Σ -Absoluteness in Forcing Extensions

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Σ -Absoluteness in Forcing Extensions 1 Σ3-Absoluteness in Forcing Extensions David Schrittesser June 2004 Diplomarbeit eingereicht zur Erlangung des akademischen Grades Magister der Naturwissenschaften an der Fakult¨atf¨urNaturwissenschaften und Mathematik der Universi¨atWien Betreuer: Sy Friedman Abstract 1 We investigate the consistency strength of the forcing axiom for Σ3 formulas, for various classes of forcings. We review that the consistency strength of 1 Σ3-absoluteness for all set forcing or even just for !1-preserving forcing is that of a reflecting cardinal. To get the same strength from the forcing axiom restricted to proper forcing, one can add the hypotheses that !1 is inaccessible to reals. Then we investigate the strength of the forcing axiom restricted to ccc forcing notions under this additional hypothesis; to gauge it we introduce a weak version of a weak compact cardinal, namely, a lightface 1 Σ2-indescribable cardinal. Contents 1 Preliminary facts 2 1.1 General set theory . 3 1.2 Forcing . 5 1.3 Reals . 14 1.4 Large cardinals . 18 2 Equiconsistency for set forcing 22 3 A lower bound for !1-preserving set-forcing 24 4 Coding and reshaping when !1 is inaccessible to reals 26 4.1 Preserving !1 ........................... 26 4.2 Preserving stationary subsets of !1 . 33 4.3 Proper forcing . 35 5 Forcing with the countable chain condition 39 1 5.1 Lightface Σ2-indescribable cardinals . 39 5.2 Coding using an Aronszajn-tree . 41 5.3 An equiconsistency . 43 1 1 Preliminary facts This section contains some definitions, well known facts and basic theorems which we will use throughout the present paper. First, we take a little time to fix our notation (we hope to include all M possible sources of confusion). For a structure M = hM; 2; P0;:::;Pki, L M denotes the language L = f2;P0;:::;Pkg. LX denotes the same language with constants for all the elements of X. We write M ≺ N to denote M elementarity (i.e. M and N have the same theory in LM ), and we write 00 π : M!Σ! N to express π is an elementary embedding (i.e. hran(π); π 2 00 00 ; π P0; : : : ; π Pki ≺ N ). For transitive models, we call the least ordinal α 2 M such that π(α) > α the critical point of π, and denote it by crit(π). For a structure N = hN; E; : : :i such that E is extensional and well-founded (and, in the case of a class sized structure, set-like), we denote its transitive collapse (that is, the unique structure hM; 2;:::i isomorphic to N and such that M is transitive) by tcoll(N ). By (φ)M we mean the formula φ holds relativized to a (possibly class-sized) structure M and by tM we mean the interpretation of a term t as from the viewpoint of M. When we talk about structures M = hM; 2; P0;:::;Pki, we sometimes omit listing the 2 as a predicate. When we use notation that is defined for structures in a context when we talk about sets M, it is implied we mean the structure hM; 2i. We denote the usual Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms by ZF , and that theory with AC (the axiom of choice) added by ZFC. ZF − and ZFC− denote the corresponding theories with the power set axiom deleted. When we talk about Skolem functions Fφ for a (possibly class-sized) struc- ture M, we consider M to be equipped with a well-ordering <M. Then, if M φ(x0; x1) is a formula of L with two free variables, for p 2 M, we define Fφ(p) to be the <M-least y 2 M such that M φ(y; p) if such y exists, and M to be ; otherwise. For X ⊆ M, we denote by hΣ! (X) the Skolem hull of X in N , that is the smallest (in the sense of ⊆) set Y ⊆ M s.t. Y ⊇ X that is M closed under all Skolem functions Fφ, for φ a formula of L . We use the familiar Σk; Πk; ∆k notation for the classes formulas that can be written with k blocks of equal quantifiers starting with 9 or 8 and for the intersection of these first two classes, respectively. We shall give a more thorough review of the analytical hierarchy in section 1.3; in section 5.1 we k quickly review the general Σn hierarchies of higher order formulas over a structure. We write Lim, Card, Reg for the class of limit ordinals, cardinals and regular cardinals respectively. For a set x, jxj is its cardinality, and we sometimes write x . y to mean that jxj < jyj. TC(x) denotes the transitive closure of x. For any cardinal κ, let Hκ denote the set of all x such that 2 TC(x) has size less than κ (i.e., the Hκ hierarchy is continuously defined also at singular cardinals). HC denotes H!1 , the set of hereditarily countable sets. As far as forcing is concerned, we sometimes write V P for a generic ex- tension V [G], where G is P -generic over V , if the particular G concerned is of no importance. We write dots over names (e.g.q _) andq _[G] for the interpretation of the nameq _ by a generic G. For sets a in the ground model we writea ˇ for the \standard name" for a. 1.1 General set theory 1.1 Definition. 1. C ⊂ [A]! is called cub if, and only if, there are predi- cates P1;:::;Pk ⊂ A such that ! C = fX 2 [A] j hX; P1;:::;Pki ≺ hA; P1;:::;Pkig 2. S ⊂ [A]! is called stationary if, and only if, for all cub sets C ⊂ [A]!, S \ C 6= ; 1.2 Fact. Let N = hN; R0;:::Rki, X 2 Hκ and X ⊆ N. Then there exists 0 0 a transitive M 2 Hκ s.t. X ⊆ M together with R0;:::Rk ⊆ M, and an 0 0 elementary embedding i : hM; R0;:::Rki !Σ! hN; R0;:::Rki s.t. i is the identity on X. Proof. First observe that since X 2 Hκ, also TC(X) 2 Hκ, whence we can assume X to be transitive. Now start by taking the Skolem-hull (with respect to the language where the additional predicates have been added): ¯ N ¯ ¯ let M := hΣ (X). M has size less than κ. Set M := tcoll(M), the transitive !¯ collapse of M. Being transitive and of size less than κ, M 2 Hκ. Let i be the inverse of the collapsing map (the new predicates are just the pullbacks of the original predicates). As X ⊆ M¯ was transitive, i is the identity on X. M 1.3 Fact. If N is transitive and λ + 1 ⊆ M ≺ N, then (Hλ+ ) is transitive. M Proof. Let x 2 (Hλ+ ) be arbitrary, we show x ⊆ M. M \9f : λ TC(x)", and so by elementarity, for some f 2 M, N \f : λ TC(x)". Now for arbitrary y 2 x, we have y = f(ξ) for some ξ 2 λ, while λ ⊆ M. It is easily checked that f; ξ 2 M by elementarity implies f(ξ) 2 M, so y 2 M. 1.4 Corollary. Let A be any set of ordinals, κ a successor cardinal. Then C := f α < κ j Lα[A] ≺ Lκ[A] g is cub in κ. 3 Proof. For ξ < κ, let χ(ξ) denote the least ordinal such that Skolem functions for Lκ[A] on Lξ[A] have values in Lχ(ξ)[A]. Then χ : κ ! κ and C is precisely the set of closure points of χ, hence cub. − 1.5 Fact. If M ZF is transitive, π : M !Σ! N an elementary embedding M M with critical point α, then α 2 Reg and π Hα = id. Proof. Assume M thinks α is singular; then there is a function f in M, with domain an ordinal below α and values below α whose range is cofinal in α. But as all these ordinals are not moved by π, π(f) = f and thus α = sup(ran(f)) = sup(ran(π(f))) = π(sup(ran(f))) = π(α), contradiction. As π α = id, α ⊆ ran(π). By hypothesis ran(π) ≺ N, we can apply 1.3: ran(π) ran(π) 00 M for each λ < α,(Hλ+ ) is transitive. So (Hπ(α)) = π (Hα) (as the union of these transitive sets) is seen to be transitive. Note that as the transitive collapse of any set A is uniquely defined as the transitive set isomorphic to A, we have that M must be the transitive collapse of ran(π) and π must be the inverse of the collapsing map. As the collapsing map is M just the identity on any transitive set, π is the identity on (Hα) . 1.6 Fact. Let M = hM; R1;:::;Rki, N = hN; S1;:::;Sri, be models such that k ≤ r, Ri has the same arity as Si for i ≤ k, and M is countable. Then the statement 9π; 9Rk+1;:::;Rr π : hM; R1;:::;Rri !Σ! hN; S1;:::;Sri (1) is absolute for transitive models U of ZF − such that U contains both N and ∼ M and U M = !. Proof. Let m : ! ! M be an enumeration of M,(φi)i2! an enumeration of formulas of the language of N . Let γ : ! ! !, δ : ! ! <!! be such N that together, they enumerate all formulas of the language LM (the language of N with constants for all the elements of M) in the following sense: for all n, ran(δ(n)) ⊆ n, the number of free variables of φγ(n) is no larger than dom(δ(n)), and γ and δ are onto in the sense that φγ(n)(m(s(0)); : : : ; m(s(l))), N for s = δ(n) and l = lh(s) − 1, runs through all formulas of LM as n runs through !.
Recommended publications
  • UCLA Electronic Theses and Dissertations
    UCLA UCLA Electronic Theses and Dissertations Title The Combinatorics and Absoluteness of Definable Sets of Real Numbers Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/0v60v6m4 Author Norwood, Zach Publication Date 2018 Peer reviewed|Thesis/dissertation eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA Los Angeles ¿e Combinatorics and Absoluteness of Denable Sets of Real Numbers A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Philosophy in Mathematics by Zach Norwood 2018 © Copyright by Zach Norwood 2018 ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION ¿e Combinatorics and Absoluteness of Denable Sets of Real Numbers by Zach Norwood Doctor of Philosophy in Mathematics University of California, Los Angeles, 2018 Professor Itay Neeman, Chair ¿is thesis divides naturally into two parts, each concerned with the extent to which the theory of LR can be changed by forcing. ¿e rst part focuses primarily on applying generic-absoluteness principles to show that denable sets of reals enjoy regularity properties. ¿e work in Part I is joint with Itay Neeman and is adapted from our forthcoming paper [33]. ¿is project was motivated by questions about mad families, maximal families of innite subsets of ω any two of which have only nitely many members in common. We begin, in the spirit of Mathias [30], by establishing (¿eorem 2.8) a strong Ramsey property for sets of reals in the Solovay model, giving a new proof of Törnquist’s theorem [48] that there are no innite mad families in the Solovay model. In Chapter3 we stray from the main line of inquiry to briey study a game-theoretic characteri- zation of lters with the Baire Property.
    [Show full text]
  • The Virtual Large Cardinal Hierarchy
    The Virtual Large Cardinal Hierarchy Stamatis Dimopoulos, Victoria Gitman and Dan Saattrup Nielsen September 10, 2020 Abstract. We continue the study of the virtual large cardinal hierarchy, initi- ated in [GS18], by analysing virtual versions of superstrong, Woodin, Vopěnka, and Berkeley cardinals. Gitman and Schindler showed that virtualizations of strong and supercompact cardinals yield the same large cardinal notion [GS18]. We show the same result for a (weak) virtualization of Woodin and a virtual- ization of Vopěnka cardinals. We also show that there is a virtually Berkeley cardinal if and only if the virtual Vopěnka principle holds, but On is not Mahlo. Contents 1 Introduction 1 2 Preliminaries 3 3 Virtually supercompact cardinals 4 4 Virtual Woodin and Vopěnka cardinals 12 5 Virtual Berkeley cardinals 18 6 Questions 24 A Chart of virtual large cardinals 25 1 Introduction The study of generic large cardinals, being cardinals that are critical points of elementary embeddings existing in generic extensions, goes back to the 1970’s. At that time, the primary interest was the existence of precipitous and saturated ideals on small cardinals like !1 and !2. Research in this area later moved to the study of more general generic embeddings, both defined on V , but also on rank-initial segments of V — these were investigated by e.g. [DL89] and [FG10]. 1 The move to virtual large cardinals happened when [Sch00] introduced the remarkable cardinals, which it turned out later were precisely a virtualization of supercompactness. Various other virtual large cardinals were first investi- gated in [GS18]. The key difference between virtual large cardinals and generic versions of large cardinals studied earlier is that in the virtual case we require the embedding to be between sets with the target model being a subset of the ground model.
    [Show full text]
  • Hierarchies of Forcing Axioms, the Continuum Hypothesis and Square Principles
    HIERARCHIES OF FORCING AXIOMS, THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS AND SQUARE PRINCIPLES GUNTER FUCHS Abstract. I analyze the hierarchies of the bounded and the weak bounded forcing axioms, with a focus on their versions for the class of subcomplete for- cings, in terms of implications and consistency strengths. For the weak hier- archy, I provide level-by-level equiconsistencies with an appropriate hierarchy of partially remarkable cardinals. I also show that the subcomplete forcing axiom implies Larson's ordinal reflection principle at !2, and that its effect on the failure of weak squares is very similar to that of Martin's Maximum. 1. Introduction The motivation for this work is the wish to explore forcing axioms for subcom- plete forcings in greater detail. Subcomplete forcing was introduced by Jensen in [18]. It is a class of forcings that do not add reals, preserve stationary subsets of !1, but may change cofinalities to be countable, for example. Most importantly, subcomplete forcing can be iterated, using revised countable support. Examples of subcomplete forcings include all countably closed forcings, Namba forcing (assu- ming CH), Pˇr´ıkr´yforcing (see [19] for these facts), generalized Pˇr´ıkr´yforcing (see [24]), and the Magidor forcing to collapse the cofinality of a measurable cardinal of sufficiently high Mitchell order to !1 (see [10]). Since subcomplete forcings can be iterated, they naturally come with a forcing axiom, the subcomplete forcing axiom, SCFA, formulated in the same way as Mar- tin's axiom or the proper forcing axiom PFA. The overlap between proper forcings and subcomplete forcings is minimal, though. Proper forcings can add reals, which subcomplete forcings cannot.
    [Show full text]
  • Large Cardinals As Principles of Structural Reflection
    LARGE CARDINALS AS PRINCIPLES OF STRUCTURAL REFLECTION JOAN BAGARIA Abstract. After discussing the limitations inherent to all set- theoretic reflection principles akin to those studied by A. L´evy et. al. in the 1960’s, we introduce new principles of reflection based on the general notion of Structural Reflection and argue that they are in strong agreement with the conception of reflec- tion implicit in Cantor’s original idea of the unknowability of the Absolute, which was subsequently developed in the works of Ack- ermann, L´evy, G¨odel, Reinhardt, and others. We then present a comprehensive survey of results showing that different forms of the new principles of Structural Reflection are equivalent to well-known large cardinals axioms covering all regions of the large-cardinal hi- erarchy, thereby justifying the naturalness of the latter. In the framework of Zermelo-Fraenkel (ZF) set theory1 the universe V of all sets is usually represented as a stratified cumulative hierarchy V V of sets indexed by the ordinal numbers. Namely, = Sα∈OR α, where V0 = ∅ Vα+1 = P(Vα), namely the set of all subsets of Vα, and Vλ = Sα<λ Vα, if λ is a limit ordinal. This view of the set-theoretic universe justifies a posteriori the ZF axioms. For not only all ZF axioms are true in V , but they are also necessary to build V . Indeed, the axioms of Extensionality, pairing, Union, Power-set, and Separation are used to define the set-theoretic operation given by G(x)= [{P(y): ∃z(hz,yi ∈ x)}. The axiom of Replacement is then needed to prove by transfinite recur- arXiv:2107.01580v1 [math.LO] 4 Jul 2021 sion that the operation V on the ordinals given by V (α)= G(V ↾ α) is well-defined and unique.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:2101.04552V1
    STRUCTURAL REFLECTION, SHREWD CARDINALS AND THE SIZE OF THE CONTINUUM PHILIPP LUCKE¨ Abstract. Motivated by results of Bagaria, Magidor and V¨a¨an¨anen, we study character- izations of large cardinal properties through reflection principles for classes of structures. More specifically, we aim to characterize notions from the lower end of the large cardinal hierarchy through the principle SR− introduced by Bagaria and V¨a¨an¨anen. Our results isolate a narrow interval in the large cardinal hierarchy that is bounded from below by total indescribability and from above by subtleness, and contains all large cardinals that can be characterized through the validity of the principle SR− for all classes of structures defined by formulas in a fixed level of the L´evy hierarchy. Moreover, it turns out that no property that can be characterized through this principle can provably imply strong inaccessibility. The proofs of these results rely heavily on the notion of shrewd cardinals, introduced by Rathjen in a proof-theoretic context, and embedding characterizations of these cardinals that resembles Magidor’s classical characterization of supercompactness. In addition, we show that several important weak large cardinal properties, like weak 1 inaccessibility, weak Mahloness or weak Πn-indescribability, can be canonically character- ized through localized versions of the principle SR−. Finally, the techniques developed in the proofs of these characterizations also allow us to show that Hamkin’s weakly compact 1 embedding property is equivalent to L´evy’s notion of weak Π1-indescribability. 1. Introduction The work presented in this paper is motivated by results of Bagaria, Magidor, V¨a¨an¨anen and others that establish deep connections between extensions of the Downward L¨owenheim– Skolem Theorem, large cardinal axioms and set-theoretic reflection principles.
    [Show full text]
  • PFA Implies AD
    PFA implies ADL(R). J.R. Steel September 25, 2007 In this paper we shall prove Theorem 0.1 Suppose there is a singular strong limit cardinal κ such that κ fails; then AD holds in L(R). See [11] for a discussion of the background to this problem. We suspect that more work will produce a proof of the theorem with its hypothesis that κ is a strong limit weakened to ∀α < κ(αω < κ), and significantly more work will enable one to drop the hypothesis that κ is a strong limit entirely. At present, we do not see how to carry out even the less ambitious project. Todorcevic ([23]) has shown that if the Proper Forcing Axiom (PFA) holds, then κ fails for all uncountable cardinals κ. Thus we get immediately: Corollary 0.2 PFA implies ADL(R). It has been known since the early 90’s that PFA implies PD, that PFA plus the existence of a strongly inaccessible cardinal implies ADL(R), and that PFA plus a measurable yields 1 an inner model of ADR containing all reals and ordinals. As we do here, these arguments made use of Tororcevic’s work, so that logical strength is ultimately coming from a failure of covering for some appropriate core models. In late 2000, A.S. Zoble and the author showed that (certain consequences of) Todorce- vic’s Strong Reflection Principle (SRP) imply ADL(R). (See [22].) Since Martin’s Maximum implies SRP, this gave the first derivation of ADL(R) from an “unaugmented” forcing axiom.2 It should be possible to adapt the techniques of Ketchersid’s thesis [2], and thereby + strengthen the conclusions of 0.1 and 0.2 to: there is an inner model of AD plus Θ0 < Θ 1 1 The first result is due to Woodin, relying heavily on Schimmerling’s proof of ∆2 determinacy from PFA.
    [Show full text]
  • CHAPTER Determinacy and Large Cardinals
    UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA Los Angeles ¿e Combinatorics and Absoluteness of Denable Sets of Real Numbers A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Philosophy in Mathematics by Zach Norwood 2018 © Copyright by Zach Norwood 2018 ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION ¿e Combinatorics and Absoluteness of Denable Sets of Real Numbers by Zach Norwood Doctor of Philosophy in Mathematics University of California, Los Angeles, 2018 Professor Itay Neeman, Chair ¿is thesis divides naturally into two parts, each concerned with the extent to which the theory of LR can be changed by forcing. ¿e rst part focuses primarily on applying generic-absoluteness principles to show that denable sets of reals enjoy regularity properties. ¿e work in Part I is joint with Itay Neeman and is adapted from our forthcoming paper [33]. ¿is project was motivated by questions about mad families, maximal families of innite subsets of ω any two of which have only nitely many members in common. We begin, in the spirit of Mathias [30], by establishing (¿eorem 2.8) a strong Ramsey property for sets of reals in the Solovay model, giving a new proof of Törnquist’s theorem [48] that there are no innite mad families in the Solovay model. In Chapter3 we stray from the main line of inquiry to briey study a game-theoretic characteri- zation of lters with the Baire Property. Neeman and Zapletal [36] showed, assuming roughly the existence of a proper class of Woodin cardinals, that the boldface theory of LR cannot be changed by proper forcing. ¿ey call their result the Embedding ¿eorem, because they conclude that in fact there is an elementary embedding from the ground-model LR to the LR of any proper forcing extension that xes every ordinal and every real.
    [Show full text]