible: or, some Arguments, Founded upon the Unalterable Laws of Society and Government, Proving that the Rights Claimed by the Jacobites, can Never Belong to any Prince or Succession of Princes. London 1747. Tucker, Josiah, Four Letters on Important National Subjects, Addresses to . . . the Earl of Shelburne . . . Th e second edition. London [1783]. Tyers, Th omas, Political Conferences Between Several Great Men, in the Last and Present Century . . . London 1780. [Anon.], Tyranny Unmasked. An Answer to a Late Pamphlet, Entitled Taxation no Tyranny. London 1775. [Anon.], Undersökning öfwer den i en utkommande Wecko-Skrift lofwade Uplysning för Swenska Folket . . . Stockholm 1769. [Anon.], Uplysning För Swenska Folket Om Anledningen, Orsaken och Afsigterne Med Urtima Riksdagen 1769. Stockholm & Götheborg 1769. [Anon.], Upmuntran För Swea Folk, Til Upmärksamhet I ett Högwigtigt Ämne. Stock- holm 1769. bibliography 507

Virgin, Arvid Bernhard, En Patriots Tankar, Om Grundlagens nödvändiga förbättring i det, som rör Fides Publica och des Befästande. [Stockholm 1769]. [Walpole, Robert], Th e Celebrated Speech of Sir Robert Walpole, Against Short Parlia- ments; to shew that a Parliamentary Reform is both Unnecessary and Dangerous. With a Preface on the Times, to the Right Honourbale Henry Dundas . . . London 1793. [Anon.], Wärkan Och Påfölgden Af Wåldsamheters Utöfwan Bland et Fritt Folk. Stock- holm 1770. Wellesley, Richard, Substance of Lord Mornington’s Speech in the House of Commons, on Tuesday, January 21, 1794, on a Motion for an Address to His Majesty at the Commencement of the Sessions of Parliament. Dublin 1794. White, William, A Dissertation on Government, with the Balance Considered; or, a Free Enquiry into the Nature of the Constitution, and the Probable Eff ect of a Parliamen- tary Reform. London 1792. Williams, David, Lectures on Political Principles; the Subjects of Eighteen Books, in Montesquieu’s Spirit of Laws: Read to Students under the Author’s Direction. London 1789. ——, Letters on Political Liberty, and the Principles of the English and Irish Projects of Reform; Addressed to a Member of the English House of Commons. Th e third edi- tion. London 1789. ——, Lessons to a Young Prince, on the Present Disposition in Europe to a General Revolution. London 1790. Workman, James, A Letter to His Grace the Duke of Portland . . . Against the Attack made . . . by the Right Hon. Edmund Burke . . . London 1797. Wycliff e, Th omas, On Government; Addressed to the Public . . . Liverpool 1786 (1779). Young, Arthur, An Enquiry into the State of the Public Mind Amongst the Lower Classes . . . Dublin 1798. Young, William, Th e Rights of Englishmen; or, the British Constitution of Government, Compared with that of a Democratic Republic . . . London 1793.

Secondary Sources

Alm, Mikael, Kungsord i elft e timmen. Språk och självbild i det gustavianska enväldets legitimitetskamp 1772–1809. Stockholm 2002. Ayling, Stanley, Fox: Th e Life of Charles James Fox. London 1991. Baker, Keith Michael, Inventing the French Revolution. Cambridge 1990. Baker, Keith Michael, ‘Political languages of the French Revolution’, Mark Goldie and Robert Wokler (eds.), Th e Cambridge History of Eighteenth-Century Political Th ought. Cambridge 2006, 626–659. Ball, Terrence, ‘Introduction’, Terrence Ball (ed.), Th e Federalist with Letter of “Bru- tus”. Cambridge 2003. Baranger, Denis, Parlementarisme des origines. Essai sur les conditions de formation d’un exécutif responsible en Angleterre (des années 1740 au début de l’âge victorien). Paris 1999. Barker, Hannah, ‘England 1760–1815’, Hannah Barker and Simon Burrows (eds.), Politics and the Public Sphere in Europe and North America, 1760–1820. Cambridge 2002, 1–22. Barker, Hannah, and Burrows, Simon, ‘Introduction’, Hannah Barker and Simon Burrows (eds.), Press, Politics and the Public Sphere in Europe and North America, 1760–1820. Cambridge 2002, 1–23. Black, Jeremy, Robert Walpole & the Nature of Politics in Early Eighteenth Century England. Basingstoke & London 1990. ——, Eighteenth–Century Britain 1688–1783. London 2001. 508 bibliography

——, Parliament and Foreign Policy in the Eighteenth Century. Cambridge 2004. Blakemore, Steven, ‘Burke and the Fall of Language: Th e French Revolution as Lin- guistic Event’, Eighteenth-Century Studies, Vol. 17, No. 3, 1984, 284–307. Bradley, James, Popular Politics and the American Revolution in England: Petitions, the Crown, and Public Opinion. Macon (GA) 1986. ——, ‘Parliament, Print Culture and Petitioning in Late Eighteenth-Century England’, Jason Peacey (ed.), Th e Print Culture of Parliament, 1600–1800. Edinburgh 2007, 96–111. Brewer, John, Party Ideology and Popular Politics at the Accession of George III. Cam- bridge 1976. ——, ‘English Radicalism in the Age of George III’, J.G.A. Pocock (ed.), Th ree British Revolutions: 1641, 1688, 1776. Princeton 1980, 323–367. Bullard, Paddy, Contexts for Edmund Burke’s Rhetoric, 1756–1780. Diss., University of Oxford 2001. Bullard, Patrick, ‘Parliamentary Rhetoric, Enlightenment and the Politics of Secrecy: the Printers’ Crisis of March 1771’, History of European Ideas, Vol. 31, 2005, 313–325. Cannon, John, Parliamentary Reform 1640–1832. Cambridge 1994 (1972). ——, ‘Petty, William’, Oxford Dictionary of National Bibliography. Electronic version 2004. Canovan, Margaret, Th e People. Cambridge 2005. Cavallin, Maria, I kungens och folkets tjänst. Synen på den svenske ämbetsmannen 1750–1780. Göteborg 2003. Christie, Ian R., Wilkes, Wyvill and Reform: Th e Parliamentary Reform Movement in British Politics 1760–1785. London 1962. ——, Wars and Revolutions: Britain 1760–1815. London 1991 (1982). Claréus, Anders, ‘Bondeståndet under slutet av frihetstiden’, Marie-Christine Skuncke & Henrika Tandefelt (eds.), Riksdag, kaff ehus och predikstol. Frihetstiden politiska kultur 1766–1772. Stockholm 2003, 95–104. Colclough, David, Freedom of Speech in Early Stuart England. Cambridge 2005. Colley, Linda, ‘Eighteenth-Century English Radicalism before Wilkes’, Transactions of the Royal Historical Society, Vol. 31, 1981, 1–19. ——, In Defi ance of Oligarchy: Th e Tory Party 1714–60. Cambridge 1982. Condren, Conal, ‘Radicalism Revisited’, Glenn Burgess & Matthew Festenstein (eds.), English Radicalism, 1550–1850. Cambridge 2007, 311–337. Corfi eld, Penelope J., Green, Edmund M. & Harvey, Charles, ‘Westminster Man; Charles James Fox and his Electorate, 1780–1806’, Parliamentary History, Vol. 20, No. 2, 2001, 157–185. Cranston, Maurice, ‘Th e Sovereignty of the Nation’, Colin Lucas (ed.), Th e French Revolution and the Creation of Modern Political Culture, Vol. 2: Th e Political Cul- ture of the French Revolution. Oxford 1988, 97–104. Crick, Bernard, Democracy: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford 2002. Cruickshanks, Eveline, ‘Th e Political Management of Sir Robert Walpole, 1720–42’, Jeremy Black (ed.), Britain in the Age of Walpole. Basingstoke & London 1992 (1984. Dahl, Robert Alan, On Democracy. New Haven & London 1998. Derry, John, English Politics and the American Revolution. London 1976. Dickinson, H.T., ‘Th e Eighteenth-Century Debate on the Sovereignty of Parliament’, Transactions of the Royal Historical Society, Fift h Series, Vol. 26, London 1976, 189–210. ——, Liberty and Property: Political Ideology in Eighteenth-Century Britain. London 1977. ——, British Radicalism and the French Revolution. Oxford 1985. bibliography 509

——, ‘Introduction: the Impact of the French Revolution and the French Wars 1789– 1815’, H.T. Dickinson (ed.), Britain and the French Revolution, 1789–1815. Basing- stoke & London 1989. ——, Th e Politics of the People in Eighteenth-Century Britain. New York 1995. ——, ‘Britain’s Imperial Sovereignty: Th e Ideological Case against the American Colo- nists’, H.T. Dickinson (ed.), Britain and the American Revolution. London & New York 1998a. ——, ‘Introduction’, Britain and the American Revolution. London & New York 1998b. ——, ‘Yonge, Sir William’, Oxford Dictionary of National Bibliography. Electronic ver- sion 2004. Dinwiddy, J.R. Radicalism and Reform in Britain, 1780–1859. London 1992. Dippel, Horst, ‘Démocratie’, Handbuch politisch-sozialer Grundbegriff e in Frankreich 1680–1820. Vol. 6, München 1986, 57–97. Ditchfi eld, G.M., ‘Th e House of Lords in the Age of the American Revolution’, Clyve Jones (ed.), A Pillar of the Constitution: Th e House of Lords in British Politics, 1640– 1784. London 1989, 199–239. Dunn, John, Setting the People Free: Th e Story of Democracy. London 2005. Edelstein, Melvin, ‘Les revolutions américaine et française et l’avancement de la démocratie’, Annales historiques de la Révolution française, No. 4, 2003, 45–58. Ehrman, J.P.W. & Smith, Anthony, ‘Pitt, William’, (known as the younger) Oxford Dictionary of National Bibliography. Electronic version 2004. Ericsson, Birgitta, ‘Arvid Schauw, Carl Fredric Sebaldt och partikampen i borgarstån- det under frihetstidens slutskede’, Marie-Christine Skuncke & Henrika Tandefelt (eds.), Riksdag, kaff ehus och predikstol. Frihetstidens politiska kultur 1766–1772. Stockholm 2003, 143–154. Evans, Chris, Debating the Revolution: Britain in the 1790s. London & New York 2006. Evans, Eric J., Th e Forging of the Modern State: Early Industrial Britain 1783–1870. London 1996 (1983). Falhbeck, Erik, ‘Studier öfver frihetstidens politiska idéer’, Statsvetenskaplig Tidskrift , Vol. 18, No. 5, 1915. ——, ‘Studier öfver frihetstidens politiska idéer’, Statsvetenskaplig Tidskrift , Vol. 19, No. 1, 1916. Fetscher, Irving, ‘Republicanism and popular sovereignty’, Mark Goldie and Rob- ert Wokler (eds.), Th e Cambridge History of Eighteenth-Century Political Th ought. Cambridge 2006, 573–597. Gelderen, Martin van, ‘Aristotelians, Monarchomachs and Republicans: Sovereignty and respublica mixta in Dutch and German Political Th ought, 1580–1650’, Martin van Gelderen and Quentin Skinner (eds.), Republicanism: A Shared European Heri- tage, Vol. 1, Cambridge 2002, 195–217. Goldsworthy, Jeff rey, Th e Sovereignty of Parliament: History and Philosophy. Oxford 1999. Goodwin, Albert, Th e Friends of Liberty: Th e English Democratic Movement in the Age of the French Revolution. Cambridge (MA) 1979. Gould, Eliga H., Th e Persistence of Empire: British Political Culture in the Age of the American Revolution. Williamsburg & London 2000. Grześkowiak-Krwawicz, Anna, ‘Anti-monarchism in Polish Republicanism in the Seventeenth and Eighteenth Centuries’, Martin van Gelderen and Quentin Skin- ner (eds.), Republicanism: A Shared European Heritage, Vol. 1, Cambridge 2002, 43–59. Gunn, J.A.W., Beyond Liberty and Property: Th e Process of Self-Recognition in Eight- eenth-Century Political Th ought. Kingston & Montreal 1983. 510 bibliography

Gustafsson, Harald, Political Interaction in the Old Regime: Central Power and Local Society in the Eighteenth-Century Nordic States. Lund 1994. Hague, William, William Pitt the Younger. London 2004. Halberg, Peter, Ages of Liberty: Social Upheaval, History Writing, and the New Public Sphere in Sweden 1740–1792. Stockholm 2003. Hampsher-Monk, Iain, ‘Introduction’, Iain Hampsher-Monk (ed.), Th e Impact of the French Revolution. Cambridge 2005, 1–24. ——, Hampsher-Monk, Iain, ‘British radicalism and the anti-Jacobins’, Mark Goldie and Robert Wokler (eds.), Th e Cambridge History of Eighteenth-Century Political Th ought. Cambridge 2006, 660–687. ——, ‘On not inventing the English Revolution: the radical failure of the 1790s as linguistic non-performance’, Glenn Burges & Matthew Festenstein (eds.), English Radicalism, 1550–1850. Cambridge 2007, 135–156. Hampson, Norman, Th e French Revolution and Democracy. Reading 1983. Hansen, Mogens Herman, Th e Tradition of Ancient Greek Democracy and its Impor- tance for Modern Democracy. Copenhagen 2005. Hanson, Russell L., ‘Democracy’, Terence Ball et al. (eds.), Political Innovation and Conceptual Change. Cambridge 1989, 66–89. Harris, Ian, ‘Introduction’, Ian Harris (ed.), Pre-Revolutionary Writings. Cambridge 1993. ——, ‘Publishing Parliamentary Oratory: Th e Case of Edmund Burke’, Jason Peacey (ed.), Th e Print Culture of Parliament, 1600–1800. Edinburgh 2007, 111–130. Haupt, Heinz-Gerhard, & Kocka, Jürgen, ‘Historischer Vergleich: Methoden, Auf- gaben, Probleme. Eine Einleitung’, Heinz-Gerhard Haupt & Jürgen Kocka (eds.), Geschichte und Vergleich. Ansätze und Ergebnisse international vergleichender Geschichtsschreibung. Frankfurt & New York 1996. Held, David, Models of Democracy. Cambridge 1989. Helmrath, Johannes, and Feuchter, Jörg, ‘Einleitung – Vormoderne Parlamentsorato- rik’, Jörn Feuchter & Johannes Helmrath (eds.), Politische Redekultur in der Vormo- derne. Die Oratorik europäischer Parlamente in Spätmittelalter und Früher Neuzeit. Frankfurt & New York 2008, 9–22. Herzog, Don, Poisoning the Minds of the Lower Orders. Princeton 1998. Hildebrand, Emil, Svenska statsförfattningens historiska utveckling från äldsta tid till våra dagar. Stockholm 1896. Holmes, Geoff rey & Szechi, Daniel, Th e Age of Oligarchy: Pre-Industrial Britain 1722– 1753. London 1993. Hunter, Ian & Saunders, David, ‘Introduction’, Ian Hunter & David Saunders (eds), Natural Law and Civil Sovereignty: Moral Right and State Authority in Early Modern Political Th ought. Basingstoke 2002, 1−10. Ihalainen, Pasi, Th e Discourse on Political Pluralism in Early Eighteenth-Century Eng- land. Helsinki 1999. ——, ‘Lutherska drag i den svenska politiska kulturen i slutet av frihetstiden. En begreppsanalytisk undersökning av fyra riksdagspredikningar’, Marie-Christine Skuncke & Henrika Tandefelt (eds.), Riksdag, kaff ehus, predikstol. Frihetstidens politiska kultur 1766–1772. Stockholm 2003, 73–93. ——, Protestant Nations Redefi ned: Changing Perceptions of National Identity in the Rhetoric of English, Dutch and Swedish Public Churches, 1685–1772. Leiden & Bos- ton 2005. ——, ‘Det svenska prästerskapet som en härold för en ny politisk kultur’, Historisk Tidsskrift , Vol. 126, No. 4, 2006, 823–829. ——, ‘Th e Sanctifi cation and Democratisation of “the Nation” and “the People” in late Eighteenth-Century Northwestern Europe: Proposing a Comparative Con- ceptual History’, Contributions to the History of Concepts, Vol. 3, No. 2, 2007, 125–151. bibliography 511

——, ‘I vilken mån talades det om folksuveränitet och representativ demokrati på den svenska riksdagen 1771–1772?’, Historisk Tidskrift för Finland, Vol. 93, No. 2, 2008a, 125–159. ——, ‘Taivaan fi losofi aa ja alkuperäistä demokratiaa. Claude Fauchet’n vallankumo- uksellinen kristinusko 1789–1791’, Historiallinen Aikakauskirja, Vol. 106, No. 2, 2008b, 26–39. ——, ‘British, Swedish and Dutch Late Eighteenth-Century Parliamentary Debates as Sources for Comparative Conceptual History’, Gürcan Koçan (ed.), Transnational Concepts, Transfers and the Challenge of the Peripheries. Istanbul 2008c, 228–260. ——, ‘Th e Enlightenment Sermon: Towards Practical Religion and a Sacred National Community’, Joris van Eijnatten (ed.), Preaching, Sermon and Cultural Change in the Long Eighteenth Century. Leiden & Boston 2008d, 219–259. Ihalainen, Pasi & Palonen, Kari, ‘Parliamentary sources in the comparative study of conceptual history: Methodological aspects and illustrations of a research proposal’, Parliaments, Estates and Representation, vol. 29 2009, 17–34. Ilie, Cornelia, ‘Unparliamentary Language: Insults as Cognitive Forms of Ideologi- cal Confrontation’, Rene Dirven, Roslyn Frank and Cornelia Ilie (eds.), Language and Ideology, Vol. II: Descriptive Cognitive Approaches. Amsterdam & Philadelphia 2001, 235–263. ——, ‘British “Consensus” vs. Swedish “Samförstånd” in Parliamentary Debates’, Paul Bayley (ed.), Cross-Cultural Perspectives on Parliamentary Discourse. Amsterdam & Philadelphia 2004a, 1–26. ——, ‘Insulting as (un)parliamentary practice in the British and Swedish parliaments: A rhetorical approach’, Paul Bayley (ed.), Cross-Cultural Perspectives on Parliamen- tary Discourse. Amsterdam 2004b, 45–86. Jedruch, Jacek, Constitutions, Elections and Legislatures of Poland, 1493–1993: A Guide to Th eir History. Pittsburgh 1998 (1982). Jeff ares, Norman A., ‘Brinsley, Richard’, Oxford Dictionary of National Bibliography. Electronic version 2004. Jones, Clyve, ‘“Th e Commons” Address of Th anks in Reply to the King’s Speech, 13 November 1755: Rank and Status Versus Politics’, Parliamentary History, Vol. 25, No. 2, 2006, 232–262. Jupp, Peter, Th e Governing of Britain 1688–1848: Th e Executive, Parliament and the People. London 2006. Koselleck, Reinhart, ‘Demokratie’, Geschichtliche Grundbergiff e. Historisches Lexikon zur politisch-sozialen Sprache in Deutschland, Vol. 1. Stuttgart 1972, 848–853. Lagerroth, Fredrik, Frihetstidens författning. En studie i den svenska konstitutionalis- mens historia. Stockholm 1915. ——, Sveriges Riksdag: historisk och statsvetenskaplig framställning. Vol. 5/1, Frihetsti- dens maktägande ständer 1719–1772. Stockholm 1934. ——, Sveriges Riksdag: historisk och statsvetenskaplig framställning. Vol. 6/2, Frihetsti- dens maktägande ständer 1719–1772. Stockholm 1934. ——, ‘En frihetstida läröbok i gällande svensk statsrätt’, Statsvetenskaplig tidskrift, Vol. 40, No. 3, 1937, 186–211. ——, Levande och dött i frihetstidens statsskick. Stockholm 1947. Langford, Paul, A Polite and Commercial People: England 1727–1783. Oxford 1989. ——, ‘Burke, Edmund’, Oxford Dictionary of National Bibliography. Electronic version 2004. Leonhard, Jörn, Liberalismus. Zur historischen Semantik eines europäischen Deutungs- musters. München 2001. ——, Bellizismus und Nation. Kriegsdeutung und Nationsbestimmung in Europa und den Vereinigten Staaten 1750–1914. München 2008. Lieberman, David, ‘Th e constitution and the common law’, Mark Goldie and Rob- ert Wokler (eds.), Th e Cambridge History of Eighteenth-Century Political Th ought. Cambridge 2006, 317–346. 512 bibliography

Lindberg, Bo, ‘Inledning. Politisk kultur och idéer’, Marie-Christine Skuncke & Hen- rika Tandefelt (eds.), Riksdag, kaff ehus och predikstol. Frihetstidens politiska kultur 1766–1772. Stockholm 2003, 13–24. ——, Den antika skevheten. Politiska ord och begrepp i det tidig-moderna Sverige. Stockholm 2006. Linnarsson, Lennart, Riksrådens licentiering. En studie i frihetstidens parlamentarism. Uppsala 1943. Livesey, James, Making Democracy in the French Revolution. Cambridge (MA) & Lon- don 2001. Lock, F.P., Edmund Burke, Vol. 1. Oxford 1998. Lowe, William C., ‘Lennox, Charles’, Oxford Dictionary of National Bibliography. Elec- tronic version 2004. Mack, Peter, Elizabethan Rhetoric. Cambridge 2002. Malmström, Carl Gustaf, Sveriges politiska historia från K. Carl XII:s död till statshvälv- ningen 1772. Stockholm 1877. Markoff , John, ‘Where and When Was Democracy Invented?’, Comparative Studies in Society and History, Vol. 41, No. 4, 1999, 660–690. Meier, Hans, ‘Demokratie’, Geschichtliche Grundbergiff e. Historisches Lexikon zur poli- tisch-sozialen Sprache in Deutschland, Vol. 1. Stuttgart 1972, 821–873. Metcalf, Michael F., ‘Frihetstidens riksdag (1719–1772)’, Herman Schück et al. (eds.), Riksdagen genom tiderna. Stockholm 1985, 117–159. ——, ‘Hattar och mössör 1766–72. Den sena frihetstiden partisystem komparativ belysning’, Marie-Christine Skuncke & Henrika Tandefelt (eds.), Riksdag, kaff ehus och predikstol. Frihetstidens politiska kultur 1766–1772. Stockholm 2003, 39–54. Mijnhardt, Wijnand, ‘Th e Limits of Present-day Historiography of Republicanism’, De Achtiende Eeuw, Vol. 37, No. 1, 2005, 75–89. Miller, Joshua, Th e Rise and Fall of Democracy in Early America, 1630–1789. Univer- sity Park, Pennsylvania 1991. Miller, Peter N., Defi ning the Common Good: Empire, Religion and Philosophy in Eight- eenth-Century Britain. Cambridge 1994. Mitchell, L.G., Charles James Fox. Oxford 1992. ——, ‘Fox, Charles James’, Oxford Dictionary of National Bibliography. Electronic ver- sion 2004. Monnier, Raymonde, ‘Démocratie et Révolution française’, Mots, Vol. 59, juin 1999, 47–68. ——, ‘ “Démocratie representative” ou “république démocratique”: de la querelle des mots (république) à la querelle des anciens et des moderns’, Annales historiques de la Révolution française, No. 3, 2001, 1–21. ——, ‘Autour des usages d’un nom indistinct: “Peuple” sous la Révolution française’, Dix-huitième siècle, Vol. 34, 2002, 389–418. ——, Républicanisme, Patrotisme et Révolution française. Paris 2005. Morgan, Edmund S., Inventing the People: Th e Rise of Popular Sovereignty in England and America. New York & London 1984. Mori, Jennifer, William Pitt and the French Revolution 1785–1795. Edinburgh 1997. ——, Britain in the Age of the French Revolution 1785–1820. Harlow 2000. Morris, Marilyn, Th e British Monarchy and the French Revolution. New Haven & Lon- don 1998. Namier, Lewis, and Brooke, John, Th e House of Commons 1754–1790. London 1964. Newman, Simon P., ‘British Historians and the Changing Signifi cance of the Ameri- can Revolution’, Simon P. Newman (ed.), Europe’s American Revolution. Basing- stoke & New York 2006, 72–93. Nilsén, Per, Att ”stoppa munnen till på bespottare”. Den akademiska undervisningen i svensk statsrätt under frihetstiden. Lund 2001. Nordin, Jonas, Ett fattigt men fritt folk. Nationell och politisk självbild i Sverige från sen stormaktstid till slutet av frihetstiden. Stockholm 2000. bibliography 513

——, ‘Frihetstidens radicalism’, Marie-Christine Skuncke & Henrika Tandefelt (eds.), Riksdag, kaff ehus och predikstol. Frihetstidens politiska kultur 1766–1772. Stock- holm 2003, 55–72. ——, ‘Von “fremder Unterdrückung” zur “Freiheitszeit”. Die Vorstellung von frihet im frühneuzeitlichen Schweden’, Georg Schmidt et al. (ed.), Kollektive Freiheitsvor- stellungen im frühneuzeitlichen Europa (1400–1850). Bern 2006, 145–158. Nurmiainen, Jouko, ‘Gemensamma privilegier för ett odalstånd. Alexander Kepplerus som borgmästare och samhällstankare’, Marie-Christine Skuncke & Henrika Tan- defelt (eds.), Riksdag, kaff ehus och predikstol. Frihetstidens politiska kultur 1766– 1772. Stockholm 2003, 171–190. ——, Edistys ja yhteinen hyvä vapaudenajan ruotsalaisessa poliittisessa kielessä. Hel- sinki 2009. O’Gorman, Frank, ‘Pitt and the “Tory” Reaction to the French Revolution 1789–1815’, H.T. Dickinson (ed.), Britain and the French Revolution, 1789–1815. Basingstoke & London 1989. ——, Th e Long Eighteenth Century: British Political and Social History, 1688–1832. London 1997. Oscarsson, Ingemar, ‘ “Rikets Frihet, Gegerlig Frihet, Skrif-Frihet”. Gjörwell och Den politiske Aristarchus 1769–72’, Marie-Christine Skuncke & Henrika Tandefelt (eds.), Riksdag, kaff ehus och predikstol. Frihetstidens politiska kultur 1766–1772. Stockholm 2003, 315–338. Palmer, R.R., ‘Notes on the Use of the Word “Democracy”’, Political Science Quar- terly, Vol. 68, No. 2, 1955, 203–226. ——, Th e Age of the Democratic Revolution: A Political History of Europe and America, 1760–1800, Vol. 1. Princeton 1959. ——, Th e Age of the Democratic Revolution: A Political History of Europe and America, 1760–1800, Vol. 2. Princeton 1964. Palonen, Kari, Th e Politics of Limited Times: Th e Rhetoric of Temporal Judgment in Parliamentary Democracies. Baden-Baden 2008. Palonen, Kari, Tuija Pulkkinen & José Maria Rosales (eds.), Th e Ashgate Research Companion to the Politics of Democratization in Europe: Concepts and Histories, London 2008. Paloposki, Toivo J., Suomen talonpoikaissäädyn valtiopäiväedustus vapaudenajalla. Helsinki 1961. Peacey, Jason, ‘Th e Print Culture of Parliament’, Jason Peacey (ed.), Th e Print Culture of Parliament, 1600–1800. Edinburgh 2007, 1–16. Perry, Keith, British Politics and the American Revolution. Basingstoke & London 1990. Pitkin, Hanna Fenichel, ‘Representation’, Terence Ball et al. (eds.), Political Innovation and Conceptual Change. Cambridge 1989, 132–154. Pole, J.R., Political Representation in England and the Origins of the American Repub- lic. London 1966. Powell, David, Nationhood & Identity: Th e British State Since 1800. London 2002. Reid, Christopher, Edmund Burke and the Practice of Political Writing. Dublin 1985. ——, ‘Whose Parliament? Political Oratory and Print Culture in the Later 18th Cen- tury’, Language and Literature, Vol. 9, No. 2, 2000, 122–134. Reid, Loren Dudley, Charles James Fox: A Study of the Eff ectiveness of an Eighteenth Century Parliamentary Speaker. Iowa City 1932. Roberts, Michael, Swedish and English Parliamentarism in the Eighteenth Century. Belfast 1973. ——, Th e Age of Liberty: Sweden 1719–1772. Cambridge 1986. Robertson, Andrew W., Th e Language of Democracy: Political Rhetoric in the United States and Britain, 1790–1900. Charlottesville & London 1995. Rogers, Nicholas, Whigs and Cities: Popular Politics in the Age of Walpole and Pitt. Oxford 1989. 514 bibliography

Rosanvallon, Pierre, La démocratie inachevée : histoire de la souveraineté du peuple en France. Paris 2000. ——, ‘Th e History of the Word “Democracy” in France’, Journal of Democracy, Vol. 6, No. 4, 1995, 140–154. Royle, Edward, Revolutionary Britannia? Refl ections on the Th reat of Revolution in Britain, 1789–1848. Manchester & New York 2000. Saastamoinen, Kari, ‘Johdatus poliittisiin käsitteisiin uuden ajan alun Ruotsissa’, Matti Hyvärinen et al. (eds.), Käsitteet liikkeessä: Suomen poliittisen kulttuurin käsitehis- toria. Tampere 2003, 19–62. Scott, Jonathan, ‘Classical Republicanism in Seventeenth-Century England and the Netherlands’, Martin van Gelderen & Quentin Skinner (eds.) Republicanism: A Shared European Heritage, Vol. 1. Cambridge 2002, 61–83. Sennefelt, Karin, ‘Mellan hemligt och off entligt: Sven Hofman vid riksdagen 1765–66’, Marie-Christine Skuncke & Henrika Tandefelt (eds.), Riksdag, kaff ehus och predik- stol. Frihetstidens politiska kultur 1766–1772. Stockholm 2003, 209–228. Skinner, Quentin, ‘Th e Principles and Practice of Opposition: Th e Case of Bolingbroke versus Walpole’, Neil McKendrick (ed.), Historical Perspectives: Studies in English Th ought and Society in Honour of J.H. Plumb. London 1974, 93–128. ——, Visions of Politics, Vol. 1: Regarding Method, Cambridge 2003 (2002). ——, ‘Rethinking Political Liberty’, History Workshop Journal, Iss. 61, 2006, 156–170. Skuncke, Marie-Christine, ‘Den svenska demokratidebatten 1766–1772’, Rut Boström Andersson (ed.), Ordets makt och tankens frihet. Om språket som maktfaktor. Uppsala 1999, 283–294. ——, ‘Medier, mutor och nätverk’, Marie-Christine Skuncke & Henrika Tandefelt (eds.), Riksdag, kaff ehus och predikstol. Frihetstidens politiska kultur 1766–1772. Stockholm 2003, 255–286. Smith, E.A., ‘Grey, Charles’, Oxford Dictionary of National Bibliography. Electronic version 2004. Steinmetz, Willibald, Das Sagbare und das Machbare. Zum Wandel politischer Hand- lungsspielräume in England 1780–1867. Stuttgart 1993. ——, ‘ “A code of its own”: Rhetoric and Logic of Parliamentary Debate in Modern Britain’, Finnish Yearbook of Political Th ought, Vol. 6, 2002, 84–104. Sveriges periodiska litteratur, www.kb.se/Sverigesperiodiskalitteratur/1/1_129.htm. Swann, Julian, ‘Politics and the State in Eighteenth-Century Europe’, T.C.W. Blanning (ed.), Th e Eighteenth Century: Europe 1688–1815. Oxford 2000, 11–51. Tackett, Timothy, Par la volonté du peuple : Comment les deputes de 1789 sont devenus révolutionnaires, traduits de l’anglais par Alain Spiess. Paris 1997 (1996). Th omas, Peter D.G., Th e House of Commons in the Eighteenth Century. Oxford 1971. ——, John Wilkes: A Friend to Liberty. Oxford 1996. ——, ‘Wilkes, John’, Oxford Dictionary of National Bibliography. Electronic version 2004. Th orne, R.G., Th e House of Commons 1790–1820. London 1986. ——, ‘Maitland, James’, Oxford Dictionary of National Bibliography. Electronic ver- sion 2004. Tilly, Charles, ‘Parliamentarization of Popular Contention in Great Britain, 1758– 1834’, Th eory and Society, Vol. 26, No. 2/3, 1997, 245–273. Turkka, Tapani, Th e Origins of Parliamentarism: A Study of Sandy’s Motion. Baden- Baden 2007. Urbinati, Nadia, Representative Democracy: Principles and Genealogy. Chicago 2006. Valentin, Hugo, Frihetstidens riddarhus. Några bidrag till dess karakteristik. Stock- holm 1915. Velema, Wyger, ‘ “Th at a Republic is Better than a Monarchy”: Anti-monarchism in Early Modern Dutch Political Th ought’, Martin van Gelderen & Quentin Skinner (eds.), Republicanism: A Shared European Heritage, Vol. 1. Cambridge 2002, 9–25. bibliography 515

——, ‘Wijnand W. Mijnhardt on the Historiography of Republicanism: A Reply’, De Achtiende Eeuw. Documentatieblad Werkgroep Achtiende Eeuw, Vol. 38, No. 2, 2005, 193–202. ——, Republicans: Essays on Eighteenth-Century Dutch Political Th ought. Leiden 2007. Virrankoski, Pentti, Anders Chydenius. Demokratisk politiker i upplysningens tid. Stockholm 1995. Wahrman, Dror, ‘Virtual Representation: Parliamentary Reporting and Languages of Class in the 1790s’, Past and Present, Vol. 136, 1992, 83–113. Winton, Patrik, Frihetstidens politiska praktik. Nätverk och off entlighet 1746–1766. Uppsala 2006. Wilson, Kathleen, Th e Sense of the People: Politics, Culture, and Imperialism in Eng- land, 1715–1785. Cambridge 1995. Wolff , Charlotta, ‘Aristocratic Republicanism and the Hate of Sovereignty in Eight- eenth-Century Sweden’, Scandinavian Journal of History, Vol. 32, No. 4, 2007a, 358–375. ——, ‘Pro Patria et Libertate. Frihetsbegreppet i 1700-talets svenska politiska språk’, Historisk Tidskrift för Finland, Vol. 92, No. 1, 2007b, 34–62. ——, Noble Conceptions of Politics in Eighteenth-Century Sweden (ca 1740–1790). Hel- sinki 2008. Wood, Gordon S., ‘Th e American Revolution’, Mark Goldie and Robert Wokler (eds.), Th e Cambridge History of Eighteenth-Century Political Th ought. Cambridge 2006, 601–625. Wootton, David, ‘Th e Levellers’, John Dunn (ed.), Democracy: Th e Unfi nished Journey 508 BC to AD 1993. Oxford 1992, 71–89. Worden, Blair, ‘Republicanism, Regicide and Republic: Th e English Experience’, Martin van Gelderen & Quentin Skinner (eds.), Republicanism: A Shared European Heritage, Vol. 1. Cambridge 2002, 307–327. Wright, Johnson Kent, ‘Th e Idea of Republican Constitution in Old Régime France’, Martin van Gelderen & Quentin Skinner (eds.), Republicanism: A Shared European Heritage, Vol. 1. Cambridge 2002, 289–305.

INDEX OF PERSONS

Abingdon, Willoughby Bertie, 3rd Earl Boscaven, Edward, see Falmouth of 92 Bowles, John 424, 454 Abingdon, Willoughby Bertie, 4th Earl Brandenburg, Henrik Albrekt 212, of 259, 269, 278, 304–305, 433–434 219 Acrelius, Israel 196 Brander, Uno 220 Adams, John 341 Brissot, Jacques-Pierre 346, 364, 397 Adam, William 265 Bristol, William Hervey, Marquis of Adolphus Frederick, King 175 261, 367–368 Almon, John 401 Bromley, William Jr. 67 Andersson, Johan 239 Browallius, Johan 173 Argyll, John Campbell, Duke of 46, 48, Browne, Isaac Hawkins 412 87, 92–93, 103, 112 Buller, John 297 Aristotle 6–7, 118, 166, 363, 424 Bunge, Sven 192, 197, 231, 237, 240, Aubyn, Sir John St 68 482 Auckland, William Eden, Baron 466 Burgh, James 249–250, 485 Burke, Edmund 26, 30, 118, 135, 138, Bailey, Nathan 74 145, 153, 264, 271, 282–283, 295–296, Balhurst, Lord 92, 94–95 302–303, 305, 323, 326, 330, 335, 348, Barclay, George 80 352, 357, 360, 362, 369, 372–374, Barnard, John 83, 100–102, 105, 377–378, 384, 391–393, 396, 398, 107–108 402–403, 408, 421, 449, 451, 487, Barré, Colonel 154 489–491, 493 Barrington, Lord 115 Burlamaqui, Jean-Jacques 257 Basset, Francis 274, 293 Bute, John Stuart, Earl of 127 Bastard, Edmund 334 Bayning, Th omas Townsend, Caesar Julius 107 Baron 386, 416 Camden, Charles Pratt, Earl 132, Beafoy 316, 333 333 Bearcroft , Edward 331 Campbell, John, see Argyll Beauchamp, Francis Seymour-Conway, Carlisle, Henry Howard, Earl of 95 Lord 395 Carteret, John, see Granville Beaufort, Charles Noel Somerset, Duke Cartwright, John 255, 257, 266, 268, of 69 –70, 81–82 290, 424, 460–461, 493 Beckford, William 120, 155 Carysfort, John Joshua Proby, Earl of Bedford, Francis Russel, Duke of 427, 268, 290 431, 433, 435 Cavendish, John 258 Bentham, Jeremy 33, 255, 257, 485 Cavendish Bentinck, William Henry, see Bentley, Th omas Richard 449 Portland Bergenstråhle, Rudman 187 Cawthorne, Joseph 293 Bertie, Willoughby, see Abingdon Cedeström, Clas 222 Billberg, Otto 230, 233 Cervin, Frans 225 Blackstone, William 130–131, 138, Chalmers, George 259 248, 255, 268, 308, 327, 359, 376, 399, Chamber, Ephraim 73 423, 457, 476, 485, 491 Chandler, Richard 53 Bodin, Jean 9, 63 Charles XII 274 Böhnen, Johan 180 Chatham, William Pitt, the Elder, Bolingbroke, Henry, Viscount 60, Lord 83, 98, 121–122, 127, 129, 74–75, 474 131–133, 140, 259, 286, 354 518 index of persons

Chesterfi eld, Philip Dormer Stanhope, Engeström, Jacob von 187 Earl of 87, 104, 264 Erskine, James, see Grange and Rosslyn Cholmondeley, James, Earl 86, 95–96 Erskine, Th omas 307, 381, 384, 389, Christian, Esbjörn 53, 166 393, 402, 441, 450–451 Chydenius, Anders 166 Essen, Fredric Ulric von 215, 231 Cobbett, William 53 Estenberg, Carl 193–194 Coke, Daniel Parker 296 Condorcet, Marie Jean Antoine Nicolas Falmouth, Edward Boscawen, Earl de Caritat, Marquis de 18, 388 of 353 Convey, Henry Seymour 307 Fauchet, Claude, Abbé 346–347 Cooper, Grey 333 Fazakerley, Nicholas 120 Cooper, Th omas 384 Fellowes, Robert 460 Corin, Samuel 214 Ferguson, Adam 134, 270 Cornewall, Velters 142 Fersen, Axel von 178, 231 Cornwallis, Charles Cornwallis, Fitzpatrick, Richard 269, 416 Marquess 279 Fitzroy, Augustus Henry, see Graft on Cotton, John Hynde 116, 475 FitzWilliam, William Wentworth, Court, Pieter de la 12 Earl 434, 448, 456 Courtenay, John 274–277, 289, Flood, Henry 359–361 360–361, 416–417 Fox, Charles James (also Foxites) 26, Creutz, Lorentz Wilhelm 178, 204 40, 59, 151–154, 261–262, 264–265, Cromwell, Oliver 224, 404 269, 277–278, 282–283, 286–290, Curwen, John Christian 438 292–294, 296, 298–300, 302–305, 307–314, 316–319, 321–326, 328, 330, Dallas, George 404 332, 334–338, 353–354, 356–358, 368, Dashwood, Francis, see LeDespencer 372–374, 383–384, 386, 389–392, D’Argenson, Comte, Marc-Pierre de 395–398, 402, 406, 412, 415–418, 421, Voyer de Paulmy 13, 64, 75, 386 427, 430–431, 436–437, 439, 443–445, Delaval, John Hussey, Baron 314, 447–455, 457–459, 462, 464, 467, 477, 318 486, 488–490, 492–494 Delolme, Jean Luis 249–251, 485 Fox, Henry 121 D’Holbach, Baron 136 Fox, Stephen 98 Dodsley, Robert 114–115 Francis, Philip 317–319, 325, 327–328, Dolben, William 275 381, 401 Dormer, Philip, see Chesterfi eld Frankenheim, Carl Nathanael 187 Douglas, Sylvester 468–469 Franklin, Benjamin 133 Dowdeswell, William 47, 142 Fraser, Archibald Carrybell 245 Duncombe, Henry 275, 321 Frederick, Prince 115 Dundas, Henry 307, 330, 384, 443 Frederick II, King 280 Dunk, George Montagu, see Halifax French, Laurence 461 Dunning, John 150, 266, 271, 477 Frese, Otto Henrik de 202 Duwall, Johan Diedric 179 Frietzcky, Clas 216, 238 Dyche, Th omas 79 Frink, Th omas 123 Dyson, Jeremiah 144 Gellius, Aulus 464 Eberhart, Johan Hartman 166 George II 89, 111 Eden, William, see Auckland George III 123–124, 129, 245–246, Egmont, John Perceval, Lord 115, 264, 279, 288, 294, 314, 331–332, 334, 120 336, 353, 390, 430, 456, 476, 487 Ehrenmalm, Samuel 180–181, 190 Gibbon, Edward 254, 485 Ekman, Anders 213, 224 Giff ord, John 451 Elliot-Murray Kynynmound, Gilbert, see Gilmour, Alexander 143 Minto Gjörwell, Carl Christian 175, 208, Ellis, Welbore 147–149, 300–301, 477 223–224 index of persons 519

Glynn, George 142–143 Hay, William 80 Godwin, William 404, 408, 417, 428, Head, Erasmus 112 450, 453, 492 Heathcote, George 109 Goldsmith, Oliver 124–125 Heathcote, William 98, 109–110 Goodricke, Henry 257 Heikkilä, Gabriel 236 Gower, John Leveson, Earl of 86 Henley, Robert, see Northington Graft on, Augustus Henry Fitzroy, Duke Hermansson, Johan 167 of 135–136, 151, 448 Hervey, John 86 Graham, Marquis of 293 Hervey, William, see Bristol Grange, James Erskine, Lord 84–85 Hierta, Carl 186 Grant, William 391 Hobbes, Th omas 118, 379 Granville, John Carteret, Earl of 86, Hobhouse, Benjamin 462–463, 494 89–93, 95, 104–105, 475 Hochschild, Johan Henrik 224 Greer, James 327 Holbach, Baron 136 Grenville, George 83, 127, 129, 138 Home, Henry, see Kames Grenville, William Wyndham, Hopetoun, George Johnstone, Earl of Baron 70–71, 336, 376, 388, 420, 252, 262, 360 422, 429, 436, 447–449, 463–464 Horn, Christer 203–204, 237–238 Grey, Charles 376, 380–382, 389, Horn, Fredric 179, 186, 190, 218, 398–399, 405, 414, 424, 439, 449–450 221–222, 225–226 Grey, Th omas de, see Walsingham Horsley, Samuel, Bishop of Rochester Guildford, George August North, Earl 431–433, 444 of 139, 145–147, 151, 154, 247, 251, Howard, Charles, see Norfolk 257, 262, 264, 266, 289, 272, 276–277, Howe, John 99 279–280, 286–289, 291, 294, 296, 298, Hume, David 254, 359 300, 302, 304–305, 307–308, 313, 315, Hussey, John, see Delaval 321–322, 333, 390, 428, 448, 472, 486 Hutcheson, Francis 113, 257 Gustavus III 161, 164, 177, 210, 226, 228, 239, 241–243, 245, 273, 280 Ingman, Carl 211 Gybbon, Phillips 98 Gyllenborg, Gustaf Adolf 182 Jackson, Jonathan 341 Gyllenhaal, Lars Herman 203, 206–208 Jaucourt, Louis de 64, 345, 409 Gyllensvahn, Fredrik 204–205, 207, Jenkinson, Charles, see Hawkesbury 237, 479 Jenkinson, Robert Banks 390, 399–402, 492 Halifax, George Montagu Dunk, Earl Jennings, John 179, 196, 231 of 96 Johnson, Samuel 53, 91–92, 97–98, Hamilton, Alexander 339 118 Hamilton, James, see Limerick Johnstone, George, see Hopetoun Hamilton, John James, Marquis of Jolliff e, Th omas Samuel 265 Abercorn 314 Hamilton, William Gerard 310–311, Kagg, Lars 221 361 Kames, Henry Home, Lord 427 Hardinge, George 303 Kepplerus, Alexander 209 Hardwicke, Philip Yorke, Earl of 87, Kimont, Earl 397 92, 94, 121, 295, 362 Kjörning, Mattias 179, 183, 193 Harrington, James 85 Knox, Vicesimus 407 Harrison, John 276–277 Kock, Johan 183 Hasencampf, Christopher 215 Kröger, Carl 234–235 Hastings, Francis Rawdon-Hastings, see Kryger, Johan Fredrik 208 Moira Hastings, Warren 325–326, 329 Lafayette, Marie-Joseph-Paul-Roch- Hawkesbury, Charles Jenkinson, Yves-Gilbert du Motier, Marquis Baron 143, 452 de 415–416 520 index of persons

Lansdowne, William Petty, Earl of Månsson, Gabriel 188–189, 236, 239 Shelbourne, Marquis of 260, 289, Marat, Paul 246, 485 294, 296, 299, 331, 335, 385–386, 388, Mårtensson, Eric 236 435, 456 Martin, James 54, 297, 316 Lauderdale, James Maitland, Earl of Mawkey, Joseph 336 381, 397, 420, 430–432, 435 Melin, Israel 214, 216–217, 220 LeDespencer, Francis Dashwood, Meredith, William 146, 154 Baron 112 Mitford, John, Baron Redesdall 467 Legge, Henry 111, 120 Milford, Richard Philips, Baron 393, Leijonancker, Fredrik Wilhelm 137, 440 226 Minto, Gilbert Elliot-Murray Leijonhufwud, Axel Gabriel 210 Kynynmound, Baronet 466–468, Leijonmarck, Gustaf Adolf 232 494 Lennox, Charles, Duke of Lennox, see Mirabeau, Honoré Gabriel de Riquetti Richmond de 385, 467 Leveson, John, see Gower Moira, Francis Rawdon-Hastings, Lewes, Watkin 312 Marquess of Hastings, Earl of Lilliehorn, Per 190, 222–223, 228, 231, 464–466, 494 233 Montesquieu, Charles-Louis de Secondat Limerick, James Hamilton, Lord 93 de 13, 18, 64, 116–119, 164, 167, Lindbom, Olof 235 208, 223–224, 254, 267, 345, 351, Linderstedt, Eric 182 424 Locke, John 10–11, 78, 85, 172–173, Montin, Johan 167 199–200, 247, 257, 268, 294, 399, 425, Moore, John 401 460–461, 477 Mornington, Richard Colley Wellesley, Lofft , Capel 373 Earl of 403–404, 411–412, 421, 441, Loughborough, Alexander Webberburn, 492 Earl of Rosslyn, Marquis of 385 Mortimer, Th omas 267 Louis XVI 380, 387, 394–395 Mullgrave, Henry Phipps, Lord 422 Lütkemann, Gabriel 179 Munthe, Johan Lorenz 214 Luttrell, John 259, 301 Murray, David, see Mansfi eld 133, 375 Luttrell, Simon Temple 252 Murray, William Vans 341 Lyttelton, George 105, 132 Lyttelton, William Henry, see Westcote Nackreii, Olof von 176 Newcastle, Th omas Pelham, Duke Mably, Gabriel Bonnot de 64, 270 of 93, 99–100, 104–107, 115–116, Macaulay, Catharine 366 119–121, 127, 475 Macdonald, Archibald 272, 292, 297, Nedham, Marchamont 133–134 303, 337 Norberg, Jonas Olofson 208 Machiavelli, Niccolò 89 Nordencrantz, Anders 166, 181, Mackintosh, James 366, 381 199–200 Macleod, Norman 396 Norfolk, Charles Howard, Duke Madison, James 339–340 of 297, 314, 325, 428–430, 456 Mahon, Charles Stanhope, Viscount North, George, see Guildford 309, 355, 397, 415, 422 Northey, William 120 Maitland, James, Earl of Lauderdale Northington, Robert Henley, Earl of 397 132–133, 155 Maitland, Th omas 412 Nugent, Robert, Earl of 271–272 Mann, Horace 47, 275 Mansfi eld, David Murray, Viscount O’Connor, Arthur 422 Stormont, Earl of 133, 140, 267, 375, Odelies, Johan 185 388–389, 411, 448 Onslow, George 147 Mansfi eld, James 277 Ord, John 304 index of persons 521

Paine, Th omas 18, 254, 257–258, 338, Redesdall, John Mitford, Baron 467 365–368, 377, 384, 396, 418–419, 442, Reuterholm, Christer Esbjörn 185–186 489, 490–491 Reuterhorn, Gustaf Gottfrid 192 Pane, John, see Westmorland Richmond, Charles Lennox, Duke Pechlin, Carl Fredrick 179, 195–197, of 245, 258–259, 266, 281, 290, 295, 205–208, 231–232, 241, 479 305, 370–377, 484 Pelham, Th omas, see Newcastle Ridderstolpe, Carl Johan 181, 190–191, Perceval, Charles George 281 201, 215, 217, 228, 231–232, 237–238, Perceval, John, see Egmont 479 Petty, John Henry, see Wycombe Rigby, Richard 266, 283, 292 Petty, William, see Landsdowne Robesbierre, Maximilien 17, 382, Pfeif, Captain 218 404–411, 413–414, 426–427, 441, 445, Phipps, Henry, see Mullgrave 448, 463, 489 Philips, Richard, see Milford Robinson, Morris 437 Pigott, Charles 424 Robinson, Th omas 71 Pitt, Th omas 280, 284, 291, 299 Rockingham, Charles Watson-Wentfort, Pitt, William, the Elder, see Chatham Marquis of (also Rockinghamites) Pitt, William, the Younger (also 129, 131, 138, 151, 258–260, 262, 269, Pittites) 26, 56, 269, 272, 284–287, 282, 289–290, 293, 303, 305 289, 291, 293, 298–300, 302–314, Rolle, John 292 316–322, 324–327, 332–336, 357–360, Rollin, Charles Erskine 73 369, 371, 373, 375, 381–384, 386, Rosslyn, Alexander Webberburn 388–390, 393–395, 397, 399–400, 403, Alexander, see Loughborough 405, 411–412, 415, 417–418, 421–422, Rosslyn, James Erskine, Earl of 303, 424, 430, 436, 430–440, 444–448, 307, 385 450–452, 458, 460–464, 486–488, Rous, George 363–364 490–494 Rousseau, Jean Jacques 14, 18, 64, Plato 125, 219 126–127, 196, 246, 338, 345, 347, 364, Plumer, William 70, 303 403–404, 432, 488 Polybius 7, 125, 166–167 Russel, Francis, see Bedford Portland, William Henry Cavendish Bemtick, Duke of 296 Sackville, George, Germain 142–143 Posse, Gustaf Mauritz 232 Sallust 106 Potter, Th omas 46 Salvius, David 167 Powys, Th omas 271, 291, 303, 312, Sandys, Samuel, Baron 90, 96–98, 103, 321–322, 336, 360, 401 475 Pratt, Charles, see Camden Savile, George 143, 148, 275 Price, Richard 255–257, 263, 270, Sawbridge, Alderman 312, 314 351–357, 362, 420, 485 Schauw, Arvid 198–200, 219, 482 Priestley, Joseph 136–137, 257, 302, Scheff er, Carl Fredrick 163–164, 366 242–243, 482 Proby, John Joshua, see Carysfort Schönberg, Anders 181, 185, 191, 195, Pulteney, William, Earl of Bath 83–84 205 Pulteney, William, Sir (born William Schönström, Johan Albrekt 188 Johnstone) 307, 309 Scott, John 336, 422 Selwyn, John 104 Quanten, Carl Jacob von 188, 238 Serenius, Jacob, Bishop 229, 481 Sharpe, Gregory 113 Raleif, Walter 118 Shelbourne, William Petty, Earl of, see Raméen, Olof 216 Landsdowne Rappe, Carl 196 Sheridan, Richard Brinsley 283, 357, Rawdon-Hastings, Francis, see Moira 381, 385, 392, 398, 412, 418, 438, 442, Raynal, Guillaume-Th omas François 445, 461, 493–494 254 Sheridan, Th omas 267 522 index of persons

Shippen, William 46, 81, 103 Wadenstierna, Carl Eric 237 Sidney, Algernon 85, 89, 257, 461 Walpole, Robert 25, 71, 73, 75–77, Sieyès, Emmanuel-Joseph 335, 82–83, 86, 88–88, 91, 96–97, 99–100, 345–347, 355 102–104, 109, 249, 269, 406–407, Skelton, Philip 84 473–475, 492 Smith, William 358 Walsingham, Th omas de Grey, Solon 134 Baron 142, 271, 280 Somerset, Charles Noel, see Beaufort Watson, Richard, Bishop of Llandaff Sparre, Carl 195, 237, 479 425–427 Sparrschiöld, Carl Magnus 181 Watson-Wentfort, Charles, see Spens, Henry 125 Rockingham Spinoza, Baruch 12 Webberburn, Alexander, see Stanhope, Charles, see Mahon Loughborough Stanhope, Philip Dormer, see Wellesley, Richard Colley, see Chesterfi eld Mornington Stanley, John Th omas 414, 437, 445 Wentfort, William, see FitzWilliam Stewart, John 412 Westcote, William Henry Lyttelton, Stormont, David Murray, Viscount, see Baron 83, 270 Mansfi eld Westmorland, John Pane, Earl of 104, Sundblad, Johan 195, 212, 218–219 111 Surrey, Charles Howard, Earl of, see Wetterberg, Peter 235 Norfolk Whitbread, Samuel II 381, 391, 395, Sydenham, Humprey 112 405, 414, 491 Svensson, Lars 236 White, William 378 Svensson, Nils 229–330 Whitmore, Th omas 392 Sydney, Th omas Townsend, Whitworth, William 154 Baron 149, 245 Wikman, [Caspar] 213 Wilberforce, William 55, 311, 372, Tacitus 323 438, 445–446 Talbot, William, Baron and Earl of Wilkes, John (also Wilkites) 25, Talbot 121–122 127–129, 136–138, 140–144, 147–148, Talleyrand, Charles Maurice de 385 153–154, 181, 185, 188, 190, 245–246, Tarleton, Banastre 412 250, 252–253, 256, 258, 261–262, 268, Taylor, M.S. 384 270, 286, 290, 476–477 Temple, Willson 118 Willes, Sir John 72 Th am, Peter 222 William III 273 Th elwall, John 428–429, 448–449, 455, Williams, David 350–351 493 Williams-Wynn, Watkin 69, 80 Th urlow, Edward, Baron Tark Wilson, James 341 149–150, 304, 435 Windham, William 54, 360, 374, 384, Tollstorp, Georg 193 390, 397, 401–401, 439, 442, 492 Torbiörnsson, Lars 184, 188 Woodfall, William 53, 462 Townsend, Charles, see Bayning Wraxall, Nathaniel 272–274 Townsend, James 148 Wray, Cecil 308 Townsend, John 271 Wycliff e, Th omas 262–263, 488 Townsend, Th omas, see Sydney Wycombe, John Henry Petty, Earl Tucker, Josiah 294 of 389 Turner, Charles 292 Wyndham, William Sir, see Grenville Tyers, Th omas 268, 278 Wywill, Christopher 262, 275, 290, 421 Uggla, Leonhard Magnus 180 Ungers, Hans 193 Yonge, William Sir 72, 83, 108–109 Yorke, Philip, see Hardwicke Virgin, Arvid Bernhard 184–185, 189 Young, William 323–324, 404, 452, Voltaire 136 475 INDEX OF SUBJECTS

Accession Charter (konungaförsäkran, see also Greece and classical Sweden) 198, 212–215, 218–219, democracy 222, 225–226, 231–232 Austria, Austrian 102, 104, 113 Address (of Th anks) 24, 46–49 Authority 8–9, 11, 16, 37, 39, 45, 47, Age of Liberty (frihetstiden, Sweden) 63, 65, 73–74, 77, 85, 93–94, 97–99, 14, 26, 34, 157–163, 165–167, 170, 104, 118, 132–134, 137, 139–140, 172–173, 176, 206, 229, 239, 242–243, 143–145, 148–149, 151, 154, 199–200, 245, 254, 273–274, 477–485 248, 250–251, 256, 259–262, 293, 305, America 3–4, 17, 127, 247–249, 317, 327, 329, 333, 336–338, 342, 362, 251–252, 254–255, 257–258, 261, 368–369, 382, 384, 396, 401, 406–408, 278–279, 289, 294, 302, 311, 324, 451, 458–459, 469, 477, 479 see also 327, 337–342, 345, 359, 368–376, people, the power of the, power, 378–380, 383, 427, 439, 441–442, sovereignty and supreme power 446, 455, 488, 490 Autocracy 143, 162, 189, 194–195, 241, American crisis, Revolution, war 2, 438 5, 7, 16–17, 26, 54, 65, 69, 120, 123, 129–133, 135, 137–138, 154, 245–246, Batavian Republic 4, 33 see also Dutch 249, 251–254, 258–262, 268–271, Republic and the Netherlands 279–280, 282, 284, 288–289, 292, 296, Bill of Rights 327, 434, 443, 445 299–300, 302, 319, 337–338, 344, 352, British Parliament (Westminster) 4–5, 371, 381, 420, 426, 448, 477–478, 484 26–27, 33, 35–36, 38, 42–43, 45–46, Anarchy 5–6, 17, 64–65, 74, 81, 113, 57, 59, 62, 65, 67, 73, 112, 116, 131, 117, 126, 148, 152–153, 157, 188, 191, 133, 135, 154–155, 157, 189, 205, 194, 202, 232, 262, 268, 293, 312, 332, 245–246, 279, 324, 335, 337, 342–343, 345, 354–355, 357, 367, 369, 383, 411, 346, 348, 353, 388, 390, 395, 416, 423, 424, 434, 445–449, 462–464, 467, 426, 455, 463, 466, 477, 484, 488–489 489 Burgher, Burgher Estate (Sweden) 34, Aristocracy, aristocratic (also 38, 50–51, 160, 170, 173, 179, 183, anti-aristocratic) 7–8, 48, 59–60, 188, 190, 193–194, 198, 210, 212–220, 64–65, 73–75, 78, 81, 85–86, 89, 224–225, 227–228, 231, 239–240, 95–96, 108–109, 114, 116–118, 121, 478–480 123, 129–130, 132, 134, 151, 166–168, 170, 176–177, 179, 183, 188, 193–194, Canada 368–369, 372, 374 206–207, 218, 220–223, 232, 238, 242, Ceremonial speaking 45–50, 119, 247, 251, 253, 265–266, 272, 278, 137, 239, 246, 251, 263, 279, 353, 455, 291–292, 301–302, 304–305, 309, 315, 486 322–323, 327, 331–334, 356, 359–360, Citizen(s) 7–8, 114, 121–122, 126, 362–364, 370–374, 376, 379, 381, 128, 134, 166–170, 172, 179, 181, 199, 385–386, 391, 394, 397, 400–401, 403, 210–211, 231, 234, 254, 280, 293, 340, 406–408, 417, 419, 424, 426–429, 444, 346, 365, 397, 406, 416 448, 454–455, 464, 479, 490–491 Civil war(s) 16, 61, 84, 107, 127, 152, Aristotelian tradition 7, 48, 59, 355, 154, 334, 377–378 363, 369, 471 Clergy, Clerical Estate 51, 60, 114, Association movement 262, 267–268, 160, 170, 173, 179, 183, 188, 193–194, 275, 290, 296–297, 299, 311 213, 216, 220, 225, 227–229, 233–235, Athens 59, 63, 73, 85, 118, 123, 159, 238–240, 242, 419, 431, 433, 479–480 196, 202, 223, 231, 242, 249, 254, 273, Common people 6, 8, 17, 60, 72, 74, 338, 360, 367, 370, 378–379, 408, 427 83, 84, 93, 99, 101, 117, 122–123, 125, 524 index of subjects

127, 167, 178, 183–184, 186, 188–189, Modern democracy 155, 160, 166, 203, 208, 214, 217, 229–230, 235–236, 169, 203, 223, 232, 240–241, 456, 239, 278, 337, 433, 479–480 466 Conceptual change, history, innovation, Representative democracy 1, 17, modifi cation, redefi nition, revision, 157–159, 162, 167–168, 171, 174, transformation 6, 10, 14, 18–19, 208, 267, 324, 331, 340, 342, 22–23, 27–28, 30, 41–42, 48, 51–52, 344, 346, 340, 355, 362–364, 374, 130, 137, 153, 279, 282, 287, 291, 320, 378–379, 382, 409, 422, 428–429, 344, 348, 380, 427, 429, 457, 464, 466, 448–449, 463, 478, 482–483, 495 468, 473, 475, 486, 494–495 Democrat(s) 61, 159, 345–346, 365, Continent, Continental 20, 63, 80, 105, 407, 416, 419, 422, 424–425, 429, 109, 116, 120, 136, 176, 258, 261, 273, 447–448, 464, 466 301, 350–351, 387, 391, 457, 463 see Democratic element (of constitution) also Europe 12, 54, 59–60, 63–64, 74–75, 78, Corresponding Societies 376, 388, 393, 80–81, 85, 121–122, 124, 130, 132, 418–420, 430, 438, 441 147, 157, 195, 203–204, 207–210, 221–222, 232, 266, 268, 272, 275, Declaration of the Rights of Man and of 278, 285–287, 301, 304, 308–310, the Citizen 346 316, 319–320, 322, 325–326, 328, 331, Deliberation 5, 19, 41, 59, 74, 86, 142, 343–344, 348, 352–353, 356–358, 361, 150, 160, 170, 249, 265, 267, 300, 320, 364, 366, 368–369, 371–375, 380–381, 334, 400–401, 408, 427, 469 385, 391–392, 395, 400–402, 405, 411, Democracy 419–420, 424, 431, 441, 446, 474, 479, Absolute, complete, extreme, perfect, 481, 484, 486–490, 492–493 pure, simple, wild democracy Democratic principles 109, 163, 168, 73–74, 221, 224, 250, 255, 257, 362, 370, 372–374, 380, 400–401, 266–269, 301, 309, 330, 333–334, 414–415, 425, 428, 439, 449, 457, 339–340, 356, 358–359, 362, 364, 490 369–370, 372, 376, 381, 401, 409, Democratization 6, 9, 15, 42, 166, 171, 413, 416, 425, 434, 446, 453, 459, 205, 409, 484 463, 467, 469, 474, 485, 489–490, Demos 76, 345 492–493 Denmark 4, 143, 185, 211, 245, 258, British (type of) democracy 12–13, 346 348, 352, 354–355, 361, 374–375, Despotism, despotic 6, 125, 134, 150, 379, 391, 401, 410, 416, 419, 473, 176–177, 191, 193–194, 219, 242, 245, 490–492 269, 282, 312, 327–328, 330, 351, 354, Classical democracy 166, 195, 357, 366–367, 381, 391, 393, 398, 205–206, 218, 221, 223–224, 232, 417, 421–422, 427, 431–432, 441–442, 242, 250, 272, 322–323, 329, 338, 447, 454, 462, 476, 487, 489 see also 343, 351, 363, 365–366, 379, 408, tyranny 427, 450, 452–453, 467, 476, 479, Diet 2–4, 14, 25–26, 33–34, 37–38, 40, 482–485, 493 46, 53, 60, 154, 157, 473, 477, 484 see Direct, immediate democracy 4, 6, also Estates and Riksdag 159, 162, 167, 206, 222, 265, 323, Dutch Republic, Dutch 4, 7, 10, 12, 339–340, 345–346, 365, 379, 387, 59, 109, 114, 165, 196, 249, 272–273, 410, 447, 470, 482 305, 315, 331, 335, 341, 344, 346, 348, French (type of) democracy 13–14, 351, 388, 439, 447 see also Batavian 17, 27, 54, 326, 344, 348, 349–350, Republic and Holland 352–358, 360–363, 365, 375, 379–381, 395, 401, 410, 413–414, Elections 49, 65, 67–73, 76–78, 85, 416, 418, 429, 434, 439, 447–449, 102, 108, 110–113, 120, 124, 127, 130, 473, 486, 490–493 133, 135–139, 143, 145–147, 160, 179, Limited democracy 167, 489, 493 190, 194, 198, 212–214, 233–234, 237, Mixed democracy 269, 448, 493 248, 252, 257, 262, 269, 277, 290, 300, index of subjects 525

308, 313–314, 316, 320, 362, 386, 389, 206, 211, 233, 238, 251, 258, 281, 291, 399, 403–404, 451, 466, 476, 480 299, 437, 454, 474, 485 Enlightenment 1, 13–14, 19, 64, 126, Free state, government 4, 91, 106–107, 152, 163, 166, 170–171, 246–247, 292, 118, 143, 158, 174, 181, 192, 208, 245, 340, 344–345, 370, 404, 412, 430, 253, 258, 292, 389–390, 425, 431, 436, 487–488 464, 477 see also republic Equality 6, 63–64, 73, 126, 166–168, French Revolution 1–2, 4–5, 9–10, 170, 212, 216–218, 222, 226, 250, 12–17, 25–28, 37, 55, 57, 64–65, 153, 339–340, 345, 358–359, 379, 387, 395, 158–160, 163, 166, 171, 276, 324, 326, 401, 406, 410, 435, 444, 450, 470, 329–330, 337–338, 342–344, 346–348, 477–484 350, 354, 356–358, 360, 362–364, Estates (ständerna, Sweden) 2–5, 8, 368–369, 371–372, 374–375, 380, 383, 11, 14, 24–25, 33–34, 37–38, 40, 385, 387, 391, 399, 403, 409–410, 50–53, 60, 64, 69, 79, 115, 157–243, 414–415, 417–420, 423, 425, 429–430, 274, 324 441–442, 447, 450–452, 455–457, 471, Europe 2, 4, 8, 12, 16–17, 19, 22–23, 478, 483–484, 487–490 30–31, 33, 62–63, 109, 125, 155, 158, Friends of the People 376, 380, 385, 160, 166, 170–171, 199, 213, 249, 391, 397–398, 416 273–274, 335, 354–355, 422, 427, 439, 463, 469–470 see also Continental Geneva 246, 250, 309, 432–433 Excise Crisis 25, 71–72, 74–75, 91 Germany, Germans 4, 22, 59, 73, 81–82, 114, 341 Factions 75, 86, 93, 99, 103, 106, 110, Glorious Revolution see the 114, 123, 134, 143–144, 161, 207, 247, Revolution of 1688 274, 276, 296, 339–340, 359, 367, 373, Gordon riots 47, 262, 266, 269, 271, 397, 406, 413, 474–475 see also parties 274–275, 283, 297 Finland, Finnish 38, 230, 243, 478 Greece, Greek 7, 17, 45, 121, 190, 196, Florence 217 223, 242, 250, 253, 340, 343, 404, 453 Folket (‘people’ in Swedish) 25, 159, see also classical democracy 172, 178, 191, 195–196, 198, 213, 229, 241, 478 Habeas Corpus 418, 427–428 Form of government (regeringsformen, Hanoverian(s) 98, 101–102, 111, 113, Sweden) 157–158, 161–162, 165, 389 167–168, 172, 176, 178, 189–190, 192, Holland 4, 292, 305, 351, 488 see also 195, 198, 203–204, 207, 219, 221–222, the Dutch Republic and the 225, 231–232, 236, 243 Netherlands France, French 3–5, 7, 13–14, 17, 33, 63–65, 105, 119, 122, 129, 157, India Bill, East India Company 296, 161–162, 166–176, 204, 211, 222, 241, 302–303, 316–318, 325–327, 329–330, 246–247, 261, 330–331, 335, 340, 487 344–350, 354–357, 359–360, 362–364, Ireland, Irish 317, 456–458, 461, 464, 366, 368, 370, 372, 374, 377, 379, 466–469, 494 381, 383–384, 386–390, 392, 394–398, 401, 404–405, 410–411, 416–417, 420, Jacobin(s) 387, 397, 402, 405, 409, 422, 426–427, 429–430, 434, 436, 438, 412–413, 421, 430, 435, 444–445, 447, 444–447, 449, 454, 462, 469, 484, 489, 454–459, 463, 469 491–493 see also French Revolution Freedom 69, 71, 80, 88, 106, 118, 125, Legislation 44, 85, 161, 165, 197, 223, 138, 149, 155, 176, 179, 185, 188–189, 293, 317, 467, 491 195, 201–202, 208, 214–217, 223–224, Legislature 60, 95, 131–132, 154, 199, 230, 272, 316, 321, 355, 368, 379, 428, 253, 259, 277, 301, 313, 320, 333, 359, 435, 440 see also liberty 394, 436–437, 462 see also power, Freedom of the press 24, 53, 80, 168, legislative 170, 180, 182, 184–185, 187–188, 202, Levellers 12, 16, 61, 388, 391 526 index of subjects

Liberties (of the people) 14, 68, 78, 385–388, 391–394, 396–397, 400–401, 80–85, 94, 97–99, 101–102, 104, 107, 403, 407–408, 412–413, 417, 419–421, 109–110, 129, 132, 138, 140, 143, 146, 426, 429, 431, 437, 445, 448–449, 451, 148, 154, 183, 196, 209, 227, 231–232, 453–454, 461, 476, 479, 485, 490–491 236, 256, 266, 271–274, 294–295, see also royal prerogative 303–305, 316, 327, 330, 332, 354, 358, Limited monarchy 16, 121, 254, 389, 415, 430, 435–436, 443, 445, 456, 310–312, 350–351, 389, 407, 465 see also freedom, liberty, people, 415–416, 461 the rights of the, and privileges Mixed monarchy 90, 152, 167, 205, Liberty 46, 73, 88, 95, 106–110, 114, 232, 393, 424, 429 118, 125, 128, 133, 146–147, 169–170, 172, 180–181, 191–194, 198, 207, 216, National Constituent Assembly 171, 220, 223–224, 232–234, 237, 241–243, 346, 355, 357, 361, 369, 491 245, 247, 257–258, 265, 269, 308, National Convention 387–388, 390, 345, 350–351, 353–354, 356, 358, 369, 393–395, 410, 420, 447 374–375, 382–383, 387, 390, 412–413, Natural rights 61, 247, 256, 260, 270, 424, 433, 437–438, 440–441, 476, 479, 332, 418, 436 see also people, rights 481, 484 see also freedom and liberties of the London 53, 83, 105, 107, 109–110, Netherlands, see also the Dutch 128, 131, 136, 144, 147–150, 153, 264, Republic and the Batavian Republic 276, 279, 290, 311, 316, 320, 338, 342, 59, 88, 324, 346 349–350, 386, 388, 405, 419, 421, 438, Nobility, Noble Estate 50–51, 60, 468, 475 107–109, 117, 130, 160–161, 163–164, Lower orders 65, 81, 137, 160–161, 168–171, 173, 175–178, 180–181, 183, 169, 173, 187, 198, 210, 212–213, 227, 186–187, 190–191, 193–195, 201, 231, 233, 239, 419, 424, 433, 435, 211–213, 215–221, 228, 230–233, 237, 441–444, 447, 456, 478, 481, 483 239–240, 266, 385, 394, 435–436, 478–481, 483 Magna Charta 96, 140, 327 Middlesex election 136, 139, 143, Oligarchy 33, 72, 81, 101, 106–107, 145–147, 151, 252, 290, 443, 470 110, 113, 118, 136, 162, 333, 398, 444, Minutes 4, 34, 38, 40, 50–52, 157 see 475 also parliamentary records Mixed constitution, government 2, Parliamentary reform 5, 17, 26, 30–31, 7–8, 10, 12, 15–16, 25–27, 33, 59, 64, 36, 42, 150, 154, 245, 252, 264–265, 77–78, 84–85, 96, 114–115, 119, 134, 269, 272, 275, 281, 286–289, 291, 144, 151, 166–168, 195, 202, 205, 207, 293–294, 296–297, 299, 301, 306, 221, 224, 249, 254, 265, 268, 271–272, 308–309, 312–313, 315–316, 319, 325, 277– 278, 285, 311–312, 317, 319–320, 331, 334, 341, 348, 350, 359–360, 366, 322–323, 328, 330, 343–345, 348, 353, 377, 380–383, 387–389, 403, 406, 411, 356–357, 363–364, 369–373, 382, 395, 414–415, 421, 444–445, 449, 454–455, 407, 411, 419–420, 426–427, 437, 441, 462, 473–474, 485–488, 492 444, 446–447, 455, 459–460, 476, 479, Parliamentary procedure 31, 33, 44, 483, 485, 487–488, 490 144, 205, 238 Monarchy, monarchical 13, 27, 32, Parliamentary records 67, 233, 452, 49, 50–61, 63–64, 66, 69–70, 74–75, 472 see also minutes 160–162, 164–165, 167, 170, 173, 175, Party, parties 26, 38, 44, 47, 61, 178, 184–185, 188, 190, 195–197, 106–107, 120, 137, 161, 165, 175–176, 202, 204, 206–207, 213, 215, 221, 179–181, 183–184, 188, 192, 198, 201, 227–229, 232, 241–242, 245–247, 254, 204–207, 209–210, 213, 217, 225, 227, 258, 261–262, 265–266, 270, 272–273, 229, 231–232, 235, 237, 239, 241, 252, 279–280, 283, 285–287, 291, 293, 295, 298, 311, 350–351, 357, 365, 378, 415, 309, 312, 322, 327, 331, 354, 356, 424, 427, 480–481, 483 see also 359, 361–362, 369–373, 376, 379–381, factions index of subjects 527

Patriotism, patriots 12, 38, 67, 130, 462, 475, 477, 480, 484 see also 235, 237, 261, 305, 307, 344, 346, 351, liberties 365, 408, 484 Sense of the people 49, 66, 86, 144, Peasant Estate, peasants (Sweden) 38, 252–253, 269, 274–275, 277, 280, 51–52, 60, 115, 160, 166, 172–173, 287–288, 292, 294, 297, 299–300, 177, 183–184, 188–189, 193–194, 308, 310, 313–314, 316–319, 321, 203–204, 208–209, 212–213, 216, 333–337, 362, 383, 396, 421, 448, 227–230, 233, 235–236, 239, 464, 475 479–480 Sentiments of the people 47, 60, 62, People see also folket 66, 89, 92–93, 95–98, 101–102, 113, Agents of the people 316, 337, 144, 198, 238, 253, 275, 283, 298, 339, 341–342, 347, 401–402, 442, 312, 314, 341, 451, 479, 481 492–493 Sovereignty of the people 2–6, Delegates of the people 60, 70, 199, 10–12, 16, 18, 22–23, 25–28, 57, 210, 234, 275, 295, 307–308, 319 61–62, 68, 153, 163, 175, 177, Interests of the people 67, 70–72, 191, 218, 246–247, 249, 254, 259, 83–84, 124, 129, 145, 153, 199, 206, 263, 267, 270, 290, 303, 331, 337, 248, 250, 280, 311–312, 316, 321, 345–350, 352, 363–368, 371, 378, 324, 333, 405, 477, 484 380, 386–387, 390–399, 403–404, Majesty of the people 149–150, 249, 406–407, 410–413, 418–419, 261, 270, 293, 352, 396, 420, 430, 421–425, 430, 437, 440, 442–444, 451, 456, 485 449, 451, 454–467, 469–473, 485, Omnipotence of the people 488–495 256–257, 270, 485 Voice of the people 25, 48, 59, Opinion of the people 93, 98, 100, 61–62, 66–68, 77–78, 88, 91, 94, 98, 102, 271, 288, 294–295, 298, 317, 102–104, 116, 122, 142–143, 451 145, 151, 153, 177–178, 182–183, Power of the people 23, 26, 34, 186–187, 189, 191–193, 201–202, 60–61, 63, 67, 71–72, 74, 103, 104, 211, 214, 228, 234, 237, 257, 110, 126, 148, 165, 166, 173, 203, 260–261, 266, 268, 276, 282, 284, 248, 253, 256, 260, 263, 273, 276, 290–293, 306–309, 311, 314, 317, 288, 293, 315, 326, 334, 336, 338, 322–323, 333–335, 362, 375–376, 342, 345, 366, 374–375, 430, 383, 405, 434, 438, 474–475, 485, 441–442, 452, 462, 474–477, 481 487 see also vox populi Representatives of the people 60, 70, Will of the people 66, 120, 169, 80, 87, 103, 121–122, 135, 143, 148, 173, 176, 201, 256, 263, 298, 152, 171, 227, 275, 281–282, 292, 314–315, 334, 336, 362, 367, 294–295, 299–300, 307, 310, 334, 394–395, 397, 405, 413, 420–421, 337, 341, 363, 366, 381–382, 389, 485, 488 415, 442, 478, 482 see also Plenipotentiaries ( fullmäktige, plenipotentiaries Sweden) 164, 167, 170, 172, 189, Rights of the people 25, 68, 71, 193–194, 197–199, 208–216, 225, 78, 80–82, 85, 94, 111, 129, 138, 234–236, 241–242, 482–483 143–144, 146–147, 150, 153, 177, Poland, Polish 4, 7, 10, 17, 33–34, 59, 180–183, 186, 191–192, 195–199, 109, 115, 117, 182, 185, 188, 194, 217, 202, 204, 206, 209–211, 214, 223, 271, 383 217–221, 225, 229, 231–232, Political agent(s) 14, 23, 48, 68–69, 234–237, 240, 250, 252–253, 141, 173, 178, 253, 255–256, 260, 280, 255, 260, 263, 268–269, 274–275, 288, 314, 345, 365, 456, 476, 486 see 277–278, 281, 283, 292, 301, 305, also people, agents of the 307, 310, 319, 322, 333, 335–336, Political community 7–8, 10, 42–43, 362, 369, 386, 389, 396, 398, 45, 49, 57, 62, 78, 80, 85, 87, 105, 420–421, 423–424, 427–428, 430, 108, 121, 158, 162, 171, 175, 183, 193, 434–435, 438–439, 441, 443, 450, 217, 229–230, 270, 273, 281, 320–321, 528 index of subjects

344–345, 350, 371, 408–409, 411, 213, 215, 221, 240, 249, 257, 274, 455–457, 471–472, 477, 484 284, 307, 310, 326, 335–337, 341, Political culture 18–23, 29, 33, 36, 41, 391, 403, 459, 461, 471, 479, 481, 52, 62, 65–67, 136, 155, 158, 163, 248, 483–484, 491 251–252, 307, 310, 345, 373, 391, 431, Power of the many 167, 238, 328, 478 487 Political discourse 2, 8, 20, 32, 42, 57, Supreme power 9, 11, 13, 81–82, 65–66, 136, 146, 158–159, 169, 183, 88, 116–117, 126, 131, 160, 162, 198, 224, 230, 256, 303, 348, 351, 366, 164–165, 173–174, 189, 191, 195, 431, 437, 440, 470, 473, 489 see also 201, 206, 211, 221, 223, 242, 263, public debate 267–268, 460, 474, 479, 481 see also Political language 1, 3–4, 12, 16, 18, sovereignty 21, 40, 55–57, 116, 174, 242, 246, 277, Press 24, 31–32, 36, 40, 52–54, 62, 67, 279, 286, 348, 352, 489 see also 81, 94, 127–128, 136, 143, 175, 180, political vocabularies 183, 210–211, 214, 220, 223, 227, 233, Political theory 9–10, 14, 16, 30, 34, 241, 454, 456, 460, 474, 478, 491–492, 41, 61, 63, 65, 72, 81, 171–172, 199, 494–495 see also freedom of the press 204, 224, 323, 329, 339, 355, 426–427, and printed literature 434, 452, 473, 482, 488 Printed, published literature 19, 31–32, Political vocabularies 20, 23, 29–32, 36, 88, 141, 171, 184, 189, 235, 254, 43, 56, 159, 198, 235, 426 see also 331, 349, 375, 380, 428, 460, 473–474, political language 480, 485, 488 see also press and public Popular consent 61, 165, 257, 341, 343, discourse 460 Privilege(s) 24, 31–32, 36, 40, 52–54, Popular government 12, 17, 24–25, 64, 62, 67, 81, 94, 127–128, 136, 143, 89–92, 94–96, 101–102, 105, 108–109, 175, 180, 183, 210–211, 214, 220, 223, 111, 113, 117–118, 134–135, 149, 155, 227, 233, 241, 454, 456, 460, 474, 478, 168, 203, 223–224, 238, 242, 246–247, 491–492, 494–495 253, 255, 260, 267–269, 273, 276, 281, pro et contra 43, 472 290, 300–304, 307, 328, 333, 337, Prussia, Prussians 176, 351, 415 339–340, 342, 365, 368–369, 388, 403, Public, publicity, public opinion, 410, 416, 454, 470, 474–475, 478, 481, public sphere 16, 19–20, 24, 29, 483, 485 31–32, 36, 40, 42, 47–48, 53–54, 56, Popular sovereignty 1–3, 6, 10–12, 60, 62, 66–67, 92–94, 111, 136, 141, 15–21, 25–26, 31, 34, 61, 66–67, 146, 149–150, 166, 180, 184, 197, 136–137, 157–159, 163, 171, 174, 199, 233, 251, 260, 264, 277, 283, 291, 242, 250, 255, 331, 334, 337, 339, 302, 327–328, 334, 384, 386, 400–401, 341–342, 365, 390–391, 393, 406–407, 405, 452, 472–473, 480 see also public 411–412, 441, 447, 459, 468, 471, 478, debate 481, 483 see also people, sovereignty Public debate, public discourse 2, 4, of the 11, 20, 23–24, 32, 34–36, 42, 54–55, Populus 7–8, 172 57, 73, 84, 107, 112–113, 118, Power, see also authority 121–122, 125–127, 134–135, 138, Absolute power 88, 169, 168, 141, 145, 169–170, 172, 182, 187, 172–173, 176, 197, 248, 328, 356, 202–203, 205, 208, 210, 218, 227, 359, 369, 394, 481, 487 234, 248, 251, 259, 267–268, 279, 293, Legislative power 2, 34, 74–75, 112, 337, 345, 349, 352, 355, 362, 366, 125, 132, 148, 160, 169, 173–174, 368, 379–380, 384, 396, 399, 401, 407, 177, 192, 199, 208, 250, 256, 267, 422–423, 471–472, 474, 476, 478, 269, 315, 340, 343, 356, 366, 462, 483, 485, 493 see also political 469, 482 discourse, press, printed literature and Political power 1, 4, 6–11, 16, 34, public 61, 65, 67, 76, 78, 99, 119, 135, 150, 152, 176, 182–183, 191, 198, 201, Quebec 368, 372, 490 index of subjects 529

Radicalism, radicalization, radicals 300–301, 305, 340–341, 346, 363, 25–26, 128, 136, 141, 158, 162, 368–371, 385, 390, 392, 394–395, 168–169, 172–173, 183, 193–194, 404, 432, 439, 472, 474, 476, 485, 197–198, 201–202, 204, 206, 210, 212, 489 216–217, 219–220, 224, 227, 230, 232, Roman Republic 7, 17, 63, 73, 84, 234–236, 238, 240, 243, 246–247, 90, 118, 127, 217–218, 230, 342, 252–253, 257, 259–260, 262–264, 266, 338, 440, 460 268, 270, 274, 278–279, 282, 288, 290, Revolution of 1688 16, 61, 103, 266, 298–299, 303, 306–307, 312, 316, 321, 273, 335, 350, 362, 369, 395–396, 422, 328, 331, 334, 336–338, 347, 350, 356, 429, 433, 437, 441, 461, 476 358, 364, 366, 368, 371, 377, 380–382, Revolutionary associations 397, 399, 384, 386–389, 391, 397, 402, 408–411, 418–419, 430, 459, 492 415, 417–421, 423–424, 428, 430, Revolutionary War 25, 395, 458 433–435, 438, 442, 447, 450, 454, 456, Rhetoric 19, 29, 33–34, 39–46, 56, 458, 461, 468, 473–474, 480, 482–485, 66–67, 70, 94, 111, 113, 124, 131, 487–488, 490, 492–493 141, 144, 173, 228, 230–231, 241–242, Representation 4–5, 8–9, 11, 13, 294, 302, 305–306, 309, 331, 338, 17–18, 21, 24–28, 31, 37, 51, 57, 341, 382, 417, 439, 443, 454–455, 475, 59–60, 64, 68–69, 100, 112, 118, 123, 484 127, 129, 131, 133, 135–136, 145, Riksdag (Sweden) 24, 26, 53, 162–163, 149–150, 159–164, 166–167, 169, 196, 166, 172–173, 175, 178–198, 202, 205, 208–209, 211–212, 214, 217, 235, 204–205, 207–210, 214, 223, 229, 245–246, 249–253, 255, 262, 265, 233–234, 236, 274, 478–481, 483 see 267, 270, 275, 285, 291–293, 295, also Diet and Estates 297, 299–301, 306, 314–316, 320–321, Rome, Roman 45, 63, 73, 106–108, 323–324, 330, 333, 338, 340, 346–348, 114, 118, 121, 123, 127, 134, 166, 352, 359–360, 362–364, 366, 377–379, 172–173, 190–191, 196, 217–218, 223, 382–383, 388, 392, 394–395, 398–400, 242, 249–250, 253–254, 273, 337–338, 402–406, 408–410, 419, 423, 444–445, 360, 370, 441 see also Roman 449–450, 454–455, 463, 468, 471, Republic 482–484, 490–494 see also Royal prerogative 157, 164, 190, 196, plenipotentiaries, representative 201, 206, 215, 232, 259, 266, 273, democracy and people, 286, 296–297, 300, 305, 309, 311, 373, representatives of the 385, 390, 414, 417, 419, 476 see also Representative assemblies, institutions monarchy 2–5, 7, 10, 15, 19–20, 22, 29, 34, 60, Russia, Russians 161, 197, 206, 211, 154, 161, 192, 248, 256, 325, 330, 335, 232 344, 348, 353, 381–382, 416, 428, 470, 473, 488 Scandinavia, Scandinavian 164, 176, Representative government 2, 18, 59, 236, 245 81–82, 270, 337, 341, 345, 363, Scotland, Scottish 111–112, 247, 293, 378–379, 409–410, 440, 447, 454–455, 331, 375, 396–397, 435 483 Secret Committee (sekreta utskottet, Republic 7, 12, 17, 64, 73, 92, 100, 106, Sweden) 24, 51–52, 172, 175, 179, 114, 116, 125, 132–133, 155, 167, 206, 183, 194–195, 197, 204–205, 207, 215, 217, 222–223, 310–312, 337–339, 209, 213–215, 218–221, 224, 227, 231, 342, 357, 365, 370, 372, 378, 387, 393, 236 409, 426–428, 477, 491 Senate (rådet, Sweden) 2, 38, 157, 161, Democratic republic, state 114, 118, 176–177, 179–184, 186–187, 190–191, 134, 145, 407, 409–410, 426–427, 193–194, 201–202, 204, 207, 214, 233, 447, 467, 469, 492 236–237, 242, 479 Republicanism 12–13, 51, 61, Septennial Act 25, 67–78 133, 163, 170, 188, 201, 211, Seven Years’ War 119–124, 127–128, 228, 237–238, 242, 261, 273, 276, 476 530 index of subjects

Society for Constitutional Information 135, 140, 152, 251, 256, 258, 270, 281, 312, 419 319, 362, 375–376, 406 Sovereignty 9, 12, 14, 18, 21, 24, Suff rage 9, 62, 131, 145, 194, 252, 255, 63–64, 69, 73, 105, 117, 119, 124, 264, 266, 299–301, 305–306, 316, 337, 126, 130–132, 134, 157, 159, 164–165, 345, 377, 386, 399, 403–405, 415, 168–169, 174, 176–177, 185, 188–189, 440–441, 444–445, 450–451, 453, 456, 191, 194, 197, 247, 254, 256, 259, 263, 466, 469, 493 268, 270–271, 277–279, 303, 332, 341, 343, 347, 366, 373, 392, 396, 456, Turkey, Turkish 327, 431 460–461, 474, 477, 485–486, 491 Tyranny, tyrants 27, 73–76, 80–81, National sovereignty 278, 346–347, 92, 106, 125, 144, 157, 167, 176, 195, 404, 407, 410 218, 226, 248, 253, 287, 310, 312, Sovereignty of parliament 132, 256, 334, 354–355, 357–358, 363, 377, 379, 303, 395, 423, 440, 443, 457, 465, 401, 405, 407, 411–414, 416, 420–422, 467–468, 473, 476–477, 481, 494 426–427, 432–433, 441, 448, 460, 492 see also people, the sovereignty of the, see also despotism popular sovereignty and supreme power United States see America Spain 79, 83, 86–87, 102, 146, 262, 447 Stamp Act 131–132 Venice 7, 59, 73, 109, 271 Sparta 114, 118, 123, 202, 249, 273, Vox populi 91, 101–102, 293, 434 see 327 also people, the voice of the Subject(s) 59–60, 68, 78, 83, 90, 98, 113, 117, 119, 122–123, 125, 131–133,