Intuitions of Infinity

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Intuitions of Infinity INTUITIONS OF INFINITY by David Tall, Mathematics Education Research Centre, University of Warwick What is infinity? It is an extrapolation of our finite experience. But for many this leaves a bitter taste in the mouth. Some· As such our intuitions of infinity depend very much on the thing has gone wrong somewhere. How can "nought point nine kind of experience which is extrapolated. For instance, if we recurring" equal one? Surely when we subtract it from one we consider the "samesize" property of sets which have a bijection* get a single digit left over, way off in the "infinitieth ):>lace": between them then we get the kind of infinity called a cardinal 1-0.999 ... 999 ... =0.000 ... 000 ...... 1.· number. This is the most widely considered notion of infinity amongst. mathematicians ,yet it has properties which usually These problems are usually explained away by quoting the seem most unintuitive to the uninitiated. If we look at the current mathematical dogma relating to the appropriate .situ· experiences of pupils in school, they rarely concern the "same· ation. In handling the limit of 1/( 1 �x) as x tends to 1 we might size" aspect of sets so this lack of intuitive appeal is hardly say that the limit from the left is + oo and from the right is � oo surprising. Secondary pupils have different ·experiences of and 1/(1-x) is "not defined at x = 1". The problem as to infinity which give them a totally different feel for the idea. whether 2oo3 + 3 is a bigger infinity than oo2 + 4 is responded For instance, in drawing the graph of to by a rap over the knuckles "don't do arithmetic with infinity, oo/oo /(x)""'1/(1-x) it leads to contradictions,, "a symbol like is meaningless" and so on.The problem of the "infinitieth place" argument also they find that as x approaches 1 from the left,/(x) gets very large has a slick response. "Let and positive but as x approaches 1 from the right, f(x) gets very sn= 0. 999... 9 (to n decimal places), large and negative. The expression 2 3 so that s1 =0.9,s =0.99, and so on. Then (x + 4)/(2x + 3) 2 1-sn= 1/1011 approaches 0 as x grows large, so although x2 + 4 and 2x3 + 3 3 both grow without limit as x gets large, 2x + 3 grows even and taking the limit as n tends to infinity gives faster than x2 + 4: 1-lims11=0, How can one reconcile these two examples? Id the first case n-+Oll f(x) tends to a "plus infinity" from one side and a "minus so infinity" from the other. Is "plus infinity" the same as "minus 2 1 -0.999... 999 ...= 1- lim S11= 0 . infinity"? In the second case if x + 4 tends to "plus infinity" ,.-.eo 3 as x grows large, how can 2x + 3 tend to something even larger? and there is no digit left over in the inflnitieth place." · Can w.e have something that is even bigger than infinity? We often learn riot to "understand" these arguments but we . One thing is certain. Talking about cardinal infinity, the do "get used to them". So we become enlightened in the true "samesize" of sets, will not resolve this problem in ':i" natural wRys of mo!1ern mathematics. way.These ideas of "growing large", "tending to infinity" and However, there are two fundamental problems with this so on have absolutely nothing to do with comparing the size of eventual acceptance of the wisdom of our elders and betters. sets. The first is why do we so persistently obtain these early As another example, consider that hoary character the decimal intuitions of infinity as a direct product of school experience? expansion The second is a more fundamental one. If everyone seems to 0.999 ... 999... get such wild ideas, in what sense is the accepted mathematical definition so utuch better? "nought point nine recurring''. Does it equal one, or is it just When we look back at the history of mathematics we find a less? Ask school pupils this question and the vast majority will new twist. Three hundred years ago when the calculus was say "less". I suspect that the majority of teachers would say invented the accepted mathematical notion of infinity was quite the same. Mathematicians assert that this decimal expansion different from what it is now. In fact it is closer to the notions equals one. For them the decimal expansion means the actual of infinity given by the limiting processes which are discussed real number which is the limit' of the decimal approximations. in school.The joke is that many of the intuitions that we sense The decimal expansion nowadays would have been perfectly acceptable in the theories 0.333 ; ..333 ... of three centuries ago. Moreover a moderfi invention called ''non·standard analysis" permits the use of these old ideas of equals a third. (On that matter most pupils and teachers might infinity and it is possible to conceive of such ideas in a muc:h agree.) Multiplying this expression by three gives the proverbial simpler context, as I tried to demonstrate in a recent article in "nought point nine recurring" which therefore should equal the Matltematital Ga�mel, one. My purpose in discussing these matters is not to suggest to * A b1j'tction is a one-one, onto function. readers that they must now learn a revolutionary new piece of 30 Mathematic& in School, May 1981 mathematics so that they may achieve mathemati<;al salvation - cardinal number n and has no element in common with IN, so far from it. What I would like to do is to give an explanation K0 + n is the cardinal number of the set as to why these intuitions of infinity are produced in school­ INU ( - 1, -2, ... , -n I work. Then I would like to demonstrate that these intuitions are not as stupid as the accepted mathematical defiriTtions make But the map f: IN ......U IN ( - 1, - 2, ... , -n I given by . out. The formal mathematical definition is perfectly alright in f(r)= -r for r�n a context where number means a comparison of size of sets and f(r)=r-n for r>n cardinal number gives a theoretical extension to the counting concept.However, in other contexts, such as limiting processes, is a bijection, so the cardinal concept is singularly inappropriate to explain K0+n= K0 (2) intuitions of infinity which arise. To demonstrate this I shall introduce a simple number system which contains infinite for any finite cardinal n. elements and infinitesimally small elements as well as the usual Equations (I) and (2) tell us that it is hopeless to try to define real numbers. I hope the average reader won't be frightened a-P for cardinals a, P; subtracting X0 from both sides of(l) by my intention to do this. I guarantee that(s)he will have met gives K 0 = 0 and subtracting K0 from both sides of (2) gives the number system before but will just have called it by a n = 0 for any natural number n! different name.We shall see that it is possible to have a number Analogous definitions and difficulties hold for the product of system with infinities of different sizes which can be added, two cardinal numbers a, p. Here we choose sets X, Y with multiplied, subtracted and divided in a sensible way, and where cardinal numbers a, P respectively and define the product the multiplicative inverse of an infinite element is an infinitesi­ cardinal ap to be the cardinal of the cartesian product X X Y. mal. This is quite different from the case of cardinal numbers For instance if a= 2, P= X0, we can take X= ( 0, 1 I, Y =IN which can only be added and multiplied. Subtraction and divi­ then X X Y is the set of ordered pairs of the form (0, n) or sion of infinite cardinal numbers cannot be defined, a fact (1, n) for n a natural number. The function which Cantor took as "proof" that infinitesimals could not exist. f:Xx Y--+IN I shall deal with these properties of cardinal infinity first since they arc instructive in showing how different kinds of infinity given by have diiierent properties. Then I shall go on to describe the /((0, n)) = 2n- I simple system which allows a full arithmetic of infinite elements /((1, n))=2n ' of diiierent sizes. After that I shall look at the way intuitions is a bijection, so of infinity arise in school and consider which mathematical 2 X0= X o· theory is more appropriate for the understanding of these This immediately tells us that we cannot define division in intuitions. The problem of "nought point nine recurring" general because dividing both sides by X 0 would give 2 = 1. requires an allusion to non-standard analysis which I shall briefly In recognising the problems of subtracting and dividing mention. Once again we shall see that the intuition, though cardinals Cantor decreed that infinitesimals (found by dividing incompatible with the modern theory of cardinal infinity does a finite number by an infinite one) could not exist2• His con­ fit very well with an alternative mathematical theory. Finally clusion is incorrect. It should have been that infinitesimals do I shall consider the consequences of what I have had to say for not exist within the context of cardinal numbers. In a similar way teachers. It will not mean the learning of new mathematics, solutions of the problems 3 + 4 or 5-8 do not exist in the rather a greater respect for the mathematics that is used in context of natural numbers IN.
Recommended publications
  • The Modal Logic of Potential Infinity, with an Application to Free Choice
    The Modal Logic of Potential Infinity, With an Application to Free Choice Sequences Dissertation Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Ethan Brauer, B.A. ∼6 6 Graduate Program in Philosophy The Ohio State University 2020 Dissertation Committee: Professor Stewart Shapiro, Co-adviser Professor Neil Tennant, Co-adviser Professor Chris Miller Professor Chris Pincock c Ethan Brauer, 2020 Abstract This dissertation is a study of potential infinity in mathematics and its contrast with actual infinity. Roughly, an actual infinity is a completed infinite totality. By contrast, a collection is potentially infinite when it is possible to expand it beyond any finite limit, despite not being a completed, actual infinite totality. The concept of potential infinity thus involves a notion of possibility. On this basis, recent progress has been made in giving an account of potential infinity using the resources of modal logic. Part I of this dissertation studies what the right modal logic is for reasoning about potential infinity. I begin Part I by rehearsing an argument|which is due to Linnebo and which I partially endorse|that the right modal logic is S4.2. Under this assumption, Linnebo has shown that a natural translation of non-modal first-order logic into modal first- order logic is sound and faithful. I argue that for the philosophical purposes at stake, the modal logic in question should be free and extend Linnebo's result to this setting. I then identify a limitation to the argument for S4.2 being the right modal logic for potential infinity.
    [Show full text]
  • Cantor on Infinity in Nature, Number, and the Divine Mind
    Cantor on Infinity in Nature, Number, and the Divine Mind Anne Newstead Abstract. The mathematician Georg Cantor strongly believed in the existence of actually infinite numbers and sets. Cantor’s “actualism” went against the Aristote- lian tradition in metaphysics and mathematics. Under the pressures to defend his theory, his metaphysics changed from Spinozistic monism to Leibnizian volunta- rist dualism. The factor motivating this change was two-fold: the desire to avoid antinomies associated with the notion of a universal collection and the desire to avoid the heresy of necessitarian pantheism. We document the changes in Can- tor’s thought with reference to his main philosophical-mathematical treatise, the Grundlagen (1883) as well as with reference to his article, “Über die verschiedenen Standpunkte in bezug auf das aktuelle Unendliche” (“Concerning Various Perspec- tives on the Actual Infinite”) (1885). I. he Philosophical Reception of Cantor’s Ideas. Georg Cantor’s dis- covery of transfinite numbers was revolutionary. Bertrand Russell Tdescribed it thus: The mathematical theory of infinity may almost be said to begin with Cantor. The infinitesimal Calculus, though it cannot wholly dispense with infinity, has as few dealings with it as possible, and contrives to hide it away before facing the world Cantor has abandoned this cowardly policy, and has brought the skeleton out of its cupboard. He has been emboldened on this course by denying that it is a skeleton. Indeed, like many other skeletons, it was wholly dependent on its cupboard, and vanished in the light of day.1 1Bertrand Russell, The Principles of Mathematics (London: Routledge, 1992 [1903]), 304.
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz and the Infinite
    Quaderns d’Història de l’Enginyeria volum xvi 2018 LEIBNIZ AND THE INFINITE Eberhard Knobloch [email protected] 1.-Introduction. On the 5th (15th) of September, 1695 Leibniz wrote to Vincentius Placcius: “But I have so many new insights in mathematics, so many thoughts in phi- losophy, so many other literary observations that I am often irresolutely at a loss which as I wish should not perish1”. Leibniz’s extraordinary creativity especially concerned his handling of the infinite in mathematics. He was not always consistent in this respect. This paper will try to shed new light on some difficulties of this subject mainly analysing his treatise On the arithmetical quadrature of the circle, the ellipse, and the hyperbola elaborated at the end of his Parisian sojourn. 2.- Infinitely small and infinite quantities. In the Parisian treatise Leibniz introduces the notion of infinitely small rather late. First of all he uses descriptions like: ad differentiam assignata quavis minorem sibi appropinquare (to approach each other up to a difference that is smaller than any assigned difference)2, differat quantitate minore quavis data (it differs by a quantity that is smaller than any given quantity)3, differentia data quantitate minor reddi potest (the difference can be made smaller than a 1 “Habeo vero tam multa nova in Mathematicis, tot cogitationes in Philosophicis, tot alias litterarias observationes, quas vellem non perire, ut saepe inter agenda anceps haeream.” (LEIBNIZ, since 1923: II, 3, 80). 2 LEIBNIZ (2016), 18. 3 Ibid., 20. 11 Eberhard Knobloch volum xvi 2018 given quantity)4. Such a difference or such a quantity necessarily is a variable quantity.
    [Show full text]
  • Measuring Fractals by Infinite and Infinitesimal Numbers
    MEASURING FRACTALS BY INFINITE AND INFINITESIMAL NUMBERS Yaroslav D. Sergeyev DEIS, University of Calabria, Via P. Bucci, Cubo 42-C, 87036 Rende (CS), Italy, N.I. Lobachevsky State University, Nizhni Novgorod, Russia, and Institute of High Performance Computing and Networking of the National Research Council of Italy http://wwwinfo.deis.unical.it/∼yaro e-mail: [email protected] Abstract. Traditional mathematical tools used for analysis of fractals allow one to distinguish results of self-similarity processes after a finite number of iterations. For example, the result of procedure of construction of Cantor’s set after two steps is different from that obtained after three steps. However, we are not able to make such a distinction at infinity. It is shown in this paper that infinite and infinitesimal numbers proposed recently allow one to measure results of fractal processes at different iterations at infinity too. First, the new technique is used to measure at infinity sets being results of Cantor’s proce- dure. Second, it is applied to calculate the lengths of polygonal geometric spirals at different points of infinity. 1. INTRODUCTION During last decades fractals have been intensively studied and applied in various fields (see, for instance, [4, 11, 5, 7, 12, 20]). However, their mathematical analysis (except, of course, a very well developed theory of fractal dimensions) very often continues to have mainly a qualitative character and there are no many tools for a quantitative analysis of their behavior after execution of infinitely many steps of a self-similarity process of construction. Usually, we can measure fractals in a way and can give certain numerical answers to questions regarding fractals only if a finite number of steps in the procedure of their construction has been executed.
    [Show full text]
  • Galileo and Leibniz: Different Approaches to Infinity
    Arch. Hist. Exact Sci. 54 (1999) 87–99. c Springer-Verlag 1999 Galileo and Leibniz: Different Approaches to Infinity Eberhard Knobloch Communicated by J. J. Gray Introduction “God exists since mathematics is consistent, and the devil exists since we cannot prove it.” In this way Andre´ Weil, one of the leading mathematicians of this century, characterized the mathematics of our time (Meschkowski 1969, p. 112; Rosenbloom 1950, p. 72). This connection between mathematics, God and the devil is not new: I would like to recall here only the study scene in Goethe’s Faust: Faust has the devil temporarily in his hand, because the pentagram is badly drawn. What is new in Weil’s saying is the insight that even mathematics cannot provide complete foundations for itself. Metamathematics and Hilbert’s proof theory are disciplines of our century. When Hilbert set about showing how the antinomies of the set theory created by Cantor could be avoided without betraying mathematics, as described in his lecture “On the Infinite” in 1925, he emphasized the necessity of clarifying the nature of the infinite (Hilbert 1926, p. 188). The infinite plays a crucial role in analysis, this most ingenious product of mathematical science, being ramified in the most refined way. As Hilbert fittingly formulated, mathematical analysis is, so to speak, a pure symphony on the infinite (Hilbert 1926, p. 184). No wonder that three years after Hilbert’s lecture his pupil Hermann Weyl character- ized mathematics as the science of the infinite (Weyl 1925–1927, p. 1; Laugwitz 1986, p. 233). He thus defined mathematics in a completely different way than his predecessors of earlier centuries.
    [Show full text]
  • Plotinus on the Soul's Omnipresence in Body
    Plotinus on the Limitation of Act by Potency Gary M. Gurtler, S.J. Boston College The limitation of act by potency, central in the metaphysics of Thomas Aquinas, has its origins in Plotinus. He transforms Aristotle’s horizontal causality of change into a vertical causality of participation. Potency and infinity are not just unintelligible lack of limit, but productive power. Form determines matter but is limited by reception into matter. The experience of unity begins with sensible things, which always have parts, so what is really one is incorporeal, without division and separation. Unity is like the esse of Thomas, since it is the act that makes a thing what it is and has its fullness in God. 1. Introduction Over fifty years ago Norris Clarke, S.J., published “The Limitation of Act by Potency: Aristotelianism or Neoplatonism,” The New Scholasticism, 26 (1952) 167–194, which highlighted the role of Plotinus in formulating some of the fundamental distinctions operative in medieval philosophy. He singled out the doctrine of participation and the idea of infinity and showed how they went beyond the limits of classical Greek thought. At the same time, his work challenged some of the basic historical assumptions of Thomists about the relation of scholastic philosophy, especially St. Thomas’s, to Plato and Aristotle. I have appreciated more and more the unusual openness and self critical character of Fr. Clarke’s historical method, and am pleased to have the chance in this response to Sarah Borden’s paper to explore some of the issues raised by Fr. Clarke’s seminal article in light of my own work on Plotinus.
    [Show full text]
  • Georg Cantor English Version
    GEORG CANTOR (March 3, 1845 – January 6, 1918) by HEINZ KLAUS STRICK, Germany There is hardly another mathematician whose reputation among his contemporary colleagues reflected such a wide disparity of opinion: for some, GEORG FERDINAND LUDWIG PHILIPP CANTOR was a corruptor of youth (KRONECKER), while for others, he was an exceptionally gifted mathematical researcher (DAVID HILBERT 1925: Let no one be allowed to drive us from the paradise that CANTOR created for us.) GEORG CANTOR’s father was a successful merchant and stockbroker in St. Petersburg, where he lived with his family, which included six children, in the large German colony until he was forced by ill health to move to the milder climate of Germany. In Russia, GEORG was instructed by private tutors. He then attended secondary schools in Wiesbaden and Darmstadt. After he had completed his schooling with excellent grades, particularly in mathematics, his father acceded to his son’s request to pursue mathematical studies in Zurich. GEORG CANTOR could equally well have chosen a career as a violinist, in which case he would have continued the tradition of his two grandmothers, both of whom were active as respected professional musicians in St. Petersburg. When in 1863 his father died, CANTOR transferred to Berlin, where he attended lectures by KARL WEIERSTRASS, ERNST EDUARD KUMMER, and LEOPOLD KRONECKER. On completing his doctorate in 1867 with a dissertation on a topic in number theory, CANTOR did not obtain a permanent academic position. He taught for a while at a girls’ school and at an institution for training teachers, all the while working on his habilitation thesis, which led to a teaching position at the university in Halle.
    [Show full text]
  • The Crisis of Infinity: Mathematics, Philosophy, and Nineteenth-Century Poetry
    The Crisis of Infinity: Mathematics, Philosophy, and Nineteenth-Century Poetry by Rachel Elizabeth Feder A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (English Language and Literature) in The University of Michigan 2012 Doctoral Committee: Professor Marjorie Levinson, Chair Professor Adela N. Pinch Professor Yopie Prins Assistant Professor Gillian C. White ! ! ! Acknowledgements This work is dedicated to Marjorie Levinson with infinite thanks. Ever since this project began to take shape in Marjorie’s 2007 seminar on Romantic poetry and philosophy, she has worked to bring out the best in both the scholar and the project. I am thankful to Marjorie for her tireless mentorship, keen insight, honest critique, and endless encouragement. I am lucky to have an advisor who is such a constant source of inspiration and support. Neither this dissertation nor I would be the same without her. Yopie Prins has shared her critical interventions and intellectual communities with me and encouraged the development of my own, expanding my sense of what is possible. Time and again, she has illuminated my scholarly endeavors, showing me how seemingly superfluous points of interest and obsession were actually crucial to my argument. Yopie encouraged experiments, organized ideas, and always saw the good. If my ideas have achieved elegance, they have done so under her watch. I am grateful to Adela Pinch for the constancy and clarity of her counsel. Adela provided an encouraging word when needed and an honest word always. She fostered critical openness, and her generous feedback and painstaking attention to detail fortified my writing process.
    [Show full text]
  • AUGUSTINE of HIPPO and HANNAH ARENDT Antonio Calcagno
    PARRHESIA NUMBER 13 • 2011 • 14-27 THE ROLE OF FORGETTING IN OUR EXPERIENCE OF TIME: AUGUSTINE OF HIPPO AND HANNAH ARENDT Antonio Calcagno Hannah Arendt’s work is deeply marked by a rich analysis of temporality. One finds references to it from her earliest works on Augustine of Hippo1 to her last major work, The Life of the Mind. Scholars have rightly explored the significance of temporality and its constitutive centrality for Arendt’s thought.2 Her views of temporality can be divided grosso modo along three axes. First, there is time-lived or the times-experienced, which comprise or touch upon such aspects as history, biography, narrative, and a timely engagement with the issues of the day, which include, for example, various moments in American Cold-War culture and civil-rights movements.3 Second, there is a sense of time understood as spontaneity, as natality, in which a new beginning is made possible today, hodiernus. Arising spontaneously, this time marks a new promise, as in the case of forgiveness.4 Perhaps we can call this the time of the kairos, the opportune time, the now-time that emerges from a set of circumstances but is not merely a result of a series of causal events. Finally, one finds in Arendt’s work a philosophical position on the very nature of time itself, understood as the past and the future that make possible the present, that condition the very existence of the human being. Particularly striking is the account of time that Arendt gives in the concluding parts of her work on “Thinking” in The Life of the Mind.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophical Approaches to Infinity: History, Ontology, Cosmology April
    Philosophical Approaches to Infinity: History, Ontology, Cosmology April 26th, 2019 The aim of this one-day symposium is to bring together an interdisciplinary group of scholars, largely from UCI, but also from off campus, to explore the philosophical issues associated with the concept of infinity in these diverse areas. We will have a dialogue between historians of philosophy, continental philosophers, philosophers and historians of science, literary scholars, and a scholar of science and religion. We have chosen the concept of infinity because of its significance in the formation of the Western modern vision of the world, its significance in contemporary (French) philosophy, and its significance and re- conceptualization in contemporary physics and philosophy of science. This is the fourth in a series of workshops that has been organized every spring by the Department of European Languages and Studies with the presence on campus of Prof. Catherine Malabou. Featuring: Peter Frei (European Languages and Studies, UCI) on infinity and Renaissance hermeneutics Catherine MalaBou (Philosophy, Kingston University; European Languages and Studies, UCI) on Descartes and Pascal Kenneth Reinhard (English and Comparative Literature, UCLA) on Badiou Mary-Jane RuBenstein (Religious Studies, Wesleyan) on God and the multiverse GaBriele SchwaB (Comparative Literature, UCI) on nuclear temporality John H. Smith (European Languages and Studies, UCI) on the infinitesimal psycho- physical difference James Weatherall (Philosophy and Logic of Science, UCI) on infinites space in General Relativity and cosmology Program: 9:00 – 9:15 Welcoming words (Coffee will be available.) 9:15 – 10:45 Peter Frei (European Languages and Studies, UCI) on infinity and Renaissance hermeneutics Catherine MalaBou (Philosophy, Kingston University; European Languages and Studies, UCI) on Descartes and Pascal 10:45 – 11:00 Coffee break 11:00 – 12:30 Kenneth Reinhard (English and Comparative Literature, UCLA) on Badiou John H.
    [Show full text]
  • 11. How Large Is Infinity?
    General Questions 25 • last expression, you need to divide a by a sequence bn with limit 0. But when a bn goes to zero, could go to +∞, if bn > 0, or to –∞, if bn < 0, or not exist bn a at all if bn alternates. Therefore, the expression must remain undefined. 0 Mathematicians call expressions like this “indeterminate forms.” In some cases, they can be thought of as having a certain value, while in other cases, as having another value or none at all. 11. HOW LARGE IS INFINITY? The first real opportunity where even young children can experience a “sense of wonder” in a mathematical context is when they make the basic observation that counting never ends. Typically, children are fascinated by very large numbers, and so was the 9-year-old Milton Sirotta, who became famous for inventing the name googol for the number 10100 in 1920. Later on, his uncle, the mathematician Edward Kasner (1878–1955), wrote about this in a book Mathematics and the Imagination, and still later, other imagi- native young fellows named their company Google after the number googol to indicate the large amount of data handled by Internet search engines. Although the number googol is already unimaginably large, we can eas- ily think of even larger numbers, for example, googol + 1 or 10googol (which has been called googolplex), or even the factorial of googol, or googolgoogol. The process of generating larger numbers from any given number obviously has no end. Therefore, the set of integers certainly cannot be finite. If it were, then there would be a largest number, which is impossible, because for any given number we can immediately find a bigger one just by adding 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz's Mathematical and Philosophical Approaches
    STUDIES IN LOGIC, GRAMMAR AND RHETORIC 4 (17) 2001 Witold Marciszewski University of Bia lystok LEIBNIZ’S MATHEMATICAL AND PHILOSOPHICAL APPROACHES TO ACTUAL INFINITY A CASE OF CULTURAL RESISTANCE The notion of cultural resistance, as introduced by Raymond L. Wilder in his treatment of the history of mathematics, is a reliable guide in any pursuit of the history of ideas. A trouble which afflicts historians of ideas is that they find inconsistencies where a perfect logic is expected, to wit with great thinkers. However, after a while of reflexion, rather something contrary to that should be expected, if a cultural resistance is taken into account. Let us dwell a while on that phenomenon. 1. Creative thought and cultural resistance 1.1. Greatness of one’s creative thought consists in surpassing the bounds of that cultural system in which one happened to be born and to live. But even the greatest mind is no supernatural being that would be able to easily overcome such confines. There must ever arise a tension between the existing paradigm and the drive of new original visions being characteristic of a genuine philosopher. This is a struggle which cannot end without victims, that is, uncertainties, changes of mind, even inconsistencies in the output of any original thinker. Thus, what a philosopher’s contemporaries firmly believe has to affect his mind, even most original and bold. Moreover, not only the beliefs which a philosopher encounters in the time he lives modify his original vision. There is even a more important factor, namely the invincible ignorance shared by him with his contemporaries.
    [Show full text]