Wawrzyniec Rymkiewicz, Editorial Introduction

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Wawrzyniec Rymkiewicz, Editorial Introduction PHILOSOPHICAL JOURNAL VOLUME II / 2013 / ISSN: 1899–9484 Wawrzyniec Rymkiewicz, Editorial Introduction . 2 Wawrzyniec Rymkiewicz, The Philosopher of Chaos . A Portrait of Schelling . 3 Paweł Dybel, The Question of Ethics in the Thought of Hei degger and Gadamer . 26 Piotr Augustyniak, “Theologia Germanica” as a Critique of the Modern Lifestyle . 51 Piotr Graczyk, Materialist History of Ideas . Warsaw – Frankfurt – Paris . 59 Mateusz Werner, The Polish Dialectic of Enlightenment . Legends of Modernity . 67 Andrzej Wawrzynowicz, August Cieszkowski’s Historiosophical Holism . 73 Piotr Nowak, Apocalypse and Politics . Some Remarks on the Political Theology of Jacob Taubes . 83 Rafał Kuczyński, Demonic Censorship . .. 97 Grzegorz Czemiel, Remembering Being . A philosophical reading of Ciaran Carson’s On The Night Watch . 101 Marta Olesik, What is there to be found on the heap of history? – the experience of time, particularity and negativity in Benjamin and Doctorow . 117 Irena Księżopolska, Visible Worlds and the Art of Narration: Cultivation of Unreliability Through Visualization by Vladimir Nabokov and Italo Calvino . 136 Marcin Rychter, How Music Turned into Philosophy and What Implications Does This Have? . 158 Notes on Authors . 165 Contributors: Piotr Augustyniak, Grzegorz Czemiel, Paweł Dybel, Piotr Graczyk, Bernhard Klein, Irena Księżpolska, Rafał Kuczyński, Piotr Nowak, Marta Olesik, Krzysztof Rosiński, Marcin Rychter, Wawrzyniec Rymkiewicz (editor-in- chief), Renata Senktas, Andrzej Wawrzynowicz, Mateusz Werner, Mikołaj Wiśniewski. Published by Fundacja Augusta hr . Cieszkowskiego ul. Mianowskiego 15/65, 02-044 Warszawa, Poland ISSN: 1899–9484 This project was financed by the Ministry of Science and Higher Education as part of the "National Programme for the Development of Humanities" 2012-2014. All material remains © copyright of the respective authors . Please address all queries to the editor at the following address . redakcja@kronos .org .pl Wawrzyniec Rymkiewicz EDITORIAL INTRODUCTION “Kronos” quarterly was established in 2007 as a project of a particular generation of philos- ophers all of whom started their studies around the transitional year 1989. “Kronos” soon became the largest philosophical journal in Poland. It is a new voice in Polish philosophy. Poland at the turn of the 21st century was and is an inspiring place for thinkers; it is an interesting vantage point for observing and studying human nature. It is a place which saw genocide and two murderous experiments – the Nazi and the Soviet – the aim of which was to create a new type of human being. A philosopher brought up in Warsaw is living in a city destroyed by Hitler and rebuilt by Stalin. The place and the time when we started studying philosophy influenced our choices and interests. Perhaps a philosopher is nothing but an emanation of the place and time which shaped him. These factors no doubt explain our interest in Hegel and Marx whom we have read through the lenses provided by religious messianists (Fyodorov) or 20th century prophets of the apocalypse (Kojève and Witkacy). The spirit of time and place prompted us also to study the Classics, to return in thought to Greece where – influenced by Hei degger and Nietzsche – we saw the eternally recurring point, where all history ends and every history begins. 2 2013 Wawrzyniec Rymkiewicz THE PHILOSOPHER OF CHAOS. A PORTRAIT OF SCHELLING And the earth was without form, and void; and darkness was upon the face of the deep. King James Bible, Genesis 1:2 Great philosophy exists in fragments. The Presocratics are in fragments. Pascal’s Thoughts and Nietzsche’s Will to Power are in fragments, too. This fragmentariness, this dispersion, this textual chaos, however, does not diminish philosophy. Nor does it obstruct the understanding of it. This has been observed by the most influential minds of the 20th century, Hei degger and Wittgenstein, who also abandoned the idea of a philosophical masterwork at some point and chose their last books, Contributions to Philosophy and Philosophical Investigations, to be published as collections of loose thoughts, notes and outlines. In this universe of fragments, in this tangle of fractions (its other name being “the European tradition”), Schelling’s late philosophy appears to be a unique galaxy. His treatise Of Human Freedom which appeared in 1809 marks the date after which Schelling did not publish any major philosophical work. Schelling falls silent, and he does so at the age of 34, almost Christ’s age. For the rest of his life he kept working on a piece which he could not finish, the more coherent form of which will be known in the 1840s as the Berlin lectures. Those lectures on the Philosophy of Mythology and Revelation were published posthumously by Schelling’s son, Karl, who is considered to have imposed on them his own order and made them a whole which they had not been originally. Schelling’s reader faces an unusual textual universe – a universe devoid of a mas- terwork (and thus devoid of a Center), where everything is a lecture (and is thus an oc- casional text intended for a particular audience), a universe full of compilations (Karl Schelling completed the Berlin lectures with the help of earlier manuscripts), and existing in many copies and transcripts (today’s editions of Schelling’s lectures of the 1820s and 30s are based on his students’ notes). In this universe one can encounter some strange objects, for example, the so-called Paulus-Nachschrift, which is a transcription of Schell- ing’s winter term 1841/42 lectures, published against his will by one of his students, Hei nrich Paulus, under the title Die endlich offenbar gewordene positive Philosophie der Offenbarung (The Finally Revealed Positive Philosophy of Revelation). Schelling sued Paulus but he lost the case. Still, the researchers today consider this work – the work of 2013 3 Wawrzyniec Rymkiewicz Schelling-Paulus or Paulus-Schelling – to be an important source of knowledge about the development of Schelling’s thought1. The dark center of this universe constitutes a group of texts written between 1810 and 1820, published as Die Weltalter (The Ages of the World). This was the last time when Schelling tried to write a philosophical work, and the first time he did not succeed. All that happened later was a result of this catastrophe. THE CATASTROPHE OF THE WELTALTER The first version of The Ages of the World was ready in the late summer of 1810. Schell- ing’s diary contains the following entry on September 15: “3 of the Ages of the World drafted.” But serious work on the book began only three months later: “The Ages of the World – Schelling noted on December 27 – started at last.”2 The previous night a violent storm hit Munich. The scene is very symbolic: the storm has passed, it is morning now, Schelling begins to write a book about God who rises from chaos.3 The book is supposed to consist of three parts, each of which is to describe one of the Aeons, or metaphysical dimensions of Time: past, present and future. Schelling’s initial belief was that the completion of the book would not take him more than half a year: “For two months – Schelling writes in a letter to his publisher on January 30, 1811 – I have been constantly immersed in work. The book that I have been pondering over for many years should finally emerge before Easter.”4 ‘Book One’ of The Ages of the World, entitled “The Past”, was indeed composed before Easter of that year and printed for proofread- ing. However, there soon occurred some difficulty, a discord of some kind, which caused Schelling to postpone the completion of the book. At first, until July. Then, until late summer. Finally, until Easter 1812. In November, however, Schelling had to stop work- ing in order to write a response to Jacobi’s polemic against him, titled Von den göttlichen Dingen und ihrer Offenbarung (Of Divine Things and Their Revelation). He published the response without delay and returned to his work on the Weltalter in February 1812. Still, rather than finish the book, he began writing it anew. That is how Schelling created the second (known to us) version of The Ages of the World, which he then published at his own expense at the turn of 1813. This second version also consisted of only the first book, “The Past.”5 Also in this case its printing would soon be suspended. Thus, in the autumn of 1813, Schelling began writing The Ages of the World for the third time. This is the most comprehensive version of all that are available to us today. While working on it, Schelling felt that he would thus give the sum of his life: “I regard 1 Its latest edition is due to Manfred Frank’s effort, see: F.W.J. Schelling, Philosophie der Offenbarung: 1841/1842. Frankfurt/M, 1992. 2 F.W.J.Schelling, Philosophische Entwürfe und Tagebücher 1809 – 1813, hrsg. von L.Knatz, H.J. Sandkühler, M.Schraven. Hamburg 1994, pp. 52, 58. Unless otherwise stated, the quoted fragments are given in a working translation prepared for the purpose of this publication. 3 See: X. Tilliette, Schelling, Biographie. Paris 1999, p. 219. For a detailed reconstruction of the process of writing The Ages of the World, see also: A. Lanfranconi, Krisis. Eine Lektüre der „Weltalter“-Texte F.W.J. Schellings. Stuttgard, Bad-Canstatt 1992, pp. 59-79. 4 Schelling und Cotta. Briefwechsel 1803-1849, hrsg. von H. Fuhrmans and L.Loher. Stuttgart 1965, p. 50. 5 The two first versions were published a hundred and thirty five years later by Martin Schröter, see: F.W.J von Schelling, Die Weltalter. Fragmente. In den Urfassungen von 1811 und 1813. München 1946. 4 2013 THE PHILOSOPHER OF CHAOS . A PORTRAIT OF SCHELLING this work – we read in his letter of August 19, 1814 – to be the fruit of all my labors over the past twenty years.
Recommended publications
  • PHILOSOPHICAL (PRE)OCCUPATIONS and the PROBLEM of IDEALISM: from Ideology to Marx’S Critique of Mental Labor
    PHILOSOPHICAL (PRE)OCCUPATIONS AND THE PROBLEM OF IDEALISM: From Ideology to Marx’s Critique of Mental Labor by Ariane Fischer Magister, 1999, Freie Universität Berlin M.A., 2001, The Ohio State University M.Phil., 2005, The George Washington University A Dissertation submitted to The Faculty of Columbian College of Arts and Sciences of The George Washington University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy January 31, 2010 Dissertation directed by Andrew Zimmerman Associate Professor of History The Columbian College of The George Washington University certifies that Ariane Fischer has passed the Final Examination for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy as of August 25, 2009. This is the final and approved form of the dissertation. PHILOSOPHICAL (PRE)OCCUPATIONS AND THE PROBLEM OF IDEALISM: From Ideology to Marx’s Critique of Mental Labor Ariane Fischer Dissertation Research Committee: Andrew Zimmerman, Associate Professor of History, Dissertation Director Peter Caws, University Professor of Philosophy, Committee Member Gail Weiss, Professor of Philosophy, Committee Member ii © Copyright 2010 by Ariane Fischer All rights reserved iii Acknowledgments The author wishes to thank her dissertation advisor Andrew Zimmerman, who has been a continuous source of support and encouragement. His enthusiastic yet demanding guidance has been invaluable. Both his superior knowledge of history and theory as well as his diligence in reviewing drafts have been crucial in the successful completion of the research and writing process. Further, many thanks are extended to Gail Weiss and Peter Caws for joining the dissertation committee, and to Dan Moschenberg and Paul Smith for agreeing to be readers.
    [Show full text]
  • August Cieszkowski's Philosophy of Future
    3(1)/2015 ISSN 2300–7648 / DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.12775/SetF.2015.002 Received: Octobre17, 2014. Accepted: January 9, 2015 Does the change have to be revolutionary... Does the change have to be revolutionary? August Cieszkowski’s philosophy of future MARCIN LISIECKI Uniwersytet Mikołaja Kopernika w Toruniu [email protected] Abstract. The main purpose of this article is analysis of question of future in philosophy of August Cieszkowski. Amog Polish philosophers Cieszkowski was one of the most important thinker, who creatively developed the philosophy of George Hegel, added new question, such as “future”. For clarity of analysis the essay is divided into two parts. The first part is connected with problem of future in Cieszkowski’s philosophy with references to social and religious fields. The second one included analysis of relations between social and religious changes and revolution. Keywords: August Cieszkowski; George Hegel; Young Hegelians; future, revolution; religion; social change. There was nothing I had considered more than the concept of destiny Charles Fourier, Théorie des quatre mouvements August Cieszkowski having emerged in the world-wide philosophy was the event that must be regarded as exceptional. That – almost panegyric – judgment results mainly from the importance of his thought and from the fact that he is apparently the only Polish XIX-century philosopher rec- ognized and highly valued abroad. We can also claim that he is much more 3(1)/2015, 213–226 213 MARCIN LISIECKI popular with Western philosophers than in Poland. As a philosopher, Ciesz- kowski was appreciated mainly for his work Prolegomena to a Historiosophy (Prolegomena zur Historiosophie, 1838), in which he included a couple of essential thoughts related to the revision of Georg W.
    [Show full text]
  • [2016 8-Koscielny.Pdf] 36 Pages, 945KB
    Illiberal Memory: How the Far Right is Rewriting History in Post-socialist Poland Pawel Koscielny Summer 2016 Pawel Koscielny is a graduate student in the Department of History at the University of California, Berkeley. Illiberal Memory: How the Far Right is Rewriting History in Post-socialist Poland In the Fall of 2015, the Law and Justice Party (PIS) took power in Poland and began undermining the pillars of Polish liberal democracy. The Western press quickly became obsessed with the question: how is it that economically vibrant Poland, the success story of post-socialist transition, has turned its back on European liberal values? The question is daunting, and I can only offer part of the explanation here. In this paper I trace an overlooked current in Polish post-socialist culture: the revival of extreme nationalism rooted in 19th century Romantic Messianism and the practice of ‘martyrology’ by the far-right press. I examine the historical myths pushed by Paweł Lisicki’s magazines Historia Do Rzeczy and Uważam Rze Historia and discuss how they have prepared a neo-nationalist counter-hegemony in Polish public discourse. I lend particular focus to how the relationship between Poland and Europe/the West are mythologized, and conclude with a psychoanalytically inflected discourse theory of how these myths function to legitimize the ideology of PIS. In the addendum I revisit the deep roots of Polish Messianism and the Martyrological practice and reflect on their revival in the far right press as part of a wider cultural development in the post-Socialist order. Mnemomachia In 1989 a process that the historian Andrzej Nowak dubbed mnemomachia began in Poland.1 He refers to the ‘clash of memory’ which erupted in the conditions of relaxed censorship and free markets brought on by the transformation of the Party-State and the end of USSR oversight.
    [Show full text]
  • Vico, Hegel and a New Historicism
    Hegelians on the Slopes of Vesuvius: A Transnational Study in the Intellectual History of Naples, 1799-1861 Alessandro De Arcangelis, University College London Thesis submitted for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy, University College London, April 2018 I, Alessandro De Arcangelis, confirm that the work presented in this thesis is my own. Where information has been derived from other sources, I confirm that this has been indicated in the thesis. 2 Acknowledgments I would like to express my gratitude to all the people who supported me in this challenging and exciting journey and contributed, in many ways, to its development and completion. Working with my main supervisor, Prof. Axel Körner, has been a terrific experience and I am deeply grateful for his undefeated enthusiasm, impeccable support, steady encouragement and, above all, for offering me so many opportunities to grow as a researcher. My second supervisor, Prof. Avi Lifschitz, has always been a dedicated mentor, whose point of view has been helping me improve my way of engaging with intellectual history since the very first day of my MA degree in 2013. I genuinely hope that the future may hold many more opportunities for me to work with them. A special mention goes to Dr. Fernanda Gallo: our common passion for Neapolitan Hegelianism has introduced us to a priceless friendship and enabled us to work together on several projects during the last year. Dr. Maurizio Isabella provided me with useful comments that greatly helped my argument to come into focus, as did Prof. Gareth Stedman Jones in 2015 and 2017. I also want to thank Dr.
    [Show full text]
  • Making Hegel Into a Better Hegelian: August Von Cieszkowski
    Making Hegel Into a Better Hegelian: August von Cieszkowski LAWRENCE S. STEPELEVICH AMONG STUDENTS OF the so-called "Young Hegelians," it is usual to name David F. Strauss (18o8-1874) as the first to develop Hegelianism after Hegel? He did not, however, see his role as anything more than being a disciple of what he understood to be orthodox Hegelianism. In merely ap- plying what he conscientiously took to be the authentic principles of the master to a hitherto unexamined field, i.e., biblical criticism, Strauss joined himself to the older school of orthodox and conservative Hegelians. These "Epigonen" were not displeased to consider themselves as but the satraps of a vanished philosophical Alexander who had been left with only the uncre- ative task of dividing and cultivating an already conquered Geisterreich/ In short, Strauss was not the first critic of Hegel, but merely the first Hegelian critic. The honor, if that is the correct term, of being the first Hegelian to criticize Hegel and thereby to create a "neo-Hegelianism" belongs to August von Cieszkowski ( x 814-1894 ). This paper has two main intentions: first, to determine the nature of Cieszkowski's radical critique of Hegel's philosophy of history, along with the reasons Cieszkowski employed to justify his critique, and second, to submit a possible objection that Hegel might have taken in regard to the corrective surgery that Cieszkowksi performed upon the corpus of his philosophy. There were indeed a number of critical studies directed against Hegel's philosophy well before Strauss's work appeared as well as a number of sympathetic studies (e.g., G6schel's Aphorismen of 18~9), but whereas the former took a stance against Hegel and the latter more or less repeated Hegel, Strauss was the first to attempt to apply Hegelianism, and in this sense he can be properly said to have "developed" it.
    [Show full text]
  • “History Is the Spectre Haunting Modern Society”: Temporality and Praxis in Guy Debord's Hegelian Marxism
    PARRHESIA NUMBER 20 • 2014 • 62-86 “HISTORY IS THE SPECTRE HAUNTING MODERN SOCIETY”: TEMPORALITY AND PRAXIS IN GUY DEBORD’S HEGELIAN MARXISM Tom Bunyard Within fields associated with the conjunction of Western Marxism and philosophy, the work of Guy Debord and the Situationist International (S.I.) often tends to receive rather less attention than it deserves. Whilst focussing on their famous concept of ‘spectacle’, this essay will try to show that Debord’s work may offer a richer resource to contemporary political philosophy than might otherwise be imagined. We will begin with a brief discussion of some of the problems and trends that have coloured the academic reception of this material, before presenting an initial interpretation of Debord’s account. This will serve to relate the concept of spectacle to the S.I.’s broader aims and ambitions.2 Our principal aim, however, is not simply to develop a reading of Debord and the S.I.’s critique of spectacular society per se, but rather to show that spectacle should also be seen to function as a much broader historical and ethical problematic. Addressing it in this manner can serve to high- light the theory of communism qua collective historical praxis that it contains. The approach attempted here is thus intended to augment more explicitly Marxian readings of Debord’s treatment of capital and commodities, by indicating the broader, more existential and Hegelian conceptions of temporality, subjectivity and agency that support his analyses, and which inform the wider conceptual framework that underlies his mature oeuvre. Developing this reading will thus require a discussion of some of the philosophical positions that support Debord’s claims.
    [Show full text]