1 Introduction 2 What Is Logical Space?

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

1 Introduction 2 What Is Logical Space? Notes 1 Introduction 1. The term (logischer Raum in German) “originates in Boltzmann’s general- ized thermodynamics, which treats the independent properties of a physical system as defining separate coordinates in a multidimensional system the points of which constitute the ‘ensemble of possible states’” (Hans-Johann Glock 1996: 220). 2. One might object here (as, indeed, an anonymous referee did during the book proposal submission stage) that recent speculative theories in physics, like Max Tegmark’s mathematical universe (or great ensemble theory), and, more generally, multiverse theories are examples of scientists dealing with logical space at the most fundamental level. However, this objection is misguided. The multiverse is not the same as a logical space; the multiverse is a hypoth- esis about the actual world, namely that it contains many spatio-temporally and causally disconnected universes. One can conceive of other worlds where there is no multiverse, but only one universe. This is obvious by the very fact that the multiverse is a hypothesis, which, for all we know, could be true or false. It must then be the case that there are open epistemic possibilities corresponding to whether the world is a multiverse or a universe. So the multiverse or the “great ensemble” is simply not enough to serve as a logical space. Also, there is virtually no discussion even in these highly speculative approaches in theoretical physics about the nature of modality, possible worlds, and so on. 3. Tractatus, 3.42: “A proposition can determine only one place in logical space: nevertheless the whole of logical space must already be given by it. (Otherwise negation, logical sum, logical product, etc., would introduce more and more new elements in co-ordination.)” 4. The original is “the mind and the world jointly make up the mind and the world”, and is a slogan for Putnam’s “Internal Realism”. See Putnam 1981: xi. 5. Although at the 2011 annual conference of the British Society for Philosophy of Religion, I learnt from Yujin Nagasawa that while I was working on this book, he was developing the very same view in a manuscript titled “Modal Panentheism”. I have read the paper and there are several ideas that I share with Yujin, and they are argued for in this book. 2 What Is Logical Space? 1. These examples were put forward to me as alleged counterexamples to logical totalitarianism by Ezgi Ulusoy Aranyosi and Ralf Bader. 2. This sentence was raised as a challenge to logical totalitarianism by Ilhan Inan. 181 182 Notes 3. The polarity of a state of affairs indicates whether the relations hold or not for the constituent objects. 4. Thus situation theory is also an alternative to the Fregean view that the semantic value (or reference) of a sentence is its truth-value. 5. To which the constraint of consistency is added, that is, that there is no world at which (P & ¬P) is true, thus the standard definition of “possible world” is that of a maximal consistent set of sentences (or propositions). 6. For details, see Zalta 1993. 3 “Life” in Logical Space 1. If unknowingly, for example because of split personality, you are writing a letter to yourself, then you are not a fictional character, so, again, the letter is self-undermining. 2. For the Russellian-Quinean the only truth about Pegasus is “Pegasus does not exist”, whereas Meinongians can assert sentences like “Pegasus is fictional”, “Pegasus is mythical”, and so on. This is one reason Meinongians fare better in accommodating the intuition that all these sentences are true or assertible. On the other hand, Meinongians would go further and also assert sentences like “Pegasus is a winged horse”, with respect to which, according to some philosophers, intuitions are indeterminate. 3. See Bernard Linsky and Ed Zalta 1991. 4. For a more elaborate treatment of this idea and, in my view, a devastating criticism of Routley’s claims to parsimony and novelty of his approach, see Lewis 1990b. 5. For the orthodox Russellian-Quinean view, see W.V.O. Quine 1948. For various Meinongian views, see Alexius Meinong (in Roderick Chisholm 1960), Routley 1980, Parsons 1980, and Zalta 1983. For Lewis’ view, see his 1986. 6. An exception is Takashi Yagisawa (2010), whose notion of existence at an index can be relative to a domain, to a time, to a place, and to a world. The relativity I propose here, as well as the argument for it, are different from Yagisawa’s. 7. As Jaakko Hintikka (1962) has pointed out, the argument is not really an inference in the classical sense, but a performance, that is we are supposed to perform its steps on ourselves in order to realize its force and soundness. 8. The fallacy is to deduce some proposition P from [(P implies Q) and P]. 9. Several people insisted, whenever I presented these ideas at various confer- ences, that if we are real, then we are not fictional, as a matter of analysis (for instance, Howard Robinson, Nick Effingham, and others). I disagree. In light of my arguments presented above, the notion of fictionality is also a rela- tive one. And so is that of reality. For instance, Sherlock Holmes is fictional relative to our world, but real relative to the world our fiction depicts him as being present in. There is also a related criticism or proposal, namely, that an object is fictional only if it is an actual nonconcrete object. My notion of Logical Space, of course, allows such a view, that is, such a view has a place in some logical region, but it is not a constraint on that space at all. Sherlock Holmes is a bona fide object in virtue of its so-sein. At a logical region that depicts Sherlock Holmes as a nonconcrete object (which means that it does not Notes 183 instantiate properties like being a detective, being smart, and so on), Holmes’ so-sein is perhaps the set of properties: {being nonconcrete, encoding the property of being a detective, encoding the property of being smart, and so on}. Although the first of these properties are, for Meinongians, paradigmatic extranuclear properties, and all of them except the first one are also higher-order, the notion of Logical Space and the doctrine of Logicalism proposed here makes it the case that they are all treated on a par, as nuclear, or so-sein making properties. 10. Meinong also posited such objects as inhabitants of his ontology. Objects of intentional states as well as certain uınderspecified, generic objects such as “the triangle”, are in this category. For Meinong these objects are determined by the properties that explicitly figure in their depiction. So the triangle is an incomplete object determined by triangularity, the isosceles triangle is determined by triangularity and being isosceles. 11. This is not to say that whenever two expressions have the same sense, the identity statement that they flank is trivial; a counterexample is the case of synonyms, because arguably an identity statement containing synonyms as its terms is not trivial, though it is a priori knowable. 12. One could object that, still, it is because of Carew’s knowledge and verbal dispositions dependent on it that substitution fails. However, it is not true that Carew would accept “Dr. Jekyll is trustworthy and friendly” and reject “Mr. Hyde is trustworthy and friendly”; he simply has no knowledge or any attitude towards the propositions regarding Dr. Jekyll and Mr. Hyde. 13. I adopt here what Thomas MacKay and Michael Nelson (2010) regard as the metaphysical conception of de re attitude. See their article for the syntactic and the semantic conception. 14. There is actually more to it, in this particular case, than the fact that the objects are named as they are, namely, the name “Superman” connotes some property like being a superior human, or something similar. To assert that it is only the way they are named that is relevant to attitude ascriptions involving some intentional objects appears to be liable to the criticism Frege – in the first paragraph of “On sense and reference” – adduced against the view that identity is to be understood as a relation between signs, which wouldn’t explain the informativeness of some identities. 15. I owe the phrase “gentrification of logical space” to Nicholas Silins. 4 Folded Logical Space 1. The notion of the definition of a situation would come to play a funda- mental theoretical role in a very influential school of thought in sociology and anthropology – Symbolic Interactionism – with applications in various subfields of these disciplines. George Herbert Mead, a key theorist of symbolic interactionism, who was a colleague of Thomas at the University of Chicago, expressed a thesis similar to the Thomas Theorem: “If a thing is not recog- nized as true, then it does not function as true in the community” (Mead 1936: 29). 2. The case that Merton made popular, namely, the self-fulfilling prophecy, implies or requires, therefore, strictly speaking, more than what the Thomas 184 Notes Theorem does. It requires not only that what is defined as real be real in its consequences, but also that it become real per se, or real in its causes. Another such example of something becoming real per se as a result of people defining it as real is the entity we call “nation”. Benedict Anderson’s seminal book on nationalism (1983) makes this clear when Anderson asserts that although the nation is an imagined community, it does not mean that it is fabricated (1983: 6); by being imagined by a sufficiently high number of otherwise spatially disconnected people who never get a chance in their lives to interact face-to-face, the nation comes to be realized, or comes into existence.
Recommended publications
  • A Developed Dynamic Reference Work
    The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: A Developed Dynamic Reference Work Colin Allen∗ Philosophy Department Texas A&M University Uri Nodelman† Computer Science Department Stanford University Edward N. Zalta‡ Center for the Study of Language and Information Stanford University 1 Introduction A fundamental problem faced by the general public and the members of an academic discipline in the information age is how to find the most author- itative, comprehensive, and up-to-date information about an important topic. The present information explosion is the source of this problem— more ideas than ever before are being published in print, on CD-ROM, and in a variety of forms on the Internet. One can nowadays use library search engines and web-indexing engines to generate lists of publications and websites about a topic and then access them immediately if they are ∗Professor of Philosophy at Texas A&M University, Principal Programmer and Associate Editor of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy †Graduate Student in Computer Science at Stanford University, Associate Pro- grammer and Assistant Editor of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy ‡Senior Research Scholar at Stanford University, Project Director and Principal Editor of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 1 online. But even limited area search engines can produce thousands of matches to keywords and even with new interface tools to narrow the search, one is typically confronted with a list that is not informed by hu- man judgment. If one wants an introduction to a topic that is organized by an expert, if one wants a summary of the current state of research, or if one wants a bibliography of print and online works that has been filtered on the basis of informed human judgment, there are few places to turn.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy Reading List ______
    Philosophy Reading List _________________________________________ INTRODUCTION We are delighted that you are joining us in the Philosophy Faculty this Autumn. A few ideas for exploratory Summer reading meanwhile: • Simon Blackburn, Think (1999) • Edward Craig, Philosophy: A Very Short Introduction (2002) • Bernard Williams, Morality: An Introduction to Ethics (1972) • Daniel C. Dennett, Intuition Pumps and Other Tools for Thinking (2013) • René Descartes, Meditations on First Philosophy, ed. J. Cottingham (1641) • David Hume, An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding (1748) • J. L. Mackie, Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong (1977) • Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, The Communist Manifesto (1848) • J. S. Mill, On Liberty (1869); The Subjection of Women (1869) • Thomas Nagel, Mortal Questions (1979) • Friedrich Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morality, ed. M. Clark and A. Swensen (1887) Plato, The Last Days of Socrates ed. Tredennick (Penguin Classics) • Graham Priest, Logic: A Very Short Introduction (2000) • Bertrand Russell, The Problems of Philosophy (1912) • Michael Sandel, Justice: What’s the Right Thing to Do? (2009) • Jonathan Wolff, An Introduction to Political Philosophy (1996) See below for links to online philosophy encyclopedia, commentary, and podcasts. Our advice is to follow your interests and keep in mind that one often gets more from close- reading a single work than from skimming several. If you have questions or would like more guidance for a specific topic, please don’t hesitate to email me ([email protected]).
    [Show full text]
  • Download (548Kb)
    Original citation: Vanzo, Alberto (2015) Christian Wolff and experimental philosophy. In: Garber , Daniel and Rutherford, Donald , (eds.) Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy, Volume VII. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 225-255. ISBN 9780198748717 Permanent WRAP URL: http://wrap.warwick.ac.uk/78577 Copyright and reuse: The Warwick Research Archive Portal (WRAP) makes this work by researchers of the University of Warwick available open access under the following conditions. Copyright © and all moral rights to the version of the paper presented here belong to the individual author(s) and/or other copyright owners. To the extent reasonable and practicable the material made available in WRAP has been checked for eligibility before being made available. Copies of full items can be used for personal research or study, educational, or not-for profit purposes without prior permission or charge. Provided that the authors, title and full bibliographic details are credited, a hyperlink and/or URL is given for the original metadata page and the content is not changed in any way. Publisher’s statement: Christian Wolff and Experimental Philosophy, by Alberto Vanzo, in Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy, VII (2015), pp. 225-255 edited by Daniel Garber and Donald Rutherford, 2015, reproduced by permission of Oxford University http://oxfordindex.oup.com/view/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198748717.003.0007#fullTextLi nks For more information, please contact the WRAP Team at: [email protected] warwick.ac.uk/lib-publications Alberto Vanzo Christian Wolff and Experimental Philosophy Published in Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy , vol. 7, edited by Daniel Garber and Donald Rutherford, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015, pp.
    [Show full text]
  • Research Guide to Philosophy
    Research Guide to Philosophy John M. Kelly Library University of St. Michael’s College MULTI-VOLUME ENCYCLOPEDIAS CONTENTS Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by Edward Craig. London: Routledge, 1998. 10 volumes. Multi –Volume Encyclopedias 1 [Available online for UofT use: http://www.library.utoronto.ca] General Dictionaries and Handbooks 2 [Print version: St. Michael's 1st Floor Reference Area – B 51 .R68 1998] Branches of Philosophy - Dictionaries & Handbooks 3 The definitive English-language philosophy encyclopedia. Over 2,000 Summaries 5 articles – thematic, biographical, and national – ranging from 500 to Manuals 5 15,000 words in length, written by over 1,200 renowned authors from Finding Journal Articles 6 around the world. Bibliographies 6 Web Guides 7 The Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2nd ed. Edited by Donald M. Borchert. Detroit: Macmillan Reference, 2006. 10 volumes. Associations 7 [Available online for UofT use: http://www.library.utoronto.ca] [Victoria Pratt and Trinity Graham, Reference Area – B 41 .E53 2006] Over 2100 lengthy articles with extensive bibliographies on every aspect of Eastern and Western philosophy, ancient, medieval, and modern. The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy [Available online: http://www.iep.utm.edu] Almost 500 peer-reviewed articles contributed by professional philosophers or graduate students. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy [Available online: http://plato.stanford.edu/] Peer-reviewed articles contributed by professional philosophers. New Catholic Encyclopedia. 2nd edition. Washington, DC: Gale, 2003. 15 volumes + annual supplements. [Available online for UofT use: http://www.library.utoronto.ca] [St. Michael’s 1st Floor Reference Area – BX 841 .N44 2003] The major English-language encyclopedia on Catholic topics. There is an article entitled “Philosophy, Articles on” which provides an overview of the encyclopedia’s philosophical content and identifies several hundred entries relating to philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Read Philosophy?
    1 (Meta-Philosophy) Why read philosophy? (of original and –creative thinking rather than derivative, academic, professional philosophers) Ulrich de Balbian Director Meta-philosophy Research Center 1 Bereft of all feeling, deprived of all passion, devoid of sense, robbed of its humanity and stripped of any humaneness ‘philosophy’ had become when in the hands of mostly anglo-saxon, so-called analytic ‘philosophers’ and mostly white, male, seemingly confused, elderly , ‘continental ‘philosophers. The passion that drives the thinker through the Socratic questioning are forgotten and the slight glimpse of a vision of the golden dawn now and then revealed in Heidegger by the lover of wisdom are replaced by pseudo-logic aspirations and sterile mathematical notions of those who produce an infinity of peer reviewed articles and endless writings to fulfil the contract of their tenure as paid, professional thinkers who must produce on the academic assembly-line of living off ‘philosophy’. We are left we the bare bones of semantics expressed by the semiotics that are reflected by the norms of reasoning and some form of, usually informal, logic. Why do philosophy, why grasp, approach and ring out the blood from almost anything, any thing, any thought, and why read every word and grasp its wrestling for meaning with the philosopher who tears them out of his heart, cleansed by his mind, why try to tune in to his stream of consciousness in an attempt to share that what he tries to catch a fleeting glimpse of and express by means of ideas, words, concepts, phrase, propositions, statements and sentences? We read philosophy so as to tune into the life, the existence, the passion, the fear, the dread, the occasional delight and happiness felt by the thinker wrestling all day and all night, like Jacob, with THE ONE.
    [Show full text]
  • Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
    Name of the Tool Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Home Page Logo URL http://plato.stanford.edu/ Subject Philosophy - Encyclopedias Accessibility Free Language English Publisher Stanford University Brief History The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (SEP) project began in September 1995 when John Perry was the Director of the Center for the Study of Language and Information (CSLI). Perry's suggestion that CSLI enhance its web presence by creating a (static) online dictionary of philosophy was taken up by Edward N. Zalta, who developed the idea into that of a dynamic reference work. Zalta then started designing the SEP to be an online encyclopedia that would satisfy the highest academic standards. After two years of support from CSLI, the prototype became a proof of concept that earned the first of a series of successful grant applications. (See the History of Grants below.) The addition of Colin Allen and Uri Nodelman to the project in 1998 resulted in significant enhancements to the design and implementation of our new academic publishing model. They introduced browser-based file-upload, workflow principles that categorized the state of every entry and possible state transitions, remote HTML editing, an engine which compares an original and revised entry side-by-side in the browser with the differences highlighted, etc. Paul Daniell programmed/developed the new search engine that the SEP brought online in September 2006. The copyright date of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is 2015by The Metaphysics Research Lab, Center for the Study of Language and Information (CSLI), Stanford University. Scope and Coverage This encyclopedia includes various philosophical articles which covers various philosophical topics.
    [Show full text]
  • APA Grant Application in Support of the Public Philosophy Network
    APAGrantApplication insupportofthe PublicPhilosophyNetwork Submittedby EllenKFeder,Ph.D. AndrewLight,Ph.D. SharonM.Meagher,Ph.D. June29,2010 APASmallGrantApplication Overthelastfewyears,theAPAhasmadethepromotionofpublicphilosophyapriority.Thislastyeara groupofphilosophershasworkedtogethertoinvestigatequestionsconcerningthevalueofpublic philosophy.Inwhatwaysisphilosophy,whenengagedwithvariouspublics,transformative,i.e.,how canordoesphilosophyimprovepubliclife?Inwhatwaysisphilosophytransformedwhenengagedwith variouspublics,i.e.,howdoes/mightpublicengagementinformphilosophicalconceptsand understandingand/oralterdisciplinaryboundaries?And,ifpublicphilosophyisvaluable—thenhow mightwepromoteandsustainitspractice?Howcanweinsurethehighestquality andmostethical practices? Thepurposeofthegrant: WeareapplyingforseedmoneytolaunchthePublicPhilosophyNetwork,anentityintendedtosupport andencourageawiderangeofprojectsofpubliclyengagedphilosophicalwork.Specifically,wewould usethemoneyfortwoprojects,theevaluationofatrialwebsiteandthehostingofaconferencein Washington,DC.Thewebsitewillfunctionasbothaclearinghouseofinformationonawiderangeof publicphilosophyprojectsandasaplacewherephilosopherscannetworkwithotherphilosopherswho sharesimilarinterestsandprojectsaswellaswithvarioussortsofpractitionerswhowishtocollaborate withthem.Theconferenceisnotaimedmerelyatpromotingdiscussion,butatputtinginstitutional supportsinplacenecessarytotheadvancementofpubliclyengagedphilosophywork. BackgroundonthePublicPhilosophyNetwork: ThePublicPhilosophyNetworkisanoutcomeofadayͲlongmeetingheldonpublicphilosophyasa
    [Show full text]
  • The Role of Imagination in Jean-Jacques Rousseau’S Emile: Or on Education and Christoph Martin Wieland’S Geschichte Des Agathon
    Where the Body touches the Spirit: the Role of Imagination in Jean-Jacques Rousseau’s Emile: or On Education and Christoph Martin Wieland’s Geschichte des Agathon by Andrea Marie Speltz Athesissubmittedtothe Department of Languages, Literatures and Cultures in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Queen’s University Kingston, Ontario, Canada October 2012 Copyright c Andrea Marie Speltz, 2012 Abstract This dissertation o↵ers a re-evaluation of the role of the imagination in Jean- Jacques Rousseau’s Emile: or On Education (1762) and Christoph Martin Wieland’s Geschichte des Agathon (1794). My central claim is that both novels develop a pedagogy of the imagination in order to overcome the dilemmas of Cartesian dualism, that is, to form a beautiful soul in whom sensuality and reason, the body and the spirit, coexist in harmony. I demonstrate that both texts highlight the important but potentially damaging role played by the imagination in the development of religious thought, moral sentiments, and sexuality. The texts suggest that while a malformed imagination results in materialism, egotism, libertinism, and despotism, a well-formed imagination provides the foundation for natural religion, cosmopolitan enthusiasm, sentimental love, and a just political constitution. Consequently, I argue that for Rousseau and Wieland, harnessing the power of the imagination becomes the key to reconciling human nature and civil society. In addition to elucidating the role of the imagination in Emile and Agathon, this dissertation also contributes to an understanding of the intellectual affinities between Rousseau and Wieland more generally. In preparation for the comparative reading of Emile and Agathon, I survey Wieland’s private and public responses to Rousseau and contend that although the two authors di↵er significantly in their narrative and i philosophical approach, they nevertheless share similar moral and political ideals.
    [Show full text]