Universals As Respects of Sameness

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Universals As Respects of Sameness Universals as Respects of Sameness Howard Joseph James Peacock University College London PhD (Philosophy) Õ Declaration I hereby declare that the work presented in this thesis is my own. Signed: Date: ó Abstract is thesis argues for realism about universals — the view that, in addition to particular things, there exist universals instantiated by those particular things. e rst half presents a positive case for realism. Here it is claimed that universals are needed in our ontology to serve as the respects in which things are the same, and the features or characteristics that things have in common. is argument is defended against nominalist responses, rst, that our apparent ‘ontological commitment’ to features and characteristics is not genuine; and second, that the same theoretical work can be achieved by treating respects of sameness as sets of particulars or sets of tropes rather than sui generis universals. e second half of the thesis defends the realist against the most serious objections to an ontology of universals. ese are the problems arising from the realist’s obligation to ascribe referential function to predicates, and the family of diculties known as ‘‘Bradley’s Regress’’. By addressing both the reasons to believe in universals, and the alleged reasons not to believe in universals, it is hoped that a coherent case for realism is achieved. ì Table of Contents Section Page Title Page Õ Declaration ó Abstract ì Table of Contents ¦ Preface ¢ Chapter Õ: e Problem of Universals Õþ Chapter ó: Ontological Evasions ¦ä Chapter ì: Doing without Universals? Chapter ¦: Predicates and Universals Õóþ Chapter ¢: Bradley’s Regress: I Õä¦ Chapter ä: Bradley’s Regress: II óþ¦ Aerword óì¦ References óìß ¦ Preface Our attempts to describe similarities between objects seem to embody a theory about the nature of resemblance itself. Confronted with two similar objects, we say that they are (qualitatively) ‘the same’; that they ‘have something in common’ or ‘share some common feature’; that one has the ‘qualities’ or ‘characteristics’ of the other; that they are ‘identical in some respects’. How should we understand this talk of ‘sameness’ and ‘features shared in common’? e apparent quantication over ‘respects’ and ‘features’, and the lack of any obvious alternative to treating sameness as identity, tempt us to recognize entities which are shared between similar objects, whose presence we advert to by talk of their ‘shared features’ and ‘sameness in some respects’. e question of whether we must recognize the existence of a special kind of entity that objects share when they exhibit qualitative sameness, or share some common feature, is the subject-matter of the debate between nominalists and realists. Realists claim that it is necessary to recognize a special kind of entity — universals — shared between qualitatively similar things; nominalists deny that belief in the existence of universals is warranted. In the following chapters, I argue in favour of a realism that recognizes a shared universal wherever objects exhibit genuine qualitative sameness or objective similarity in some respect. Before entering the debate, it would be well to ask, what is a universal, anyway? Without some answer to that question, we cannot know what claim we make when we say that universals exist. e rst thing to say is that a universal is a special kind of entity that is literally identical across its instances, although it is shared by numerically distinct things. is serves to distinguish realism from some radical nominalisms, and from some trope theories, for the trope theorist considers the redness of a and the redness of b to be distinct entities, and may deny that there is any one thing shared between a and b as a universal is supposed to be shared between its instances. However, not every nominalist will deny that there is something literally identical shared between qualitatively similar things — for example, the Predicate Nominalist claims that what is shared is some actual or possible predicate, while the Class Nominalist claims that what is shared is a set containing the things that exhibit the similarity in question. For that reason, we must stipulate that universals are a sui generis kind of entity: they are not to be ‘reduced’ to one or another already recognized metaphysical kind, such as sets of individuals or tropes. is characterization tells us more about what universals are not than about what they are. Can we supplement this with any positive account? It has already been observed that everyday discourse embodies a theory of universals in its vocabulary of characteristics, ¢ features, attributes, qualities, properties, and relations.Õ All these words seem to pick out the same kind of entity; moreover they are entities which may be shared by dierent objects, for example when I am said to have some of the characteristics of my father. One of the reasons why it is rarely felt necessary to give a general account of what universals are is that the notion can be explained with reference to such usages in everyday discourse, and we may see our philosophical account of universals as clarifying and extending a theory already embodied in our everyday thought and talk. One element of everyday discourse about universals is that they are capable of combining with particulars: objects have properties, and stand in relations. is combination is not a matter of the particular being a constituent of the universal, in the way in which the Class Nominalist asserts that objects are constituents of the sets that are identied as their properties and relations. However, it is not an essential part of realism to hold the converse, that universals are constituents (Armstrong ÕÉÉa: ¢) or ‘non-spatiotemporal parts’ (Lewis ÕÉä: äß) of some further objects, whether these are construed as ‘thick particulars’ (Armstrong ÕÉÉa: äþ) or ‘states of aairs’ (Armstrong ÕÉÉß: Õó¢); nor is it mandatory to treat the combination between universals and particulars as an entity — the relation of instantiation — although I shall argue later that this is in fact the best approach for the realist. A feature of philosophical characterizations of universals is that they are considered immune to causal inuence; nothing we could do would change the intrinsic nature of a given universal. is is not to say that universals need be causally inert. Certainly we are able to aect which combinations hold between universals and particulars, for our inuence in the world extends as far as changing which properties objects have, and which relations they stand in. Moreover, universals may be said to have causal inuence on us, even if we cannot change their nature. It would be hard to state a theory of perception which did not describe us as perceiving either the properties of objects, or the properties of our sensory impressions, and such perception requires that these properties be capable of exerting a causal inuence on the world. Interlinked with this conception of universals as immune to inuence is the idea that universals are mind-independent; nothing about the nature or existence of universals is determined by the activity of the human mind. is stipulation serves to distinguish realism from conceptualism, the position that what qualitatively similar things have in common is some man-made concept under which they fall. Finally, any account of universals should mention the question of their location. So- called ‘aristotelians’ say that universals are located at the same places as the particulars ÕOn this point I am in agreement with Quine (ÕÉäÉ: Õ¢). ä that instantiate them, while ‘platonists’ may say that universals lack spatio-temporal location, or may take the extreme view that universals are located in a ‘Platonic heaven’. A premature decision between ‘platonism’ and ‘aristotelianism’ should not be allowed to prejudice the discussion; for now we should observe merely that it cannot be assumed that universals must have spatio-temporal location. I oer a tentative suggestion about how the controversy may be be resolved in my conclusion. e present work falls into two parts: chapters Õ-ì make the case for realism about universals, while chapters ¦-ä address diculties for the realist project. is division is necessary because nominalists attack both the realist’s reasons for introducing universals in the rst place, and the coherence and plausibility of the theory of universals itself. Discussion of problems for a realist ontology is helpful also because it enables us to see more clearly what kind of realist theory we may accept. My positive case for universals is based on a development of the argument known since antiquity as the ‘One over Many’, while the problems I consider are the diculties associated with the thesis that predicates refer to universals, and Bradley’s regress. Chapter one discusses the ‘One over Many’ argument. Realists sometimes talk as though there is one ‘Problem of Universals’, some single problem to which the existence of uni- versals provides a prima facie solution (Armstrong ÕÉÉ: ¢; Rodriguez-Pereyra óþþó: Õ¦), where the burden of proof falls on the nominalist to explain why universals are not, aer all, required (Armstrong ÕÉßa: ÕÉ). We should not assume that there is only one way to argue successfully for the existence of universals, and in fact the historical debates that may be subsumed under the Problem of Universals cover everything from accounting for the objectivity of mathematical truth to explaining how a predicate can be true of more than one thing (MacBride óþþó: óß). At times, in the absence of adequate dialectic, realists have been known even to resort to violence and intimidation to promote their position.ó Indeed, it would be strange to hold that universals are among the fundamental constituents of reality, yet deny that their existence could be established by more than one argument.
Recommended publications
  • PHI 351 Nominalism
    Philosophy 351 September 9, 2008 Prof. Clare Batty Universals: Nominalism 1. Recap Metaphysical realism: the world contains both universals and particulars. Certain things (particulars) are alike in attribute (property, relation, kind) because they exemplify the same universal. Metaphysical realists claim that their two-category framework not only provides us with the machinery with which to explain attribute agreement/similarity/resemblance but also a pair of important phenomena: i. The truth of subject-predicate discourse ii. Our use of abstract reference. 2. Issues we have raised about metaphysical realism a. What universals is the metaphysical realist willing to allow into his/her ontology? • Does he/she allow the universal bachelor or just unmarried, adult, male (does he/she even allow unmarried?). What about he universal green or just green (or light green)? 52 b. Are there unexemplified universals? • Certainly there might have been different properties in the world. Are there universals corresponding to these non-existent, but possible, properties? c. Is the relation of exemplification itself a universal? If so, doesn’t this commit the metaphysical realist to an infinite regress? • Suppose a and b are both F. That is, they exemplify the universal F-ness. But now they have an additional thing in common: they are both exemplifications of F-ness. That is, they both exemplify the universal exemplification of F-ness. Can you see where this is going? d. Doesn’t the metaphysical realist overestimate the degree of agreement/likeness/resemblance in the world? • Grass, peas and wasabi paste are all similar; but they are not exactly alike. 3.
    [Show full text]
  • Medieval Western Philosophy: the European Emergence
    Cultural Heritage and Contemporary Change Series I, Culture and Values, Volume 9 History of Western Philosophy by George F. McLean and Patrick J. Aspell Medieval Western Philosophy: The European Emergence By Patrick J. Aspell The Council for Research in Values and Philosophy 1 Copyright © 1999 by The Council for Research in Values and Philosophy Gibbons Hall B-20 620 Michigan Avenue, NE Washington, D.C. 20064 All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Aspell, Patrick, J. Medieval western philosophy: the European emergence / Patrick J. Aspell. p.cm. — (Cultural heritage and contemporary change. Series I. Culture and values ; vol. 9) Includes bibliographical references and index. 1. Philosophy, Medieval. I. Title. III. Series. B721.A87 1997 97-20069 320.9171’7’090495—dc21 CIP ISBN 1-56518-094-1 (pbk.) 2 Table of Contents Chronology of Events and Persons Significant in and beyond the History of Medieval Europe Preface xiii Part One: The Origins of Medieval Philosophy 1 Chapter I. Augustine: The Lover of Truth 5 Chapter II. Universals According to Boethius, Peter Abelard, and Other Dialecticians 57 Chapter III. Christian Neoplatoists: John Scotus Erigena and Anselm of Canterbury 73 Part Two: The Maturity of Medieval Philosophy Chronology 97 Chapter IV. Bonaventure: Philosopher of the Exemplar 101 Chapter V. Thomas Aquinas: Philosopher of the Existential Act 155 Part Three: Critical Reflection And Reconstruction 237 Chapter VI. John Duns Scotus: Metaphysician of Essence 243 Chapter
    [Show full text]
  • Thomas Aquinas: Soul-Body Connection and the Afterlife Hyde Dawn Krista University of Missouri-St
    University of Missouri, St. Louis IRL @ UMSL Theses Graduate Works 4-16-2012 Thomas Aquinas: Soul-Body Connection and the Afterlife Hyde Dawn Krista University of Missouri-St. Louis, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://irl.umsl.edu/thesis Recommended Citation Krista, Hyde Dawn, "Thomas Aquinas: Soul-Body Connection and the Afterlife" (2012). Theses. 261. http://irl.umsl.edu/thesis/261 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate Works at IRL @ UMSL. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses by an authorized administrator of IRL @ UMSL. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Thomas Aquinas: Soul-Body Connection and the Afterlife Krista Hyde M.L.A., Washington University in St. Louis, 2010 B.A., Philosophy, Southeast Missouri State University – Cape Girardeau, 2003 A Thesis Submitted to The Graduate School at the University of Missouri – St. Louis in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree Master of Arts in Philosophy April 2012 Advisory Committee Gualtiero Piccinini, Ph.D. Chair Jon McGinnis, Ph.D. John Brunero, Ph.D. Copyright, Krista Hyde, 2012 Abstract Thomas Aquinas nearly succeeds in addressing the persistent problem of the mind-body relationship by redefining the human being as a body-soul (matter-form) composite. This redefinition makes the interaction problem of substance dualism inapplicable, because there is no soul “in” a body. However, he works around the mind- body problem only by sacrificing an immaterial afterlife, as well as the identity and separability of the soul after death. Additionally, Thomistic psychology has difficulty accounting for the transmission of universals, nor does it seem able to overcome the arguments for causal closure.
    [Show full text]
  • The Idea of Mimesis: Semblance, Play, and Critique in the Works of Walter Benjamin and Theodor W
    DePaul University Via Sapientiae College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences 8-2012 The idea of mimesis: Semblance, play, and critique in the works of Walter Benjamin and Theodor W. Adorno Joseph Weiss DePaul University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd Recommended Citation Weiss, Joseph, "The idea of mimesis: Semblance, play, and critique in the works of Walter Benjamin and Theodor W. Adorno" (2012). College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations. 125. https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd/125 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences at Via Sapientiae. It has been accepted for inclusion in College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Via Sapientiae. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Idea of Mimesis: Semblance, Play, and Critique in the Works of Walter Benjamin and Theodor W. Adorno A Dissertation Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy October, 2011 By Joseph Weiss Department of Philosophy College of Liberal Arts and Sciences DePaul University Chicago, Illinois 2 ABSTRACT Joseph Weiss Title: The Idea of Mimesis: Semblance, Play and Critique in the Works of Walter Benjamin and Theodor W. Adorno Critical Theory demands that its forms of critique express resistance to the socially necessary illusions of a given historical period. Yet theorists have seldom discussed just how much it is the case that, for Walter Benjamin and Theodor W.
    [Show full text]
  • Medieval Philosophy
    | 1 Course Syllabus Medieval Philosophy INSTRUCTOR INFORMATION Dr. Wm Mark Smillie, Professor, Philosophy Department 142 St Charles Hall Email: [email protected]; Ph: 447 - 5416 Office Hours Spring 2017 : MW, 3:30 - 4:30; Th, 2:30 - 4:30; Fri, 2:00 - 3:30; & by appointment. For issues about this course, students can contact me before/after class, at my office hours (posted above), by phone or email (either Carroll email or through moodle email). I will respond to email and phone inquiries within one busine ss day (Saturdays and Sundays are not business days). I will post notifications about the course in the Moodle News Forum. Students should also be aware of the Moodle Calendar that announces assignment deadlines. COURSE INFORMATION PHIL202, Medieval Phil osophy Meets: Tuesday and Thursdays, 9:30 - 10:45, 102 O’Connell; 3 credit hours Course Description This course is an introductory survey of medieval philosophical thought. We will consider some philosophical questions and issues that were central to medieval discussion, including the relationship between faith and reason, the problem of evil, our abili ty to know God’s nature and describe it in human language, the implications of believing in God as a creator, and the famous “problem of universals.” Significant medieval philosophers studied in this course include St. Augustine, Boethius, Peter Abelard, St. Anselm, Avicenna, St. Thomas Aquinas and Bonaventure. An effort will be made to convey general medieval life and values and their connection to medieval philosophy, as well as to relate the thought of the middle Ages to the philosophy of other historic al periods.
    [Show full text]
  • The Problem of Universals in Contemporary Philosophy∗ Scuola Normale Superiore [Pisa - July 5, 2010]
    93 Reportage 7 novembre 2010 International conference on Ontology The problem of universals in contemporary philosophy∗ Scuola Normale Superiore [Pisa - July 5, 2010] Gianmarco Brunialti Masera Overview The three-day conference opened in the afternoon of July, 5 and, after taking a quick look at the programme and the names of the important thinkers standing out on it, one could have expected to find a crowded audience room. Actually that was not quite the case. What I could afford to follow and am going to write about here is only the first day of the conference. The debate started right on time, after a short introduction given by Gabriele Galluzzo, both organizer of the conference and member of the scientific board. I would ac- tually like to underline the word debate: each speech (about 40 minutes) was immediately followed by a short discussion of the issues introduced by the proponent. Unfortunately, de- spite of the accurate and punctual speeches, the little time dedicated to each is what most penalized the conference, in my opinion: this inevitably obliged both the speakers and the audience to be plunged in medias res, without standing too much on ceremonies. I take this to be ‘penalizing’, considering the debate on universals is a very wide one and composed by an incredibly great number of positions which can sometimes start from oppo- site sides and some other times depart at some specific middle point of one single theory of properties and relations. Moreover, most (if not all) of them entail a certain number of other metaphysical themes from which the specific problematics of universals cannot be cut off.
    [Show full text]
  • Measuring Conceptual Similarity in Ontologies: How Bad Is a Cheap Measure?
    Measuring Conceptual Similarity in Ontologies: How Bad is a Cheap Measure? Tahani Alsubait, Bijan Parsia, and Uli Sattler School of Computer Science, The University of Manchester, United Kingdom falsubait,bparsia,[email protected] Abstract. Several attempts have been made to develop similarity mea- sures for ontologies. Motivated by finding problems in existing measures, we design a new family of measures to address these problems. We carry out an empirical study to explore how good the new measures are and to investigate how likely it is to encounter specific task-oriented problems when using a bad similarity measure. 1 Introduction The process of assigning a numerical value reflecting the degree of resemblance between two ontology concepts or the so called conceptual similarity measure- ment is a core step in many ontology-related applications (e.g., ontology align- ment [7], ontology learning [2]). Several attempts have been made to develop methods for measuring conceptual similarity in ontologies [22, 32, 23, 20, 4]. In addition, the problem of measuring similarity is well-founded in psychology and a number of similarity models have been already developed [6, 30, 26, 19, 29, 8, 12]. Rather than adopting a psychological model for similarity as a foundation, we noticed that some existing similarity measures for ontologies are ad-hoc and unprincipled. This can negatively affect the application in which they are used. However, in some cases, depending on how simple the ontology/task is, using a computationally expensive \good" similarity measure is no better than using a cheap \bad" measure. Thus, we need to understand the computational cost of the similarity measure and the cases in which it succeeds/fails.
    [Show full text]
  • A Model of Human Categorization and Similarity Based Upon Category Theory Michael Healy
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by University of New Mexico University of New Mexico UNM Digital Repository Electrical & Computer Engineering Technical Engineering Publications Reports 7-1-2008 A Model of Human Categorization and Similarity Based Upon Category Theory Michael Healy Thomas Caudell Timothy Goldsmith Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalrepository.unm.edu/ece_rpts Recommended Citation Healy, Michael; Thomas Caudell; and Timothy Goldsmith. "A Model of Human Categorization and Similarity Based Upon Category Theory." (2008). https://digitalrepository.unm.edu/ece_rpts/28 This Technical Report is brought to you for free and open access by the Engineering Publications at UNM Digital Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electrical & Computer Engineering Technical Reports by an authorized administrator of UNM Digital Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. DEPARTMENT OF ELECTRICAL AND COMPUTER ENGINEERING SCHOOL OF ENGINEERING UNIVERSITY OF NEW MEXICO A Model of Human Categorization and Similarity Based Upon Category Theory Michael John Healy Department of Electrical and Computer Engineering e-mail: [email protected] Thomas Preston Caudell Department of Electrical and Computer Engineering and Department of Computer Science e-mail: [email protected] Timothy E. Goldsmith Department of Psychology e-mail: [email protected] University of New Mexico Albuquerque, New Mexico 87131, USA UNM Technical Report: EECE-TR-08-0010 Report Date: June 19, 2008 Abstract Categorization and the judgement of similarity are fundamental in cognition. We propose that these and other activities are based upon an underlying structure of knowledge, or concept representation, in the brain.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy.Pdf
    Philosophy 1 PHIL:1401 Matters of Life and Death 3 s.h. Contemporary ethical controversies with life and death Philosophy implications; topics may include famine, brain death, animal ethics, abortion, torture, terrorism, capital punishment. GE: Chair Values and Culture. • David Cunning PHIL:1636 Principles of Reasoning: Argument and Undergraduate major: philosophy (B.A.) Debate 3 s.h. Undergraduate minor: philosophy Critical thinking and its application to arguments and debates. Graduate degrees: M.A. in philosophy; Ph.D. in philosophy GE: Quantitative or Formal Reasoning. Faculty: https://clas.uiowa.edu/philosophy/people/faculty PHIL:1861 Introduction to Philosophy 3 s.h. Website: https://clas.uiowa.edu/philosophy/ Varied topics; may include personal identity, existence of The Department of Philosophy offers programs of study for God, philosophical skepticism, nature of mind and reality, undergraduate and graduate students. A major in philosophy time travel, and the good life; readings, films. GE: Values and develops abilities useful for careers in many fields and for any Culture. situation requiring clear, systematic thinking. PHIL:1902 Philosophy Lab: The Meaning of Life 1 s.h. Further exploration of PHIL:1033 course material with the The department also administers the interdisciplinary professor in a smaller group. undergraduate major in ethics and public policy, which it offers jointly with the Department of Economics and the PHIL:1904 Philosophy Lab: Liberty and the Pursuit of Department of Sociology and Criminology; see Ethics and Happiness 1 s.h. Public Policy in the Catalog. Further exploration of PHIL:1034 course material with the professor in a smaller group. Programs PHIL:1950 Philosophy Club 1-3 s.h.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy 305 a Early Medieval Philosophy (4Th to the 12Th Century CE)
    1 Philosophy 305 A Early Medieval Philosophy (4th to the 12th Century CE) This course begins with a brief presentation of the philosophies of Plato, Aristotle and Plotinus insofar as these were influential on medieval philosophical thought. It then considers major thinkers in the Christian traditions from the 4th to the 12th century CE, and includes a brief introduction to major Islamic and Jewish philosophers within that time period insofar as their speculations were influential on medieval Christian philosophy. Instructor: E-H. W. Kluge Office: CLE B313 Phone: (250)721-7519 e-mail: [email protected] Office Hours: Mondays and Thursdays 10:00am - 11:20am Text: Arthur Hyman, James J. Walsh, & Thomas Williams, eds. Philosophy in the Middle Ages (3rd ed.) Cambridge, MA: Hackett. Formal Course Requirements and Grading Procedures Grades will be based on two mid-terms and a final examination. The mid-term examinations are fifty minutes long and the final examination is three hours in length. The mid-term examinations are each worth 20% of the course grade; the final examination is worth 60%. Students who have taken (and received a grade for) both mid-term examinations have the option of having the final examination count for 100% of their course grade. The mid-term examinations cover only the material that has not been tested before in the semester; the final examination is cumulative and covers all of the material dealt with in the course. Students are encouraged to discuss their mid- term examination with the instructor. Significant dates: - Mid-term examination #1: app. October 1 - Mid-term examination #2: app.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein and Religion
    Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Theses Department of Philosophy 8-3-2006 Wittgenstein and Religion Daniel Patrick Corrigan Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Corrigan, Daniel Patrick, "Wittgenstein and Religion." Thesis, Georgia State University, 2006. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses/13 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Philosophy at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Theses by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. WITTGENSTEIN AND RELIGION by DANIEL CORRIGAN Under the Direction of Robert L. Arrington ABSTRACT This thesis considers the implications of Wittgenstein’s early and later philosophy for the issue of religious belief, as well as the relation of religion to Wittgenstein’s thought. In the first chapter I provide an overview of the Tractatus and discuss the place of religion within the Tractarian framework. I then provide an overview of Philosophical Investigations . In the second chapter I consider interpretations by Norman Malcolm and Peter Winch of Wittgenstein’s comment that he could not help seeing every problem from a religious point of view, as well as Kai Nielsen’s famous critique of ‘Wittgensteinian Fideism.’ The third and final chapter takes up the issue of construing religious belief as a distinctive language-game. I consider arguments from D. Z. Phillips and criticisms of Phillips from Mark Addis and Gareth Moore. INDEX WORDS: Wittgenstein, Religion, Language-games WITTGENSTEIN AND RELIGION by DANIEL CORRIGAN A Thesis Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts in the College of Arts and Sciences Georgia State University 2006 Copyright by Daniel Patrick Corrigan 2006 WITTGENSTEIN AND RELIGION by DANIEL CORRIGAN Major Professor: Robert L.
    [Show full text]
  • How Language Expresses the World After Early Wittgenstein
    [VOLUME 5IISSUE 3 I JULY– SEPT 2018]E ISSN 2348 –1269, PRINT ISSN 2349-5138 How Language Expresses the World after Early Wittgenstein NOOR BANU KHATUN Research Scholar in Philosophy, University of Gour Banga, Mokdumpur, Malda, West Bengal. India Received: May 25, 2018 Accepted: July 15, 2018 ABSTRACT In twentieth century philosophy, Ludwig Wittgenstein holds a unique position as far as his development of linguistic philosophy is concerned. We know his philosophy as early (T.L.P) and later (P.I) Wittgenstein. His both philosophy is very important for us. Language is the universal medium of communication. Only language can reveal the world. Ludwig Wittgenstein is the most proponent of ideal language philosophy. He proposes the ideal language in his early philosophy in Tractatus logico-Philosophicus. He says that language is the picture of the world or reality. Wittgenstein also holds that language always is corresponding to the world and he also prefers in T.L.P the semantic relationship between picture and reality, where picture is a model of reality. Keywords:Language, world (reality), Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (T.L.P). Introduction During twentieth century philosophy, most of the analytic philosophers conceived that philosophical problems are linguistic, because philosophical problems arise due to the misinterpretation of language or misuse of language or ambiguity of the words or expressions or definitions of language. Since Ludwig Wittgenstein emphasizes on language. Language is the most important medium of our communication in our life. Only language can express the world. There are two types of language viz. ideal language and ordinary language. However, in twentieth century philosophy, most proponents of ideal language philosopher are …viz.
    [Show full text]