<<

ALTERNATIVE PERSPECTIVES IN MARXIST THEORY OF ACCUMULATION AND CRISIS*

Erik Olin Wright

Because of space limitations, some sections of the original version of this paper had to be cut. In particular, throughout the paper, discus- sions that mainly engaged technical issues in the labor theory of or extended reviews of debates on particular concepts, have been cut. One section of the original paper, “ the meaning of accumulation,” in which the foundations of the and its relation to , has been entirely eliminated. Readers interested in this speciŽ c discussion can Ž nd a version of it in Erik Olin Wright, Class, Crisis and the State (London: Verso, 1978), pp. 113–124. There is not one Marxist theory of economic crisis, but several com- peting theories. While all Marxist perspectives on economic crisis tend to see crisis as growing out of the contradictions inherent in the process of accumulation, there is very little general consensus on which contradictions are most central to understanding crisis, or even on how the contradictions in accumulation should be conceptualized in the Ž rst place. This paper will attempt to lay bare the logical structure of each of the general Marxist perspectives on economic crisis and to provide a preliminary synthesis. I will argue that there is no intrinsic incompati- bility in these diverse conceptions of the contradictions in accumulation if they are viewed as part of a historical process. Speci Ž cally, I will make the following argument: 1. At diVerent stages of capitalist development the accumulation proc- ess faces di Verent dominant constraints or impediments. These impediments are not exogenous factors which interfere with the accumulation process but are generated by the accumulation process itself. 2. In order for capitalist to continue, these constraints must be overcome. In a fundamental sense capitalists do not have the choice of passively accepting the impediments to accumulation. As individuals, capitalists must attempt to overcome these impediments

Critical Sociology 25,2/3 116 erik olin wright

in order to survive in a competitive world; as a class, capitalists must strive to remove the impediments to accumulation in order to con- tain the class struggle. 3. The systemic solutions to the dominant impediments at a given stage of capitalist development generate the new impediments which con- strain the accumulation process in the subsequent stage. It is in this sense that the impediments to accumulation can be considered con- tradictions in accumulation rather than merely obstacles to accumula- tion. They are contradictions because the “solutions” to a particular impediment become themselves impediments to accumulation. 4. The current world-wide capitalist economic crisis can be (tentatively) understood as part of a transition from one pattern of constraints on accumulation, characterized by Keynesian solutions, to a new set of emergent constraints which were in part caused by those very Keyne- sian strategies in earlier crises and which are no longer amenable to Keynesian solutions. We will begin, in the next section of this paper, by examining how diVerent traditions of Marxist crisis theory identify di Verent potential constraints on the process of . This will be followed by an analysis of how these potential constraints on accumulation assume diVerent importance in di Verent periods of capitalist development. The paper will conclude with a more speculative discussion of likely devel- opments in the immediate future.

I. Impediments and Contradictions in the Accumulation Process 1 Contemporary Marxist literature on contradictions in the accumula- tion process generally focuses on one of four critical impediments to accumulation: 1) the rising organic composition of capital (Mattick 1969, YaVe 1973a, Cogoy 1973, Mage 1963); 2) the problem of realizing sur- plus value, and in particular problems of in capital- ist society (Sweezy 1942, Baran and Sweezy 1966, Gillman 1965); 3) a low or falling resulting from rises in wages (Glyn and SutcliVe 1972); and 4) the contradictory role of the state in accu- mulation (Cogoy 1972, Ya Ve 1973a, O’Connor 1973, O Ve 1973 and 1974). Most of our discussion of these four impediments to accumula- tion will be based on the value categories discussed in part I. It is impor- tant to stress that such a value analysis does not exhaust the Marxist work on economic crisis. A complete understanding of crisis would also involve an analysis of monetary instability, credit imbalances, and other alternative perspectives in marxist theory 117 problems strictly in the sphere of circulation. These issues will not be discussed in the present paper, since, while such problems are impor- tant, there is a theoretical priority to analyzing the impediments to accu- mulation in terms of contradictions in the sphere of production. It is on these contradictions that my analysis will be focused. (For a collec- tion of papers on economic crisis which is not restricted to value analy- sis, see Mermelstein 1975.)

1. The organic composition of capital and the falling rate of pro Žt. It is a fundamental premise of Marxist that only living labor can produce , and thus pro Ž ts. The rate of proŽ t, however, is based not merely on labor costs of the capitalist (v) but on all capital costs (c + v). Therefore, the reasoning goes, if it should happen in the course of capitalist development that the value of the dead labor used in production should grow much more rapidly than the living labor, there will be a tendency all other things being equal, for the rate of pro Ž t to decline. This consti- tutes the basic logic for studying the relationship between changes in the of capitalist society—the technology broadly con- ceived—and the rate of pro Ž t. The “organic composition of capital” is a ratio that is designed to re  ect the salient aspects of technology that impinge on the rate of pro Ž t. The most useful simple expression for this is the ratio of dead labor () to living labor in production: 2 c Q = v + s

One other expression, the rate of exploitation (also called the rate of surplus value), will be important in the discussion of the falling rate of proŽ t. The rate of exploitation is de Ž ned as the ratio of the unpaid to the paid portions of the working day, or, alternatively, the ratio of sur- plus value to variable capital: s e = v We can then write the rate of pro Ž t as: s e r = = (1) c + v Q (l + e) + l 118 erik olin wright

Equation (1) will help us to explain the theory of the falling tendency of the rate of pro Ž t. There are six propositions in the argument: 1) There are forces intrinsic to the process of capital accumulation which tend to raise the level of the organic composition of capital. 2) As the organic composition of capital rises, there is a tendency for the rate of pro Ž t to fall unless the rate of exploitation increases suYciently to counter-balance the rise in the organic composition of capital (or unless some other counteracting force intervenes). 3) In the long run, rises in the rate of exploitation cannot completely counteract the rising organic composition of capital, and thus there will be a deŽ nite tendency for the rate of pro Ž t to decline. 4) When the decline in the rate of pro Ž t becomes su Yciently seri- ous and can no longer be compensated for by the existing rate of exploitation, an economic crisis occurs: the least pro Ž table capitals dis- appear as go bankrupt; and capitalists increasingly withhold because there are no pro Ž table outlets. , which is fundamentally derived from the rate of accumulation, there- fore declines with the result that the crisis takes on the appearance of a crisis of of commodities. Whereas underconsumptionists (see below, subsection 2) argue that crisis is caused by an overproduc- tion of commodities, by an overproduction of surplus value, the theory of the falling rate of pro Ž t argues the exact opposite.

Because not enough [surplus value] has been produced, capital cannot ex- pand at a ratewhich wouldallow for the full realization of what has been produced. The relative scarcity of surplus-labor in the production process appears as an absolute abundance of commodities in circulation. (Mattick 1969: 79)

5) These conditions of crisis, however, serve the function of restor- ing conditions favorable for subsequent pro Ž table accumulation. Several mechanisms accomplish this: a) unproductive capital is eliminated from the market, thus leaving the remaining capital at a higher level of pro- ductivity; b) in addition, when individual capitals go bankrupt they are forced to sell their existing constant capital at prices below real exchange values. This devaluation of capital means that in the aggregate the numerator in the organic composition of capital declines, thus raising the rate of pro Ž t; c) Ž nally, workers are thrown out of work, the reserve army of the unemployed swells, and capitalists can push the wage below its value, thus increasing the rate of exploitation. Once these processes have advanced su Yciently to restore an acceptable rate of pro Ž t, accu- mulation resumes and the crisis ends. alternative perspectives in marxist theory 119

6) While the crisis tendency of capitalist society takes the form of periodic cycles, there is also an over-arching tendency for cycles to become progressively more severe. Each successive crisis occurs at a higher level of accumulation and thus a higher level of the organic com- position of capital. The problems of restoring conditions for renewed proŽ table accumulation thus tend to become more di Ycult in each suc- cessive crisis (Mattick 1969: 69). With slight variations, these six propositions are all held by propo- nents of the theory of the falling tendency of the rate of pro Ž t. The Ž rst three constitute the heart of the theory, for if it can be demon- strated that there is a tendency for the rate of pro Ž t to fall, the par- ticular conception of how this in turn produces economic crisis and how economic crisis itself restores conditions of renewed accumulation fol- lows fairly naturally. We will therefore concentrate our attention on the Ž rst three propositions. The second and third of these can be dealt with purely formally in terms of equation (1). It is immediately obvious from equation (1) that for any Ž xed value of the rate of exploitation, the rate of pro Ž t becomes simply a function of the inverse of the organic composition of capital. Thus, if Q rises and e remains constant, the rate of pro Ž t will neces- sarily fall. The second proposition in the argument therefore follows immediately from the de Ž nitions of r, Q, and e. The validity of the third proposition is less obvious. While it is clear that if the organic composition were to rise to in Ž nity even an in Ž nite rate of exploitation could not counteract the fall in the rate of pro Ž t, this limiting case is not very helpful for understanding the movements of the rate of pro Ž t in the real world. What we would like to know is the extent to which a rise in the organic composition of capital will constrain in the accumulation process at any arbitrary level of Q, and not just in the limiting case where Q is in Ž nite. One way of examin- ing this problem is to ask if the extent to which the rate of exploita- tion can function as a counteracting force is itself a Vected by rises in the organic composition of capital. It is easy to show using elementary calculus that as the organic composition of capital rises, the rate of proŽ t becomes progressively less sensitive to changes in the rate of exploitation. Thus, not only does a high organic composition of capi- tal produce a lower possible pro Ž t, but it also makes changes in the rate of exploitation less useful as a strategy for bolstering the rate of proŽ t. Furthermore, the higher the rate of exploitation already is, the less sensitive will the rate of pro Ž t be to subsequent changes in the rate 120 erik olin wright of exploitation. Thus, if in fact there is a secular rise in the organic composition of capital, then, even if the rate of exploitation also rises, it becomes progressively less and less likely that it will be able to coun- teract completely the rising organic composition of capital. It is there- fore quite reasonable to regard rises in the organic composition of capital as a signiŽ cant impediment to the accumulation process, and equally reasonable to assume that if it does tend to rise, complementary rises in the rate of exploitation will not be able to counteract the fall in the rate of pro Ž t in the long run. The Ž rst proposition in the argument is the most problematic. Neither the empirical demonstrations of a general tendency for the organic composition of capital to rise over time, nor the theoretical arguments marshalled in its support, have been particul arly convincing . It is unquestionably true that in physical terms the amount of machines, raw materials, buildings, etc., per worker has vastly increased with capital- ist development. But the organic composition of capital is a value con- cept, and it is far from obvious that the value of constant capital per worker has risen or has tendency to rise, especially in the later stages of capitalist development. For the value of constant capital per worker to rise there must be a net excess of labor-saving technological innovations (inovations which substitute machinery for labor power) over capital-saving innovations (inno- vations which substitute cheap machines— machines that require rela- tively little socially necessary labor time to produce—for expensive machines). When Marx wrote Capital, this was a fairly plausible assump- tion to make. Although Marx did recognize the possibility that increas- ing productivity in the capital goods sector of the economy might result in a “cheapening of the elements of constant capital” (Marx 1967: 236), he regarded this as at most a transient counter-tendency to a generally rising organic composition of capital. In Marx’s view, progressive intro- duction of labor-saving technologies was an intrinsic part of the accu- mulation process. There are several plausible arguments which suggest that in advanced capitalist economies there should be some tendency for a relative increase to occur in the selective pressures for capital-saving over labor-saving innovations. In earlier periods of capitalist development, when mecha- nization was Ž rst occuring, the introduction of machines necessarily implied the substitution of machines for workers. Once an industry is fully mechanized, however, all innovations tend to take the form of machines replacing machines. Even if such machines do in fact still replace workers, there is no reason why they should not also be cheaper alternative perspectives in marxist theory 121 machines. In the competitive struggle among the producers of machines, after all, there will be attempts to expand markets by producing less expensive machines as well as more productive machines (i.e., machines which produce more output per total labor input). Furthermore, it might also be expected that as constant capital increases as a proportion of total costs (i.e., as the value composition of capital, c/ v, rises), individ- ual capitalists will tend to be more concerned about saving on constant capital. A plausible model for the rate of increase in the organic com- position of capital could postulate that, all other things being equal, the net rate of labor-saving innovations over capital-saving innovations is inversely related to the proportion of labor costs in production. Thus as the organic composition of capital rose, it would tend to rise at a slower and slower rate, perhaps even asymptotically approaching some high relatively stable level. Furthermore, even if it should happen that in highly mechanized industries the organic composition of capital continues to rise, the aggre- gate social level of the organic composition might remain constant if there were a relatively faster rate of growth in unmechanized sectors of the economy. The enormous growth of “service sector” , which is typically highly labor-intensive, could counterbalance the con- tinuing growth in capital intensity in the industrial sector. The ten- dency for the competitive labor-intensive sector of the economy to grow in a symbiotic relation with the monopoly sector would also tend to counter to some degree the rise in the aggregate organic composition (see O’Connor 1973, chap. 2). All of these pieces of suggestive reasoning indicate that, while a thorough model predicting the relative propor- tions of labor-savingand capital-saving innovations has yet to be worked out, there is no a priori reason to assume a general preponderance of labor-saving innovations in a developed capitalist economy. The empirical evidence is at best indecisive on the question of whether or not the organic composition of capital has risen, done nothing, or even fallen. Since national income accounts are not Ž gured in terms of embodied labor times, and since data on capital invested includes many entries that Marxists would not even consider capital, it is of course highly problematic how data on the organic composition could be reli- ably gathered. Even as strong a proponent of the rising organic com- position thesis as Cogoy has to admit that the meager data which support his views are as equivocal as the data which oppose them (Cogoy 1973: 63). If the theoretical basis is weak, for assuming there is a tendency for the organic composition to rise, and if the empirical evidence is non- 122 erik olin wright existent, why bother with the theory at all? There are several reasons. First, while there is considerable dispute about the relevance of the the- ory of the rising organic composition of capital to late-20 th-century cap- italism, there is general agreement among Marxists that it was a signi Ž cant characteristic of 19 th-century . As we will see in section III of this paper, the theory of the rising organic composition of capital is essential for a historical understanding of the development of capitalist accumulation. Second, even if it is true that there is no consistent long term ten- dency for the organic composition of capital to rise, it (the organic com- position) still acts as a real constraint on the accumulation process. The results we discussed above indicate that when an economy is in a sit- uation of relatively high organic composititon of capital, the rate of proŽ t becomes less sensitive to increases in the rate of exploitation. This means that if the rate of pro Ž t were to decline because of some factor other than the organic composition of capital (for example, the growth of unproductive expenditures), the system would be more rigid because of the high organic composition. No one has argued that the organic composition of capital has fallen to any great extent in the past several decades, and thus one can say that it still acts as an impediment to accumulation, even though it may not be the great dynamic source of crisis that its defenders claim. Finally, even if a secular rise in the organic composition of capital is not the general cause of capitalist crisis, a destruction of values and a corresponding temporary fall in the organic composition of capital may be a crucial part of the solution to crises. If sometime during the Ž rst quarter of the 20 th century, a relatively stable, fairly high level of organic composition of capital was reached, it could still be the case that the organic composition of capital has dropped considerably dur- ing periods of crisis, and then returned to this stable level during peri- ods of prosperity as post-crisis un-devaluated constant capital replaced the cheap, devaluated capital acquired during the crisis. A fall in the organic composition of capital can be a solution to crisis without a rise in the organic composition being the fundamental cause of crisis. Under these assumptions, if it should happen that institutional changes in the economy—in particular, growth of government subsidies of ine Ycient monopolistic Ž rms—should block the fall in capital values during a cri- sis, then it would be expected that a serious “ crisis of crisis manage- ment” might occur. This issue will be more fully discussed in section II below. alternative perspectives in marxist theory 123

2. Underconsumptionist theories of economic crisis. Marx very explicitly states in the that the inherent ten- dency for the rate of pro Ž t to fall is

the most important law of modern political economy and the most essen- tial one for understanding the most complicated relationships. It is the most important law from an historical standpoint. (Quoted in Ya Ve 1972a: 200.) But he also makes a number of statements which some Marxists have taken to indicate that Marx supported an underconsumptionist view of crisis. “The last cause of all real crisis,” Marx writes in Capital, Vol. III,

always remains the poverty and restricted of the masses as comparedto the tendency of capitalist production to develop the produc- tive forces in such a way, that only the absolute power of consumption of the entire society would be their limit. (Marx 1967) As often happens in debates among Marxists, the dispute between the two positions has frequently taken the form of competiting exegeses of passages from Capital. On that score it seems to me that the proponents of the falling rate of pro Ž t probably have the upper hand. While Marx did see the underconsumption of the masses as a chronic state in cap- italist society, it only became a factor in crisis given the dynamics of accumulation and the problem of the rising organic composition of cap- ital. Engels states this position very clearly:

The underconsumption of the masses, the restriction of the consumption of the masses to what is necessary for their maintenance and reproduc- tion, is not a new phenomenon. It has existed as long as there have been exploiting and exploited classes. . . . The underconsumption of the masses is a necessary condition of all forms of society based on exploitation, con- sequently also of the capitalist form; but it is the capitalist form of pro- duction which Ž rst gives rise to crises. The underconsumption of the masses is therefore also a prerequisite condition for crises, and plays in them a role which has long been recognized. But it tells us just as little why crises exist today as why they did not exist before. (Quoted in Ya Ve 1973a: 216.) A correct exegesis of Marx, however, doth not a correct interpretation of the world make. The cogency of underconsumptionist views must be assessed on the strength of their logical status, not on their formal agree- ment or disagreement with Marx’s own work. 124 erik olin wright

One of the initial problems in assessing the underconsumptionist logic is that most writings from the underconsumptionist perspective fail to lay out the assumptions and structure of the argument in as coherent a way as the falling-rate-of-pro Ž t theorists. The following acccount of underconsumptionist theory is thus not taken directly from any one defender of the perspective. It is rather my own construction of what I feel a coherent Marxist underconsumptionist theory would be. A Marxist theory of underconsumption contains four basic proposi- tions: 1) There is a general tendency in capitalist society for absolute level of surplus value to rise. In addition, with increases in productiv- ity, there is a tendency for the rate of surplus value to increase as well. 2) There is an intrinsic contradiction in capitalist society between the conditions of production of surplus value and the conditions of the realization of surplus value. For realization not to be a prob- lem, the growth in aggregate demand must occur at the same rate as the growth in productivity and surplus value. This is always problematic in capitalist society since individual capitalists always try to minimize their wage bills. There is an intrinsic tendency for demand to lag behind growth in surplus value and thus for part of the surplus value to remain unrealized. 3) The inability of the capitalist to realize the full value of the pro- duced surplus value is experienced by capitalists as a fall in the actual rate of pro Ž t. This leads to a reduction of , bank- ruptcies, unemployment, etc. Such crisis conditions are resolved when some exogenous source of new demand—such as the state— steps in and restores conditions of pro Ž table realization of surplus. 4) While underconsumptionist tendencies are present at all stages of capitalist development, they become especially acute, and become the source of serious economic crisis, only in the monopoly stage of capitalism. Monopoly power greatly augments the tendency for surplus value to rise, and thus the tendency for underconsump- tion to occur. There is relatively little disagreement over the Ž rst of these proposi- tions. With some exceptions most Marxists feel that with increasing pro- ductivity, the value of wage goods tends to fall and that thus, although the standard of living of workers might even rise in real terms, the value of labor power will also tend to decline. This results in an increase in the rate of surplus value and, with expanded of capital, alternative perspectives in marxist theory 125 an increase in the mass of surplus value as well. While the undercon- sumptionists and the falling-rate-of-pro Ž t theorists disagree vehemently on the relationship of monopoly to a rising rate of surplus value, they agree on the general proposition that it tends to rise. On the second proposition there is no such agreement. The falling- rate-of-pro Ž t theorists insist that realization problems are a consequence rather than acauseof the fall in the rate of pro Ž t (see Cogoy, 1973: 64). If all aggregate demand is derived from accumulation, and if capi- talists are constantly striving to maximize the rate of accumulation, then clearly the only reason there can ever be an e Vective demand inade- quate for absorbing all of the produced surplus value would be if some- thing happened to the rate of accumulation. This is precisely what the theory of the rising organic composition of capital attempts to provide. The problem with this reasoning, and that of similar critics of under- consumption theories, is that aggregate demand in capitalist society is not simply derived from accumulation. Especially under monopoly con- ditions, a sizable part of total demand does not come directly from accumulation but from such nonaccumulating sources as capitalist per- sonal consumption, much of state expenses, and so on. To analyze the underconsumption problem it is useful to introduce a distinction between potential pro Ž ts and actual pro Ž ts. Potential pro Ž ts are those that would occur in the absence of any realization problems. Actual proŽ ts will always be less than or equal to such potential pro Ž ts. The underconsumption argument is an analysis of why there are ten- dencies for a portion of the surplus to remain unrealized, and thus for actual proŽ ts to fall short of potential pro Ž ts. If the organic composition of capital is more or less constant and the rate of exploitation is rising, there will necessarily occur a rise in the rate of potential pro Ž ts in value terms. The question then becomes, what are the equilibrium conditions such that all of this increasing surplus will be realized? That is, what total demand must be forth- comingso that the entire surplusproduct in valueterms will be sold? The tendency toward underconsumption in capitalist society stems fundamentally from the fact that there are no automatic mechanisms which guarantee that the rate of unproductive demand will grow su Yciently fast to Ž ll the gap between the rate of accumulation and the rate of potential pro Ž t.3 The demand for unproductive, wasteful consumption does not grow spontaneously in the same way that demand directly derived from accumulation grows automatically with economic growth. Waste is a social invention, and the maintenance of high levels of waste- 126 erik olin wright ful consumption requires conscious planning and intervention. The growth on a massive scale of consumer credit, and built-in obsolescence of many consumer durables, the wide range of state interventions in the econ- omy of the Keynesian variety, and so on and so forth, all represent conscious strategies to increase the rate of unproductive demand and thus avoid realization/underconsumption crises. As we will see in sec- tion III, these solutions themselves create new problems which the cap- italist economy is only beginning to face. While underconsumptionist tendencies are present at all stages of capitalist development, they have remained largely latent until the monop- oly stage. As long as the organic composition of capital did have a tendency to rise, much of the rising surplus was in fact automatically absorbed by the accelerating rate of investment (of accumulation). With the emergence of , however, the situation decisively changes, both because, as already argued, there appears top be a ten- dency for the organic composition of capital to become relatively sta- ble in this stage of capitalism (or at least to rise at a much slower rate), and because in monopoly capitalism surplus value is extracted from workers not only in the labor process but also through monopoly pric- ing in the sphere of circulation. Two general social processes have evolved which at least partially counteract this tendency toward underconsumption in monopoly capi- talist society. The Ž rst has already been mentioned: the invention and growth of Keynesian policies designed to stimulate aggregate demand through the expansion of unproductive spending, primarily by the state. Such spending has the secondary consequence of bolstering the con Ž dence of in the stability of the economy, and thus fosters a higher rate of accumulation. Second, the growth of collective bargaining may have the e Vect of reducing the rate of increase in the rate of surplus value itself. Especially in monopoly sector industries, where wages since the war have been fairly closely tied to productivity increases, the gradual rise in the wage has undoubtedly lessened to some extent underconsumption tendencies. The continued growth of monopoly power, however, has at least par- tially neutralized this counteracting process, since much of the produc- tivity wage increases have in turn been passed on to the as a whole in the form of monopoly pricing. This has the e Vect of fur- ther increasing the rate of surplus value for capital as a whole. The most serious weakness in the underconsumptionist position is that it lacks any theory of the determinants of the actual rate of accu- mulation. The falling-rate-of-pro Ž t theorists have a speci Ž c theory of the alternative perspectives in marxist theory 127 determinants of the rate of accumulation. In equating the rate of pro Ž t with the rate of accumulation, they see a combination of the organic composition of capital and the rate of exploitation as the basic deter- minant of the actual rate of accumulation. Since they view the organic composition of capital as rising and thus constantly pushing down the rate of pro Ž t, the assumption that the rate of pro Ž t and the rate of accumulation are equivalent does no damage to their general argument. If anything, the impact of the rising organic composition of capital would be even greater if not all pro Ž ts were accumulated. In the underconsumption argument, however, the rate of pro Ž t and the rate of accumulation cannot be equated. If they were, there would not be a tendency for underconsumption (i.e., there would be no need for the rate of unproductive spending to increase). Much undercon- sumptionist writing has, at least implicitly, opted for Keynes’ solution to this problem by focusing on the subjective anticipations of pro Ž t on the part of capitalists as the key determinant of the rate of accumulation. From a Marxist point of view, this is an inadequate solution. I have not yet seen an elaborated theory of investment and the rate of accu- mulation by a Marxist underconsumptionist theorist, and thus for the time being the theory remains incomplete.

3. Theories of the pro Žt squeeze. Both underconsumptionistsand organic-composition-of-capital theorists maintain that with capitalist development there tends to be a rising rate of surplus value. Where they di Ver is in their view of the relationship between this rising rate of surplus value and the movements of the rate of proŽ t. The organic-composition theorists insist that changes in tech- nology within the production process itself tend to negate rise in the rate of surplus value and thus produce a fall in pro Ž ts; undercon- sumptionists argue that the forces for a rising surplus tend to be stronger than any counterforces, especially under conditions of monopoly capital. The proponents of the pro Ž t squeeze view of crisis agree with the organic-composition theorists that the rate of pro Ž t tends to fall, but they do not agree that this has anything to do with changes in tech- nology, and they disagree with both the organic-composition theorists’ and the underconsumptionists’ belief that there is any tendency for the rate of surplus value to rise. The essential argument of the pro Ž t squeeze is very simple: the rel- ative share of the national income going to workers and to capitalists is almost entirely a consequence of their relative strengths in the class 128 erik olin wright struggle. There is therefore no intrinsic reason for wage struggles to be limited, even in the long run, to demands that real wages rise as rapidly as productivity. To the extent that the working class develops a strong enough labor movement to win wage increases in excess of productiv- ity increases, there will be a tendency for the rate of pro Ž ts to fall (to be “squeezed” by rising wage bills). Such a decline in pro Ž ts results in a corresponding decline in investments and thus in even slower increases in productivity. The end result is economic crisis. Condition s for proŽ tability are restored to the extent that—because of the growth of the reserve army of the unemployed during the crisis—the bargaining strength of the working class is lessened relative to capitalists and thus the proŽ t squeeze is relaxed. This position has been most thoroughly argued by Andrew Glyn and Bob Sutcli Ve in a recent analysis of the current stagnation of British capitalism (1971, 1972). (For a similar analy- sis dealing with American business cycles, see Body and Crotty, 1975.)

4. State expenditure and accumulation. Marxist theories of accumulation and crisis have generally conceptu- alized state expenditures as unproductive (again: unproductive in the sense of not producing surplus value). In the underconsumptionist model of crisis this unproductive quality of state expenditures constitutes the central mechanism by which crisis is averted or at least minimized; in rising-organic-composition models, the expansion of such unproductive expenditures is seen as a critical factor which exacerbates the inherent crisis tendencies in the system. In both theories, however, state activity is seen as largely unproductive and as absorbing an increasing share of the surplus value produced in the economy. This traditional conception canbe criticized both in terms of its view of the sources of state revenue andof its view of the impact of state spending. The view that all taxes constitute a tax on the existing pool of sur- plus value is based on a mechanistic and static interpretation of the meaning of the value of labor power. Since it is obviously the case that taxation reduces the real wages of workers, the view that all taxes come from surplus value implicitly assumes that prior to taxation the real wages were above the true value of labor power. Taxation then merely appropriates that part of the surplus value which had previously been in the disguised form of an in  ated wage. The implicit logic is that if taxation did not occur, wages would be reduced to the present after-tax level anyway. In other words, if the state did not tax this sur- alternative perspectives in marxist theory 129 plus value it would be available to the capitalist for accumulation. These assumptions are at best dubious, if real wages and taxation are seen as at least partially the outcome of class struggle. Because of the enormous weight of the state’s power of legitimation, it is reasonable to assume that many workers are willing to accept a level of taxation on their money incomes greater than a corresponding wage cut that might occur in the absence of such taxes. Taxation can thus be seen as, in part, a weapon in the class struggle by which the state appropriates a certain amount of surplus labor that is unavailable to private capitalists. From a total social point of view, therefore, taxation, like monopoly pricing, has the capacity to increase the aggregate rate of surplus value. This is not to say that there are no limits on the extent to which taxes can have this eVect; and certainly not that all or even most taxation in fact expands surplus value, but merely that the assumption that all taxation constitutes a drain on the existing pool of surplus value is incorrect. Quite apart from the problem of the relationship of taxation to exist- ing surplus value, there is the question of the impact of taxation on the subsequent production of surplus value. It is certainly true that, with very few exceptions, state production itself is not production for the market and the state does not accumulate capital out of any realized proŽ ts from its own production. Most state expenditures therefore do not directly produce surplus value. But as O’ Connor (1973) has thor- oughly argued, this does not keep the state from playing an important role in indirectly expanding surplus value and accumulation. Many state expenditures have the e Vect of reducing the reproduction costs of labor power by socializing many expenses that would otherwise have to be paid for by individual capitalists (medical care, training and education, social security, etc.). Furthermore, a great deal of state spending on research and development, transportation infrastructures, communica- tions, etc., has the e Vect of increasing the level of productivity of cap- ital as a whole and thus contributing to accumulation. Even in terms of classical, wasteful, Keynesian demand-maintenance state interven- tions, such state spending may have the side e Vect of increasing capac- ity utilization and thus increasing productivity. Again, this is not to say that such indirectly- productive expenditures are necessarily the dominant modeof state activity, butrather that it is incorrect to see the state’s role in the accumulation process as being simply a drag on accumulation. Given that to some extent taxes themselves can expand surplus value and that to some extent state spending can expand accumulation, the crucial thing to analyze becomes not merely the forces which produce 130 erik olin wright a general expansion of state activity, but also the extent to which those forces selectively expand the unproductive or indirectly-productive activ- ities of the state, and the extent to which either surplus-expanding or surplus-absorbing taxation tends to grow more rapidly. Little can be said about the latter issue. The current growth of the so-called taxpayers’ revolt might indicate that the growth of surplus- expanding taxation has reached some sort of limit. Certainly the general battering that the legitimacy of the state has taken in the last several years would tend to reduce the state’s capacity to use taxes to extract extra surplus value from the working class. At any rate, for the rest of this discussion we will assume that there has not been any major trend one way or the other in the balance between surplus-expanding and surplus-absorbing taxation. More can be said about the relationship between unproductive state expenditures and indirectly-productive state expenditures. Given the underconsumptionist tendencies inherent in monopoly capital, it is obvi- ously necessary for unproductive expenditures to grow more rapidly than productive expenditures. The growth of classical Keynesian madework and waste programs, most notably in military spending, re  ects this requirement. There are several critical contradictions contained within this role of the state, however, which disrupt the smooth adjustment of unproductive state spending to the needs of monopoly capital. a) Contradiction of legitimation and accumulation : The state does not serve the function merely of facilitating accumu- lation through demand maintenance; the state also serves a vital legit- imation function in capitalist society which helps to stabilize and reproduce the class structure as a whole. The legitimation function directs much state activity toward co-opting potential sources of popular discontent by attempting to transform political demands into economic demands. The expansion of Keynesian programs beginning in the 1930’s created a perfect political climate for dramatically expanding such legitimating state expenditures. For a long time it appeared that the state could kill two functional birds with one economic-policy stone. The diYculty, however, is that once a demand on the state to pro- vide some social service or to meet some social need is granted and becomes institutionalized, it becomes viewed as a right. There is a cer- tain logic to legitimation which decrees that the political apparatus gets progressively diminishing returns in added legitimation for a given pro- gram over time. Once a program becomes seen as a right the contin- uation of that program adds little to the legitimacy of the state, whereas alternative perspectives in marxist theory 131 a cutback in the program would constitute a source of delegitimation. There is thus not only a tendency for programs once established to con- tinue, butalso a constant pressure for programs to expand, regardless of the requirements of the accumulation process. The hypothesis can there- fore be advanced that, once Keynesian demand maintenance programs become bound up with the legitimation functions of the state, there is a tendency for unproductive spending to rise more rapidly than the sys- temic requirements for realization of surplus value might dictate. b) Military Keynesianism and productivity : The particular institutional form that much Keynesian spending takes— speciŽ cally the system of state contracting known as the military-indus- trial complex—tends not only to absorb surplus but also to put a con- siderable damper on the subsequent development of productivity (except for occasional technological “spin-o Vs” from military research and devel- opment). who are major suppliers of military hardware are guaranteed a given pro Ž t rate by the state (especially in cost-plus contracts) and are thus under relatively little pressure to introduce in- expensive, e Ycient innovations into their production processes. Since for most military production there are only one or two potential suppli- ers, and since the criterion for awarding contracts generally has little to do with the e Yciency of the , military Keynesianism tends generally to reduce the average level of productivity in the economy. c) The weakening of mechanisms of crisis management : The usual scenario for crisis and recovery is for the least productive capitals to be wiped out, capital to be devaluated, and conditions for proŽ table accumulation to be restored. The growth of monopoly capi- tal, and especially of the dominant role of the state in regulating the economy, tends to weaken seriously this restorative mechanism. This is most obvious in the case of corporations which become locked into pro- duction for the state. In part because of the personal ties between the corporate elite and the state apparatus (especially in the military-indus- trial nexus), and in part because of the social dislocation that would result from the bankruptcy of a major monopoly corporation, the state Ž nds it very di Ycult to abandon a corporation, even as that corpora- tion’s productivity declines. But the state is also forced to underwrite the low productivity of many other sectors of the economy, simply in order to avoid major disruptions of the economy (the railroads are a good example). 132 erik olin wright

The upshot of these contradictions in the role of the state is as fol- lows: although Keynesian policies originally emerged in an e Vort to cope with the problem of excessive surplus—as portrayed in the under- consumptionist model—, the policies in the end recreated the image of crisis held by the organic-composition-of-capital model— inadequate levels of surplus value— while simultaneously undermining the restora- tive mechanisms in the economy. That is, in spite of the necessity for waste in a period of monopoly capital, there is a tendency for the level of waste (i.e., unproductive spending) to expand more rapidly than the capacity of the system to produce waste (i.e., the rate of increase in productivity). Because the crisis-solving mechanisms are partially blocked, the result is chronic in  ation combined with relatively high levels of unemployment, or what has come to be called “stag  ation.”4 The obvious solution to these dilemmas is, of course, for the state to shift the balance of its activities from unproductive to indirectly-pro- ductive spending. Indirectly-productive expenditures have certainly been steadily growing over the past several decades, although generally at a slower rate than unproductive expenditures. The state is increasingly involved not merely in what O Ve (1974) calls “allocative” policies (poli- cies which basically redistribute resources already produced or which mobilize the production of resources strictly for Keynesian purposes), but in “productive” policies as well (policies which directly impinge on the production process and which contribute to the productivity of the economy). As the productive forces in have devel- oped (i.e., highly sophisticated techonologies, increasingly interdependent productive processes, increasing requirement for highly specialized tech- nical labor, etc.), it has become more and more di Ycult for individual capitals to provide all of the requirements for their own expanded repro- duction, and they have turned to the state for various forms of social- ized investments. It might well be thought, therefore, that the solution to the contradictions of Keynesian policies can be found in a dramatic expansion of these emergent forms of indirectly-productive socialized investments. The problem is that the fundamentally Keynesian politics of the contemporary capitaliststate— apolitics rooted in pluralist interest- group demands, special interest subsidies, military production, etc.— act as a serious constraint on the potential growth of these newer productivity-enhancing forms of state intervention. This is the heart of the “Ž scal crisis of the state”: the constant pressures from the growth of unproductive spending, which are exceedingly di Ycult to curtail (for the reasons spelled out above), make it highly problematic for the state to Ž nance the new forms of state policy which would help reverse the alternative perspectives in marxist theory 133 problem of declining productivity itself. Until such time as new politi- cal forces can be mobilized successfully to generate what O’Connor (1973) has aptly called a new “social industrial complex,” it is di Ycult to see how this impasse can be overcome.

II. The Historical Development of Capitalism and the Impediments to Accumulation

It should be obvious by now what the punch line of this paper is: At each stage of capitalist development there is a characteristic pattern of impediments to the accumulation process. Through a combination of class strategies by the and individual strategies by indi- vidual capitalists attempting to maximize their pro Ž ts, these impediments are overcome and the accumulation process continues in new forms. The solutions to the dominant impediments at each level of capitalist development, however, contain within themselves new contradictions which gradually emerge in the subsequent stages. This of the accumulation process is summarized in Chart 1. 5 The chart is, of course, highly oversimpli Ž ed. The structural “ solu- tions” to a particular impediment to accumulation do not generally elim- inate the problemaltogether, butmerely helpit recede into the back- ground. Every period of capitalist development contains, if only in a residual form, the contradictions characteristic of earlier periods. The purpose of the chart is not to present a rigid “ stage theory” of capi- talism, but rather to capture the overarching problems and movements of the capitalist system. 6 Let us brie  y examine each of the stages in the chart.

1. Transition from simple production to expanded reproduction. The two crucial constraints on the accumulation process in the early period of primitive accumulation were, on the one hand, the existence of institutional forms of production which made close supervision and control of the workforce di Ycult, and, on the other, the relatively small size of the and thus the limited amount of exploitable labor. The lack of supervision of workers under conditions of cottage indus- try meant that the capitalist had little control over exactly how much the worker worked per day; it was also often exceedingly easy for the worker to embezzle considerable amounts of raw materials from the capitalist (see Marglin 1974 for an excellent discussion of these issues). The result was that the rate of exploitation tended to be low because 134 erik olin wright the eVective unpaid portion of the work day was low. In combination with the restricted size of the proletariat, this meant that the mass of surplus value available for accumulation tended to be quite low. As Stephen Marglin has argued, in the English the creation of the factory provided the structural solution to the Ž rst of these constraints. Workers were brought together under a single roof and closely supervised in their work. They were forced to work as many hours as the capitalist dictated, and thus the amount of surplus labor increased considerably. The creation of factories, however, only height- ened the problem of the shortage of free exploitable labor. A variety of state policies, such as open immigration, rural depopulation, clos- ing of the poor houses, etc., contributed to the solution of the labor shortage.

2. Transition from primitive accumulation to manufacture. The continual expansion of the proletariat and of the factory system characterizes the transition from primitive accumulation to the period of manufacture. In the early period of this transition the major way of increasing the rate of exploitation was through the expansion of “absolute surplus value” (i.e., increases in surplus value resulting from the expan- sion of the working day and the intensity of work). Very quickly, the working day was increased virtually to its biological maximum. In spite of this, however, the actual rate of exploitation remained relatively low because of the generally low productivity of technology and the accom- panying high value of labor power. Even when the standard of living of the worker was pushed down to bare subsistence, it still took a rel- atively high proportion of the working day for the worker to reproduce the value of his/her labor power. The solution to the problem of the relatively low rate of surplus value came through the proliferation of technical innovations, which drasti- cally cheapened the goods consumed by wage labor and thus lowered the value of labor power. Since many of these innovations were labor saving, they also had the e Vect of expanding the reserve army of the unemployed, thus further alleviating the general problem of the short- age of labor that characterized the period.

3. Transition from manufacture to machinofacture. The progressive introduction of machines into the production process deŽ nes the transition from simple manufacture to machinofacture. The alternative perspectives in marxist theory 135 earlier tendencies—expansion of factories, expansion of the proletariat, and so on—continue, but there is added a constant stream of new inno- vations. In addition, in this period the Ž rst eVective forms of proletar- ian class organizations emerge. Demands are made both for a shortening of the working day and for raises in real wages. The increasing inten- sity of class struggle creates considerable additional pressure on capital to introduce labor-saving innovations. The result is that in the period of transition from manufacture to machinofacture there is a very rapidly growing organic composition of capital. Thus, in spite of an increasing rate of surplus value, there was a de Ž nite tendency for the rate of pro Ž t to fall. The solution to this impediment to accumulation was contained within the impediment itself. The classic pattern of unproductive capitals, and increasing concentration and centralization of capital, provided the social mechanisms for periodically restructuring capital in ways which restored conditions favorable to accumulation. 7

4. Rise of monopoly capital. As the organic composition of capital continued to rise in the 19 th century and into the 20 th century, two things occurred: capital tended to become ever more concentrated and centralized, and the rate of increase in the organic composition of capital tended to slow down. By some time in the Ž rst quarter of this century, it appears, the organic composition of capital more or less stabilized. The rate of exploitation, however, continued to rise, both because of general increases in pro- ductivity (both capital-saving and labor-saving) and because of monop- oly power itself. The result was that a strong tendency toward realization and underconsumption problems emerged. Simultaneous with these developments, the labor movement began to gather considerable strength, especially in the monopolized sectors of the economy. While demands tended to center on issues of wages and immediate working conditions, the growth of socialist and communist forces within the labor movement made the potential for a more gen- uinely revolutionary labor movement seem likely. The great social invention of state-sponsored waste, academically legit- imated as Keynesianism, constituted the major solution to the impedi- ment of underconsumption. The discovery of collective bargaining and the creation of complex systems of job hierarchies and promotion struc- tures (see Stone 1974 and Braverman 1974) helped to contain the labor movement in bounds compatible with such Keynesian solutions. 136 erik olin wright

t f t - - - s s s e k k g g d n h s a e i o t r r n n n d n e c n i n a r i i i o o a l a r u o u o n c i t s c y h u g a o u t g w w l r

t i a e l l n d t ; g n a s w s

e i o ) i e t s a h a l v n t . e i e e i t . r n l p n v r a o t c s o i n d c h h c a t r e

f e a t t e n n t e n o m r e n s i y p p o e t i c d i p o n e f f m s p i i a s

,

t m g n o e o a y m u ; e e s y r l o a n s n c h e g

h l e h l a a l t m v a a , c v n C r n h t c

e r i o s i a t i o h o o u f i e r

a h v o g n c h p s c t n o t t o c v

e

a m t n o a o l r

n n e e s i w l h

s f i y e c

- e a t e o t v l r c p

n s r o b

a r z c n d s

s o o f i n e s o g e i v o a s s e e r t e n b e o s i n b o i n l e n e e t u h a e i i

l l a o ; t l e c n e , h o u r l i r o v i t r n t t t

h y h n n i o t l S a t i e e o t

t t d r e u d c c s o i

u l s

e c h l i - t o h n n s w .

l u s t t f o n d t a r d a a s e a i a d f a o r a

d a r S n o n s r e c u e r e t e f p e s o

t a i l a s b e

r r l s y g r n c n o u s i p n a p i a c a a o n u h u e r p l e t o l x i r s x r h e n i c i c n . t c m o i s m s i p e r e r u c y o p r n S o e t e e b c i a e h u m r a r e r t m a c o h o o a o i n V t ( a t p d T t w l a i e B c c p t d u r t S

t n e g l . r f t ------e e e y i r w e a y c c e k o Ž s u h u b n r m r

o o a l l a v t u o l o o m e e ( o r o i a p a o d . d

t p

) d n c f v e u p E v

s o a w l

e ” e c m k l o s r h

d f m s a r e a s t g u i e s e d p r o o v

u o c a u u

u m h n n f

l c o l l a n t o f d e p u w a o o a h b

t p c r a p c i o n f n

r v c g a c a s r r p

i l i

i a o u r n n

u l h e

y u A

s n v h r t s t

o s o e e i a e r e i i r y a u o e

v ) t t n l z h e f d h o g g f w i b t o h e y a a t p l r o s p l t l o h a o

r f l u l e e s s o g u r

u

t s u s o s o d n v e i o

n n s e s i n w i t f i a e m n r i t . t e s a o t

h a o

k r a e u l t h a r n h e c y g r r s l m o i m o t t c t c

s c o

t e n r o r s o t c n e b u e

i l c t i r n i l n t l o e w r ( s a w c h e d f A o l ; o a

s t h e o o

m t d s r l n f t s i e C r g i f y f l e e a n f n l a b

h n o p l l o

r e h t e i a o o y y n ; w c a t t a l m a y s h “ c

r o c o f e t k e e s e s t

n e g g f n t

c p f o g v n a f d s ; a s i e l n e n o o l n a a o i t t o i u l t i l t c p r t d i

C y k y a a a r a

t o n l r n e f e n n i r c n m m o e t e g e b e t o i o v o u e a o a s h i h i i o n a L d i t t w r R b t c l s T t p t m n o C

f o

- - - e n o l t r u x u p e c c

e t c c e t

m r t a i a A o s n u

t P e t

e

e . c l m v e v n a i m p a i f r t o t o o c i l i i u u i r e t r f t . n v m c m o e i c

a n i t a r r n u f s D o i p i m o

u P d t i t

t s c n H o i i f . a l r u s m m e o a d p n o t o r

i M r o r a

u f p f d r r t y a t

o

o c p t t i i C e n n a r :

f r

d o o e f n n i i o o o t t p o o d n i i

i i i s s e t e t m g h y a n a n d l l l a c a a t m r n u u a r r S a a o m c p T m T m E . . . 1 2 3 alternative perspectives in marxist theory 137

, f , t e e e g b n n t d t o m n d c n o o o a e n i a i i j o e n t t t t s r s

a s g a , f s m a a n t n s d e e e m e : e p o f r r v e e ” v n i l r l e l c c t r d e  o u c o a i e s n a - t i ; c t v i t l t l ” e c i r . l t g a n n n u t

i u i a n e u

s o s

p m r i l f g t i v s t s e u e a d i e s . r

e t n v l r r d i e n g c y a a a a t e t l g n t e t n o n t c i i g s i n n r f p o c m - i a

a i e p s n t p e f o t

i s a g r

o o o e d a i n c t o y t

n , g e d n a r s p . a m i r o c e a d

a t i c s “ t o a t s t m t p n ( d n i r e a r l b c

e x a e t e i p f n o u r s e

y f g

o y , e m a t “ d m

r s x i e v e o e o i t n e e e v d e t n r g l i

y i K a .

l c v t i o ) p p d l h m i e

i s e s s c

e c s a l s e v e e e e i l s m r i e u l n i i n t c n e o o a h c c g d p e c e r e i r i i y t c c t l l e s o e p e p h x m r i o o e f f s V i e n K d e o h o E s e i p p p T r ? . , , t f ------e c e e n d d h n i s r e i c e o r d n m t n n t r e t h h o n o e i . n e i t u d t i o o n o t n a n p w a d t t s

r t . n o d c e a e t n f f l o a a n m s m f r y t r l o s l o g r l

o a z o i e u r o r m h a i t h o g u e t g e n g c e l v t i i l u c e r g p c c s i n h n ; a d i i o p c i m o u a i i t d s n u r p e r e r a s c u y t n e e h a a o t f d m h m h t c i a s s t i c s o v t i c o t i i o i n o n t

w s e i c e : t r f r d t m r i f n r n o o a

o a s w l c i c y t e y o e s c o c p o c z o

u l

e t t n i

u b c h u e n n s b s o n f y l p o c t i m t n m n

d d e i i a h i

c p o o p l e t t t o e o i o n d d m i m n l i n r i o n t m c s h r l f t e t a e n s e e t o t o u u a a o n t n

p o o a a r s s e e e d

z c h n a o

u t e C i z e n s p c n

d n n f l s i a r w b e

w l e o o h t g t e d m a . n o r n i i r t e r h a t e l n a g p t i e c n a e t o s g a i t f c s p r i n o b a

c n u a g e s

t i i

n o i u r / s o a n i t m q n r c n h i t n

d n i s n d o i a n t a x o e s t p f a o n e i i h e l a o T o r d o e a i i l e t i t o i h t r Ž

e m u p t a

r y t a n c r i

t i f m s r . a i r c p w e l t r c y o l p e g i u p t d e c i c l n e e t o e r n u d d o g n p y n s s t n s o r b o m m d i l i t e e i s a a o o u y i a t g n - a - l m t u l r m d l i d r

s c r r r

s t i a a u

h e p u n h p e e e n d d t t m n n p t c r e s e e  e i i v v d o e f f n c a o o o a e i u h h h i n T r w c o w E t t a r i s u t E a c o v s t c - p a C l

a t y i l l p a o t a i p p C o a

n y C l o

o y M p l o o n d p o e o t n c M o e

r d i M e

D f c o n m

e a s t e i v l s a i d t a t R A S i . . . 4 5 6 138 erik olin wright

5. Advanced monopoly capital.

The Keynesian solutions to underconsumption tended at least ini- tially to dovetail with the political requirements for legitimation. But the initial harmony was shattered as the growth of unproductive state expenditures tended to expand faster than the surplus-absorbing require- ments of the system. The continuing growth of monopoly on both a national and international scale has further contributed to the deterio- ration of the trade-o V between in ation and unemployment. The inter- nationalization of capital in particular has confounded the situation by undermining the capacity of national governments in the advanced cap- italist countries to regulate e Vectively their own national economies. The emergent solution to these problems of the ever-expanding repro- ductive costs of monopoly capitalism relative to the growth in produc- tivity, is to move from simply Keynesian interventions in the economy to active state involvement in the production process itself. This is the juncture at which American monopoly capital Ž nds itself in the mid- 1970’s. Qualitatively new forms of state intervention are called for, but the state apparatus seems prepared only to try once more the old Keyne- sian solutions. After this Ž nal attempt  ounders, as it almost surely will, it is reasonable to expect that some tentative steps toward these new forms of state intervention and control of the economy will be taken. It is dangerous to make predictions about history, and especially dan- gerous to make predictions about the new forms of contradiction that are likely to emerge in the future. Nevertheless, some things seem fairly safe to say. As monopoly capitalism moves toward qualitatively new forms of state involvement in production, toward State Directed Monopoly Capital, there will be an ever-deepening politicization of the accumula- tion process itself. It will become increasingly di Ycult to apply a “neu- tral” market rationality to production; political criteria will become more and more central to production itself. Although it is almost certain that in the United States few major corporations would be formally nation- alized, a greater and greater proportion of production will be de facto organized by the state. This does not mean, of course, that commod- ity production (production for exchange) would disappear, but rather that an increasingly important part of total production would be organ- ized by a logic other than commodity logic. All of this would occur within the continuing context of capitalist social relations and a capitalist state which serves the function of re- producing the class structure of capitalist society. The expanded de- commodiŽ ed sphere of production would be strictly constrained by the alternative perspectives in marxist theory 139 requirements of reproducing commodity production itself. The new forms of impediments to accumulation would therefore center on the height- ened contradiction between the progressive (and politiciza- tion) of the process of production and the continuing private appropriation (through commodity production) of the . While in a sense is always an immanent potentiality in advanced capitalist society, the ever-increasing role of the state in accu- mulation is likely to move the socialist alternative more into the center of working class politics. This however in no sense implies that social- ism is the only solution to these emergent contradictions. It is quite pos- sible to imagine the development of a full-  edged in the United States (although dressed in the symbols of private capital- ism) which would deal with the glaring contradictions between legiti- mation and accumulatio n by means of considerable repression and centralized planning. There is, however, no automatic reason for the “solution” which is functional for capitalism to be the solution which emerges. Whether or not such a structural reordering of monopoly cap- ital occurs depends, on the one hand, on the cohesiveness of the cap- italist class and its capacity to generate a class politics in the interests of capital as a whole, and, on the other, on the strength of socialist movements in the working class and its capacity to organize a class pol- itics capable of transforming decommodi Ž ed production in the service of capital into socialist production controlled by the working class.

Notes

Original version of this article appeared in The Insurgent Sociologist , 6:1 (Fall, 1975), pp. 5–39. 1. This discussion presupposes basically familiarity with the basic concepts of the labor theory of value as it was traditionally deployed within . In the original pub- lished version of this paper, the relvant elements in Marxist political economy were pre- sented on pp. 6–13. See also Wright (1978: 113–125). 2. This expression is not the traditional way that Marxists have de Ž ned the organic composition of capital. The usual practice has been to regard the ratio c/v as the organic composition of capital. This has been the usage by economists such as Sweezy, Dobb, Mattick, and Gillman. This expression constitutes the ratio of dead to living capital and is generally treated by these writers as re  ecting in value terms what in bourgeois eco- nomics is called the capital-intensity of the technology. In a number of recent works (Cogoy 1973, Mage 1963, Laibman 1974) it has been argued that the ratio c/v is not an adequate measure of capital intensity since, the level of v depends in part upon the rate of exploitation and not merely on the relative amounts of constant capital and human labor in production. The ratio of dead labor to living labor in production, c/v + s, has therefore been substituted for the ratio of constant capital to variable capital. 3. It must be stressed that the expression “unproductive” is being used in a non- 140 erik olin wright normative sense. An expenditure is unproductive in capitalist society if it does not con- tribute directly or indirectly to the production of value and surplus value. Some of these expenditures might in fact be “productive” in terms of meeting human needs, but they are not productive in terms of the functioning of a capitalist economy. 4. The implications of the internationalization of capital are that a given amount of eVort by the state to reduce in  ation will result in greater increases in unemployement than would otherwise be the case, since such state policies will tend to increase the movements of capital across national boarders (see Martinelli 1973). Internationalization will thus tend to push the Phillips curve away from the origin. It is probably impossi- ble to disaggregate empirically the relative e Vects of (a) increasing internationalization of capital, and (b) increasing unproductive state spending, on the deterioration of the trade- oV of in ation and unemployment, since empirically the two tend to move together. 5. This chart draws heavily from a number of sources. The Ž rst three stages come fairly directly from Marx’s discussion of primitive accumulation in Part VIII of Vol. I of Capital; the shift from stage 3 to stage 4 is quite similar to the analysis by David Levine (1973), especially Part III of his analysis, “The Theory of the Growth of the Capitalist Economy”; the analysis of stage 5 is based largely on that of James O’Connor (1973); and the analysis of the emergent problems of stage 6 has grown out of the analy- sis of OVe (1974). 6. The chart may give the impression that the particular path of capitalist develop- ment, and the particular pattern of contradictions which emerges at each stage in the process, are rigidly determined. This raises some extremely important questions about the underlying logic of the concept of “contradiction.” In what exact sense are the con- tradictions schematically laid out in the chart “inevitable”? Do the solutions to impedi- ments to accumulation in one period necessarily lead to future impediments? While it is obvious that each of the “solutions” outlined in the chart have certain inherent lim- its, it is less obvious that each of the “solutions” outlined in the chart have certain inher- ent limits, it is less obvious that the social forces in capitalist society necessarily push the system toward the limits, and thus transform a structural solution into a contradiction. Why, in other words, does each adaptive strategy of the capitalist system tend to exhaust itself in time? A simple answer is that none of these adaptive strategies can eliminate the inherent class antagonisms of capitalism. Class antagonisms make a simple, homeostatic repro- duction of the system impossible. A more complex answer is that the forms that class struggle takes are themselves molded by the dominant adaptive strategies of the system. The working class is not merely a passive force, even in its most integrated and con- tained periods. It adapts its strategies to the “structural solutions” which emerge in the course of capitalist development. In their most class-conscious form, these working class strategies are explicitly focused on exploiting the structural solutions and pushing them to their limits. A similar argument can be made about the e Vects of struggle among capitalists (com- petition): as solutions to the impediments of accumulation emerge, individual capitalists adopt new forms of , new strategies for maximizing their individual accu- mulation. Since there is no overall planning in capitalist society to coordinate these indi- vidual strategies, there is an inherent tendency for these strategies gradually to push toward the limits of the existing structure within which accumulation takes place. There is thus a dialectic between the structural solutions to earlier constraints on accumulation and the forms of class struggle and competition which develop in response to those struc- tural solutions. 7. In addition to these structural solutions, many Marxists have argued, classical 19 th- century European colonialism provided a (temporary) structural solution to the problem of the falling rate of pro Ž t. By bringing technologically backward, labor-intensive economies into the world capitalist system, colonialism in e Vect lowered the organic composition of capital on a world scale. Furthermore, colonialism involved the transfer of vast amounts alternative perspectives in marxist theory 141 of surplus value from the third world to the developed capitalist countries. This further reduced the tendency for the rate of pro Ž t to fall. For a discussion of this perspective on imperialism, see Mattick 1969, chap. 19. 8. This expression should not be confused with the theory of “State Monopoly Capital” (commonly referred to as StaMoCap theory), in which the state is seen as manipulated by the dominant Ž nancial interest groups of monopoly capita. The implicit theory of the state underlying the present discussion is much closer to O’Conner’s (1973) and OVe’s (1973, 1974) than to StaMoCap theory. See Gold, Lo, and Wright (1975) for a general discussion of the theory of the state.

References Amin, Samir 1975 “Towarda StructuralCrisis of World Capitalism,” Socialist Revolution , No. 23. Baran, Paul, and 1966 Monopoly Capital . New York: . Body, Raford, and James Crotty 1975 “Class Con  ict and Macro-Policy: The Political ,” Review of Radical Political Economics , Vol. 7, No. 1. Braverman, Harry 1974 Labor and Monopoly Capital . New York: Monthly Review. Cogoy, Mario 1972 “Les Theories Neo-Marxistes, Marx et l’Accumulation du Capital,” Les Temps Modernes, September–October, pp. 396–427. 1973 “The Fall in the Rate of Pro Ž t and the Theory of Accumulation,” BSCE, Winter, pp. 52–67. Gillman, J. 1965 Prosperity in Crisis . New York: Marzani and Munsell. Glyn, Andrew, and Bob Sutcli Ve 1971 “The Critical Condition of British Capital,” Review , No. 66. 1972 British Capitalism, Workers and the Pro Žt Squeeze. London: Penguin Books. Gold, David, Clarence Lo, and Erik Olin Wright 1975 “Some Recent Developments in Marxist Theories of the State,” Monthly Review (in press). Hodgson, G. 1974 “The Falling Rate of Pro Ž t,” New Left Review , No. 84. Laibman, David 1974 “The Organic Composition of Capital: A Fresh Look at Marxian Accumulation Theory.” Unpublished Ms. Levine, David 1973 Accumulation and Technical Change in . Unpublished Ph.D. dis- sertation, Yale University. Mage, S.H. 1963 The Law of the Falling Tendency of the Rate of Pro Žt. Unpublished Ph.D. dis- sertation, Columbia University. Marglin, Stephen A. 1974 “What do Bosses Do?” Review of Radical Political Economics , Vol. 6, No. 2, Summer. Martinelli, Alberto 1973 “Nation States and Multinational Corporations,” Kapitalistate , No. 1. Marx, K. 1906 Capital, Vol. I (Charles H. Kerr & edition). New York: The Modern Library. 142 erik olin wright

1962 Wages, Price and Pro Žt, in Selected Works , Vol. I. Moscow: Foreign Languages Publishing House. 1967 Capital, Vol. III. New York: New World Paperbacks. Mattick, Paul 1969 Marx and Keynes . Boston: Porter Sargent. Mermelstein, David 1975 The Economics Crisis Reader . New York: Random House. O’Connor, James 1973 The Fiscal Crisis of the State . New York: St. Martin’s Press. OVe, Claus 1973 “The Structural Problem of the State.” Unpublished Ms. 1974 “The Theory of the State and the Problem of Policy Formation.” Unpub- lished Ms. Poulantzas, Nicos 1973 Political Power and Social Classes . London: NLB. Rowthorn, Bob 1974 “Skilled Labor in the Marxist System,” BCSE , September, pp. 25–45. Stone, Katherine 1974 “The Origins of Job Structures in the Steel Industry,” Review of Radical Political Economics , Vol. 6, No. 2, Summer. Sweezy, Paul 1942 The Theory of Capitalist Development . New York: MR Press. 1974 “Some Problems in the Theory of Capital Accumulation,” Monthly Review , Vol. 26, No. 1. YaVe, David 1973a “The Marxian Theory of Crisis, Capital and the State,” Economy and Society , Vol. 2, pp. 186–232. 1973b “The Crisis of Pro Ž tability, A Critique of the Glyn-Sutcli Ve Thesis,” New Left Review , No. 80, pp. 45–62.