Dictionary of Philosophy of Mind 07/07/2014 12 08 AM

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Dictionary of Philosophy of Mind 07/07/2014 12 08 AM imagination - Dictionary of Philosophy of Mind https:/ / sites.google.com/ site/ minddict/ imagination Dictionary of Philosophy of Mind Search this site H_Q|V|EAB_O_UILND_EXC_QNlRLBlJlQRSCQ_NIACLliSSJlEJV|AE imaginatiQn See page 6 for citation information and publication history. Traditionally, the mental capacity for experiencing, constructing, or manipulating 'rnental imagery’ (quasi-perceptual experience). Imagination is also regarded as responsible for fantasy, inventiveness, idiosyncrasy, and creative, original, and insightful thoughtin general, and, sometimes, fora much wider range ofmental activities dealing with the non-actual, such as supposing, pretending, ‘seeing as’, thinking ofpossib ilities, and even being mistaken. See representation. Navigating the Dictionary: There are different ways to Details: navigate the dictionary. You can use our search engine at Introduction the top of the page, the index located in the menu above, or Despite being a familiar word of everydaylanguage, imagination is a very complex, contested, browse entries alphabetically. and evaluativelyloaded concept. lt, like many cognate terms, often appears to have radically Alphabetical entries can be differentsenses and connotations when used in different contexts. Furthermore, although it accessed via the alphab eton plays onlya small overt role in mostcontemporarytheories ofthe mind, it has played a much the home page. more prominent part in the past. The conceptwill thus best be understood through its history. Ancient and Medieval Conception Other Resources: The concept ofthe imagination seems to have been first introduced into philosophy by - Stanford Encyclopedia of Aristotle, who tells us that "imagination [phantasia] is (apart from any metaphorical sense of Philosophy the word) the process bywhich we saythat an image [phantasma] is presented to us" (De Anima, 428a 1-4). It has been questioned in recenttimes whetherthe Greek words phantasia - Dictionary of Cognitive and phantasma are really equivalentto "imagination" and "(menta|) image" as heard in Science contemporary usage. However, there can be little doubt that, at least until very recenttimes, theoretical discussions ofphantasia, its Latin translation imaginatio, and their etymological - Philpapers descendants, continued to be rooted in the concepts introduced byAristotle and the problems arising from his rather elliptical explanation ofthem. Very arguablythis is true of all Western - Internet Encyclopedia of philosophical schools: Stoics, Epicureans and Neoplatonists quite as much as avowed Philosophy Aristoteleans; Muslims as much as Christians; and, come to that, Empiricists quite as much as Rationalists. - Phi/job s: Job s in Philosophy According to Aristotle "The soul never thinks without a mental image [phantasma]" (De Anima, 431a 15-20). ltwould appearthat, for him (and, again, for mostofsuccessors, until very recently), such images played something like the role that is played in contemporary cognitive theory by "mental representations". In this tradition, imagery, and thus imagination, has an essential role to playin all forms ofthinking (with the possible exception ofdirect intuitions of Platonic forms, or ofthe divine). It has no special connection with inventiveness or creativity. tdoes, however, have a special connection with desire. Aristotle argues that our desire for (and, thus, pursuitof) anything notactually presentto the senses must be mediated by an 'mage ofthe desired object. Aristotle's treatment is morally neutral, but his notion ofdesirous 'magination maylater have become conflated with the Hebraic concept of yetser, the willful (but also semi-divine) faculty in humanitythat led to Adam's (and, indeed, all subsequent) sin. Atany rate, in the Judaeo-Christian intellectual tradition (from ancientto relatively recenttimes) 'magination, although recognized as indispensable to cognition, was usually profoundly distrusted. Unless strictly disciplined by reason itwould soon lead us into concupiscence and sin. But, of course, the connection between imagination and perception is the more fundamental. Aristotle's conception ofphantasia/imagination seems to be closely bound up with his 1of6 07/07/2014 12 08 AM imagination - Dictionary of Philosophy of Mind https:/ / sites.google.com/ site/ minddict/ imagination postulation ofwhat came to be called the "common sense" or sensus communis. This is the part of the psyche responsible forthe binding of the deliverances ofthe individual sense organs into a coherent and intelligible representation, and for apprehending the so called "common sensibles", those aspects ofthe world (broadly, the spatio-temporal aspects) that can be known through more than one sense mode without being the characteristic proper object ofany ofthem (Aristotelian common sensibles are broadly coextensive with Lockean "primary qualities"). In fact, it is plausible to interpret phantasia and sensus communis as different aspects or modes ofa single faculty, depending on whether it is regarded as receptive or productive, or on whether it is operating in the presence orthe absence of whatever is being mentally represented. Phantasmata are generated in either case, butwhen their immediate cause is an objectdirectly before us the tendencyis to referto them as percepts, and to the process as perception; when memoryof previouslyobserved things is the source, reference will more likely be to imageryand imagination. Thus imagination came to be particularly associated with thinking about things that are not actually currently present to the senses: things thatare not reallythere. Some ofAristotle's successors tended to laythe stress on the conceptual separation ofthe notions ofimagination and sensus communis. Thus Early Christian and Medieval anatomists often located sensus communis at the frontofthe brain's firstventricle, readyto receive sense impressions, whereas imagination was placed at the rear ofthis ventricle (or even in the second ventricle), and was responsible for holding and perhaps consolidating the resultant images, and passing them back to the other ventricles and faculties (where they could be used in thoughtor stored in memory). Imagination mightalso, sometimes, be held responsible forthe recombining ofvarious image parts into chimerical forms. This lattertype ofprocess would allow the individual mind a degree offreedom and a scope for idiosyncracythatwould hardly have been available from the othertraditional faculties, constrained as theywere by reality and the laws oflogic. It would also, of course, give rise to images even more removed from presentactualitythan images retrieved intact from memory, and thus even more quintessentiallyimaginary In this vein, we sometimes find modern writers making a distinction between "memoryimagery" and "imagination imagery", or even restricting the use of "imagination" (and, a fortiori, "imaginary") to thoughts aboutthings that have never (or never yet) been actually experienced. (For some reason, words derived from the original Greek term, such as "fantasy", "fancy", or "phantasm", seem to have come to connote unrealityeven more stronglythan "imagination" and its cognates. It is worth noting thatsome medieval authors, finding both the Greek and the Latin terms available, did attempt to draw functional and anatomical distinctions between imaginatio and phantasia, but no clear consensus on how this distinction was to be drawn is apparent, and these attempts seem unlikelyto have significantlyinfluenced more recent usages.) Modern Usage Other ancient and medieval authors, however, were more inclined to stress the underlying identity ofthe imagination and the common sense, and this interpretation probably became more widespread with the increased availability of more accurate Aristotelian texts and translations in the later middle ages and renaissance. We find this tendency even in such a consciously anti-Aristotelian figure as Descartes, who, in the Treatise on Man, explicitly identifies both the sensus communis and the imagination with the surface ofthe pineal gland, upon which images (ldeés) both ofsense and ofmemory orfancy are inscribed. Although it is important not to confuse these "corporeal ideas" with the "clear and distinct ideas" that play so prominent a part in Descartes‘ epistemology, it is surely not coincidental that the site of the Cartesian imagination/sensus communis, the pineal surface, is also the privileged site of mind-bodyinteraction, the lynchpin that holds togetherthe two metaphysical worlds of Cartesianism. As it had done for Aristotle, the imagination/sensus communis mediated between the bodily senses, and the (now incorporeal) rational mind. Afterthe conceptual revolutions of the 17th centurythe Aristotelian concept of sensus communis largely disappeared from philosophical discussion, and, inasmuch as the functions that had been ascribed to itwere considered ofinterest, theywere likelyto be directly ascribed to imagination. In the Em piricisttradition, images, underthe rubric of "ideas", came more than everto be seen as the preeminent, even the only, form ofmental content. Hume, indeed, frequently uses "imagination" as a virtual synonym for "mind". This is reasonable enough inasmuch as he regards the mind as no more than a bundle ofimages (impressions 2 of 6 07/07/2014 12 08 AM imagination - Dictionary of Philosophy of Mind https:/ / sites.google.com/ site/ minddict/ imagination and ideas), and cognition as a matter oftheir vicissitudes and associative interactions. But even for Hume, imagination
Recommended publications
  • Ryle's Behaviorist View of the Mind
    Ryle’s behaviorist view of the mind Jeff Speaks August 31, 2006 1 The dogma of the ghost in the machine . 1 1.1 The problem of mental causation . 1 1.2 The problem of other minds . 2 2 The Cartesian view as a category mistake . 2 3 Ryle’s positive view . 3 1 The dogma of the ghost in the machine Ryle calls the kind of dualist view that we found in Descartes ‘the official doctrine’, and summarizes it like this: “The official doctrine, which hails chiefly from Descartes, is something like this. With the doubtful exceptions of idiots and infants in arms every human being has both a body and a mind. His body and mind are ordinarily harnessed together, but after the death of his body his mind may continue to exist and function. Human bodies are in space and are subject to the mechanical laws which govern all other bodies in space . But minds are not in space, nor are their operations subject to mechanical laws. A person therefore lives through two collateral histories, one consisting of what happens in and to his body, the other consisting of what happens in and to his mind. The events in the first history are events in the physical world, those in the second are events in the mental world.” Now, it is clear that Ryle thinks that this view is not the right one; he says that he will refer to it, ‘with deliberate abusiveness’, as the dogma of the ghost in the machine. What we have to get clear on is why he thinks the Cartesian view is so clearly false.
    [Show full text]
  • Mind Body Problem and Brandom's Analytic Pragmatism
    The Mind-Body Problem and Brandom’s Analytic Pragmatism François-Igor Pris [email protected] Erfurt University (Nordhäuserstraße 63, 99089 Erfurt, Germany) Abstract. I propose to solve the hard problem in the philosophy of mind by means of Brandom‟s notion of the pragmatically mediated semantic relation. The explanatory gap between a phenomenal concept and the corresponding theoretical concept is a gap in the pragmatically mediated semantic relation between them. It is closed if we do not neglect the pragmatics. 1 Introduction In the second section, I will formulate the hard problem. In the third section, I will describe a pragmatic approach to the problem and propose to replace the classical non-normative physicalism/naturalism with a normative physicalism/naturalism of Wittgensteinian language games. In subsection 3.1, I will give a definition of a normative naturalism. In subsection 3.2, I will make some suggestions concerning an analytic interpretation of the second philosophy of Wittgenstein. In the fourth section, I will propose a solution to the hard problem within Brandom‟s analytic pragmatism by using the notion of the pragmatically mediated semantic relation. In the fifth section, I will make some suggestions about possible combinatorics related to pragmatically mediated semantic relations. In the sixth section, I will consider pragmatic and discursive versions of the mind-body identity M=B. In the last section, I will conclude that the explanatory gap is a gap in a pragmatically mediated semantic relation between B and M. It is closed if we do not neglect pragmatics. 2 The Hard Problem The hard problem in the philosophy of mind can be formulated as follows.
    [Show full text]
  • Thinking About False Belief: It’S Not Just What Children Say, but How Long It Takes Them to Say It
    Cognition 116 (2010) 297–301 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Cognition journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/COGNIT Brief article Thinking about false belief: It’s not just what children say, but how long it takes them to say it Cristina M. Atance a,*, Daniel M. Bernstein b,c, Andrew N. Meltzoff c a School of Psychology, University of Ottawa, 200 Lees Avenue, Room E228, Ottawa, Ontario, Canada K1N 6N5 b Kwantlen Polytechnic University, 12666, 72nd Avenue, Surrey, BC, Canada V3W 2MB c Institute for Learning and Brain Sciences, University of Washington, CHDD Building, Room 373, Box 357920, Seattle, WA 98195, USA article info abstract Article history: We examined 240 children’s (3.5-, 4.5-, and 5.5-year-olds) latency to respond to questions Received 29 January 2009 on a battery of false-belief tasks. Response latencies exhibited a significant cross-over Revised 22 March 2010 interaction as a function of age and response type (correct vs. incorrect). 3.5-year-olds’ Accepted 4 May 2010 incorrect latencies were faster than their correct latencies, whereas the opposite pattern emerged for 4.5- and 5.5-year-olds. Although these results are most consistent with con- ceptual change theories of false-belief reasoning, no extant theory fully accounts for our Keywords: data pattern. We argue that response latency data provide new information about under- Theory of mind lying cognitive processes in theory of mind reasoning, and can shed light on concept acqui- False-belief reasoning Conceptual development sition more broadly. Response latencies Ó 2010 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved.
    [Show full text]
  • Ryle's Behaviorist View of the Mind
    Ryle’s behaviorist view of the mind Jeff Speaks August 28, 2018 1 The dogma of the ghost in the machine . 1 1.1 The problem of mental causation . 1 1.2 The problem of other minds . 2 2 The Cartesian view as a category mistake . 2 3 Ryle’s view of mental states . 3 4 Full-blown behaviorism . 5 1 The dogma of the ghost in the machine Ryle calls the kind of dualist view that we found in Descartes ‘the official doctrine’, and summarizes it like this: “The official doctrine, which hails chiefly from Descartes, is something like this. With the doubtful exceptions of idiots and infants in arms every human being has both a body and a mind. His body and mind are ordinarily harnessed together, but after the death of his body his mind may continue to exist and function. Human bodies are in space and are subject to the mechanical laws which govern all other bodies in space . But minds are not in space, nor are their operations subject to mechanical laws. A person therefore lives through two collateral histories, one consisting of what happens in and to his body, the other consisting of what happens in and to his mind. The events in the first history are events in the physical world, those in the second are events in the mental world.” Now, it is clear that Ryle thinks that this view is not the right one; he says that he will refer to it, ‘with deliberate abusiveness’, as the dogma of the ghost in the machine.
    [Show full text]
  • PHI 110 Lecture 2 1 Welcome to Our Second Lecture on Personhood and Identity
    PHI 110 Lecture 2 1 Welcome to our second lecture on personhood and identity. We’re going to begin today what will be two lectures on Rene Descartes’ thoughts on this subject. The position that is attributed to him is known as mind/body dualism. Sometimes it’s simply called the dualism for short. We need to be careful, however, because the word dualism covers a number of different philosophical positions, not always dualisms of mind and body. In other words, there are other forms of dualism that historically have been expressed. And so I will refer to his position as mind/body dualism or as Cartesian dualism as it’s sometimes also called. I said last time that Descartes is not going to talk primarily about persons. He’s going to talk about minds as opposed to bodies. But I think that as we start getting into his view, you will see where his notion of personhood arises. Clearly, Descartes is going to identify the person, the self, with the mind as opposed to with the body. This is something that I hoped you picked up in your reading and certainly that you will pick up once you read the material again after the lecture. Since I’ve already introduced Descartes’ position, let’s define it and then I’ll say a few things about Descartes himself to give you a little bit of a sense of the man and of his times. The position mind/body that’s known as mind/body dualism is defined as follows: It’s the view that the body is a physical substance — a machine, if you will — while the mind is a non-physical thinking entity which inhabits the body and is responsible for its voluntary movements.
    [Show full text]
  • A Dual Mind Approach to Understanding the Conscious Self and Its Treatment
    Article A Dual Mind Approach to Understanding the Conscious Self and Its Treatment Fredric Schiffer Developmental Biopsychiatry Research Program, Department of Psychiatry, McLean Hospital, Harvard Medical School, Belmont, MA 02478, USA; [email protected]; Tel.: +1-617-969-1188 Abstract: In this paper I will address questions about will, agency, choice, consciousness, relevant brain regions, impacts of disorders, and their therapeutics, and I will do this by referring to my theory, Dual-brain Psychology, which posits that within most of us there exist two mental agencies with different experiences, wills, choices, and behaviors. Each of these agencies is associated as a trait with one brain hemisphere (either left or right) and its composite regions. One of these agencies is more adversely affected by past traumas, and is more immature and more symptomatic, while the other is more mature and healthier. The theory has extensive experimental support through 17 peer-reviewed publications with clinical and non-clinical research. I will discuss how this theory relates to the questions about the nature of agency and I will also discuss my published theory on the physical nature of subjective experience and its relation to the brain, and how that theory interacts with Dual-Brain Psychology, leading to further insights into our human nature and its betterment. Keywords: consciousness; subjective experience; self; psychopathology; treatment; transcranial near infrared light; biophotomodulation Citation: Schiffer, F. A Dual Mind Approach to Understanding the 1. Introduction Conscious Self and Its Treatment. Dual-brain Psychology comes out of my early clinical experiences in which I observed NeuroSci 2021, 2, 224–234.
    [Show full text]
  • Ryle and the Para-Mechanical
    BRYAN BENHAM Ryle and the Para-mechanical WINNER OF mE 1999 LARRY TAYLOR MEMORIAL AWARD The thesis of this paper is the unconventional claim that Gilbert Ryle is not a logical behaviorist. The popular account ofRyle clearly places his work in The Concept ofMind (1949) in the camp oflogical behaviorist.! The object of this paper, however, will be to illustrate how the conventional interpretation of Ryle is misleading. My argument is not an exhaustive account of Ryle, but serves as a starting point for understanding Ryle outside of the behaviorist label that is usually attached to his work. The argument is straightforward. First, it is apparent on any reasonable construal that logical behaviorism is a reductionist project about the mind. The basic claim of logical behaviorism is that statements containing mental vocabulary can be analyzed into statements containing only the vocabulary of physical behavior. Second, any reasonable account ofRyle will show that he is not a reductionist about the mental, in fact he was adamantly anti-reductionist about the mind. Once these two claims are established it follows quite readily that Ryle was not a logical behaviorist. The first premise is uncontroversial. Anyone familiar with logical behaviorism understands that its aim is to show that mental terminology doesn't refer to unobserved phenomena, supposedly in the head of the person described, but rather to the observed physical behaviors or dispositions to behave (Hempel 1999). In fact, in its strict formulation, logical behaviorism claims that mental terminology signifies only these observed behaviors or dispositions to behave. Thus, I will take it as a reasonably established claim that logical behaviorism is reductionist about the mind.
    [Show full text]
  • Consciousness and Theory of Mind: a Common Theory?
    Consciousness and Theory of Mind: a Common Theory? Keywords: Consciousness, Higher-Order Theories, Theory of Mind, Mind-reading, Metacognition. 1 Introduction Many of our mental states are phenomenally conscious. It feels a certain way, or to borrow Nagel's expression, there is something it is like to be in these states. Examples of phenomenally conscious states are those one undergoes while looking at the ocean or at a red apple, drinking a glass of scotch or a tomato juice, smelling coee or the perfume of a lover, listening to the radio or a symphonic concert, or feeling pain or hunger. A theory of consciousness has to explain the distinctive properties that phe- nomenally conscious states have and other kind of states lack. Higher-Order Representational (HOR) theories1 attempt to provide such an explanation. Ac- coding to these theories, phenomenally conscious states are those that are the objects of some kind of higher-order process or representation. There is some- thing higher-order, a meta-state, in the case of phenomenal conscious mental states, which is lacking in the case of other kind of states. According to these theories, consciousness depends on our Theory of Mind. A Theory of Mind, henceforth ToM, is the ability of humans to identify their own mental states and attribute mental states dierent from their owns to others. Such an ability can, at least conceptually, be decomposed into another two: mindreading and metacognition. Human beings are able to entertain representations of other people men- tal states thanks to the mindreading ability. We attribute beliefs, perceptions, feelings or desires to other people and predict and explain their behaviour ac- cordingly.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Mind
    Introduction to Philosophy: Philosophy of Mind INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY: PHILOSOPHY OF MIND ERAN ASOULIN, PAUL RICHARD BLUM, TONY CHENG, DANIEL HAAS, JASON NEWMAN, HENRY SHEVLIN, ELLY VINTIADIS, HEATHER SALAZAR (EDITOR), AND CHRISTINA HENDRICKS (SERIES EDITOR) Rebus Community Introduction to Philosophy: Philosophy of Mind by Eran Asoulin, Paul Richard Blum, Tony Cheng, Daniel Haas, Jason Newman, Henry Shevlin, Elly Vintiadis, Heather Salazar (Editor), and Christina Hendricks (Series Editor) is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, except where otherwise noted. CONTENTS What is an open textbook? vii Christina Hendricks How to access and use the books ix Christina Hendricks Introduction to the Series xi Christina Hendricks Praise for the Book xiv Adriano Palma Acknowledgements xv Heather Salazar and Christina Hendricks Introduction to the Book 1 Heather Salazar 1. Substance Dualism in Descartes 3 Paul Richard Blum 2. Materialism and Behaviorism 10 Heather Salazar 3. Functionalism 19 Jason Newman 4. Property Dualism 26 Elly Vintiadis 5. Qualia and Raw Feels 34 Henry Shevlin 6. Consciousness 41 Tony Cheng 7. Concepts and Content 49 Eran Asoulin 8. Freedom of the Will 58 Daniel Haas About the Contributors 69 Feedback and Suggestions 72 Adoption Form 73 Licensing and Attribution Information 74 Review Statement 76 Accessibility Assessment 77 Version History 79 WHAT IS AN OPEN TEXTBOOK? CHRISTINA HENDRICKS An open textbook is like a commercial textbook, except: (1) it is publicly available online free of charge (and at low-cost in print), and (2) it has an open license that allows others to reuse it, download and revise it, and redistribute it.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Philosophy
    An Introduction to Philosophy W. Russ Payne Bellevue College Copyright (cc by nc 4.0) 2015 W. Russ Payne Permission is granted to copy, distribute and/or modify this document with attribution under the terms of Creative Commons: Attribution Noncommercial 4.0 International or any later version of this license. A copy of the license is found at http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0/ 1 Contents Introduction ………………………………………………. 3 Chapter 1: What Philosophy Is ………………………….. 5 Chapter 2: How to do Philosophy ………………….……. 11 Chapter 3: Ancient Philosophy ………………….………. 23 Chapter 4: Rationalism ………….………………….……. 38 Chapter 5: Empiricism …………………………………… 50 Chapter 6: Philosophy of Science ………………….…..… 58 Chapter 7: Philosophy of Mind …………………….……. 72 Chapter 8: Love and Happiness …………………….……. 79 Chapter 9: Meta Ethics …………………………………… 94 Chapter 10: Right Action ……………………...…………. 108 Chapter 11: Social Justice …………………………...…… 120 2 Introduction The goal of this text is to present philosophy to newcomers as a living discipline with historical roots. While a few early chapters are historically organized, my goal in the historical chapters is to trace a developmental progression of thought that introduces basic philosophical methods and frames issues that remain relevant today. Later chapters are topically organized. These include philosophy of science and philosophy of mind, areas where philosophy has shown dramatic recent progress. This text concludes with four chapters on ethics, broadly construed. I cover traditional theories of right action in the third of these. Students are first invited first to think about what is good for themselves and their relationships in a chapter of love and happiness. Next a few meta-ethical issues are considered; namely, whether they are moral truths and if so what makes them so.
    [Show full text]
  • Mind Mapping Writing Centre Learning Guide
    Mind Mapping Writing Centre Learning Guide Mind mapping is an effective means to take notes and brainstorm essay topics. A mind map involves writing down a central theme and thinking of new and related ideas which radiate out from the centre. By focusing on key ideas written down in your own words and looking for connections between them, you can map knowledge in a way that will help you to better understand and retain information. What is mind mapping? Mind mapping was developed as an effective method for generating ideas by association. In order to create a mind map, you usually start in the middle of the page with the central theme/main idea and from that point you work outward in all directions to create a growing diagram composed of keywords, phrases, concepts, facts and figures. It can be used for assignments and essay writing especially in the initial stages, whereit is an ideal strategy to use for your ‘thinking’. Mind mapping can be used for generating, visualising, organising, note-taking, problem-solving, decision-making, revising and clarifying your university topic, so that you can get started with assessment tasks. Essentially, a mind map is used to ‘brainstorm’ a topic and is a great strategy for students. How do I use mind mapping? You can use mind mapping for the following: . taking notes in a lecture and listening for the most important points or keywords . showing links and relationships between the main ideas in your subject . brainstorming all the things you already know about an essay question . planning the early stages of an essay by visualising all the aspects of the question .
    [Show full text]
  • Re-Introducing the Concept of Mind
    RE-INTRODUCING THE CONCEPT OF MIND IMAGINE somebody whose enthusiasm for metaphysical musings is so matched by ineptitude that when his bank informs him that his account is overdrawn, he manages to convince himself that the mod­ ern banking system had created a new kind of Cosmic Substance: anti--cash, convertible into minus-pounds-sterling, nego-dollars, vac­ euros, and so forth. Being a staunch 'realist' about all things, he decides that his bankers have just informed him that they are hold­ ing, somewhere within their walls, in a container with his name on it, a particular quantity of anti-cash. It's like matter and anti-matter, he thinks, and he supposes that the annihilation that happens when his overdraft of -£200.43 meets his deposit of £300.46 is - shazam! - the explosive generation of£100.03 of ordinary cash (minus a small quan­ tity extracted by the bank) plus, perhaps, a few stray photons or quarks or gravity waves. He wonders: What kind of containers does the bank use to hold the anti-cash till the regular cash arrives? How are they insulated? Can you store cash and anti-cash in the same box and somehow prevent them from getting in contact? Might there be zombanks that only seemed to store cash and anti-cash? How could we tell? This is a hard problem indeed! What this poor chap needs is a good dose of Gilbert Ryle's 'logical behaviourism,' which is the plain truth about bank balances, however controversial it might be as a theory of the mind.
    [Show full text]