U.S. Constitution--1996 Supplement

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

U.S. Constitution--1996 Supplement This publication supplements Senate Document 103±6, The Constitution of the United States of America: Analysis and InterpretationÐit should be inserted in the pocket on the inside back cover of that volume 104TH CONGRESS DOCUMENT SENATE 2d Session No. 104±14 " ! THE CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA ANALYSIS AND INTERPRETATION 1996 SUPPLEMENT ANALYSIS OF CASES DECIDED BY THE SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES TO JULY 1, 1996 PREPARED BY THE CONGRESSIONAL RESEARCH SERVICE LIBRARY OF CONGRESS JOHNNY H. KILLIAN GEORGE A. COSTELLO KENNETH R. THOMAS EDITORS U.S. GOVERNMENT PRINTING OFFICE 22±725 CC WASHINGTON : 1997 For sale by the Superintendent of Documents, U.S. Government Printing Office Washington, DC 20402 ARTICLE I Delegation [P. 78, add to text following n.79:] The infirm state of the nondelegation doctrine was dem- onstrated further in Loving v. United States. 1 Article 118 of the Uniform Code of Military Justice (UCMJ) 2 provides for the death penalty for premedicated murder and felony murder for persons subject to the Act, but the statute does not comport with the Court's capital punishment jurisprudence, which requires the death sentence to be cabined by standards so that the sentencing author- ity is constrained to narrow the class of convicted persons to be so sentenced and to justify the individual imposition of the sentence. 3 However, the President in 1984 had promulgated standards that purported to supply the constitutional validity the UCMJ needed. 4 The Court held that Congress could delegate to the President the authority to prescribe standards for the imposition of the death penaltyÐCongress' power under Article I, § 8, cl. 14, is not exclu- siveÐand that Congress had done so in the UCMJ by providing that the punishment imposed by a court-martial may not exceed ``such limits as the President may prescribe.'' 5 Acknowledging that a delegation must contain some ``intelligible principle'' to guide the recipient of the delegation, the Court nonetheless held this not to be true when the delegation was made to the President in his role as Commander-in-Chief. ``The same limitations on delegation do not apply'' if the entity authorized to exercise delegated authority itself possesses independent authority over the subject matter. The President's responsibilities as Commander-in-Chief require him to superintend the military, including the courts-martial, and thus the delegated duty is interlinked with duties already assigned the President by the Constitution. 6 In the course of the opinion, the Court distinguished between its usual separation-of-powers doctrineÐemphasizing arrogation of power by a branch and impairment of another branch's ability to carry out its functionsÐand the delegation doctrine, ``another 1 116 S. Ct. 1737 (1996). The decision was unanimous in result, but there were several concurrences reflecting some differences among the Justices. 2 10 U.S.C. §§ 918(1), (4). 3 The Court assumed the applicability of Furman v. Georgia, 408 U.S. 238 (1972), and its progeny, to the military, 116 S. Ct. at 1742, a point on which Justice Thomas disagreed, id. at 1753. 4 Rule for Courts-Martial; see 116 S. Ct. at 1740, 1741±42. 5 10 U.S.C. §§ 818, 836(a), 856. 6 116 S. Ct. at 1750±51. 1 2 ARTICLE IÐLEGISLATIVE DEPARTMENT branch of our separation of powers jurisdiction,'' which is informed not by the arrogation and impairment analyses but solely by the provision of standards, 7 thus confirming what has long been evi- dent that the delegation doctrine is unmoored to separation-of-pow- ers principles altogether. Qualifications of Members of Congress [P. 111, add to n.297:] Powell's continuing validity was affirmed in U.S. Term Limits, Inc. v. Thornton, 514 U.S. 779 (1995), both by the Court in its holding that the qualifications set out in the Constitution are exclusive and may not be added to by either Congress or the States, id. at 787±98, and by the dissent, who would hold that Congress, for dif- ferent reasons, could not add to qualifications, although the States could. Id. at 875± 76. [P. 114, add to text following n.312:] The long-debated issue whether the States could add to the qualifications that the Constitution prescribed for Senators and Representations was finally resolved, by a surprisingly close vote, in U.S. Term Limits, Inc. v. Thornton. 8 Arkansas, along with twen- ty-two other States, all but two by citizen initiatives, had imposed maximum numbers of terms that Members of Congress could serve. In this case, the Court held that the Constitution's qualifications clauses 9 establish exclusive qualifications for Members that may not be added to either by Congress or the States. The four-Justice dissent argued that while Congress had no power to increase quali- fications, the States did. Richly embellished with disputatious arguments about the text of the Constitution, the history of its drafting and ratification, and the practices of Congress and the States in the early years of the United States, the actual determination of the Court as con- troverted by the dissent was much more over founding principles than more ordinary constitutional interpretation. 10 Thus, the Court and the dissent drew different conclusions from the text of the qualifications clauses and the other clauses re- 7 Id. at 1743±44. 8 514 U.S. 779 (1995). The majority was composed of Justice Stevens (writing the opinion of the Court) and Justices Kennedy, Souter, Ginsburg, and Breyer. Dis- senting were Justice Thomas (writing the opinion) and Chief Justice Rehnquist and Justices O'Connor and Scalia. Id. at 845. 9 Article I, § 2, cl. 2, provides that a person may qualify as a Representative if she is at least 25 years old, has been a United States citizen for at least 7 years, and is an inhabitant, at the time of the election, of the State in which she is chosen. The qualifications established for Senators, Article I, § 3, cl. 3, are an age of 30 years, nine years citizenship, and an inhabitant of the State. 10 See Sullivan, Dueling Sovereignties: U.S. Term Limits, Inc. v. Thornton, 109 HARV. L. REV. 78 (1995). ARTICLE IÐLEGISLATIVE DEPARTMENT 3 specting the elections of Members of Congress; the Court and the dissent reached different conclusions after a minute examination of the records of the Convention respecting the drafting of these clauses and the ratification debates; and the Court and the dissent were far apart on the meaning of the practices in the States in leg- islating qualifications and election laws and in Congress in decid- ing election contests based on qualifications disputes. A default principle relied on by both Court and dissent, given the arguments drawn from text, creation, and practice, had to do with the fundamental principle at the foundation of the Constitu- tion's founding. In the dissent's view, the Constitution was the re- sult of the resolution of the peoples of the separate States to create the National Government. The conclusion to be drawn from this was that the peoples in the States agreed to surrender powers ex- pressly forbidden them and to surrender those limited powers that they had delegated to the Federal Government expressly or by nec- essary implication. They retained all other powers and still re- tained them. Thus, ``where the Constitution is silent about the ex- ercise of a particular powerÐthat is, where the Constitution does not speak either expressly or by necessary implicationÐthe Federal Government lacks that power and the States enjoy it.'' 11 The con- stitution's silence about the States being limited meant that the States could legislate additional qualifications. Radically different were the views of the majority of the Court. After the adoption of the Constitution, the States had two kinds of powers: powers that they had before the founding and that were re- served to them. The States could have no reserved powers with re- spect to the Federal Government. ``As Justice Story recognized, `the states can exercise no powers whatsoever, which exclusively spring out of the existence of the national government, which the constitu- tion does not delegate to them. No state can say, that it has reserved, what it never possessed.' '' 12 The States could not before the founding have possessed powers to legislate respecting the Fed- eral Government, and since the Constitution did not delegate to the States the power to prescribe qualifications for Members of Con- gress, the States did not have it. 13 Evidently, the opinions in this case reflect more than a deci- sion on this particular dispute. They rather represent conflicting philosophies within the Court respecting the scope of national power in the context of the States, an issue at the core of many controversies today. 11 514 U.S. at 848 (Justice Thomas dissenting). See generally id. at 846±65. 12 Id. at 802. 13 Id. at 798±805. And see id. at 838±45 (Justice Kennedy concurring). 4 ARTICLE IÐLEGISLATIVE DEPARTMENT [P. 115, add to n.317:] Another census controversy was resolved in Wisconsin v. City of New York, 116 S. Ct. 1091 (1996), in which the Court held that the decision of the Secretary of Commerce not to conduct a post-enumeration survey and statistical adjustment for an undercount in the 1990 Census was reasonable and within the bounds of discre- tion conferred by the Constitution and statute. Commerce Clause [P. 207, add to text following n.820:] For the first time in almost sixty years, 14 the Court invali- dated a federal law as exceeding Congress' authority under the commerce clause. 15 The statute was a provision making it a federal offense to possess a firearm within 1,000 feet of a school.
Recommended publications
  • <I>United States V. Morrison</I>
    University of Pennsylvania Carey Law School Penn Law: Legal Scholarship Repository Faculty Scholarship at Penn Law 2015 Bait and Switch: Why United States v. Morrison is Wrong about Section Five Kermit Roosevelt III University of Pennsylvania Carey Law School Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.upenn.edu/faculty_scholarship Part of the Civil Rights and Discrimination Commons, Constitutional Law Commons, Courts Commons, Fourteenth Amendment Commons, Jurisprudence Commons, and the Public Law and Legal Theory Commons Repository Citation Roosevelt, Kermit III, "Bait and Switch: Why United States v. Morrison is Wrong about Section Five" (2015). Faculty Scholarship at Penn Law. 748. https://scholarship.law.upenn.edu/faculty_scholarship/748 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Penn Law: Legal Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship at Penn Law by an authorized administrator of Penn Law: Legal Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. \\jciprod01\productn\C\CRN\100-3\CRN302.txt unknown Seq: 1 18-MAR-15 8:28 BAIT AND SWITCH: WHY UNITED STATES V. MORRISON IS WRONG ABOUT SECTION 5 Kermit Roosevelt III† In United States v. Morrison, the Supreme Court announced the rule that the Section 5 power cannot be used to regulate private individuals. This is one of the most meaningful and, thus far, durable constraints that the Court has placed on federal power. It is the more surprising, then, that it turns out to be based on essentially nothing at all. The Morrison Court asserted that its rule was derived by—indeed, “controlled by”—precedent, but a closer reading of the Reconstruction-era decisions it cites shows that this is simply not the case.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Judicial Independence Fails
    Copyright 2021 by Aziz Z. Huq Printed in U.S.A. Vol. 115, No. 4 WHY JUDICIAL INDEPENDENCE FAILS Aziz Z. Huq ABSTRACT—Judicial independence seems under siege. President Trump condemns federal courts for their political bias; his erstwhile presidential opponents mull various court-packing plans; and courts, in turn, are lambasted for abandoning a long-held constitutional convention against institutional manipulation. At the same time, across varied lines of jurisprudence, the Roberts Court evinces a deep worry about judicial independence. This preoccupation with threats to judicial independence infuses recent opinions on administrative deference, bankruptcy, patent adjudication, and jurisdiction-stripping. Yet the Court has not offered a single, overarching definition of what it means by the term “judicial independence.” Nor has it explained how its disjointed doctrinal interventions add up to a coherent theory of institutional autonomy. And it remains unclear how debates on judicial independence among jurists relate to debates about the same term in the larger public sphere. This Article’s first contribution is to analyze how the Roberts Court understands the term judicial independence and how its doctrinal rules fall far short of realizing even the aspirations the Court has for that term. This case study in doctrinal specification illuminates the gap between the Justices’ own ethical aspiration toward judicial independence and its institutional realization—a gap that generates confusion, uncertainty, and opportunities for circumvention. This Article then abstracts away from the particulars of the Roberts Court’s jurisprudence to explore the origins of this aspiration– implementation gap. To motivate this more general analysis, it first demonstrates that there is a large range of constitutional-design options for a founder seeking to create independent courts.
    [Show full text]
  • Piercing the Surface of Commerce Clause Doctrine
    University of Pennsylvania Carey Law School Penn Law: Legal Scholarship Repository Faculty Scholarship at Penn Law 2004 Guillen and Gullibility: Piercing the Surface of Commerce Clause Doctrine Mitchell N. Berman University of Pennsylvania Carey Law School Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.upenn.edu/faculty_scholarship Part of the Conflict of Laws Commons, Constitutional Law Commons, Courts Commons, Legal History Commons, Legal Theory Commons, and the State and Local Government Law Commons Repository Citation Berman, Mitchell N., "Guillen and Gullibility: Piercing the Surface of Commerce Clause Doctrine" (2004). Faculty Scholarship at Penn Law. 1471. https://scholarship.law.upenn.edu/faculty_scholarship/1471 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Penn Law: Legal Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship at Penn Law by an authorized administrator of Penn Law: Legal Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Guillen and Gullibility: Piercing the Surface of Commerce Clause Doctrine Mitchell N. Berman* INTRODUCTION ................................................................................................1489 I. THE CASE ..............................................................................................1492 A. THE FACTS......................................................................................1492 B. THE WASHINGTON SUPREME COURT INVALIDATES THE ACT .............1493 C. THE UNITED STATES
    [Show full text]
  • Prophylactic Rules and State Constitutionalism Arthur Leavens Western New England University School of Law, [email protected]
    Western New England University School of Law Digital Commons @ Western New England University School of Law Faculty Scholarship Faculty Publications 2011 Prophylactic Rules and State Constitutionalism Arthur Leavens Western New England University School of Law, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.law.wne.edu/facschol Part of the Constitutional Law Commons Recommended Citation 44 Suffolk U. L. Rev. 415 (2011) This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Publications at Digital Commons @ Western New England University School of Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ Western New England University School of Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Prophylactic Rules and State Constitutionalism 1 Arthur Leavens ABSTRACT When the post-Warren Supreme Court began trimming back individual rights, some state courts responded by interpreting analogous or cognate state- constitutional provisions to find broader protections, prompting a vigorous debate concerning the legitimacy and interpretive methodology of such state constitutionalism. How can two constitutional provisions, sharing the same language and history, mean different things? This article looks at that question in the context of so-called prophylactic rules—those specific constitutional rules meant to guide the implementation of broader federal constitutional principles. Miranda’s warning-and-waiver construct is probably the best known prophylactic rule, but such rules abound, particularly in criminal procedure. This article argues that even if states ought to defer to the Supreme Court concerning the meaning of cognate constitutional provisions, such deference is not required in considering the reach of prophylactic rules.
    [Show full text]
  • The Surprisingly Strong Case for Tailoring Constitutional Principles
    THE SURPRISINGLY STRONG CASE FOR TAILORING CONSTITUTIONAL PRINCIPLES † MARK D. ROSEN INTRODUCTION................................................................................... 1515 I. ONE-SIZE-FITS-ALL AND TAILORING IDENTIFIED............................. 1523 A. A Simple Jurisprudential Model.................................................1524 B. Four Approaches to Constitutionally Limiting the Different Levels of Government ..............................................................1527 1. Different Levels, Different Constitutional Principles: The Example of “Fundamental Fairness”............................ 1528 2. Total Incorporation............................................................... 1532 3. Selective Incorporation......................................................... 1534 4. Tailoring: A Variant of Selective Incorporation ................. 1536 C. One-Size-Fits-All Outside of the Fourteenth Amendment .................1538 II. THE (ULTIMATELY) PRAGMATIC GROUNDS FOR ONE-SIZE-FITS-ALL ....................................................................... 1541 A. The Disappointing Search for a Justification................................1542 B. The “Watering-Down” Thesis and the Structure of Rights...............1545 C. Plausible Justifications for Selective Incorporation and Their Relation to One-Size-Fits-All .............................................1553 1. Limiting Judicial Discretion.................................................. 1554 2. Judicial Administration ........................................................
    [Show full text]
  • ROPER V. SIMMONS
    (Slip Opinion) OCTOBER TERM, 2004 1 Syllabus NOTE: Where it is feasible, a syllabus (headnote) will be released, as is being done in connection with this case, at the time the opinion is issued. The syllabus constitutes no part of the opinion of the Court but has been prepared by the Reporter of Decisions for the convenience of the reader. See United States v. Detroit Timber & Lumber Co., 200 U. S. 321, 337. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES Syllabus ROPER, SUPERINTENDENT, POTOSI CORREC- TIONAL CENTER v. SIMMONS CERTIORARI TO THE SUPREME COURT OF MISSOURI No. 03–633. Argued October 13, 2004—Decided March 1, 2005 At age 17, respondent Simmons planned and committed a capital mur- der. After he had turned 18, he was sentenced to death. His direct appeal and subsequent petitions for state and federal postconviction relief were rejected. This Court then held, in Atkins v. Virginia, 536 U. S. 304, that the Eighth Amendment, applicable to the States through the Fourteenth Amendment, prohibits the execution of a mentally retarded person. Simmons filed a new petition for state postconviction relief, arguing that Atkins’ reasoning established that the Constitution prohibits the execution of a juvenile who was under 18 when he committed his crime. The Missouri Supreme Court agreed and set aside Simmons’ death sentence in favor of life impris- onment without eligibility for release. It held that, although Stan- ford v. Kentucky, 492 U. S. 361, rejected the proposition that the Con- stitution bars capital punishment for juvenile offenders younger than 18, a national consensus has developed against the execution of those offenders since Stanford.
    [Show full text]
  • Backdoor Balancing Elizabeth Earle Beske
    Washington Law Review Volume 94 | Number 2 6-1-2019 Backdoor Balancing Elizabeth Earle Beske Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.law.uw.edu/wlr Part of the Supreme Court of the United States Commons Recommended Citation Elizabeth E. Beske, Backdoor Balancing, 94 Wash. L. Rev. 645 (2019). Available at: https://digitalcommons.law.uw.edu/wlr/vol94/iss2/4 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Reviews and Journals at UW Law Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Washington Law Review by an authorized editor of UW Law Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 06 - Beske (2).docx (Do Not Delete) 6/18/2019 7:57 PM BACKDOOR BALANCING AND THE CONSEQUENCES OF LEGAL CHANGE Elizabeth Earle Beske* Abstract: The U.S. Supreme Court has employed various mechanisms to blunt the systemic impact of legal change. The Warren Court balanced the interests advanced by new rules against the disruption of their retroactive application and frequently limited new rules to prospective effect. The Rehnquist Court decisively rejected this approach in the mid-1990s and committed itself to full adjudicative retroactivity as to pending cases. This Article argues that, although the Court slammed a door, it subsequently opened a window. The Court has spent the intervening decades devising ostensibly independent and unrelated doctrines to mitigate disruption. Despite the Rehnquist Court’s insistence that these doctrines do not relate to retroactivity, they reflect the same balance and, in almost every case, yield the same results as Warren-era balancing.
    [Show full text]
  • Constitutional Theory for Criminal Procedure: Dickerson, Miranda, and the Continuing Quest for Broad-But-Shallow
    William & Mary Law Review Volume 43 (2001-2002) Issue 1 Article 5 October 2001 Constitutional Theory for Criminal Procedure: Dickerson, Miranda, and the Continuing Quest for Broad-but-shallow Donald A. Dripps Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/wmlr Part of the Criminal Procedure Commons, and the Supreme Court of the United States Commons Repository Citation Donald A. Dripps, Constitutional Theory for Criminal Procedure: Dickerson, Miranda, and the Continuing Quest for Broad-but-shallow, 43 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 1 (2001), https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/wmlr/vol43/iss1/5 Copyright c 2001 by the authors. This article is brought to you by the William & Mary Law School Scholarship Repository. https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/wmlr William and Mary Law Review VOLUME 43 No. 1, 2001 CONSTITUTIONAL THEORY FOR CRIMINAL PROCEDURE: DICKERSON,MIRANDA, AND THE CONTINUING QUEST FOR BROAD-BUT-SHALLOW DONALD A. DRIPPS* The very first paragraph of the Supreme Court's much-awaited decision in Dickerson v. United States1 declares that Miranda v. Arizona,2 being a constitutional decision of this Court, may not be in effect overruled by an Act of Congress, and we decline to overrule Miranda ourselves. We therefore hold that Miranda and its progeny in this Court govern the admissibility of statements made during custodial interrogation in both state and federal courts.3 One might suppose that such a simple reaffirmation of the status quo would call for little scholarly comment. In the context of constitutional criminal procedure in general, and of Miranda in particular, however, there is nothing simple about reaffirming the status quo.
    [Show full text]
  • Separation of Powers Or Separation of Personnel , 79 Cornell L
    Cornell Law Review Volume 79 Article 1 Issue 5 July 1994 One Person One Office:ep S aration of Powers or Separation of Personnel Steven G. Calabresi Joan L. Larsen Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.cornell.edu/clr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Steven G. Calabresi and Joan L. Larsen, One Person One Office: Separation of Powers or Separation of Personnel , 79 Cornell L. Rev. 1045 (1994) Available at: http://scholarship.law.cornell.edu/clr/vol79/iss5/1 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at Scholarship@Cornell Law: A Digital Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Cornell Law Review by an authorized administrator of Scholarship@Cornell Law: A Digital Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. ONE PERSON, ONE OFFICE: SEPARATION OF POWERS OR SEPARATION OF PERSONNEL? Steven G. Calabres4 and Joan L. Larsent "The accumulation of all powers, legislative, executive, and judici- ary, in the same hands ... whether hereditary, self-appointed, or elec- tive, may justly be pronounced the very definition of tyranny."' TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION ................................................. 1047 I. BRITISH AND COLONIAL ANTECEDENTS TO THE INCOMPATIBILITY PRINCIPLE ................................ 1052 A. The British Background ............................... 1053 B. The State Constitutions and the Articles of Confederation ......................................... 1057 C. Summary of the Decisions at the Federal Convention ........................................... 1061 II. THE INCOMPATIBILITY CLAUSE .............................. 1062 A. The Original Meaning and Purpose of the Incompatibility Clause ................................. 1062 1. Text and Context .................................... 1062 2. Public Statements Contemporaneous With Ratification... 1065 3. Private Statements Made Prior to Ratification: The Convention Debates .................................
    [Show full text]
  • Constitutional Decision Rules
    University of Pennsylvania Carey Law School Penn Law: Legal Scholarship Repository Faculty Scholarship at Penn Law 2004 Constitutional Decision Rules Mitchell N. Berman University of Pennsylvania Carey Law School Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.upenn.edu/faculty_scholarship Part of the Conflict of Laws Commons, Constitutional Law Commons, Courts Commons, Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, Legal Commons, Legal History Commons, and the Legal Theory Commons Repository Citation Berman, Mitchell N., "Constitutional Decision Rules" (2004). Faculty Scholarship at Penn Law. 1468. https://scholarship.law.upenn.edu/faculty_scholarship/1468 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Penn Law: Legal Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship at Penn Law by an authorized administrator of Penn Law: Legal Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. BERMANBOOKALTERED.DOC 4/7/04 10:46 AM 2 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 90:1 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW VOLUME 90 MARCH 2004 NUMBER 1 ARTICLES CONSTITUTIONAL DECISION RULES Mitchell N. Berman* INTRODUCTION.................................................................................4 I. DICKERSON, MIRANDA, AND THE PROPHYLACTIC RULES DEBATE.....................................................................................17 A. The Miranda Controversy in a Nutshell ...............................18 B. Dickerson’s Failure to Resolve Miranda’s Status and Legitimacy ................................................................................22
    [Show full text]
  • Constitutional Law in an Age of Proportionality
    TH AL LAW JO RAL VICKI C. JACKSON Constitutional Law in an Age of Proportionality ABSTRACT. Proportionality, accepted as a general principle of constitutional law by many countries, requires that government intrusions on freedoms be justified, that greater intru- sions have stronger justifications, and that punishments reflect the relative severity of the of- fense. Proportionality as a doctrine developed by courts, as in Canada, has provided a stable methodological framework, promoting structured, transparent decisions even about closely con- tested constitutional values. Other benefits of proportionality include its potential to bring con- stitutional law closer to constitutional justice, to provide a common discourse about rights for all branches of government, and to help identify the kinds of failures in democratic process warrant- ing heightened judicial scrutiny. Earlier U.S. debates over "balancing" were not informed by re- cent comparative experience with structured proportionality doctrine and its benefits. Many areas of U.S. constitutional law include some elements of what is elsewhere called proportionality analysis. I argue here for greater use of proportionality principles and doctrine; I also argue that proportionality review is not the answer to all constitutional rights questions. Free speech can benefit from categorical presumptions, but in their application and design pro- portionality may be relevant. The Fourth Amendment, which secures a "right" against "unrea- sonable searches and seizures," is replete with categorical rules protecting police conduct from judicial review; more case-by-case analysis of the "unreasonableness" or disproportionality of police conduct would better protect rights and the rule of law. "Disparate impact" equality claims might be better addressed through more proportionate review standards; Eighth Amendment review of prison sentences would benefit from more use of proportionality principles.
    [Show full text]
  • Congressional Power to Enforce the Reconstruction Amendments A
    University of Cincinnati College of Law University of Cincinnati College of Law Scholarship and Publications Faculty Articles and Other Publications College of Law Faculty Scholarship 2010 The Pursuit of Perfection: Congressional Power to Enforce the Reconstruction Amendments A. Christopher Bryant University of Cincinnati College of Law, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.uc.edu/fac_pubs Part of the Civil Rights and Discrimination Commons, Constitutional Law Commons, Election Law Commons, and the Fourteenth Amendment Commons Recommended Citation A. Christopher Bryant, The urP suit of Perfection: Congressional Power to Enforce the Reconstruction Amendments, 47 Hous. L. Rev. 579 (2010) This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Law Faculty Scholarship at University of Cincinnati College of Law Scholarship and Publications. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Articles and Other Publications by an authorized administrator of University of Cincinnati College of Law Scholarship and Publications. For more information, please contact [email protected]. ARTICLE THE PURSUIT OF PERFECTION: CONGRESSIONAL POWER TO ENFORCE THE RECONSTRUCTION AMENDMENTS A. ChristopherBryant* ABSTRACT In June 2009 the Supreme Court avoided a decision on the constitutionality of the Voting Rights Act's preclearance requirement, while at the same time managing to foreshadow that provision's ultimate demise. In a separate opinion, Justice Thomas announced that he would have reached the issue
    [Show full text]