Franziska AIGNER

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Franziska AIGNER Kant and technics: From the Critique of Pure Reason to the Opus Postumum Franziska AIGNER June 2020 Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements of the Centre for Research in Modern European Philosophy (CRMEP), Kingston University, for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy. Abstract This dissertation aims to critically intervene in twentieth century European philosophical thought on technics, the discourse concerning skills, tools, instruments, and machines, as well as technology, the scientific meta-discourse on technics, by way of a critical reading and conceptualization of the role and meaning of technics for Immanuel Kant’s transcendental philosophy. Starting from a critical analysis of Martin Heidegger, Gilbert Simondon, and Bernard Stiegler’s thought on technics, I will show how Kant came to stand for a philosophy that could not, and, further did not think technics. Against Heidegger, Simondon and Stiegler, according to whom Kant was incapable of recognizing the technical problematic at the center of his philosophy, I argue that we should read Kant’s philosophy as being constitutively shaped by an ongoing, developing concern for technics. Following a close reading of Kant’s texts from the Critique of Pure Reason (1781) until his very last unfinished manuscript, the Opus Postumum (1796-1803), my project works chronologically through Kant’s explicit references to technics (die Technik), as I aim to synthesize a concept of technics out of the Kantian text and lay out the role and meaning of technics through the various stages of Kant’s thought. I will show that Kant did not only ‘know’ something about technics, but that his transcendental philosophy is essentially of technics, at once explicitly constituted against, while at the same time relying on, being built upon, and proceeding from technics. While the Critique of Pure Reason will be shown to be at heart a critique of instrumental reason, which is to be remedied by a two-fold critical program, both sides of which already harbor a positive concept of technics, it is in the final Opus Postumum that Kant will be seen to articulate the systematic place and vital role of technical-practical reason for the system of transcendental philosophy. The Opus Postumum charges technical-practical reason with the technical- practical task of world-building, and thus the cosmo-technical context for both the universal laws of science and any particular technical-practical action. Consequently, then, while for Heidegger, Simondon, and Stiegler, Kant came to stand for a philosophy that could not think technics, I aim to re-open the larger question concerning the relation between philosophy and technics through the restricted discussion of the relation between Kant and technics, and the concept of technics that I discover in the Kantian text. 2 Acknowledgements I am fortunate to have written this dissertation in the company of many friends and colleagues. Most of all, I would like to thank my first supervisor, Howard J. Caygill, for having first sparked my interest in Kant, for having taught me how to read Kant and Simondon long before becoming my supervisor, and for having become my friend in the process. In our first PhD supervision meeting, Howard put me on the trail of an old, blue and long out-of-print book that one might be able to find in the British Library. Written by the little known Gerhard Lehmann, this book would soon become the key to my project. Little did I know, back then, of Howard’s gift to detect long before myself where it was that I was going, and to provide, so generously, the horizon upon which my philosophical intuitions could develop. I would like to thank Peter Hallward, my second supervisor, for being the critical, perceptive, and sharp reader that he is, and for his continued insistence on rigorous argumentation and clarity. I am greatly indebted to the incisive and critical questions posed to me by Peter Osborne, some of which have forced me into crisis, resulting in necessary decisions long overdue. It has been an intense honor to discuss my project with Étienne Balibar, whose brilliant insights have helped me navigate through difficult passages more than once, and whose teachings will stay with me through all that lies ahead. I would also like to thank Stephen Howard for having read my work on the famously difficult Opus Postumum at various stages throughout the process, and for his generous comments, which have both improved my argument and my confidence. I could not have written this dissertation without all the professors and students at the Center for Research in Modern European Philosophy, which has become my home throughout the last six years of my life. I would like to thank in particular Matt Hare, Isabell Dahms, Marie Louise Krogh, Austin Gross, Francis Cooper, Kylie Gilchrist, and Nathaniel Wooding for their friendship, their philosophical insights, and for having read and discussed my writing with me at various stages. My immense gratitude also goes to Iain Campbell, who has helped me improve my work in the final stage. I completed this dissertation in my mother’s house during the lockdown declared due to the global Corona-virus pandemic. Her love and support have guided me, not only during these last stages of writing. I am also greatly indebted to my sister and brother, to Lawrence, and to my friends at 113, in London, Salzburg, and Berlin. My infinite gratitude goes to Sam, who has supported me in all imaginable ways in thought and love. 3 Last but not least, I would like to thank my grandmother, Gertrude Fischer, whose love and defiance has always been my guide. This dissertation is dedicated to her. I completed this thesis thanks to the generous support of Kingston University (2016- 2019) 4 A critique is not a matter of saying that things are not right as they are. It is a matter of pointing out on what kinds of assumptions, what kinds of familiar, unchallenged, unconsidered modes of thought, the practices that we accept rest.... Criticism is a matter of flushing out that thought and trying to change it: to show that things are not as self-evident as we believed, to see that what is accepted as self-evident will no longer be accepted as such. Practicing criticism is a matter of making facile gestures difficult. - Michel Foucault, Practicing Criticism 5 Table of Contents INTRODUCTION 7 KANT AND/WITHOUT TECHNICS 7 THE PROBLEM AND THE PROMISE 10 OUTLINE 11 CHAPTER 1. TECHNICS, PERIODIZATION, AND THE ECLIPSE OF KANT IN THE TECHNCIAL THOUGHT OF HEIDEGGER, SIMONDON, AND STIEGLER 16 CHAPTER 1.1 HEIDEGGER AND THE QUESTION OF TECHNICS 17 FROM TECHNE TO TECHNICS 18 THE SECOND TERM: THE HUMAN 21 HEIDEGGER AND THE HISTORY OF TECHNICAL THOUGHT 23 FROM METAPHYSICS TO TECHNICS 26 HEIDEGGER AND KANT 28 CHAPTER 2.2. SIMONDON AND THE PROBLEM OF TECHNICS 32 THE PROBLEM OF TECHNICS AND BECOMING IN SIMONDON’S ON THE MODE OF EXISTENCE OF TECHNICAL OBJECTS 34 SIMONDON’S HISTORY OF TECHNICAL THOUGHT 38 SIMONDON AND KANT 39 CHAPTER 1.3. STIEGLER AND THE REPRESSION OF TECHNICS 46 INTRODUCING STIEGLER’S FRAMEWORK OF EXHUMATION 47 STIEGLER’S ACCOUNT OF THE HISTORY OF TECHNICAL THOUGHT 50 PHILOSOPHICAL MODERNITY 52 THE “OLD METAPHYSICAL DOXA” 53 STIEGLER AND KANT 54 CHAPTER 1.4. A FUTURE FOR KANT DESPITE HEIDEGGER, SIMONDON, AND STIEGLER 59 CHAPTER 2. KANT’S CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY AND TECHNICS 62 CHAPTER 2.1 REASON’S DRIVE 64 THE ORGANON OF REASON 65 ELEMENTS, SOURCES, AND BOUNDARIES: THE DOCTRINE OF ELEMENTS AND THE CANON 67 THE CANON AND ITS TECHNICAL CRITIQUES 69 THE CANON, AN A PRIORI MANUFACTURE? 74 A PRIORI OPERATIONS (HANDGRIFFE) 75 CHAPTER 2.2 INSTRUMENTAL EXPANSION AND THE TRANSCENDENTAL DOCTRINE OF METHOD 81 THE EMERGENCE OF THE GERMAN TERMS DIE TECHNIK AND DIE TECHNOLOGIE 82 TECHNICS IN THE TRANSCENDENTAL DOCTRINE OF METHOD 88 INSTRUMENTALITY, TECHNICS, AND THE PROBLEM OF ADDICTION 91 THE DISCIPLINING OF REASON 94 CHAPTER 2.3 THE MANY FACES OF TECHNICS IN THE CRITICAL FRAMEWORK 99 CHAPTER 3. TECHNICS BETWEEN THEORY AND PRACTICE: THE CRITIQUE OF THE POWER OF JUDGMENT 102 CHAPTER 3.1 THE SYSTEM OF PHILOSOPHY AND THE PLACE OF TECHNICS WITHIN IT 104 CHAPTER 3.2 THE CRITIQUE OF THE POWER OF JUDGMENT AND THE PROBLEM OF NATURE’S UNRULY THINGS 109 CHAPTER 3.3 A TECHNICS OF NATURE 114 NATURE 114 TECHNICS 116 A HYPOTHETICAL RESTRICTION 118 CHAPTER 3.4 THREE KINDS OF TECHNICS 121 CHAPTER 3.5 THE RETURN OF THE PROBLEM OF TECHNICS 124 CHAPTER 4. TECHNICS IN THE OPUS POSTUMUM 126 CHAPTER 4.1 KANT’S OPUS POSTUMUM AND GERHARD LEHMANN 128 CHAPTER 4.2 TECHNICAL-PRACTICAL REASON IN THE OPUS POSTUMUM 133 ON THE RELATION BETWEEN FASCICLES VII AND I 140 CHAPTER 4.3 TECHNICAL-PRACTICAL REASON AND THE DOCTRINE OF SELF-POSITING 142 SELF-POSITING IN THE OPUS POSTUMUM 144 THE FIRST ACT OF SELF-POSITING 146 THE TRANSITION BETWEEN THE FIRST AND THE SECOND ACT OF SELF-POSITING 147 IDEAS, IDEALS, ORIGINAL IMAGES 149 GOD, THE WORLD, AND THE HUMAN 153 WORLD AND KNOWLEDGE OF THE WORLD 155 PHILOSOPHY IN THE WORLD CONCEPT 158 GOD, THE WORLD, AND THE HUMAN IN THE OPUS POSTUMUM, THE SYSTEM OF TRANSCENDENTAL PHILOSOPHY 159 REASON, SELF-POSITING AND TRANSCENDENTAL REFLECTION 163 TECHNICAL-PRACTICAL AND MORAL PRACTICAL-REASON 165 CHAPTER 4.5 TECHNICAL-PRACTICAL SELF-POSITING 169 THE PROBLEM OF CONSTRUCTION 173 SELF-AFFECTION AND APPEARANCES OF APPEARANCES 176 CHAPTER 4.5 CONCLUSION 180 CONCLUSION 182 BIBLIOGRAPHY 188 6 INTRODUCTION Kant and/without technics In 1936, the German Akademie der Wissenschaften published the first part of the Opus Postumum (Nachlasswerk), containing the hitherto unpublished manuscript on which Immanuel Kant had worked over the last decade of his life.
Recommended publications
  • The Return of Vitalism: Canguilhem and French Biophilosophy in the 1960S
    The Return of Vitalism: Canguilhem and French Biophilosophy in the 1960s Charles T. Wolfe Unit for History and Philosophy of Science University of Sydney [email protected] Abstract The eminent French biologist and historian of biology, François Jacob, once notoriously declared ―On n‘interroge plus la vie dans les laboratoires‖1: laboratory research no longer inquires into the notion of ‗Life‘. Nowadays, as David Hull puts it, ―both scientists and philosophers take ontological reduction for granted… Organisms are ‗nothing but‘ atoms, and that is that.‖2 In the mid-twentieth century, from the immediate post-war period to the late 1960s, French philosophers of science such as Georges Canguilhem, Raymond Ruyer and Gilbert Simondon returned to Jacob‘s statement with an odd kind of pathos: they were determined to reverse course. Not by imposing a different kind of research program in laboratories, but by an unusual combination of historical and philosophical inquiry into the foundations of the life sciences (particularly medicine, physiology and the cluster of activities that were termed ‗biology‘ in the early 1800s). Even in as straightforwardly scholarly a work as La formation du concept de réflexe aux XVIIe et XVIIIe siècles (1955), Canguilhem speaks oddly of ―defending vitalist biology,‖ and declares that Life cannot be grasped by logic (or at least, ―la vie déconcerte la logique‖). Was all this historical and philosophical work merely a reassertion of ‗mysterian‘, magical vitalism? In order to answer this question we need to achieve some perspective on Canguilhem‘s ‗vitalism‘, notably with respect to its philosophical influences such as Kurt Goldstein.
    [Show full text]
  • Panel Proposal: the Necessity of Critique II Organizer: Darryl Cressman, Maastricht University
    Panel Proposal: The Necessity of Critique II Organizer: Darryl Cressman, Maastricht University Functionalization and the World – Causality, Culture, and Planetary Technology Jochem Zweer University of Twente My contribution focusses on Feenberg’s recent rearticulation of his widely discussed instrumentalization theory, in which the pairing of primary and secondary instrumentalization is addressed in terms of causal and cultural functionalization. First, I show how this conceptualization of functionalization aligns with existing approaches in contemporary philosophy of technology and STS inasmuch as it departs from technological artefacts, but contrasts with such approaches inasmuch as it attends to how such artefacts reveal a world, which is to say a political world of formal biases, operational autonomy, and democratic potential. Secondly, in following Feenberg’s explicit association of philosophy of technology and environmental thought, I inquire after his understanding of the technological world as an outcome of social conditions. Via a phenomenological interpretation of the Anthropocene and associated planetary functionalization, I argue that Feenberg’s treatment of causal functionalization tends to reduce to cultural functionalization. While the resulting critical constructivist account of is both urgent and worthwhile in light of today’s ecological emergency, I suggest that it does not exhaust the implications of the advent of the Anthropocene. I therefore conclude by discussing causal functionalization in light of the analysis of causality that Heidegger develops in the Question concerning Technology, thereby drawing attention to the ontological conditioning of functionalization. I suggest that attending to such ontological conditioning must have a place in the critical constructivist project of uncovering the biases of contemporary functional rationality.
    [Show full text]
  • Print This Article
    Gilbert Simondon and the Philosophy of Information An Interview with Jean-Hugues Barthélémy Jean-Hugues Barthélémy Andrew Iliadis Journal of French and Francophone Philosophy - Revue de la philosophie française et de langue française, Vol XXIII, No 1 (2015) pp 102-112. Vol XXIII, No 1 (2015) ISSN 1936-6280 (print) ISSN 2155-1162 (online) DOI 10.5195/jffp.2015.679 www.jffp.org This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 United States License. This journal is operated by the University Library System of the University of Pittsburgh as part of its D-Scribe Digital Publishing Program, and is co-sponsored by the UniversityJournal of Pittsburgh of French and Press Francophone Philosophy | Revue de la philosophie française et de langue française Vol XXIII, No 1 (2015) | www.jffp.org | DOI 10.5195/jffp.2015.679 Gilbert Simondon and the Philosophy of Information An Interview with Jean-Hugues Barthélémy Jean-Hugues Barthélémy Centre international des études simondoniennes Andrew Iliadis Purdue University Jean-Hugues Barthélémy is a French philosopher and a leading authority on the philosophy of Gilbert Simondon (1924-1989). Barthélémy is Director of the Centre international des études simondoniennes (CIDES – MSH Paris-Nord), Professor of philosophy, Doctor in epistemology of the University Paris VII – Denis Diderot, Editor and Director of Cahiers Simondon, and Research Associate at the University Paris Ouest – Nanterre La Défense. He is the author of Penser l’individuation. Simondon et la philosophie de la nature (Paris: L’Harmattan, 2005), Penser la connaissance et la technique après Simondon (Paris: L’Harmattan, 2005), Simondon ou l’encyclopédisme génétique (Paris: P.U.F., 2008), and Simondon (Paris: Les Belles Lettres, 2014 – translation forthcoming: Bloomsbury, 2016).
    [Show full text]
  • On Cosmotechnics: for a Renewed Relation Between Technology And
    Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology ISSN: 1091-8264 21:2–3 (2017): 1–23 DOI: 10.5840/techne201711876 On Cosmotechnics: For a Renewed Relaton between Technology and Nature in the Anthropocene Yuk Hui Abstract: This article aims to bring forward a critical refection on a renewed relation between nature and technology in the Anthropocene, by contextualizing the question around the recent debates on the “ontological turn” in Anthropology, which attempts to go beyond the nature and culture dualism analysed as the crisis of modernity. The “politics of ontologies” associated with this movement in anthropology opens up the question of participation of non-humans. This article contrasts this anthropological attempt with the work of the philosopher Gilbert Simondon, who wants to overcome the antagonism between culture and technics. According to Simondon, this antago- nism results from the technological rupture of modernity at the end of the eighteenth century. This paper analyses the differences of the oppositions presenting their work: culture vs. nature, culture vs. technics, to show that a dialogue between anthropology of nature (illustrated through the work of Philippe Descola) and philosophy of tech- nology (illustrated through the work of Simondon) will be fruitful to conceptualize a renewed relation between nature and technology. One way to initiate such a conversa- tion as well as to think about the reconciliation between nature and technology, this article tries to show, is to develop the concept of cosmotechnics as the denominator of these two trends of thinking. Key words: ontological turn, Gilbert Simondon, Philippe Descola, cosmotechnics, modernity Introducton It is scarcely deniable that the Anthropocene, beyond its obvious signifcation as a new geological era, also represents a crisis that is the culmination of two- Yuk Hui, Institut für Kultur und Ästhetik Digitaler Medien, Leuphana University, Scharnhorststraße 1, 21335, Lüneburg, Germany; [email protected].
    [Show full text]
  • Simondon: Investigating the Pre-Organizational
    Fichier auteur. Une version ultérieure est parue : Letiche Hugo & Moriceau Jean-Luc, 2017, "Simondon. Investigating the pre-organizational", Culture and Organization, Vol. 23, n°1, pp.1-13; Doi: 10.1080/14759551.2016.1240358. Simondon: Investigating the Pre-Organizational 1 2 Hugo Letiche & Jean-Luc Moriceau 1 The University of Leicester School of Business, Leicester UK; 2 Institut Mines-Télécom / Télécom Ecole de Management, France. Gilbert Simondon (1924-1989) was a radical process thinker; forms of relatedness and not objects were his focus. This is all the more remarkable as he was not a vitalist prioritizing Gaia or autopoesis. He based his thought on analyses of technology / technics and communication / cybernetics, and in both cases rejected the perspective of the machine or message as in-itself objectifiable. Life objects, machines and societies, according to Simondon, individuate; that is, they are self-evolving, self-generating, and self-differentiating in what he calls processes of ‘transduction’. Simondon, in fact, is more a thinker of transindividuation than of individuation. His is a theory of how the pre-individual leads to the transindividual, without the individual ever really playing much of a role. The motor of change and activity is 'transduction' – or a force of form taking that operates on the pre- individual level. Transduction is, thus, the life-force of Simondon’s becoming. It is the energy that propels action, change, event and occurrence. No one in particular is the subject of transduction; transduction is the pre-individual manifestation of an all-encompassing process of genesis. Simondon attends to the genesis of the person, society, information, collective, technology, organization, whatever.
    [Show full text]
  • Literary Theory and Critical Thought, Lectures MT17 on The
    Literary Theory and Critical Thought, Lectures MT17 On the following pages you find a presentation of the lecture-series on ‘Literary Theory and Critical Thought’. You also find a number of bibliographical references. Please note that these references are not the prescribed readings for ‘Paper 12: Literary Theory’ or for the graduate module ‘Key Questions in Critical Thought’. These two courses each have their own bibliographies. What is listed below is material we will be engaging with in the lectures. Texts (Weeks 1 and 2, Ian Maclachlan) The idea that in studying literature we’re involved with texts may seem like just about the most unilluminating ‘no-brainer’ imaginable. But in the latter part of the 20th century the resonances of a lexicon of textuality, writing and difference were bound up with a radical reconception of the literary work, its meaning, and its cultural role and value. This reconception may be summarised in terms of the movement from structuralism to post-structuralism and beyond, and these two lectures will offer an account of those intellectual developments, focusing on such figures as Roland Barthes, Julia Kristeva, Jacques Derrida and Jacques Rancière, and discussing notions of semiology, intertextuality, deconstruction, and différance. They will also explore the idea that Derrida’s famous proclamation ‘Il n’y a pas de hors-texte [There is no outside-text]’ in no way implies a schism between text and world, but rather heralds their ceaseless interweaving and, therefore, an essentially political dimension of the literary text, as we see, for example, in the later work of Barthes and in Rancière’s thinking of the politics of literature.
    [Show full text]
  • Leadership in State Genesis: Creative Vicediction, Guardianship, and the Crystallization of Sovereign Authority
    Leadership in State Genesis: Creative Vicediction, Guardianship, and the Crystallization of Sovereign Authority DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Tahseen Kazi Graduate Program in Comparative Studies The Ohio State University 2014 Dissertation Committee: Eugene Holland, Advisor Sonja Amadae Philip Armstrong Mathew Coleman Luis Lobo-Guerrero Copyrighted by Tahseen Kazi 2014 Abstract The complicity of leadership in the genesis of sovereign authority is neglected in contemporary political thought to the detriment of our understanding of both of these concepts. Dissatisfied with contemporary reliance on notions such as sovereign decision which ultimately imply primal repression as the sole source of all authority, my research takes the genesis of sovereignty as a problem to be solved rather than as an unalterable, natural occurrence to be presumed. Drawing on such diverse resources as Foucault’s concept of parrhesia, Weber’s concept of charisma, anthropological and mythological accounts of authority, Simondon’s theory of the genesis of the individual as crystallization, and primarily on Deleuzian philosophy, I offer an account of the genesis of the sovereign state as the result of the conjugation of two modes of leadership: leadership by guardianship and leadership by creative vicediction. Whereas leadership by guardianship in the Platonic tradition makes claim to judgment on the authority of customary founding myths, thereby severely limiting leadership’s transformative potential, leadership by creative vicediction, a ii concept I develop, trespasses on such myths to critically engage with their representation of the present circumstance, and presubjectively and affectively guides others toward another way of being.
    [Show full text]
  • Animate Biology: Data, Visualization, and Life's Moving Image Adam J. Nocek a Dissertation Submitted in Partial Fulfillment Of
    Animate Biology: Data, Visualization, and Life’s Moving Image Adam J. Nocek A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Washington 2015 Reading Committee: Phillip Thurtle, Chair James Tweedie Robert Mitchell Program Authorized to Offer Degree: Comparative Literature ©Copyright 2015 Adam J. Nocek University of Washington Abstract Animate Biology: Data, Visualization, and Life’s Moving Image Adam J. Nocek Chair of the Supervisory Committee: Associate Professor Phillip Thurtle Animate Biology: Data, Visualization, and Life’s Moving Image examines how biologists are using 3D animation technologies developed by the entertainment industry (Pixar and DreamWorks) to visualize biological data sets. Over the course of four chapters, the project develops a concept of scientific aesthetics in order to counter the neoliberalization of these visualization practices. The first chapter, “Molecular Control,” shows how there is significant controversy among scientists regarding the scientific value of molecular animations, since it is unclear whether they faithfully depict biological data. Drawing on Lorraine Daston and Peter Galison’s scholarship on the history of scientific visualization, the dissertation intervenes in this debate by clarifying what the criteria are for determining the scientific value of images. The study demonstrates that representation, instead of objectivity, is the epistemic norm that determines the scientific value of images, and that the norm of representation is fully operative in 3D molecular animations. I argue that what is often missed in debates over scientific imaging is that representation has undergone many transformations in the history of scientific epistemology, and that it now obeys the logic of flexibility and competition that exemplifies neoliberal market values.
    [Show full text]
  • Simondon Information
    CHAPTER 2 SIMONDON INFORMATION Perhaps the next step to take would be to reject either an information constructivism (where information is a product of external forces that renders information an effect of these relations) as well as information realism (where information is presented as an objective truth about nature and thus positioned as its cause). In either of these formulations we are given a strict binary choice between declaring information as a prescriptive foundation or an end product of forces and relations. In more dangerous contexts, information constructivism can lead to an ideologization of information, and information realism may simply be a fog in which one can hide ideology. Information constructivism may never narrow the gulf between what information signifies and its analog in reality since, very much the issue in social constructivism, what the information refers to is locked in a mediation process that is a sign referring to––not reality––other signs in a simulacral network. Such dangers aside, curiously very little attention has been paid to the idea that transduction may function as an alternative to models of deduction and induction that currently dominate either generalized or unified theories of information. This chapter is an attempt to explore and expand upon Gilbert Simondon’s use of the word information in his philosophy with a view to emphasizing its importance in an operant ontology. As a model, Simondon information (hereafter SI) would reject either the formulation of information based on hylomorphic or substantialist accounts that assume a primacy of individuation prior to the operant process by which individuation manifests itself.
    [Show full text]
  • BRIAN MASSUMI on GILBERT SIMONDON with Arne De Boever, Alex Murray and Jon Roffe
    PARRHESIA NUMBER 7 • 2009 • 36–45 “TECHNICAL MENTALITY” REVISITED: BRIAN MASSUMI ON GILBERT SIMONDON With Arne De Boever, Alex Murray and Jon Roffe Parrhesia Several years ago, you already tried to get Simondon translated--and to no avail. We thought we could start with the question: why Simondon today? One can see why it would be important, historically, that Simondon is finally translated into English. But is there any reason why his thought strikes you as particularly relevant--philosophically, politically, culturally-- today? Brian Massumi I did make strenuous efforts over a number of years, starting almost twenty years ago, to have Simondon translated for a book series I was co-editing. The director of the press flatly refused to consider it, saying there was no interest in Simondon and no audience for the work. At the time, he was probably right. Now the translations are under way, and are impatiently awaited in many quarters, with a sense that they are long overdue. So what changed? Why today? It might help to start by talking about, why not then? The early 1990s was a very particular moment in English- speaking academics and cultural thought. The intellectual movements of the preceding three decades had succeeded in chipping significant cracks into the walls separating the academic disciplines, which had undergone a process of increasing specialization in the post-War period that many experienced as a Balkanization of knowledge. It wasn’t just a question of the much-discussed “two cultures” divide between science on the one hand and the humanities and social sciences on other.
    [Show full text]
  • The Data Sensorium Davide Panagia
    The Data Sensorium Davide Panagia Cultural Critique, Volume 101, Fall 2018, pp. 234-248 (Review) Published by University of Minnesota Press For additional information about this article https://muse.jhu.edu/article/712983 Access provided by UCLA Library (5 Mar 2019 17:31 GMT) THE DATA SENSORIUM BEAUTIFUL Data: A HISTORY OF VISION AND REASON SINCE 1945 BY ORIT HALPERN Duke University Press, 2015 Davide Panagia Orit Halpern’s Beautiful Data is a major contribution in contempo- rary media studies, aesthetics, political theory, and history— not to mention science and technology studies and visual culture. It aims to account for the emergence of a set of ambitions that has changed our world. “Beautiful data” isn’t simply the title of the book but also the book’s central contention; that is, it refers to the moment (now ubiq- uitous) when something called data stopped being an object in the world and became a world all on its own with powers of calculation, measurement, and (most important for this reader) administration. Data is beautiful not just because it appeals to a coder’s sense of beauty (though that’s part of it) but because it makes a claim on our indi- vidual and collective sensorium; it makes appeals on our ways of ori- enting ourselves to what is and what isn’t experiential, as the Greek origin of the term “aesthetic” (meaning sensory perception) implies. The moment when data became a world instead of an object is the moment when a radical shift occurred in our sensorial dispositions, affective attachments, sensibilities, behaviors, and attitudes.
    [Show full text]
  • Simondon's Technical Culture and a Politics of Problems
    Simondon’s Technical Culture and a Politics of Problems Stefano Daechsel Abstract: There is a timeliness to Gilbert Simondon’s call in On the Mode of Existence of Technical Objects (1958) for a technical culture that fosters a ”genuine awareness of technical realities.” Writing in the context of mid-20th century France, Simondon worried about a lack of technological understanding and envisaged a technical culture in which technological education would be considered as essential as literacy to meaningful participation in society. Sixty years on, the need for widespread technological awareness is greater than ever. The aim of this article is to clarify and support this claim by examining it through the lens of a politics of problems that can be found in Deleuze’s Difference and Repetition (1968). Keywords: Simondon, Deleuze, technical culture, problems 5 Sensorium Journal, 2021:3 © The Authors This work is licensed under a CC BY 4.0 licence From artificial intelligence to climate change, the big challenges of the 21st century will revolve around the evolution and distribution of technology. The problems we face locally, nationally and globally are increasingly defined by technical conditions that feel so complex and opaque to the average person that it can induce a sense of impotence or apathy. It is against this backdrop that the thought of the 20th century philosopher Gilbert Simondon is belatedly garnering interest within and outside of his native France. There are many reasons for this delayed interest in Simondon, not least his influence on better known French philosophers, such as Gilles Deleuze and Bernard Stiegler, but one of his most important and timely contributions is his call in On the Mode of Existence of Technical Objects* for a technical culture in which technical education would be considered as essential as literacy to meaningful participation in society.
    [Show full text]