<<

Theaggregationproblem AntonioQuesada †

Departamentd’Economia,UniversitatRoviraiVirgili,AvingudadelaUniversitat1,43204Reus,Spain

26thOctober2008 Abstract Thispaperpresentsthebasicpreferenceaggregationmodelandprovestwoofthemostsignificantresults inthetheoryofpreferenceaggregation:Arrow’stheoremandSen’stheorem. Keywords :Socialwelfarefunction,preferenceaggregation,Paretoefficiency,independenceofirrelevant alternatives,decisiveness,dictatorship. JEL Classification :D71

†Emailaddress:[email protected].FinancialsupportfromtheSpanish Ministerio de Educación y Ciencia under research project SEJ200767580C0201 and from the Departament d’Universitats, Recerca i Societat de la Informació ( Generalitat de Catalunya )underresearchproject2005SGR00949isgratefully acknowledged.

−1− 1. Introduction Thedistinctivefeatureofamicroeconomicmodelconsistsoftakingdecisionsmadeby individualsasthebasicelementofthemodel:inamicroeconomicmodel,individuals andthewaytheymakedecisionsarethebuildingblocksofthemodel. Individualsinamicroeconomicmodelaretypicallyassumedtomakedecisionsonthe basisoftheirpreferencesovertheresultsthatthose decisions generate. Specifically, individualsaresupposedtomakedecisionsthatleadtosomeoftheirmostpreferred results.Soingametheory,theindividuals(players)choosestrategiesinordertoobtain themaximumpayoff;inconsumertheory,theindividuals(consumers)choosebundles to maximize their functions; and in the theory of industrial organization, the individuals(firms)choosetheamountofproductiontomaximizetheirfunctions. Theviewthateveryeconomicphenomenoninvolvesindividualsmakingsomedecision impliesthatalleconomicmodelsare,inthelastinstance,microeconomicmodels.But eventhenthefollowingquestionarises:isitlegitimatetotaketheshortcutconsistingof dispensingwithindividualsinamodel?Thatis,towhatextentissatisfactorytohavean economicmodelinwhichindividualsarenotexplicitlymodelled? Theseconsiderationsmakethefollowingquestioninteresting:whencanacollectivebe treatedasanindividual?Forincasesinwhichacollectivecanbesafelymodelledasan individual then there is no need to deal explicitly with individuals: handling the collective directly, without having to care about individuals, would be a reasonably valid approximation for the extended model in which individuals are modelled. For instance,themodelsbasedontheideaof“representativeconsumer”analyzeagroupof individualsbyjustanalyzingasingleindividual. So there seems to be a legitimate research question to ascertain in which cases collectivescanbetreatedasindividuals.Andaslongasthebasicinformationrequired from individuals are preferences, it appears necessary for collectives to be treated as individualsthatcollectivescanbeassignedpreferencesofthesortthatcanbeassigned toindividuals.Theproblemofwhenacollectivecanbeconsideredanindividualisin itself a decision problem, so economists have handled the question by means of microeconomic models. In particular, the standard model to study what type of preferencecanbeascribedtoacollectivetakesthepreferencesoftheindividualsinthe collectiveastheprimitiveelementofthemodel.Thispaperpresentstwofundamental resultsobtainedinthismodel.

−2− 2. Model Let N = {1, … , n} be a nonempty finite set whose n ≥ 2 members designate individuals.Let Abeafinitesetwhose m≥2elementsrepresentoutcomes,alternatives, choicesoranythingoverwhichindividualscandefinepreferences. Definition 2.1. Apreferenceon Aconsistsofabinaryrelation pon AsatisfyingIRR, COMandTRA.Thesetofpreferencesthatcanbedefinedon Aisdenotedby L. IRR.Irreflexivity.Forall x∈A,itisnotthecasethat x p x. COM.Completeness.Forall x∈Aand y∈A\{x},either x p yor y p x. TRA.Transitivity.Forall x∈A,and y∈Aand z∈A,if x p yand y p zthen xpz. Theinterpretationof“ xpy”isthattheindividualwithpreference pprefers xto y.A preferenceon Acanbeidentifiedwitharanking(orlinearorder)oftheelementsofthe set A.Thedefinitionofpreferenceisrestrictivebecauseitdoesnotallowindifference. This restriction is adopted for convenience, because the results in this paper can be extendedtothecaseinwhichindifferenceisallowed. Definition 2.2. Apreferenceprofileconsistsofanassignmentofapreferenceon Ato everyindividualin N.Thesetofpreferencesisdenotedby Ln.

Apreferenceprofile Pcanberepresentedbyan ndimensionalvector( P1, P2,…, Pn), where Pistandsforthepreferencethatcorrespondstoindividual i ∈N inpreference profile P.Hence,apreferenceprofileisalistofthepreferenceheldbyeveryindividual. Inthismodel,theproblemconsistsofassociating, with every preferenceprofile P, a preference P*representingthecollectivepreferencewhenindividualshavepreferences asrepresentedby P.Therefore, P*canbeviewedasasummarizingpreference:when membersofacollectivehavepreferencesrepresentedby P=(P1, P2,…, Pn)thenthe collective can be attributed preference P*. The rule creating the synthesizing (or collective)preferencefromtheindividualpreferencesiscalledsocialwelfarefunction. Definition 2.3. Asocialwelfarefunction(SWF)isamapping f: Ln→L. ASWFtakestheindividuals’preferencesasinputsandoutputsacollectivepreference associated with the group of individuals. A SWF is a mechanism transforming individual into collective preferences. Alternatively, a SWF attributes preferences to collectivestakingintoaccountthepreferencesofthemembersofthecollective.

−3− 3. Axioms ThereisanimportantpresumptioninthedefinitionofSWF,namely,thatthecollective preferenceisdrawnfromthesameset Lasanyindividualpreference.Suchafactmakes acollectivepreferenceformallyindistinguishablefromanindividualpreference.After all,lookingforacollectivepreferenceintheset Lseemstobeareasonablerequirement if one pretends a collective to be treated as an individual: if individual preferences satisfyIRR,COMandTRA,thenitisaprioridesirabletoexpectacollectivepreference toenjoythoseproperties. Thisconsiderationsuggeststheideathat,whenconstructing the collectivepreference outoftheindividuals’preferences,aSWFshouldbe“respectful”withtheindividuals’ preferences.Infact,ifaSWFdisregardedtheinformationcontainedintheindividuals’ preferences,whyaskforthosepreferences? TherearemanyconditionsthatcanbeimposedonaSWF ftocapturetheideathatthe SWFshouldrespecttheindividuals’preferences.OneistheParetoprinciple.Fornon n emptysubset I⊆Nofthesetofindividuals, P∈L , x∈Aand y∈A\{x},let xPIy abbreviate“forall i∈I, xPiy”. n PAR.Paretoprinciple.Forall P∈L , x∈Aand y∈A\{x}, xPIyimplies xf(P) y. PAR asserts that the process by means of which a SWF f generates the collective preference f(P) ∈Lusingthepreferenceprofile Pasinputshouldrespecttheunanimous preference of one alternative x over another alternative y. In other words, if all the individuals prefer x to y then, in the collective preference created by f, x should be preferredto y.Thisseemstobeaplausiblerequirement:ifallindividualsprefer xto y, howcouldonecontendthatthecollectivedoesnotprefer xto y? Unfortunately,PARisnotalwaysapplicable:whathappensifsomeindividualsprefer x to yandtherestprefer yto x?Oneprincipleusedinpracticeismajority:ifamajorityof individualsprefer xto ythentheSWFshoulddeclare xcollectivelypreferredto y.A political election can be viewed as a mechanism that implicitly constructs collective preferences:ifpoliticalparty xhasmorevotesthanparty yandthismorevotesthan z thenitappearsthatonecouldinferthat“society” prefers x to both y and z and also prefers yto z.ItmaybethentemptingtodemandaSWFtoaggregatepreferencesusing themajorityrule.

−4− Unfortunately, the Condorcet paradox (see Wikipedia (2008a)) shows this to be impossible:noSWF fexistssuchthat,forall P∈Ln, x∈Aand y∈A\{x},ifamajority ofindividualsprefers xto ythe,inthecollectivepreference f(P), xispreferredto y.To seethis,considerExample3.1. Example 3.1. Let n= m=3,withsets N={1,2,3}and A={ x, y, z}.Define Ptobethe preferenceprofilesuchthat:(i) xP1yP1z;(ii) yP2zP2x;and(iii) zP3xP3y.Suppose thatSWF fconstructsthecollectivepreferencebyapplyingthemajorityrule.Then,asa majorityofindividuals(1and3)prefer x to y,itmustbethat x f(P) y. Andsincea majorityofindividuals(1and2)prefer yto z,itmustbethat yf(P) z.Finally,giventhat amajorityofindividuals(2and3)prefer zto x,itmustbethat zf(P) x.Since f(P)isa memberof L,itsatisfiesCOM.Therefore, zf(P) ximpliesthatnot xf(P) z.And,asa result,TRAisviolated: xf(P) y, yf(P) zbutnot xf(P) z.Thiscontradictsthefactthat f(P)belongsto L. Example3.1showsthatnoSWFcanbeconstructedusingmajorityrule.Thequestionis then how much of majority rule can be retained. Observe that PAR is one of the properties of majority rule. Another property of majority rule is that, when deciding whether xiscollectivelypreferredto y,onlytheindividuals’preferencebetween xand y istakingintoaccount.Hence,whendeterminingthecollectivepreferenceof xagainst y bymajorityrulethepreferenceovertherestofalternativesisirrelevant.InExample3.1, majorityranks xabove yinthecollectivepreferencenomatterhowindividualsrank z against xoragainst y.Consequently,majorityrulesatisfiesthefollowingproperty of independenceofirrelevantalternatives. IIA. Independence of irrelevant alternatives. For all P ∈ Ln, Q ∈ Ln, x ∈ A and y ∈

A\{x},if,forall i ∈N, xPiy⇔xQiythen xf(P) y⇔xf(Q) y. By IIA, if each individual has the same preference over x and y in two preference profiles Pand Qthen,inbothcases,thecorrespondingcollectivepreferences f(P)and f(Q)havethesamepreferenceover xand y.IIAcanalsobeseenasaformofrespecting the individuals’ preferences: if x was declared collectively preferred to y when some subsetofindividualspreferred xto yandtherestpreferred yto xthen,wheneverthe samesubsetofindividualsprefer x to y and the rest prefer y to x, xhastobeagain declaredcollectivelypreferredto y.

Forpreference p∈L,let p{x,y}representtherestrictionofpreference ptotheset{ x, y}. For instance, in Example 3.1, P1{x,y} is such that x is preferred to y whereas

−5− P2{x,y}issuchthat yispreferredto x.Withthisnotation,“forall i ∈N, xPiy⇔xQi y”meansthat,foreachindividual i,therestrictionof i’spreferencetotheset{ x, y}is thesameinbothpreferenceprofiles;thatis,“forall i ∈N, xPiy⇔xQiy”isequivalent to“forall i ∈N, Pi{x,y}= Qi{x,y}”:eachindividualhasthesamepreferencebetweenx and yinboth Pand Q.Similarly,“ xf(P) y⇔xf(Q) y”isequivalentto“ f(P){x,y}= f(Q){x,y}”.Consequently,afterdefining P{x,y}=( P1{x,y}, P2{x,y},…, Pn{x,y}),IIA canbealternativelyexpressedasfollows. n n IIA.Forall P∈L , Q∈L , x∈Aand y∈A\{x},if P{x,y}= Q{x,y}then f(P){x,y}= f(Q){x,y}. Example 3.2. Let n=2and m=3,withsets N={1,2}and A={ x, y, z}.Let Pand Q bethepreferenceprofilessuchthat xP1yP1z, zP2yP2x, yQ1xQ1zand xQ2zQ2y. IfSWF fsatisfiesIIAthen fshouldrank yand zinthesamewayinboth f(P)and f(Q), because:(i)1ranks yand zinthesamewayinboth P1and Q1(1prefers yto z);and(ii)

2ranks yand zinthesamewayinboth P2and Q2(2prefers zto y).NotethatIIAdoes notsaythat ymustbepreferredto z(or zto y)inboth f(P)and f(Q).Itjustcompelsthe SWFtomakethesamechoicein f(P)and f(Q):thecollectivepreferencebetween yand zresultinginonecase,mustalsoresultintheother case. On the other hand, for the preference between x and y, IIA imposes no restriction on f in this particular case, because P1{x,y}≠ Q1{x,y}. 4. Arrow’s theorem Definition 4.1. Anonemptysubset Iofindividualsisdecisivefor x∈Aagainst y∈ n A\{x}inSWF fif,forall P∈L , xPIyimplies xf(P) y. Thatasubset Iofindividualsisdecisivefor xagainst ymeansthatthegrouphasthe powerto“impose”onthecollectivepreferencetheirunanimouspreferencefor xagainst y.Thus,if Iisdecisivefor xagainst ythen,whenallmembersof Iprefer xto y,the collectivepreferencedictatesthat xispreferredto y.ItisworthnoticingthatPARis equivalenttopostulatingthat Nisdecisiveforeach x∈Aagainsteach y∈A\{x}. Definition 4.2. A SWF f is dictatorial if there exists some individual i ∈ N (called “dictator”)suchthat,forall x∈Aand y∈A\{x},{ i}isdecisivefor xagainst y.

−6− A SWF is dictatorial if there is some individual such that the collective preference alwayscoincideswiththatindividual’spreference.Thatis, fisdictatorialifthere i∈I n suchthat,forall P∈L , x∈Aand y∈A\{x}, xPiyimplies xf(P) y. Theorem 4.3. (Arrow(1963,p.97)).For n≥2and m≥3,aSWF fsatisfiesPARand IIAif,andonlyif, fisdictatorial. Proof .“ ⇐”ItisleftasanexercisetoverifythatadictatorialSWFsatisfiesPARand IIA.“ ⇒”With n≥2< m,let fbeaSWFthatsatisfiesPARandIIA.Theproofthat fis dictatorialproceedsintwosteps. Step1:forsome i∈N, x∈Aand y∈A\{x},{ i}isdecisivefor xagainst y.Thisresult willbeprovedbycontradiction:ifthenegationofasentenceleadstoacontradiction thenthesentencemustbetrue.Sosupposeotherwise: for no i ∈ N, x ∈ A and y ∈ A\{x},{ i}isdecisivefor xagainst y.Equivalently,forall i∈N, x∈Aand y∈A\{x}, {i}isnotdecisivefor xagainst y.Asaconsequence(why?), forall i∈N, x∈Aand y∈A\{x}, N\{i}isdecisivefor xagainst y. (1) By the assumption that m ≥ 3, choose any three different members x, y and z of A. Consider xand y.By(1),everygroupwith n–1individualsisdecisivefor xagainst y. Itwillbeshownthateverygroupwith n–2individualsisalsodecisivefor xagainst y. Tothisend,let P∈Lnbeanypreferenceprofileinwhichtheindividuals’preferences restrictedto{ x, y, z}areasfollows.

P1 P2 P3 P4 … Pn f (P) x z y y y y z y x x x → x y x z z z z Itwillbenowarguedthat f(P) restricted to { x, y, z}isasindicated above. In P, all individuals except 1 prefer y to x. By (1), N\{1} is decisive for y against x and, accordingly, yf(P) x.Similarly,in P,allindividualsexcept2prefer xto z.By(1), N\{2} isdecisivefor xagainst zand,asaresult, xf(P) z.ByTRA, yf(P) xand xf(P) zimply y f(P) z.

Considertherestriction P{y,z}oftheindividuals’preferencestotheset{ y, z},depicted next.

−7− Individual 1 2 3 4 … n Collective z z y y y → y y y z z z z ByIIA,everyprofile Q∈Lnwiththispreferenceconfigurationbetween yand zmust resultinacollectivepreferenceinwhich yispreferredto z.Inotherwords, N\{1,2}is decisivefor yagainst z.Actually,IIAassertsthatwhathappensonce,happensalways: since there is a situation (profile P) in which the above preference configuration between y and z leads to having y preferred to z, by IIA, whenever the above configurationoccurs, ywillbepreferredto z.Let Q∈Lnbeanypreferenceprofilein whichtheindividuals’preferencesrestrictedto{ x, y, z}areasfollows.

Q1 Q2 Q3 Q4 … Qn f (Q) z z y y y y x x z z z → z y y x x x x Itwillbenowarguedthat f(Q)restrictedto{ x, y, z}isasdepictedabove.Observethat

P{y,z}= Q{y,z}.Asshownbefore, yf(P) z.Consequently,byIIA, yf(Q) z.Onthe otherhand, zQNx:everybodyprefers zto x.Hence,byPAR, zf(Q) x.Given y f (Q) z and zf(Q) x,itfollowsfromTRAthat yf(Q) x.AndIIAyieldstheresult:allindividuals except1and2(whichhavebeenarbitrarilychosen)prefer yto xandtheSWFmakes y collectivelypreferredto x.ByIIA,thismakesallgroupsof n–2individualsdecisive for xagainst y. Thesamelineofreasoningcanbeappliedtoprovethatallgroupsof n–3individuals aredecisivefor xagainst y,thatallgroupsof n–4individualsaredecisivefor xagainst y,thatallgroupsof n–5individualsdecisivefor xagainst y…andsoon.Itisevident thatthislineofreasoningwilleventuallycontradict(1). Step2:if,forsome i∈N, x∈Aand y∈A\{x},{ i}isdecisivefor xagainst ythen,for all x∈Aand y∈A\{x},{ i}isdecisivefor xagainst y.Toprovestep2,itsufficesto showthat{ i}decisivefor xagainst yimplies:(i)that{i}isdecisivefor xagainst z;and (ii)that{i}isdecisivefor zagainst y.Sosuppose{ i}isdecisivefor xagainst y.Choose z∈A\{x, y},whichexistsbecause m≥3.Case1:{ i}isdecisivefor xagainst z.This meansthat,nomatterthepreferencesoftherestofindividualsover xand z,if iprefers x to zthenthecollectivepreferencehas xpreferredto z.

−8− n Let R∈L beanypreferenceprofilesatisfying:(i)xRiyRiz;and(ii)forall j∈N\{i}, y Ri x and y Ri z. Notice that individuals different from i may have any arbitrary preferenceover xand z.Noticeaswellthat,byTRA, xRiyand yRizimply xRiz. Theaimistodemonstratethat xf(R) z.First,bytheassumptionthat{ i}isdecisivefor x against y, xRiyyields xf(R) y.Second, yRNzandPARimply yf(R) z.Andthird,by TRA,itfollowsfrom xf(R) yand yf(R) zthat xf(R) z.Giventhat xRizhasresultedin x f(R) znomatterthepreferencesoftherestofindividualsover xand z,IIAimpliesthat {i}isdecisivefor xagainst z. Case2:{ i}isdecisivefor zagainst y.Leftasanexercise.  5. Remarks What is Arrow’s theorem telling? The most evident lessonisthatitisimpossibleto construct a SWF using two properties of the majority rule: unanimity (PAR) and requiring the collective preference over two alternatives to depend only on the individuals’ preferences over these two alternatives (IIA). In this respect, Arrow’s theoremgeneralizestheCondorcetparadoxandmakesevidentthedifficultiesoftrying to consider collectives as individuals by ascribing to collectives preferences that individuals could hold. For more on the interpretations of Arrow’s theorem, see Wikipedia(2008b). Arrow’stheoremisalandmarkineconomictheory.Foronething,modernsocialchoice theory emerged from this result; see Wikipedia (2008c) and Sen (1998). And, for another, Arrow’s theorem is one of the single results in economic theory that has generated more literature; see, for instance, Kelly (2008). This literature has grown followingtwostrands:onecriticizingtheresult;andtheothertryingtoescapefromits negativeconclusion(theexistenceofadictator)byrelaxingsomeoftheassumptions. Arrow’s(1963,p.97)theoremis,infact,amoregeneralresultthantheonepresented here: it is still true when individuals, as well as the collective, can be indifferent betweentwoalternatives.Inthatcase,therealsoarisesadictator:ifthedictatorprefers xto ythentheSWFdeclares xtobecollectivelypreferredto y.Thedifferenceisthatthe collectivepreferenceisnotidenticalwiththedictator’spreference:thatthedictatoris indifferentbetweentwo alternativesdoesnotimply that the two alternatives are also indifferentinthecollectivepreference.

−9− Generalizations of Arrow’s theorem have followed fourbasicroutes;seeSen(1986) andMoulin(1994).Oneconsistedofconsideringmoregeneraltypesofpreferencesas admissible;see,forinstance,BlairandPollak(1979)andreferencestherein.MasColell andSonnenschein(1972)assumethearguablyweakesttypeofpreferencethatcanbe deemedadmissible:acyclicpreferences.Apreferenceisacyclicif,foranysequence( x1, x2,…, xk−1, xk)ofalternativesitisnotthecasethat x1ispreferredto x2, x2ispreferred to x3,…, xk−1ispreferredto xkand xkispreferredto x1.Theypostulateacondition MONofmonotonocity:ifxispreferredorindifferentto yinthecollectivepreference then x becomes preferred to y if some individual just prefers x to y “a little more” (transforms indifference in preference for x or transforms preference for y in indifference). MasColellandSonnenschein(1972,p.189)Theorem 3 states that rules generating acyclicpreferencesandthatsatisfyPAR,IIAandMONhaveaweakdictator.Aweak dictatorisanindividual isuchthat,forall x∈Aand y∈A\{x},if iprefers xto ythen thecollectivepreferencecannothave ypreferredto x(so xispreferred,orindifferent,to y).ResultslikethisonehavecontributedtoreinforcetheviewthatArrow’stheoremisa robustresult. Another route tried to ascertain what would happen if PAR were removed. Wilson (1972,p.484)provesthataSWF(asdefinedhere)satisfyingIIAiseitherdictatorialor inverselydictatorial,whereSWF fisinverselydictatorialifthereis i∈Nsuchthat,for n all P∈L , x∈Aand y∈A\{x}, xPiyimplies yf(P) x. Athirdrouteconsidereddomainrestrictions.Asdefined,thedomainofaSWFcontains all the preference profiles. But it is wellknown that Arrow’s theorem fails on some restricted domains. For instance, majority rule creates collective preferences when preferences are singlepeaked; see Black (1948) and Wikipedia (2008d). In addition, majority ruleisconsistentwhenthereareonlytwoalternatives,thecaseexcludedby Arrow’stheorem.Quesada(2002)identifiesasubsetof LninwhichPARandIIAstill sufficetogeneratedictators.ForthesimplestcaseinwhichArrow’stheoremholds( n= 2and m=3),6profilesareidentifiedwhosepresencesufficeforPARandIIAtomake theSWFdictatorial(comparethemwiththe13profilesrequiredinFeldman’s(1980, ch.10)proof). ButmostefforthasbeendevotedtoascertaintheeffectsofweakeningIIA.Sincethe literature is immense, just three contributions are singled out for the purpose of illustration.OneisBaigent(1987),whoslightlyweakensIIAbyrequiringthatifP{x,y}

−10 − = Q{x,y}and xispreferredto yin f(P)then xispreferredorindifferentto yin f(Q).He showsthataSWFsatisfyingPARandthisweakeningofIIAhasaweakdictator. AsecondinterestingcontributionisDenicolò(1998),whoobtainsadictatorialSWFby replacingIIAwithRIDbelow.Defineanonemptysubset Iofindividualstoenforce x n ∈Aagainst y∈A\{x}ifforanypreferenceprofile P∈L suchthat xPI y thereissome n profile Q ∈ L satisfying P{x,y} = Q{x,y} and x f(Q) y.Thissaysthatwheneverall membersof Iprefer xto ythereissomewayofcompletingallthepreferencessothat x iscollectivelypreferredto y. RID.Relationalindependentdecisiveness.Forall x∈A, y∈A\{x}and I⊆N,if Ican enforce xagainst ythen Iisdecisivefor xagainst y. One of the most interesting recent contributions to the literature relaxing IIA is CampbellandKelly(2000),whoshowhoweasyitistoweakenIIAandobtainnon dictatorialSWFs. TurningtothecriticismstoArrow’stheorem,itisworthmentioningSaari(1998),who severelycriticizesIIA(andconditionMILinSen’stheorem);seealsoSaari(2001).In particular,hearguesthatIIAisaninappropriaterequirementforSWFsbecauseSWFs treat the transitivity of preferences as a valuable input and IIA is indifferent to the presenceorabsenceoftransitivity.Hispointisthatpreferenceaggregationprocedures satisfying IIA do not take into account the transitivity of preferences and that, accordingly,itdoesnotseemreasonabletoimposeonaproceduretakingtransitivity intoaccount(SWFs)apropertythatneglectsthatinformation.Heremarks(p.255):“If wemustbuildavehicleusingonlyoxenandcarts,donotexpectaPorsche.Similarly,if wecanonlyusecrudeunsophisticatedprocedures,donotexpectrationaloutcomes”. Quesada(2007)suggestsaninterpretationofSWFsthatmaylowerthenegativeimpact ofArrow’sresult.Arrow’stheoremhasbeenhailedasanegativeandundesirableresult because the outcome is the existence of a dictator,thatis,anindividualwhohashis preferencecoincidewiththecollectivepreference.Butadictatorissomethingtoworry aboutonlyincasesinwhichthedictator’spreferenceisnot“representative”.Thepaper showsthesenseinwhichadictatorcanbeseento never have more “power” than 3 votersnorlessthan2. PAR and IIA can be viewed as “vertical” conditions, because they refer to whether somealternativeisaboveanotheroneinapreferenceranking.Finally,Quesada(2003)

−11 − and Houi (2006) have suggested a conceptual twist to the analysis of preference aggregation:toconsider“horizontal”conditionsinstead,thatis,conditionstellinghow todeterminethealternativethatoccupiesacertainpositioninthecollectivepreference usingasinputthealternativesoccupyingthatpositionintheindividuals’preferences. Both authors show that positional conditions similar to PAR and IIA also generate dictatorialSWFs. 6. Sen’s theorem AsdiscussedinSection5,Arrow’stheoremisfatherofmany,manysons.Oneofthe mostreputedsonsisSen’stheorem,whichismotivatedbytheideaofhowmuchpower canaSWFascribetoindividuals.Inparticular,Sen(1970a,1970b)isconcernedwith thepossibilityofhavingSWFsthatare“liberal”inthesensethatallowsindividualsto retainaminimumoffreedom. Specifically, Sen’s motivating situation is the following: “Given other things in the society,ifyouprefertohavepinkwallsratherthanwhite,thensocietyshouldpermit youtohavethis,evenifamajority ofthe community would like to see your walls white”.Therefore,if x=“individual i’swallsarepink”and y=“individual i’swallsare white”then,for itoenjoyaveryweakformofindividualliberty, iwouldhavetobe decisive for x against y and for y against x: if i prefers x to y (or y to x) then the collective preference should adopt i’s view. Sen’s theorem asserts that no SWF satisfyingPARcansecurethisweakformofindividuallibertytotwoindividuals. Definition 6.1. Anonemptysubset Iofindividualsisdecisiveover{ x, y}inSWF fif I isbothdecisivefor xagainst yanddecisivefor yagainst x. MIL.Minimalliberalism.Thereare i∈I, j∈I\{i}, x∈A, y∈A\{x}, v∈Aand w∈ A\{v}suchthat{ i}isdecisiveover{ x, y}in fand{ j}isdecisiveover{ v, w}in f. Theorem 6.2. (Sen(1970a)).For n≥2and m≥2,thereisnoSWF fsatisfyingPARand MIL. Proof .Suppose fisaSWFsatisfyingPARandMIL.Therefore,thereare i∈I, j∈I\{i}, x∈A, y∈A\{x}, v∈Aand w∈A\{v}suchthat{ i}isdecisiveover{ x, y}in fand{ j} is decisive over { v, w} in f. By definition of decisiveness, { x, y} ≠ { v, w}: two individuals cannot be decisive over the same set. Despite this, there are two

−12 − possibilities.Case1:{ x, y} ∩{ v, w}= ∅.Consideranypreferenceprofile P∈Lnin which the restriction of the individuals’ preferences over the set { x, y, v, w} are as follows.

Pi Pj restofindividuals f (P) w y x x v w y → y y w x v v v x w

Bytheassumptionthat{ i}isdecisiveover{ x, y}, xPiyimplies xf(P) y.ByPAR, yPN vimplies yf(P) v.Consequently,byTRA, xf(P) yand yf(P) vimply xf(P) v.Bythe assumptionthat{ j}isdecisiveover{ v, w}, vPjwimplies vf(P) w.Thus,byTRA, x f(P) vand vf(P) wimply xf(P) w.BythiscontradictsPAR,because wf(P) x. Case2:{ x, y} ∩{ v, w}≠ ∅.Leftasanexercise.  Sen’s theorem has also generated a large literature; see, by way of illustration, Wriglesworth(1985)andWikipedia(2008e).

References Arrow,K.(1963): Social Choice and Individual Values ,2nded.,Wiley,NewYork. Baigent,N.(1987):“Twitchingweakdictators”,Journalof47,407 −411. Black, D. (1948): “On the rationale of group decisionmaking”, Journal of Political Economy56,23–34. Blair,D.andPollak,R.(1979):“Collectiverationalityanddictatorship:Thescopeof theArrowtheorem”,JournalofEconomicTheory21,186 −194. Campbell,D.and Kelly,J.(2000):“Informationand preference aggregation”, Social ChoiceandWelfare17,3 −24. Denicolò,V.(1998):“IndependentdecisivenessandtheArrowtheorem”,SocialChoice andWelfare15,563 −566. Houi,N.(2006):“Positionalindependenceinpreferenceaggregation:Aremark”,Social ChoiceandWelfare27,341 −345. Feldman,A.(1980): and ,MartinusNijhoff, Boston.

−13 − Kelly,J.S.(2008):“Socialchoicebibliography”,http://faculty.maxwell.syr.edu/jskelly/ biblioho.htm ,accessedthe27thOctober2008. MasColell,A.andSonnenschein,H.(1972):“Generalpossibilitytheoremsforgroup decisions”,ReviewofEconomicStudies39,185 −192. Moulin,H.(1994):“Socialchoice”,inAumann,R.and Hart, S. (eds.): Handbook of , volume 2 ,NorthHolland,Amsterdam,pp.1091 −1125. Quesada, A. (2002): “Preference profiles sustaining Arrow’s theorem”, Economic Theory20,623 −627. Quesada, A. (2003): “Positional independence in preference aggregation”, Social ChoiceandWelfare20,363 −370. Quesada,A.(2007):“1dictator=2voters”,PublicChoice130,395 −400. Saari, D. (1998): “Connecting and resolving Sen’s and Arrow’s theorems”, Social ChoiceandWelfare15,239 −261. Saari, D. (2001): Decisions and Elections: Explaining the Unexpected , Cambridge UniversityPress,Cambridge. Sen,A.(1970a):“TheimpossibilityofaParetianliberal”,JournalofPoliticalEconomy 78,152 −157. Sen,A.(1970b):Collective Choice and Social Welfare ,HoldenDay,SanFrancisco. Sen, A. (1986): “Social choice theory”, in Arrow, K. and Intriligator, M. (eds.): Handbook of , volume III ,NorthHolland,Amsterdam,pp. 1073 −1181. Sen,A.(1998):Prizelecturefor The Sveriges Riksbank Prize in Economic Sciences in Memory of Alfred Nobel 1998 , http://nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/ economics/laureates/1998/senlecture.pdf ,accessedthe27thofOctober,2008. Wikipedia(2008a): http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Condorcet_paradox ,accessedthe27th ofOctober,2008. Wikipedia (2008b): http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Arrow%27s_impossibility_theorem , accessedthe27thofOctober,2008. Wikipedia (2008c): http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Social_choice , accessed the 27th of October,2008. Wikipedia (2008d): http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Majority_rule , accessed the 27th of October,2008. Wikipedia(2008e): http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Liberal_paradox ,accessedthe27thof October,2008. Wilson,R.B. (1972):“SocialchoicewithouttheParetoprinciple”,JournalofEconomic Theory5,478 −486. Wriglesworth,J.(1985): Libertarian Conflicts in Social Choice ,CambridgeUniversity Press,Cambridge.

−14 −