Hume's Problem: Induction and the Justification of Belief Colin Howson

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Hume's Problem: Induction and the Justification of Belief Colin Howson Hume's Problem: Induction and the Justification of Belief Colin Howson offers a solution to one of the central, unsolved problems of Western philosophy, the problem of induction. In the mid-eighteenth century David Hume argued that successful prediction tells us nothing about the truth of the predicting theory. No matter how many experimental tests a hypothesis passes, nothing can be legitimately inferred about its truth or probable truth. But physical theory routinely predicts the values of observable magnitudes to many places of decimals and within very small ranges of error. The chance of this sort of predictive success without a true theory seems so remote that the possibility should be dismissed. This suggests that Hume's argument must be wrong; but there is still no consensus on where exactly the flaw in the argument lies. Howson argues that there is no flaw, and examines the implications of this disturbing conclusion for the relation between science and its empirical base. end p.i end p.ii Hume's Problem Induction and the Justification of Belief CLARENDON PRESS · OXFORD 2000 end p.iii Great Clarendon Street, Oxford ox2 6dp Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide in Oxford New York Auckland Bangkok Buenos Aires Cape Town Chennai Dar es Salaam Delhi Hong Kong Istanbul Karachi Kolkata Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Mumbai Nairobi São Paulo Shanghai Taipei Tokyo Toronto Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries Published in the United States by Oxford University Press Inc., New York © Colin Howson 2000 The moral rights of the authors have been asserted Database right Oxford University Press (maker) First published 2000 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above You must not circulate this book in any other binding or cover and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Howson, Colin. Induction and the justification of belief: Hume's problem / Colin Howson. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. 1. Induction (Logic). 2. Science—Philosophy. 3. Hume, David, 1711–1776—Contributions in logical induction. I. Title. BC91 .H69 2000 161—dc21 00–056652 ISBN 0–19–825037–1 (alk. paper) end p.iv None but a fool or madman will ever pretend to dispute the authority of experience. (David Hume) The greatest, and perhaps the only, use of philosophy of pure reason is thus purely negative, since it serves not as an organon for the extension of knowledge, but as a discipline for determining knowledge's limits; and, instead of discovering truth, has only the modest merit of preventing error. (Immanuel Kant) The laws of probability are laws of consistency, an extension to partial beliefs of formal logic, the logic of consistency. (F. P. Ramsey) end p.v end p.vi Acknowledgements To Tom Baldwin, Richard Bradley, Craig Callender, David Corfield, Philippe Mongin, Margie Morrison, Demetris Portides, Jon Williamson, all the students taking the Philosophy of Science option in the LSE 1997–8, and two anonymous referees: many thanks for their kind help. I am also very grateful to Charlotte Jenkins for her patience and able assistance in seeing this book through the press. I would also like to acknowledge the patient support of Peter Momtchiloff, a constant source of encouragement and help. My greatest debt of all is to Peter Urbach, whose ideas on these issues over a period of twenty-five years, which included co- authorship of a book on the Bayesian theory, have become so inextricably linked with my own that I can no longer tell which are which, except that his are probably the better ones. end p.vii end p.viii Contents INTRODUCTION 1 1. HUME'S ARGUMENT 6 2. RELIABILISM 22 3. REALISM AND THE NO-MIRACLES ARGUMENT 35 4. PROBABILISM 61 5. DEDUCTIVISM 94 6. THE NATURALISTIC FALLACY 109 7. ‘A NEW SPECIES OF LOGIC’ 121 8. THE LOGIC OF SCIENTIFIC DISCOVERY 168 9. CHANCE AND PROBABILITY 221 FINALE 239 CODA: ‘OF MIRACLES’ 241 References 247 Index 257 end p.ix end p.x Introduction Colin Howson 1 Half-way through the eighteenth century the Scottish 1 Not English, as Glymour states (1992: 108). philosopher David Hume published a philosophical argument that was, metaphorically, dynamite. Its famous conclusion, that there is no justification for regarding what has been observed to happen in the past as any sort of reliable guide to the future, subverted the prevailing methodology of observation and experiment on the back of which rode the new mathematical sciences that seemed at the time Hume wrote to have attained an extraordinary degree of success, and have gone on doing so. Yet no uncontroversially definitive answer has ever been forthcoming to Hume, and most people have followed his own example of behaving as though nothing had happened. I find this extraordinary, and I believe it is time to face up to the unpalatable possibility revealed by Hume that all our hard-won factual knowledge is not secured by any process of demonstrably sound reasoning (and I mean sound reasoning in general, not merely deductive) to an empirical base, and see whether that is true and, if so, what follows from it. In the course of the investigation we shall be obliged to consider the respective claims of all the major ‘isms’ of contemporary philosophy of science: reliabilism, realism, falsificationism, naturalism, and Bayesianism. We shall also encounter the Anthropic Principle, significance tests, and miracles. Evaluating Hume's argument can therefore be made into a stimulating way of acquainting students with a wider class of philosophical issues, at the same time challenging them with a classic open problem which can be simply stated but not simply solved, if it can be solved at all. This book grew out of a course of lectures in philosophy of science employing just such an approach. The first chapter sketches the intellectual background to Hume's argument, presents that argument and then looks at some of the quicker attempts to rebut it. The subsequent chapters examine the more sophisticated replies, touching as they proceed on each of the ‘isms’ listed above. end p.1 My primary purpose in writing this book is not pedagogic, however. It is to support a claim that, despite its seeming absurdity, Hume's argument is actually correct. I shall present the argument, in Chapter 1, in a way that I think best reveals its quite extraordinary power, a power which, I believe, is still too little appreciated. The argument is deservedly one of the great classics of philosophy: Hume, no mean wielder of crushing arguments, produced in this one possibly the most crushing of them all. And not only crushing, but apparently attended by the gravest consequences for our standards of justified belief. But just as the force of Hume's argument is usually underestimated, so the devastation it is supposed to bring in its wake is usually exaggerated, and my supplementary thesis is that there is none the less a positive solution to Hume's problem. Indeed, I will argue the apparently paradoxical claim that there are nevertheless demonstrably sound inductive inferences! The resolution of the paradox is that inductive inference arises as a necessary feature of consistent reasoning, given the sorts of initial plausibility assumptions scientists habitually make. We are already familiar with and accept the idea that deductive soundness is a property of inferences and not their conclusions; I believe that the correct analysis of Hume's problem, and Hume's own view of inductive reasoning, forces us to view inductive soundness in the same way, a property of inferences rather than of what we conclude from them. This may not sound the sort of conclusion to warrant fanfares, but in mitigation two things can be said. First, Hume's argument gives us no reason to suppose that relying on our scientific knowledge is in any way misguided; it does not tell us we are wrong to do so. It merely says that the attempt to show that there is any sound inductive reasoning to that knowledge from observation alone will fail. But it may well be that we are fully justified, in terms of its truth or nearness to the truth, in relying on it. Secondly, I believe that Hume genuinely has solved the problem of induction. He solved it by showing, in general terms, that a sound inductive inference must possess, in addition to whatever observational or experimental data is specified, at least one independent assumption (an inductive assumption) that in effect weights some of the possibilities consistent with that evidence more than others. I take this to be a great logical discovery, comparable to that of deductive inference itself, and with consequences of as much practical as theoretical importance. For the problem of induction, considered as end p.2 the problem of characterizing soundness for inductive inferences, has recently become hot (so to speak). People are now for the first time in their chequered, too-frequently-bloody, history allocating substantial intellectual and material resources to the design of intelligent machinery, and in particular machinery that will learn from data.
Recommended publications
  • Liberal Neutrality: a Reinterpretation and Defense*
    Liberal Neutrality: A Reinterpretation and Defense* Alan Patten, Princeton University (1) Introduction After a brief ascendancy in the 1970s and `80s, the idea of liberal neutrality has fallen out of favor in recent years. A growing chorus of liberal writers has joined anti-liberal critics in arguing that there is something confused and misguided about the insistence that the state be neutral between rival conceptions of the good. Assuming we can even make sense of the idea of neutrality, these writers contend, it is a mistake to think that there is anything in liberal principles that commits the liberal state to neutrality.1 With a number of former neutralists softening their support for the idea, the rejection of neutrality is quickly becoming a consensus position, even amongst liberal political philosophers.2 According to one writer, all that remains to be done is an “autopsy” on the idea of state neutrality.3 Much of the critique of neutrality has proceeded on the basis of four assumptions. The first contrasts neutrality with perfectionism. To defend state neutrality is to deny that the state can legitimately use its power to encourage ways of life that it supposes to be valuable or to discourage ones that it regards * Earlier versions of this paper were presented at Washington University, at Queenʼs University, at the Canadian Political Science Associationʼs 2010 Annual Conference , and in a workshop at Princetonʼs University Center for Human Values. In addition to thanking the participants in and organizers of these events, I am grateful to Arash Abizadeh, Andrew Lister, Stephen Macedo, Ian MacMullen, Jonathan Quong, Ryan Pevnick, and Anna Stilz for their written feedback.
    [Show full text]
  • Would ''Direct Realism'' Resolve the Classical Problem of Induction?
    NOU^S 38:2 (2004) 197–232 Would ‘‘Direct Realism’’ Resolve the Classical Problem of Induction? MARC LANGE University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill I Recently, there has been a modest resurgence of interest in the ‘‘Humean’’ problem of induction. For several decades following the recognized failure of Strawsonian ‘‘ordinary-language’’ dissolutions and of Wesley Salmon’s elaboration of Reichenbach’s pragmatic vindication of induction, work on the problem of induction languished. Attention turned instead toward con- firmation theory, as philosophers sensibly tried to understand precisely what it is that a justification of induction should aim to justify. Now, however, in light of Bayesian confirmation theory and other developments in epistemology, several philosophers have begun to reconsider the classical problem of induction. In section 2, I shall review a few of these developments. Though some of them will turn out to be unilluminating, others will profitably suggest that we not meet inductive scepticism by trying to justify some alleged general principle of ampliative reasoning. Accordingly, in section 3, I shall examine how the problem of induction arises in the context of one particular ‘‘inductive leap’’: the confirmation, most famously by Henrietta Leavitt and Harlow Shapley about a century ago, that a period-luminosity relation governs all Cepheid variable stars. This is a good example for the inductive sceptic’s purposes, since it is difficult to see how the sparse background knowledge available at the time could have entitled stellar astronomers to regard their observations as justifying this grand inductive generalization. I shall argue that the observation reports that confirmed the Cepheid period- luminosity law were themselves ‘‘thick’’ with expectations regarding as yet unknown laws of nature.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Three Separation Theses James Morauta Abstract. Legal Positivism's
    Three Separation Theses James Morauta Abstract . Legal positivism’s “separation thesis” is usually taken in one of two ways: as an analytic claim about the nature of law—roughly, as some version of the Social Thesis ; or as a substantive moral claim about the value of law—roughly, as some version of the No Value Thesis . In this paper I argue that we should recognize a third kind of positivist separation thesis, one which complements, but is distinct from, positivism’s analytic and moral claims. The Neutrality Thesis says that the correct analytic claim about the nature of law does not by itself entail any substantive moral claims about the value of law. I give careful formulations of these three separation theses, explain the relationships between them, and sketch the role that each plays in the positivist approach to law. [A version of this paper is published in Law and Philosophy (2004).] 1. Introduction Everybody knows that legal positivists hold that there is some kind of “separation”— some kind of distinction—between law and morality. But what exactly is this positivist separation thesis ? In what way, according to legal positivism, are law and morality distinct? There are many possible answers to this question. Legal positivism is standardly thought of as a cluster of three kinds of claims: an analytic claim about the nature of law; a moral claim about law’s value; and a linguistic claim about the meaning of the normative terms that appear in legal statements. 1 I won’t have anything to say here about the linguistic issue.
    [Show full text]
  • Akrasia: Plato and the Limits of Education?
    Akrasia: Plato and the Limits of Education? Colm Shanahan Submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Dublin, Trinity College Supervisor: Prof. Vasilis Politis Submitted to the University of Dublin, Trinity College, August 2017 Declaration I declare that this thesis has not been submitted as an exercise for a degree at this or any other university and it is entirely my own work. I agree to deposit this thesis in the University’s open access institutional repository or allow the library to do so on my behalf, subject to Irish Copyright Legislation and Trinity College Library conditions of use and acknowledgement. Signed: __________________________ Date:_____________ (Colm Shanahan) Summary In this dissertation, I shall argue for the following main claim: (1a) the motivational neutrality of reason. I will show that this concept reveals that, for Plato, (1b) reason is itself a necessary condition of the possibility of akrasia, and a central explanatory element in his account of akrasia. In presenting the soul with the capacity to take account of the whole soul, the motivational neutrality of reason seems to be the precondition of moving from having such a capacity, in a speculative manner, to generating desires and actions based upon such considerations. If this were not so, then how could the rational part of the soul, for example, put its good to one side, where such is required, to achieve the good of the whole soul? This distancing from the good associated with the rational part of the soul is precisely the grounding upon which the rational part of the soul generates the space to assess the goods of the other soul parts.
    [Show full text]
  • There Is No Pure Empirical Reasoning
    There Is No Pure Empirical Reasoning 1. Empiricism and the Question of Empirical Reasons Empiricism may be defined as the view there is no a priori justification for any synthetic claim. Critics object that empiricism cannot account for all the kinds of knowledge we seem to possess, such as moral knowledge, metaphysical knowledge, mathematical knowledge, and modal knowledge.1 In some cases, empiricists try to account for these types of knowledge; in other cases, they shrug off the objections, happily concluding, for example, that there is no moral knowledge, or that there is no metaphysical knowledge.2 But empiricism cannot shrug off just any type of knowledge; to be minimally plausible, empiricism must, for example, at least be able to account for paradigm instances of empirical knowledge, including especially scientific knowledge. Empirical knowledge can be divided into three categories: (a) knowledge by direct observation; (b) knowledge that is deductively inferred from observations; and (c) knowledge that is non-deductively inferred from observations, including knowledge arrived at by induction and inference to the best explanation. Category (c) includes all scientific knowledge. This category is of particular import to empiricists, many of whom take scientific knowledge as a sort of paradigm for knowledge in general; indeed, this forms a central source of motivation for empiricism.3 Thus, if there is any kind of knowledge that empiricists need to be able to account for, it is knowledge of type (c). I use the term “empirical reasoning” to refer to the reasoning involved in acquiring this type of knowledge – that is, to any instance of reasoning in which (i) the premises are justified directly by observation, (ii) the reasoning is non- deductive, and (iii) the reasoning provides adequate justification for the conclusion.
    [Show full text]
  • Fallibilism and Organizational Research: the Third Epistemology
    FALLIBILISM AND ORGANIZATIONAL RESEARCH: THE THIRD EPISTEMOLOGY Published as : Powell, T.C. 2001. Fallibilism and Organizational Research: The Third Epistemology, Journal of Management Research , 4, 201-219. Correspondence to : Thomas Powell Professor of Strategy, Oxford University Said Business School Park End Street Oxford OX2 8BZ UK [email protected] 1 FALLIBILISM AND ORGANIZATIONAL RESEARCH: THE THIRD EPISTEMOLOGY Abstract Epistemology is the study of knowledge - of what is known and how we know it. Organizational epistemology is dominated by the dualist opposition of objectivist and subjectivist philosophies of science. Objectivists accept knowledge claims as potentially true and warranted on objective evidence, whereas subjectivists ground knowledge in perception, phenomenology and social construction. Though these two perspectives differ in their ontologies (the reality of constructs and relations) and methodologies (how these relations can be observed), both views accept that reliable organizational knowledge is possible. This paper introduces a third epistemological perspective - fallibilism - and shows how neglect of this third epistemology has constrained advance in the objectivist-subjectivist debate. Fallibilism, which challenges the foundations and reliability of knowledge claims, occupies a significant place in every major philosophical tradition, but contradicts the prevailing rhetoric of knowledge-claiming in organizational research, and has been systematically excluded from the debate. In this article we present the foundations and precepts of fallibilism, show how its absence has invited divisive and sectarian dogmatism, and explores its potential contributions to organizational research. 2 FALLIBILISM AND ORGANIZATIONAL RESEARCH: THE THIRD EPISTEMOLOGY Organization and epistemology It is customary in the philosophy of social science to depict organizational epistemology as a debate between objectivist and subjectivist perspectives (Burrell and Morgan, 1979; Morgan and Smircich, 1980; Gioia and Pitre, 1990; Knights, 1992).
    [Show full text]
  • VU Research Portal
    VU Research Portal Realism, Instrumentalism, and Scientific Symbiosis: Psychological Theory as a search for truth and the discovery of solutions Cacioppo, J.T.; Semin, G.R.; Berntson, G.G. published in American Psychologist 2004 DOI (link to publisher) 10.1037/0003-066X.59.4.214 document version Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Link to publication in VU Research Portal citation for published version (APA) Cacioppo, J. T., Semin, G. R., & Berntson, G. G. (2004). Realism, Instrumentalism, and Scientific Symbiosis: Psychological Theory as a search for truth and the discovery of solutions. American Psychologist, 59, 214-233. https://doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.59.4.214 General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal ? Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. E-mail address: [email protected] Download date: 03. Oct. 2021 Realism, Instrumentalism, and Scientific Symbiosis Psychological Theory as a Search for Truth and the Discovery of Solutions John T.
    [Show full text]
  • The Law and the Brain: Judging Scientific Evidence of Intent
    The Journal of Appellate Practice and Process Volume 1 Issue 2 Article 4 1999 The Law and the Brain: Judging Scientific videnceE of Intent Erica Beecher-Monas Edgar Garcia-Rill Follow this and additional works at: https://lawrepository.ualr.edu/appellatepracticeprocess Part of the Evidence Commons, Jurisprudence Commons, and the Science and Technology Law Commons Recommended Citation Erica Beecher-Monas and Edgar Garcia-Rill, The Law and the Brain: Judging Scientific videnceE of Intent, 1 J. APP. PRAC. & PROCESS 243 (1999). Available at: https://lawrepository.ualr.edu/appellatepracticeprocess/vol1/iss2/4 This document is brought to you for free and open access by Bowen Law Repository: Scholarship & Archives. It has been accepted for inclusion in The Journal of Appellate Practice and Process by an authorized administrator of Bowen Law Repository: Scholarship & Archives. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE LAW AND THE BRAIN: JUDGING SCIENTIFIC EVIDENCE OF INTENT Erica Beecher-Monas* and Edgar Garcia-Rill, Ph.D.** INTRODUCTION As evidentiary gatekeepers, judges must be ready to evaluate expert testimony about science and the brain. A wide variety of cases present issues of mental state, many doubtless with battling experts seeking to testify on these issues. This poses a dilemma for nonspecialist judges. How is a nonscientist to judge scientific evidence? How can a nonscientist decide if testimony about mental state meets the criteria of good science? This essay offers a general overview of the issue of evaluating scientific evidence and is aimed at exploring the issues involved, but not attempting easy answers. Of necessity, this requires thinking about how science works.
    [Show full text]
  • Publications • Reference Works O the Routledge Companion to Evidence
    Curriculum Vitae for Trent Dougherty POSITIONS Fall 2009-Present: Assistant Professor of Philosophy, tenure track, Baylor University Trinity Term 2014 Visiting Scholar, Oxford University Spring 2014 Visiting Scholar, University of St. Andrews Fall 2011-Spring 2012 Visiting Research Professor, University of Notre Dame Fall 2008-Spring 2009 Visiting Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Saint John Fisher College, Rochester, NY (while completing PhD) EDUCATION • PhD, University of Rochester, Rochester, New York, Richard Feldman, advisor, May 2009. • MA, Philosophy, University of Missouri-Columbia, Director Jon Kvanvig • AB, Philosophy and Classics, University of Missouri-Columbia DISSERTATION • Against Pragmatic Encroachment: A Defense of Simple Moderate Invariantism. • Committee: o Richard Feldman, Chair, Earl Conee, Greg Carlson, Chairman, Department of Linguistics, University of Rochester, Jeff Runner, Department of Linguistics, University of Rochester AREAS OF SPECIALIZATION • Epistemology/Rationality Theory (Evidence/Reasons) • Philosophy of Religion • Philosophy of Language AREAS OF COMPETENCE • Philosophy of Science • Metaphysics and Mind • Decision Theory • Applied Ethics Publications • Reference Works o The Routledge Companion to Evidence. (ed) Routledge. In progress. • Textbooks o A Critical Introduction to Justification (with Kevin McCain, Jon Matheson, and Jason Rogers). Acumen. In progress. • Edited Collections o Skeptical Theism: New Essays, (with Justin McBrayer) Oxford University Press, (2014). Edited volume of leading philosophers of religion on epistemic response to the problem of evil. o Evidentialism and Its Discontents, Oxford University Press, 2011. Edited volume of leading epistemologists on the role of evidence in epistemology. • Books o The Problem of Animal Pain: A Theodicy for All Creatures Great and Small, (2014) Palgrave MacMillan. o God and the Mystery of Evil. Under contract with OUP.
    [Show full text]
  • Realism and Instrumentalism in Philosophical Explanation
    Simchen, O. 2019. Realism and Instrumentalism in Philosophical Explanation. Metaphysics, 2(1), pp. 1–15. DOI: https://doi.org/10.5334/met.20 RESEARCH Realism and Instrumentalism in Philosophical Explanation Ori Simchen University of British Columbia, CA [email protected] There is a salient contrast in how theoretical representations are regarded. Some are regarded as revealing the nature of what they represent, as in familiar cases of theoretical identification in physical chemistry where water is represented as hydrogen hydroxide and gold is represented as the element with atomic number 79. Other theoretical representations are regarded as serving other explanatory aims without being taken individually to reveal the nature of what they represent, as in the representation of gold as a standard for pre-20th century monetary systems in economics or the representation of the meaning of an English sentence as a function from possible worlds to truth values in truth-conditional semantics. Call the first attitude towards a theoretical representation realist and the second attitude instrumentalist. Philosophical explanation purports to reveal the nature of whatever falls within its purview, so it would appear that a realist attitude towards its representations is a natural default. I offer reasons for skepticism about such default realism that emerge from attending to several case studies of philosophical explanation and drawing a general metaphilosophical moral from the foregoing discussion. Keywords: realism; instrumentalism; philosophical explanation; philosophical methodology 1 Introduction Any theoretical endeavour employs representations and philosophy is no exception. A representation for present purposes is a theoretical apparatus that stands for some subject matter within a purported explana- tion.
    [Show full text]
  • Charles Taylor and George Grant on the Problem of Instrumentalism: Expressivism and Justice As Alternative Ontologies
    CHARLES TAYLOR AND GEORGE GRANT ON THE PROBLEM OF INSTRUMENTALISM: EXPRESSIVISM AND JUSTICE AS ALTERNATIVE ONTOLOGIES Carlos Colorado Bachelor of Arts, Simon Fraser University, 2001 THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS Under Special Arrangements in the Faculty of Arts O Carlos Colorado 2004 SIMON FRASER UNIVERSITY August 2004 All rights reserved. This work may not be reproduced in whole or in part, by photocopy or other means, without permission of the author. APPROVAL Name: Carlos Colorado Degree: Master of Arts Charles Taylor and George Grant on the Problem of Title of Thesis: Instrumentalism: Expressivism and Justice as Alternative Ontologies Examining Committee: Chair: Dr. Jonathan C. Driver Dean of Graduate Studies Dr. Ian Angus Senior Supervisor Professor Department of Humanities Dr. David Laycock Supervisor Professor Department of Political Science Dr. Samuel LaSelva External Examiner Professor Department of Political Science University of British Columbia Date Approved: &b! 208~ Partial Copyright Licence The author, whose copyright is declared on the title page of this work, has granted to Simon Fraser University the right to lend this thesis, project or extended essay to users of the Simon Fraser University Library, and to make partial or single copies only for such users or in response to a request from the library of any other university, or other educational institution, on its own behalf or for one of its users. The author has further agreed that permission for multiple copying of this work for scholarly purposes may be granted by either the author or the Dean of Graduate Studies.
    [Show full text]
  • Achievements and Fallacies in Hume's Account of Infinite
    -1- ACHIEVEMENTS AND FALLACIES IN HUME’S ACCOUNT OF INFINITE DIVISIBILITY James Franklin Hume Studies 20 (1994): 85-101 Throughout history,almost all mathematicians, physicists and philosophers have been of the opinion that space and time are infinitely divisible. That is, it is usually believedthat space and time do not consist of atoms, but that anypiece of space and time of non-zero size, howeversmall, can itself be divided into still smaller parts. This assumption is included in geometry,asinEuclid, and also in the Euclidean and non- Euclidean geometries used in modern physics. Of the fewwho have denied that space and time are infinitely divisible, the most notable are the ancient atomists, and Berkeleyand Hume. All of these assert not only that space and time might be atomic, but that theymust be. Infinite divisibility is, theysay, impossible on purely conceptual grounds. In the hundred years or so before Hume’s Tr eatise, there were occasional treatments of the matter,in places such as the Port Royal Logic, and Isaac Barrow’smathematical lectures of the 1660’s, 1 Theydonot add anything substantial to medievaltreatments of the same topic. 2 Mathematicians certainly did not take seriously the possibility that space and time might be atomic; Pascal, for example, instances the Chevalier de Me´re´’s belief in atomic space as proof of his total incompetence in mathematics. 3 The problem acquired amore philosophical cast when Bayle, in his Dictionary, tried to showthat both the assertion and the denial of the infinite divisibility of space led to contradictions; the problem thus appears as a general challenge to "Reason".
    [Show full text]