Resolution in Max-SAT and Its Relation to Local Consistency in Weighted Csps

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Resolution in Max-SAT and Its Relation to Local Consistency in Weighted Csps Resolution in Max-SAT and its relation to local consistency in weighted CSPs Javier Larrosa, Federico Heras {larrosa, fheras}@lsi.upc.edu Dept. LSI, Universitat Politecnica de Catalunya Barcelona, Spain Abstract that best respects the clauses/constraints. Two well-known examples are Max-SAT [Hansen and Jaumard, 1990] and Max-SAT is an optimization version of the well- weighted CSP (WCSP) [Bistarelli et al., 1999], where most known SAT problem. It is of great importance from of recent algorithmic work has focused. In both cases the both a theoretical and a practical point of view. In importance of the clauses/constraints is given by a weight recent years, there has been considerable interest and the goal is to minimize the sum of weights associated in finding efficient solving techniques [Alsinet et with the clauses/constraints violated by the assignment. It is al., 2003; Xing and Zhang, 2004; Shen and Zhang, known that Max-SAT instances can be translated into WCSP 2004; de Givry et al., 2003]. Most of this work instances and vice versa [de Givry et al., 2003]. In both cases focus on the computation of good quality lower the main solving technique are enumeration algorithms based bounds to be used within a branch and bound algo- on branch and bound search. rithm. Unfortunately, lower bounds are described In the CSP side, several local consistency properties have in a procedural way. Because of that, it is difficult been recently generalized to the WCSP framework [Cooper, to realize the logic that is behind. 2003; Larrosa and Schiex, 2004; 2003; de Givry et al., 2005]. In this paper we introduce a logical framework for As a result, a new family of algorithms have been proposed. Max-SAT solving. Using this framework, we in- Besides being efficient, these algorithms have a highly desir- troduce an extension of the Davis-Putnam algo- able property: they can be neatly described as a basic back- rithm (that we call Max-DPLL) and the resolution tracking search in which certain local consistency property is rule. Our framework has the advantage of nicely enforced at every search state. integrating branch and bound concepts such as the In [de Givry et al., 2003], it was shown that Max-SAT in- lower and upper bound, as well as hiding away stances could be efficiently solved by translating them into implementation details. We show that Max-DPLL equivalent WCSP instances and later using a WCSP solver. augmented with a restricted form of resolution at The level of local consistency maintained by the WCSP each branching point is an effective solving strat- solver was fundamental in the efficiency of the algorithm. egy. We also show that the resulting algorithm is In this paper we analyze the interpretation of WCSP lo- closely related with some local consistency proper- cal consistency properties and related algorithms when ap- ties developed for weighted constraint satisfaction plied to Max-SAT instances. To facilitate the connection, we problems. start by providing a reformulation of Max-SAT in which it is possible to explicitly express a lower and an upper bound of the optimal cost (Section 3). Such reformulation makes 1 Introduction possible an elegant extension of DPLL in which each branch- Since the eighties, both boolean satisfiability and constraint ing point is just a Max-SAT instance, similarly to what hap- satisfaction have been the topic of intense algorithmic re- pens with DPLL in SAT (Section 4). In Section 5 we present search. In both areas, the goal is to assign values to variables our main contribution: a generalization of the resolution rule in such a way that no forbidden combination of values appear (x ∨ A,x¯ ∨ B ⇒ A ∨ B) and the proof that neighborhood reso- in the solution. In satisfiability, forbidden combinations are lution (i.e., a restricted form of resolution) suffices to enforce specified by means of clauses. In constraint satisfaction they (weighted) node and arc consistency. In Section 6 we put our are specified by means of arbitrary constraints. Given its sim- approach in context with other Max-SAT algorithms. Finally, ilarity, it is hardly a surprise that both research communities in Section 7 we provide conclusions and directions of future have developed closely related techniques. work. In both fields, the original decision problem (SAT and CSP, respectively) has been augmented to deal with unfea- 2 Preliminaries sible problems (namely, not all the clauses or constraints In the sequel X = {x1,...,xn} will denote a set of boolean can be satisfied). The new goal is to find an assignment variables. They take values over the set {t,f}, which stands for true and false, respectively. A literal l is either a variable Example 1 Consider the formula {(x,1),(y¯,5),(x¯ ∨ x or its negationx ¯. l¯ stands for the negation of l. y,2),(x ∨ y,4)}, with > = 5. The second clause is hard. The If variable x is instantiated to t, noted x ← t literal x is sat- assignment x = f,y = f is not a model because its cost is isfied and literalx ¯ is falsified. Similarly, if x is instantiated to 1 ⊕ 4 = >. The assignment x ← t,y ← f is a (optimal) model f,x ¯ is satisfied and x is falsified. An assignment is an instanti- with cost 2. ation of a subset of the variables. The assignment is complete Note that in Max-SAT truth tables are tables with a cost if it instantiates all the variables in X (otherwise it is partial). associated to each truth assignments. A brute-force solving An assignment satisfies a clause (i.e., a disjunction of liter- method consists in computing the truth table of the input for- als) C iff it satisfies one or more of its literals. It satisfies a set mula and finding the minimal cost model. For instance, the of clauses F iff it satisfies all its clauses. A satisfying com- truth-table of the previous formula is, plete assignment is called a model. Given a boolean formula encoded by a set of clauses F , the SAT problem consists in x y cost determining whether there is any model for it or not. f f 1 ⊕ 4 = > We will use the symbol 2 to denote the empty clause f t 1 ⊕ > = > which, obviously, cannot be satisfied. When 2 ∈ F we say t f 2 that there is an explicit contradiction. t t > When there is no model for the formula , one may be F It is worth mentioning the role of the empty clause (2,w). interested in finding the complete assignment with minimum Since it cannot be satisfied, w will be added to the cost of any number of violated clauses. This problem is known as Max- model. Therefore, w is an explicit lower bound of the optimal SAT. model. When the lower bound and the upper bound have the same value (i.e., (2,>) ∈ F ) the formula does not have any 3 An equivalent reformulation of Max-SAT model and we call this situation an explicit contradiction. There is a weighted version of Max-SAT in which (weighted) clauses are pairs (C,w) such that C is a classical clause and w is the cost of its falsification. In weighted Max-SAT F is a set 4 Generalization of DPLL to Max-SAT of weighted clauses. The cost of an assignment is the sum of 4.1 Max-SAT Basic Simplification Rules weights of all the clauses that it falsifies. The goal is to find complete assignments with minimal cost. We make the usual SAT solvers take advantage from some equivalence rules that assumption of weights being natural numbers. are used to simplify the CNF formula without changing its set It is easy to see that Max-SAT and weighted Max-SAT of models. Not all of these formulas can be applied directly to have exactly the same expressive power. A Max-SAT in- Max-SAT. In this Section we state some useful Max-SAT spe- stance can be rewritten as a weighted instance replacing ev- cific rules. We use the notation [P,...,Q] ⇒ [R,...,S], where ery clause C by a weighted clause (C,1). A weighted Max- P,Q,... are weighted clauses. It means that if there are in SAT instance can be rewritten as a Max-SAT instance replac- F weighted clauses matching with [P,...,Q], they can be re- ing every weighted clause (C,w) by w copies of clause C. placed by [R,...,S]. A and B are arbitrary disjunctions of Clearly, weighted Max-SAT encodings may be exponentially literals. more compact than Max-SAT. Thus, in the following, we will assume, without loss of generality, weighted Max-SAT. • BR1: [(A,>),(A ∨ B,w)] ⇒ [(A,>)] Following previous work in weighted constraint satisfac- • BR2: [(A,w),(A,u)] ⇒ [(A,w ⊕ u)] tion [Larrosa and Schiex, 2004], we assume the existence of a known upper bound k of the optimal solution. This is also • BR3: If (w ⊕ u = >) then [(A,w),(A ∨ B,u)] ⇒ done without loss of generality because, if a tight upper bound [(A,w),(A ∨ B,>)] is not known, k can be set to the sum of weights of all the • BR4: [(A,0)] ⇒ [] clauses. Consider the set F of weighed clauses. We say that a BR1 shows that classical absorption can only be applied model is a complete assignment with cost less than k. Max- when the absorbing clause is hard. BR2 generalizes the SAT is the problem of finding a model of minimal cost, if standard idempotency of the conjunction: In Max-SAT the there is any. weights of the repeated clauses must be added in the result- Observe that weights w ≥ k indicate that the associated ing clause.
Recommended publications
  • Automated Theorem Proving Introduction
    Automated Theorem Proving Scott Sanner, Guest Lecture Topics in Automated Reasoning Thursday, Jan. 19, 2006 Introduction • Def. Automated Theorem Proving: Proof of mathematical theorems by a computer program. • Depending on underlying logic, task varies from trivial to impossible: – Simple description logic: Poly-time – Propositional logic: NP-Complete (3-SAT) – First-order logic w/ arithmetic: Impossible 1 Applications • Proofs of Mathematical Conjectures – Graph theory: Four color theorem – Boolean algebra: Robbins conjecture • Hardware and Software Verification – Verification: Arithmetic circuits – Program correctness: Invariants, safety • Query Answering – Build domain-specific knowledge bases, use theorem proving to answer queries Basic Task Structure • Given: – Set of axioms (KB encoded as axioms) – Conjecture (assumptions + consequence) • Inference: – Search through space of valid inferences • Output: – Proof (if found, a sequence of steps deriving conjecture consequence from axioms and assumptions) 2 Many Logics / Many Theorem Proving Techniques Focus on theorem proving for logics with a model-theoretic semantics (TBD) • Logics: – Propositional, and first-order logic – Modal, temporal, and description logic • Theorem Proving Techniques: – Resolution, tableaux, sequent, inverse – Best technique depends on logic and app. Example of Propositional Logic Sequent Proof • Given: • Direct Proof: – Axioms: (I) A |- A None (¬R) – Conjecture: |- ¬A, A ∨ A ∨ ¬A ? ( R2) A A ? |- A∨¬A, A (PR) • Inference: |- A, A∨¬A (∨R1) – Gentzen |- A∨¬A, A∨¬A Sequent (CR) ∨ Calculus |- A ¬A 3 Example of First-order Logic Resolution Proof • Given: • CNF: ¬Man(x) ∨ Mortal(x) – Axioms: Man(Socrates) ∀ ⇒ Man(Socrates) x Man(x) Mortal(x) ¬Mortal(y) [Neg. conj.] Man(Socrates) – Conjecture: • Proof: ∃y Mortal(y) ? 1. ¬Mortal(y) [Neg. conj.] 2. ¬Man(x) ∨ Mortal(x) [Given] • Inference: 3.
    [Show full text]
  • Logic and Proof Computer Science Tripos Part IB
    Logic and Proof Computer Science Tripos Part IB Lawrence C Paulson Computer Laboratory University of Cambridge [email protected] Copyright c 2015 by Lawrence C. Paulson Contents 1 Introduction and Learning Guide 1 2 Propositional Logic 2 3 Proof Systems for Propositional Logic 5 4 First-order Logic 8 5 Formal Reasoning in First-Order Logic 11 6 Clause Methods for Propositional Logic 13 7 Skolem Functions, Herbrand’s Theorem and Unification 17 8 First-Order Resolution and Prolog 21 9 Decision Procedures and SMT Solvers 24 10 Binary Decision Diagrams 27 11 Modal Logics 28 12 Tableaux-Based Methods 30 i 1 INTRODUCTION AND LEARNING GUIDE 1 1 Introduction and Learning Guide 2008 Paper 3 Q6: BDDs, DPLL, sequent calculus • 2008 Paper 4 Q5: proving or disproving first-order formulas, This course gives a brief introduction to logic, including • resolution the resolution method of theorem-proving and its relation 2009 Paper 6 Q7: modal logic (Lect. 11) to the programming language Prolog. Formal logic is used • for specifying and verifying computer systems and (some- 2009 Paper 6 Q8: resolution, tableau calculi • times) for representing knowledge in Artificial Intelligence 2007 Paper 5 Q9: propositional methods, resolution, modal programs. • logic The course should help you to understand the Prolog 2007 Paper 6 Q9: proving or disproving first-order formulas language, and its treatment of logic should be helpful for • 2006 Paper 5 Q9: proof and disproof in FOL and modal logic understanding other theoretical courses. It also describes • 2006 Paper 6 Q9: BDDs, Herbrand models, resolution a variety of techniques and data structures used in auto- • mated theorem provers.
    [Show full text]
  • Solving the Boolean Satisfiability Problem Using the Parallel Paradigm Jury Composition
    Philosophæ doctor thesis Hoessen Benoît Solving the Boolean Satisfiability problem using the parallel paradigm Jury composition: PhD director Audemard Gilles Professor at Universit´ed'Artois PhD co-director Jabbour Sa¨ıd Assistant Professor at Universit´ed'Artois PhD co-director Piette C´edric Assistant Professor at Universit´ed'Artois Examiner Simon Laurent Professor at University of Bordeaux Examiner Dequen Gilles Professor at University of Picardie Jules Vernes Katsirelos George Charg´ede recherche at Institut national de la recherche agronomique, Toulouse Abstract This thesis presents different technique to solve the Boolean satisfiability problem using parallel and distributed architec- tures. In order to provide a complete explanation, a careful presentation of the CDCL algorithm is made, followed by the state of the art in this domain. Once presented, two proposi- tions are made. The first one is an improvement on a portfo- lio algorithm, allowing to exchange more data without loosing efficiency. The second is a complete library with its API al- lowing to easily create distributed SAT solver. Keywords: SAT, parallelism, distributed, solver, logic R´esum´e Cette th`ese pr´esente diff´erentes techniques permettant de r´esoudre le probl`eme de satisfaction de formule bool´eenes utilisant le parall´elismeet du calcul distribu´e. Dans le but de fournir une explication la plus compl`ete possible, une pr´esentation d´etaill´ee de l'algorithme CDCL est effectu´ee, suivi d'un ´etatde l'art. De ce point de d´epart,deux pistes sont explor´ees. La premi`ereest une am´eliorationd'un algorithme de type portfolio, permettant d'´echanger plus d'informations sans perte d’efficacit´e.
    [Show full text]
  • Exploring Semantic Hierarchies to Improve Resolution Theorem Proving on Ontologies
    The University of Maine DigitalCommons@UMaine Honors College Spring 2019 Exploring Semantic Hierarchies to Improve Resolution Theorem Proving on Ontologies Stanley Small University of Maine Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.library.umaine.edu/honors Part of the Computer Sciences Commons Recommended Citation Small, Stanley, "Exploring Semantic Hierarchies to Improve Resolution Theorem Proving on Ontologies" (2019). Honors College. 538. https://digitalcommons.library.umaine.edu/honors/538 This Honors Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by DigitalCommons@UMaine. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors College by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@UMaine. For more information, please contact [email protected]. EXPLORING SEMANTIC HIERARCHIES TO IMPROVE RESOLUTION THEOREM PROVING ON ONTOLOGIES by Stanley C. Small A Thesis Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for a Degree with Honors (Computer Science) The Honors College University of Maine May 2019 Advisory Committee: Dr. Torsten Hahmann, Assistant Professor1, Advisor Dr. Mark Brewer, Professor of Political Science Dr. Max Egenhofer, Professor1 Dr. Sepideh Ghanavati, Assistant Professor1 Dr. Roy Turner, Associate Professor1 1School of Computing and Information Science ABSTRACT A resolution-theorem-prover (RTP) evaluates the validity (truthfulness) of conjectures against a set of axioms in a knowledge base. When given a conjecture, an RTP attempts to resolve the negated conjecture with axioms from the knowledge base until the prover finds a contradiction. If the RTP finds a contradiction between the axioms and a negated conjecture, the conjecture is proven. The order in which the axioms within the knowledge-base are evaluated significantly impacts the runtime of the program, as the search-space increases exponentially with the number of axioms.
    [Show full text]
  • Deduction and Resolution
    Lecture 12: Deduction and Resolution 1 Hilbert’s System Hilbert discovered a very elegant deductive system that is both sound and com- plete. His system uses only the connectives {¬, →}, which we know are an adequate basis. It has also been shown that each of the three axioms given below are necessary for the system to be sound and complete. Hilbert’s System consists of the following: • Three axioms (all are strongly sound): – A1: (p → (q → p)) Axiom of simplification. – A2: ((p → (q → r)) → ((p → q) → (p → r))) Frege’s axiom. – A3: ((¬p → q) → ((¬p → ¬q) → p)) Reductio ad absurdum. • Inference Rules: p,p→q – Modus Ponens: q (Strongly Sound) ϕ – Substitution: ϕ[θ] , where θ is a substitution (p → ψ). (Sound) The Substitution Inference Rule is shorthand for all sequences of the form hϕ, ϕ[θ]i. It is sometimes called a schema for generating inference rules. Note that in general, it is not the case that ϕ |= ϕ[θ], for example p 6|= q. However, in assignment 2, we showed that if |= ϕ, then |= ϕ[θ]. This is why this rule is sound but not strongly sound. Theorem 1. Hilbert’s system is sound, complete, and tractable. Proof. We prove each property separately. • Soundness: Since all axioms are strongly sound, and the two inference rules are sound, the whole system is sound. • Completeness: The proof of this property is fairly involved and thus it is outside the scope of the class. 1 + • Tractability: Given Γ ∈ Form and ϕ1, . , ϕn, is ϕ1, . , ϕn ∈ Deductions(Γ)? Clearly, < ϕ1 > is in Γ only if it is an axiom.
    [Show full text]
  • Inference (Proof) Procedures for FOL (Chapter 9)
    Inference (Proof) Procedures for FOL (Chapter 9) Torsten Hahmann, CSC384, University of Toronto, Fall 2011 85 Proof Procedures • Interestingly, proof procedures work by simply manipulating formulas. They do not know or care anything about interpretations. • Nevertheless they respect the semantics of interpretations! • We will develop a proof procedure for first-order logic called resolution . • Resolution is the mechanism used by PROLOG • Also used by automated theorem provers such as Prover9 (together with other techniques) Torsten Hahmann, CSC384, University of Toronto, Fall 2011 86 Properties of Proof Procedures • Before presenting the details of resolution, we want to look at properties we would like to have in a (any) proof procedure. • We write KB ⊢ f to indicate that f can be proved from KB (the proof procedure used is implicit). Torsten Hahmann, CSC384, University of Toronto, Fall 2011 87 Properties of Proof Procedures • Soundness • KB ⊢ f → KB ⊨ f i.e all conclusions arrived at via the proof procedure are correct: they are logical consequences. • Completeness • KB ⊨ f → KB ⊢ f i.e. every logical consequence can be generated by the proof procedure. • Note proof procedures are computable, but they might have very high complexity in the worst case. So completeness is not necessarily achievable in practice. Torsten Hahmann, CSC384, University of Toronto, Fall 2011 88 Forward Chaining • First-order inference mechanism (or proof procedure) that generalizes Modus Ponens: • From C1 ∧ … ∧ Cn → Cn+1 with C1, …, Cn in KB, we can infer Cn+1 • We can chain this until we can infer some Ck such that each Ci is either in KB or is the result of Modus Ponens involving only prior Cm (m<i) • We then have that KB ⊢ Ck.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Prolog
    Appendix A An Introduction to Prolog A.1 A Short Background Prolog was designed in the 1970s by Alain Colmerauer and a team of researchers with the idea – new at that time – that it was possible to use logic to represent knowledge and to write programs. More precisely, Prolog uses a subset of predicate logic and draws its structure from theoretical works of earlier logicians such as Herbrand (1930) and Robinson (1965) on the automation of theorem proving. Prolog was originally intended for the writing of natural language processing applications. Because of its conciseness and simplicity, it became popular well beyond this domain and now has adepts in areas such as: • Formal logic and associated forms of programming • Reasoning modeling • Database programming • Planning, and so on. This chapter is a short review of Prolog. In-depth tutorials include: in English, Bratko (2012), Clocksin and Mellish (2003), Covington et al. (1997), and Sterling and Shapiro (1994); in French, Giannesini et al. (1985); and in German, Baumann (1991). Boizumault (1988, 1993) contain a didactical implementation of Prolog in Lisp. Prolog foundations rest on first-order logic. Apt (1997), Burke and Foxley (1996), Delahaye (1986), and Lloyd (1987) examine theoretical links between this part of logic and Prolog. Colmerauer started his work at the University of Montréal, and a first version of the language was implemented at the University of Marseilles in 1972. Colmerauer and Roussel (1996) tell the story of the birth of Prolog, including their try-and-fail experimentation to select tractable algorithms from the mass of results provided by research in logic.
    [Show full text]
  • Propositional Logic. Inferences
    CS 1571 Introduction to AI Lecture 12 Propositional logic Milos Hauskrecht [email protected] 5329 Sennott Square CS 1571 Intro to AI M. Hauskrecht Logical inference problem Logical inference problem: • Given: – a knowledge base KB (a set of sentences) and – a sentence (called a theorem), • Does a KB semantically entail ? KB | ? In other words: In all interpretations in which sentences in the KB are true, is also true? CS 1571 Intro to AI M. Hauskrecht 1 Sound and complete inference Inference is a process by which conclusions are reached. • We want to implement the inference process on a computer !! Assume an inference procedure i that KB • derives a sentence from the KB : i Properties of the inference procedure in terms of entailment • Soundness: An inference procedure is sound • Completeness: An inference procedure is complete CS 1571 Intro to AI M. Hauskrecht Sound and complete inference. Inference is a process by which conclusions are reached. • We want to implement the inference process on a computer !! Assume an inference procedure i that KB • derives a sentence from the KB : i Properties of the inference procedure in terms of entailment • Soundness: An inference procedure is sound If KB then it is true that KB | i • Completeness: An inference procedure is complete If then it is true that KB KB | i CS 1571 Intro to AI M. Hauskrecht 2 Solving logical inference problem In the following: How to design the procedure that answers: KB | ? Three approaches: • Truth-table approach • Inference rules • Conversion to the inverse SAT problem – Resolution-refutation CS 1571 Intro to AI M.
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture 8: Rule-Based Reasoning
    Set 6: Knowledge Representation: The Propositional Calculus ICS 271 Fall 2013 Kalev Kask Outline • Representing knowledge using logic – Agent that reason logically – A knowledge based agent • Representing and reasoning with logic – Propositional logic • Syntax • Semantic • validity and models • Rules of inference for propositional logic • Resolution • Complexity of propositional inference. • Reading: Russel and Norvig, Chapter 7 Knowledge bases • Knowledge base = set of sentences in a formal language • • Declarative approach to building an agent (or other system): – Tell it what it needs to know – • Then it can Ask itself what to do - answers should follow from the KB • • Agents can be viewed at the knowledge level i.e., what they know, regardless of how implemented • Or at the implementation level – i.e., data structures in KB and algorithms that manipulate them – Knowledge Representation Defined by: syntax, semantics Computer Inference Assertions Conclusions (knowledge base) Semantics Facts Imply Facts Real-World Reasoning: in the syntactic level Example:x y, y z | x z The party example • If Alex goes, then Beki goes: A B • If Chris goes, then Alex goes: C A • Beki does not go: not B • Chris goes: C • Query: Is it possible to satisfy all these conditions? • Should I go to the party? Example of languages • Programming languages: – Formal languages, not ambiguous, but cannot express partial information. Not expressive enough. • Natural languages: – Very expressive but ambiguous: ex: small dogs and cats. • Good representation language:
    [Show full text]
  • My Slides for a Course on Satisfiability
    Satisfiability Victor W. Marek Computer Science University of Kentucky Spring Semester 2005 Satisfiability – p.1/97 Satisfiability story ie× Á Satisfiability - invented in the ¾¼ of XX century by philosophers and mathematicians (Wittgenstein, Tarski) ie× Á Shannon (late ¾¼ ) applications to what was then known as electrical engineering ie× ie× Á Fundamental developments: ¼ and ¼ – both mathematics of it, and fundamental algorithms ie× Á ¼ - progress in computing speed and solving moderately large problems Á Emergence of “killer applications” in Computer Engineering, Bounded Model Checking Satisfiability – p.2/97 Current situation Á SAT solvers as a class of software Á Solving large cases generated by industrial applications Á Vibrant area of research both in Computer Science and in Computer Engineering ¯ Various CS meetings (SAT, AAAI, CP) ¯ Various CE meetings (CAV, FMCAD, DATE) ¯ CE meetings Stressing applications Satisfiability – p.3/97 This Course Á Providing mathematical and computer science foundations of SAT ¯ General mathematical foundations ¯ Two- and Three- valued logics ¯ Complete sets of functors ¯ Normal forms (including ite) ¯ Compactness of propositional logic ¯ Resolution rule, completeness of resolution, semantical resolution ¯ Fundamental algorithms for SAT ¯ Craig Lemma Satisfiability – p.4/97 And if there is enough of time and will... Á Easy cases of SAT ¯ Horn ¯ 2SAT ¯ Linear formulas Á And if there is time (but notes will be provided anyway) ¯ Expressing runs of polynomial-time NDTM as SAT, NP completeness ¯ “Mix and match” ¯ Learning in SAT, partial closure under resolution ¯ Bounded Model Checking Satisfiability – p.5/97 Various remarks Á Expected involvement of Dr. Truszczynski Á An extensive set of notes (> 200 pages), covering most of topics will be provided f.o.c.
    [Show full text]
  • Solvers for the Problem of Boolean Satisfiability (SAT)
    Solvers for the Problem of Boolean Satisfiability (SAT) Will Klieber 15-414 Aug 31, 2011 Why study SAT solvers? Many problems reduce to SAT. Formal verification CAD, VLSI Optimization AI, planning, automated deduction Modern SAT solvers are often fast. Other solvers (QBF, SMT, etc.) borrow techniques from SAT solvers. SAT solvers and related solvers are still active areas of research. 2 Negation-Normal Form (NNF) A formula is in negation-normal form iff: all negations are directly in front of variables, and the only logical connectives are: “ ∧”, “∨”, “ ¬”. A literal is a variable or its negation. Convert to NNF by pushing negations inward: ¬(P ∧ Q) ⇔ (¬P ∨ ¬Q) (De Morgan’s Laws) ¬(P ∨ Q) ⇔ (¬P ∧ ¬Q) 3 Disjunctive Normal Form (DNF) Recall: A literal is a variable or its negation. A formula is in DNF iff: it is a disjunction of conjunctions of literals. (ℓ ∧ ℓ ∧ ℓ ) ∨ (ℓ ∧ ℓ ∧ ℓ ) ∨ (ℓ ∧ ℓ ∧ ℓ ) 11 12 13 21 22 23 31 32 33 conjunction 1 conjunction 2 conjunction 3 Every formula in DNF is also in NNF. A simple (but inefficient) way convert to DNF: Make a truth table for the formula φ. Each row where φ is true corresponds to a conjunct. 4 Conjunctive Normal Form (CNF) A formula is in CNF iff: it is a conjunction of disjunctions of literals. (ℓ ∨ ℓ ∨ ℓ ) ∧ (ℓ ∨ ℓ ∨ ℓ ) ∧ (ℓ ∨ ℓ ∨ ℓ ) 11 12 13 21 22 23 31 32 33 clause 1 clause 2 clause 3 Modern SAT solvers use CNF. Any formula can be converted to CNF. Equivalent CNF can be exponentially larger.
    [Show full text]
  • Traditional Logic and Computational Thinking
    philosophies Article Traditional Logic and Computational Thinking J.-Martín Castro-Manzano Faculty of Philosophy, UPAEP University, Puebla 72410, Mexico; [email protected] Abstract: In this contribution, we try to show that traditional Aristotelian logic can be useful (in a non-trivial way) for computational thinking. To achieve this objective, we argue in favor of two statements: (i) that traditional logic is not classical and (ii) that logic programming emanating from traditional logic is not classical logic programming. Keywords: syllogistic; aristotelian logic; logic programming 1. Introduction Computational thinking, like critical thinking [1], is a sort of general-purpose thinking that includes a set of logical skills. Hence logic, as a scientific enterprise, is an integral part of it. However, unlike critical thinking, when one checks what “logic” means in the computational context, one cannot help but be surprised to find out that it refers primarily, and sometimes even exclusively, to classical logic (cf. [2–7]). Classical logic is the logic of Boolean operators, the logic of digital circuits, the logic of Karnaugh maps, the logic of Prolog. It is the logic that results from discarding the traditional, Aristotelian logic in order to favor the Fregean–Tarskian paradigm. Classical logic is the logic that defines the standards we typically assume when we teach, research, or apply logic: it is the received view of logic. This state of affairs, of course, has an explanation: classical logic works wonders! However, this is not, by any means, enough warrant to justify the absence or the abandon of Citation: Castro-Manzano, J.-M. traditional logic within the computational thinking literature.
    [Show full text]